Routledge Advances in International Relations and Global Politics
The Duty of Care in
International Relations
Protecting Citizens Beyond the Border
Christianity and American State Violence in Iraq
Priestly or Prophetic?
Christopher A. Morrissey
Small States and Hegemonic Competition in Southeast Asia
Pursuing Autonomy, Security and Development amid Great Power Politics
Chih-Mao Tang
Empires of Knowledge in International Relations
Edited by
Nina Grreger and Halvard Leira
Education and Science as Sources of Power for the State
Anna Wojciuk
Joining the Non-Proliferation Treaty
Deterrence, Non-Proliferation and the American Alliance
Edited by John Baylis and Yoko Jwama
New Geographies of Global Policy-Making
South-South Networks and Rural Development Strategies
Carolina Milhorance
Norm Dilemmas in Humanitarian Interv~ntion
How Bosnia Changed NATO
Yuki Abe
American Hegemony in the 21st Century
Iii
1.1•
1111
A Neo Neo-Gramscian Perspective
Jonathan Pass
The Duty of Care in International Relations
Protecting Citizens Beyond the Border
Nina Grceger and Halvard Leira
The Global Politics of Jazz in the Twentieth Century
Cultural Diplomacy and "American Music"
Yoshiomi Saito
For information about the series: https://www.routledge.com/RoutledgeAdvances-in-Intemational-Relations-and-Global-Politics/book-series/IRGP
I~ ~?io~;~!n~R~up
LONDON AND NEW YORK
~1111TH'll'r•nr l'lflnr:t· ::::;:;;allilllWfr:-1~ , t l l i j f ! f ! - l l l l t B -
Contents
First published 2020
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an info1ma business
© 2020 selection and editorial matter, Nina Grreger and Halvard Leira;
individual chapters, the contributors
The right of Nina Grreger and Halvard Leira to be identified as the authors
of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has
been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright,
Designs and Patents Act 1988.
List of figures
Preface
Contributors
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
Vll
Vlll
X
Introduction: The Duty of Care in International Relations
HALYARD LEIRA AND NINA GRAoGER
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
2
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record has been requested for this book
Le souci de soi: The Duty of Care and the humanitarian politics
of life
18
ANNA LEANDER
ISBN: 978-1-138-54589-2 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-1-351-00168-7 (ebk)
3
Typeset in Times New Roman
by Taylor & Francis Books
Caring, protecting and disciplining: The surveillance of social
science researchers in the dangerhood?
34
ALESSANDRA RUSSO AND FRANCESCO STRAZZARI
4
Exploring the duty of care in science diplomacy: Challenges for
secure states in an insecure world
53
!LAN KELMAN AND CAROLIN KALTOFEN
5
l!f
Negotiating duty of care after intervention: Afghan interpreters,
Danish veterans and the moral responsibilities of a small state
72
KRISTIAN S0BY KRISTENSEN
1_1_.
1!1
6
1
Caring for the 'enemy'?: Enacting the duty of care for
Norwegians fighting for the Islamic State, Jabhat Al Nusra, and
the Harakat Al Shabaab
87
STIG JARLE HANSEN
7
/J
FSC
wwwfKcrg
•
The duty of care and deterritorialized citizenship: From
governing citizenship to acts of citizenship
XAVIER GUILLAUME
MIX
Paper from
responsible sources
FSC- C013056
Printed and bound in Great Britain by
TJ International Ltd, Padstow, Cornwall
•
-~111- '1'111'111'f-•ff'lf'ltTr•:1•::::WWl'llflV,'1!-I--.W-.at:t,l11J-l,
--I
105
vi
Contents
8
The politics of diasporas and the duty of care: Legitimizing
interventions through the protection of kin
118
Figures
MINDA HOLM
Conclusion
136
KYLE GRAYSON
Index
147
l.l The Social Contract of Care
1.2 The Intermediaries of Care
1.3 Extensions of Care
Ii!i,i
l!!I
11
12
12
Le souci de soi
2
Le souci de soi
The Duty of Care and the humanitarian
politics of life 1
Anna Leander
More than a decade ago, the then board-member and former vice president of
Medecins sans Frontieres (MSF), Didier Fassin who is also a well-established
anthropologist published an article about the politics of humanitarianism
(Fassin 2007). His ambition was to establish the peculiar nature of the politics
of humanitarianism and the particular inescapable aporia 2 this politics generates by imposing a hierarchisation of lives that necessarily violates the moral
and ethical principles of humanitarian action. Fassin identifies three dividing
lines along which humanitarians constantly classify lives, namely the line
separating lives risked and lives that can only be sacrificed; that separating
expatriates and locals; and the line separating the lives of those of those who
speak from those whose lives can only be spoken of He insists that the obvious
aporia involved in having to classify lives along these lines are foundational not
only for humanitarianism but for our present condition and its politics; 3 an
argument he has subsequently expanded and developed in greater detail in
other places (Fassin 2011). In this chapter, I wish to follow up on Fassin's reasoning. I will engage neither his general ' conclusion about the aporia the
humanitarian politics of life nor its overarching significance but rather his view
on how this aporia is generated. For this how matters not only for academic
reasons but because it is crucial for the possibility to act on and govern with
the indeed inescapable aporia; that is for how we understand the possibility for
political agency and the responsibility associated with it.
My overall contention in this chapter is that tending carefully to sociomaterial dispositives4 at the most lowly practical level is essential for understanding how the aporia is fashioned and how we might therefore re-fashion
it. Yet, following Fassin's line of thought makes this difficult. Fassin locates
the distinctiveness of the politics of humanitarianism by contrasting it to
biopolitics. On his account, while this politics has a clear biopolitical dimension (the obvious place of camps, migration and aid flows etc.), its distinctiveness lies in the classification of lives that Fassin suggests is not related to
"technologies of power" but to "the evaluation of human beings and the
meaning of their existence". 5 This delinking from technologies of power from
the evaluation and of human beings and the meaning of their existence
and the related separation of matter and meaning is what I will show is
19
problematic if one wants to understand how the aporia Fassin is interested in
is produced and how it might therefore also be altered. I make this argument
looking carefully at one specific socio-material dispositive, namely the Duty
of Care (DoC). I will show that the DoC has contributed to making the
humanitarian politics of life revolve ever more around a souci de soi [care of
the self] of the humanitarians. It has done so by turning care for the individual's security into a technology of the self.
I will pursue each point in order, concluding on the avenues for agency
these points somewhat paradoxically open; that is on the import of focussing
on socio-material practices for re-fashioning the discomforting humanitarian
politics of life (ever more) characterised by a souci de soi.
A Duty of Care for the humanitarian self
Humanitarian missions often face harsh critique and outright hostility from
the populations they are caring for. Yet, at the same time another critique is
occupying a growing space among the humanitarians themselves, namely that
revolving around how the missions are carried out and in particular the
security of those involved in them (Kralunann and Leander 2019). The care
for the humanitarian self is moving into the centre. This discussion has many
aspects and nuances. Its emergence obviously is also a complex process. Here
I wish to focus on the place of one specific dispositive, tracing one particular
process that has deepened the aporia of humanitarian work and reason. More
specifically, I want to trace how the DoC became established as dispositive
pertinent to the governance of humanitarian action redirecting the focus
toward the security of the humanitarians themselves.
The ascent of the DoC as a legal principle was far from preordained. The
DoC has had a long, and perhaps happy, life in common law since the
emergence of unlimited liability in the 18th century (see Introduction to this
volume; Davies 1989; Davies 2018). It was a principle making it possible to
take producers of goods or services to task if they did fail to take reasonable
measures to limit the risks of their customers. With the move to neo-liberal
forms of new public management, the DoC became used also for public services and particularly in health care. There, it was invoked to protect the
increasingly exposed and vulnerable "clients" of underfunded public services
and to discipline health care personnel into caring better for their patients
(Sevenhuijsen 2003; Munro and Turner 2010). As commercial security and
military markets began to grow it was occasionally gleaned to as one of the
potential dispositives that might be drawn upon to regulate also this area. It
was invoked by states, organisations, companies and their employees as outsourcing increased the confusions and disagreements surrounding who was
responsible for providing security to whom and on what terms. 6 Howeve1~ it
was not until the Norwegian Refugee Council was asked to pay damages to
one of its former employees by a District Court in Oslo, Norway, that the
DoC took on any particular and specific significance for humanitarians.
20
A. Leander
The court case, Dennis v. NRC, was initiated by Steven Patrick Dennis who
had been held hostage by a Somali militia for four days after being kidnapped
while driving in a convoy through Dadaab refugee camp complex in Northern Kenya in June 2012 (OSD 2015). Dennis complained that his suffering
during captivity, as well as the lasting consequences it would have on his life,
could have been avoided had the NRC provided appropriate protection. In its
judgement the court agrees with him. Drawing on statements from the
involved parties but also on reports by the NRC, the UNHCR and the NGO
Safety Program (NSP), the court argues that the NRC should be held "strictly
liable" for its "gross negligence". Since there is no precedent, the court posits
that the NRC should pay damages similar to those stipulated by Norwegian
labour law for Norwegian employees in Norway in similar situations. The
reasoning of the court rests on an analysis of the way that the security
managers had performed, communicated and acted upon the conflicting
risk assessments of the situation in which Dennis and his colleagues were
kidnapped and several people shot dead. At the heart of the ruling are the
arguments that the local security management (i) did not heed previously
established assessments, (ii) failed to communicate upward to the central
risk manager, (iii) did not inform those travelling in the convoy of the risks
involved and (iv) handled the practicalities of the visit unsatisfactorily. 7 As
this makes clear, the court makes no direct reference to the DoC in its
ruling but refers to the Norwegian labour law. However, it did locate the
import of caring for humanitarians-for the humanitarian self-at the
centre of discussions.
The focus on the care for the security of humanitarians drew attention to
the case. Dennis v. NRC was hailed as a "landmark case", "precedentsetting", a "game-changer" and a "wake-up call'' for the aid industry (Wall
2015; Young 2015; Hoppe and Williamson 2016). The reason is that it played
into the complex and often contentious relations between the "aid-industry"
and its security mangers. 8 In fact, it took sides in it. From the perspective of
the aid industry, the security managers often impose unreasonable, too costly
and counterproductive measures. They eat up the budget, hamper what
should be the core activities in humanitarian crises and they claim too much
say over how things should be done by and in the organisations. From the
perspective of the security managers, theirs is an uphill struggle against a
culture of irresponsibility dominating in an aid industry that refuses to face
the all-too-real risks in contemporary humanitarian missions and, on top, it
resists the best efforts of the security managers to assist and protect.
The Norwegian district court ruling weighed in on the side of the security
managers. The court is well aware that precisely this is how its reasoning
might/could be interpreted and therefore tries to caution against it writing
that:
The Court emphasises that this case does not concern the security management within the NRC or the aid industry in general. The Court is to
..'l'ID1''11:llllfflIITJU:~• lilt!I!
Le souci de soi 21
decide only on whether employees of the NRC acted negligently in connection with the kidnapping incident in Dadaab.
(OSD 2015: 15)
Caution disregarded. Not only was the case, picked upon as a "game changer",
imposing the security of the humanitarians as a central concern, the move was
given force by associating the Dennis v. NRC judgement to a more general
legal principle, namely the DoC. This association had to be constructed. The
DoC did not have any place in the judgement itself It is mentioned in the
reasoning of the comi only in the form of a citation of the expert reports, that
by NRC security advisor Chris Allen. Chris Allen in his report refers to the
DoC. In so doing he establishes a link to a common law principle. This is
hardly surprising. Chris Allen is from the UK, with a degree from the University of Essex, and has worked for security companies in contexts where
common law principles would be expected reference points. 9 However, the
reference by the Norwegian court to it is strictly limited to citations of Chris
Allen's report. Hence the court writes
... on page 3 of his report, Chris Allan also concluded that: "The recent
critical incident demonstrates strongly that NRC is not currently fulfilling
its duty of care to staff. This is clearly the case in Dadaab and may also
be relevant in missions elsewhere."
(OSD 2015: 21)
The Norwegian court can hardly be understood to place the DoC at the centre
of its reasoning and judgement. Yet, this is precisely how the case comes to be
constructed in the commentaries following it. For example, a report commenting on Dennis v. NRC written for an umbrella organisation of humanitarian
NGOs [the ESF] 10 is given the title: "Duty of Care: A review of the Dennis v.
Norwegian Refugee Council ruling and its implications" (Merkelbach and
Kemp 2016). The discussion of the purported novel and reinforced significance
of the DoC then rather rapidly ushered in the launch of the Voluntary Guideline on Duty of Care (Merkelbach 2017). The link between the case and the
DoC in other words is not only established, but used to generate regulatory
instruments in its own right: the voluntary guidelines. With this, the DoC and
its peculiar focus on the security of the humanitarians becomes one of the dispositives regulating the security of humanitarian workers.
To clarify the significance of this establishment of the DoC as a dispositive
of humanitatian security governance, two further comments are warranted.
Both pertain to its practical significance for those involved. First, for the
security managers working in the rapidly expanding and largely commercialised "field" 11 of humanitarian security (or wishing to expand their activities
into it!), the developments were obviously warmly welcome. They bolstered
their position giving a legal foundation to the claim on which their activities
are based; that precisely the security of the humanitarians themselves
Le souci de soi
22 A. Leander
demanded careful tending to. Moreover, the court confirmed the responsibility
of the security managers in assessing what exactly tending to this security
entails (Leander 2019). Linking the security of humanitarian workers to a legal
principle was a welcome move Leander, (2018). The voluntary guidelines even
suggested that humanitarian organisations needed to create a "security culture"
for themselves. Translated to plain language, such a culture is one where
security managers have a stronger say in shaping the organisations and their
preferences. Unsurprisingly therefore, the security professionals were prone to
affirm a reading of the Dennis v. N RC judgement affirming the centrality of the
DoC in this peculiar humanitarian-centred edition. It provided them with an
attractive key for entering and consolidating their positions in the sector and its
12
organisations; not to say the promise of carte blanche for remodelling it.
Second, and perhaps more surprisingly, the humanitarians whose culture
was to be changed into a security culture have done little to resist the ascent
of the DoC as a dispositive pertinent for the sector. The NRC position on
Dennis v. NRC is a case in point. The chair-person of the NRC, Jan Egeland,
objected to engaging the judicial process on the grounds that it might lead to
a "counterproductive witch-hunt" in the NRC (OSD 2015: 18). 13 When the
ruling came he limited himself to express his regrets with regard to the
security failures and their consequences for Steven Patiick Dennis. 14 He did
not tackle the bigger question regarding authority the court bestowed on the
professional security management through its ruling nor did he subsequently
address the way the case became associated with the DoC. With this silence,
the NRC is acquiescing to and in the process also reinforcing the ascent of the
DoC as a regulatory dispositive. This is mirrored across the humanitarian
sector. The ESF commissioning of a report on the topic and the wide range
of institutions supporting the Voluntary Guidelines on the Duty of Care is a
case in point. Maarten Merkelbach, the initiator of the Voluntary Guidelines,
is himself committed to humanitarianism with a longstanding field experience
deeply and personally concerned with the development of (in-)security in the
sector. As many humanitarians and organisations, Egeland, the NRC and
Merkelbach, who pushed through the Voluntary Guidelines, appear concerned
p1imarily with adjusting to, accommodating and supporting the development
of humanitarian security governance the DoC is part of
There are good reasons for this support lended to the ascent of a DoC
prioritising the lives of humanitarian workers. Some are to be found in the
growing securitisation/militarisation of neo-liberal life in general that is
affecting also humanitarianism. 15 However, more directly, resisting the securitisation or militarisation of humanitarian organisations from within is ethically exceedingly difficult. It necessarily requires arguing that the security of
colleagues and co-workers should not be placed at the centre. Who would-or
indeed possibly could-argue that the DoC should not apply to them, their
colleagues and friends? Even more strongly, who would not actively embrace
and further the DoC? This is a stark expression of the aporia this chapter
discusses. For the argument here, directing attention to it helps clarify why the
1
1
1
1
na,&w•-fivllifiif-il!I~1
23
ascent of the DoC remains unhampered and often actively supported and
promoted in the practices of the humanitarians.
In sum, this ascent of the DoC as a socio-material dispositive tilts the
humanitarian politics of life in a particular direction. It focuses attention on
the security of the humanitarian workers. While there obviously is nothing
explicit that pits this security against that of the surroundings, the zooming in
on the humanitarian-self enshrines priority and privilege. The DoC concerns
the security of the humanitarians, not the security of those they are assisting.
It is a DoC for the humanitarian self The DoC weighs in on the humanitarian politics of life shifting the scales (ever further) so that humanitarian lives
weigh more. The DoC refashions the "evaluations and meanings given to
life" to reiterate Fassin's formulation. This is not to say that DoC alone could
account for the shifts in the humanitarian politics of life, nor is it to pretend
that the DoC reigns supreme. It does however show the significance of the
neither linear nor preordained socio-material micro-processes through which
contestable and constantly emerging technologies of power come to be constituted through the integration of dispositives such as the DoC. It therefore
also underscores the import of recognising the link between socio-material dispositives (such as the DoC) and the evaluations and meanings informing the
humanitarian politics of life and why it is therefore difficult to follow Fassin in
locating the 01iginality of humanitarian politics of life in their separation.
Inscribing the Duty of Care in technologies of the self
Directing close attention to how the DoC brings out a second interesting side
of its relation to the humanitarian politics of life: namely the way this politics
is enacted by the humanitarian subject, through processes that are part of
what Foucault might have termed "technologies of the self'. The DoC fashions the evaluations and meanings that make up Fassin's humanitarian politics of life tilting it toward the care for the security of the humanitarians. It
does so by inscribing this souci for the own security as something the ethical
and moral humanitarian should prioritise, embody and enact. Perhaps this
should come as no surprise? In work on neo-liberal governance much
emphasis has been placed on the ever-increasing diffusion, decentralisation,
individualisation of governance forms that have become capillary to the
extent that they often seem to decompose subjects into their biometric or
digitally composed parts of an extended socio-material self (Haggerty and
Ericson 2000; Muller 2010). It would therefore seem only logical that also the
humanitarian politics of life could/should be understood as working at this
level. This said, reasoning along these lines implies a dual conceptual move.
The first deepens the argument in the preceding section showing that material
technologies of power are imbricated with meaning/evaluations (hence closing
the gap Fassin posits between the two). The second shifts the relationship
between technologies of power and technologies of the self. Foucault thought
of these as separate things; associating technologies of self with self-initiated
24
A. Leander
empowerment and technologies of power with domination tied to overarching
knowledge systems. 16 Linking technologies of the self to technologies of power
also re-connects them to domination.
A technology of the self is a technology for curating the self in view of
empowering and improving it, notably by rendering it more ethical and happy
(see Note 15 for full citation). As Foucault also insists, such technologies cannot
be conceived of in abstract. On the contrary, to work they need to be tangible,
practical. As he puts it, referring to the place of oracles: "the Delphic principle
was not an abstract one concerning life; it was technical advice, a rule to be
observed for the consultation of the oracle. 'Know yourself' meant 'Do not
suppose yourself to be a God'." (Foucault 1988: 18). As this also underscores,
technologies of the self, besides being tangible, are not formulated by individuals
in isolation but generated in a context, in this case in dialogue with an oracle.
The DoC does not speak and is no oracle. However, it is imbricated in the speech
of authorities in matters of security, namely the security professionals who draw
upon it when they posit that locating the security of the humanitarian self at the
core of humanitarian work is not only important but an ethical and individual
duty of humanitarians. Both Duty and Care are morally and ethically charged
concepts (Tronto 2013). This makes the DoC particularly effective in this sense.
The force of law further adds to the effectiveness of the invocation. The DoC
dispositive in clear inscribes security as a technology of the self to be worked with
by each person individually. Lest the humanitarian actively turns security into
something central to the self, s/he runs the risk of being morally unethical, jeopardising operations, colleagues and therefore ultimately entire humanitarian
projects. I wish to look more closely at three distinct ways in which the DoC
specifically is mobilised by security professionals to inscribe the care for the own
security as a technology of the self
A first way in which this is done is through the demand that the own
security should be prioritised. From the point of security professional this
implies heeding their advice and following their instructions, including at the
cost of reshuffling the own habits and priorities. A presentation about the
Duty of Care at an ASIS conference (ASIS 2016) gave a graphic illustration
of the idea. After outlining the history of the DoC and its current pertinence,
the presenter proceeded to link it what s/he termed a "Duty of Obedience" of
the clients. S/he illustrated this point with a slide (entitled "A Duty of Obedience") showing the (headless) bust of a woman with big breasts wearing a
red corset and long black gloves holding a long, black whip. How, if the
protected subjects failed to obey the instructions of their security providers,
could they possibly expect their protectors to fulfil their protective duties? The
speaker pointed out that this duty of obedience was bound to be stifling, as it
would encroach on and limit not only activities and but also initiatives and
imagination. This point was supported by slide depicting a male pelvis
squeezed into a pair of Roman Gladiator style metal shorts.
This theme of prioritising through obedience and the frustration with disobedience is recurring among security providers. For example, one of the
Le souci de soi
25
promoters of a tracking-software for phones explained in a lecture at an
SCTX [Security and Counter Terrorism Expo] that: "sometimes they [clients]
behave irresponsibly [... ] we actually make it their duty not to leave it [the
phone] behind or turn it off'' (SCTX 2016). Or again, in a discussion about
the place of the Central Security Officer (CSO) in organisations/companies,
the representative of a professional organisation argued that the greatest
challenge facing CSOs was to secure a position where their instructions would be
followed. He thought that the CSO needed to be integrated into the leadership of
the company. As he explained, "security priorities" must be reflected in decisions
at all levels and pertaining to the full range of company activities, to ensure that
they do not remain " ... confined to a corner called security but followed through
the entire organisation". The DoC is in clear cited to demand of humanitarians
that they work to improve their own security concerns in their individual (obeying
the security professional), material (carrying the phone) and collective/organisational (placing the CSO at the centre) activities. The DoC becomes a dispositive
inscribing hierarchies of priorities, including a duty of obedience toward security
professionals, in the technology of through which humanitarian works can realise
themselves as ethical and moral subject "with the help of others" to retake Foucault's terms. 17
A second way in which the DoC contributes to inscribing care for the own
security as part of the technology of the humanitarian self, is by embodying it in
the humanitarian. Security professionals see it as part and parcel of their role to
not only make their clients (or as they will often phrase it "assets") aware of the
import of their physical shape and appearance for their own safety. For this
reason security packages offered to humanitarians will involve courses with
instructions for how to react to threats and avoid finding oneself exposed to
threats. Such courses are offered routinely to employees as part of training
packages. They are often required by insurance companies for covering kidnap,
ransom and extortion, personal security or simply travelling. As part of the field
preparation many organisations, including many states, the EU, the UN, or the
ICRC offer their employees (e.g. O'Reilly 2011; Krahmann 2014; de Guttry
2015). Failure to offer such training is a failure for organisations to fulfil their
DoC toward their employees. This training encourages humanitarians to work
on their own body, its reactions and appearance so as to care for its security. It in
effect posits that caring for the embodied security is something humanitarians
can and should do for their own sake but also for the sake of their operations,
projects and organisations. As digital technologies have extended the self online,
humanitarians are trained to care also for information security and its import
(Duffield 2016). Even more strongly, as I have argued elsewhere (Leander
2019b), with the rapid expansion of tracking technologies (Thumala, Goold and
Loader 2015), humanitarians are increasingly asked to make integrate online
security technologies into their embodied selves. Security professionals work
increasingly with not only with location tracking, but also with portable video
devices as well as devices tracking heartbeat, blood pressure, chemicals and
crowd movements. Tracking devices locate humanitarians, they see, hear and
26
Le souci de soi 27
A. Leander
sense through them, paving the way for more effective protection. Security professionals therefore demand, sometimes threatening to withdraw insurance/
security coverage, that humanitarians accept these invasive tracking technologies.
To be ethical and responsible in ensuring the own security humanitarians must
carry out these operations on their bodies (to reiterate Foucault's expression)
extending them digitally into a security realm. The DoC in clear is mobilized to
turn security into a technologies of the humanitarian self, operating on/in the
body, including its physical form and appearance as well as its digital extensions.
Third and finally, the DoC inscribes the care for the own security as a
technology of the humanitarian self, positing it at the centre also of humanitarian conduct toward the surrounding environment. As logical prolongation of
inscribing the care of the own security as a duty to obey security professionals
and as an embodiment to be embraced, the DoC is also contributing to a
view of the relationship to the environment that places the security of the
humanitarians at the centre. This implies protecting them from the threats of
this environment or making them more resilient. To do that requires that
humanitarians work on their selves so that they can see their relations from
the perspective of the security professionals. This perspective of course is not
unified. One security manager may have a preference for working with what
Hansen has termed "networked" security that is security working through
close connections with local groups combined with a good understanding of
the context (Hansen 2012; and this volume). However, part and parcel of the
move toward a professionalisation of the humanitarian security field (Beerli
2017) has been the standardisation of procedures as well as a tendency to
privilege the understanding of security officers located in the headquaiters. 18
They are prone to be privilege well-tried procedures based on lessons learned. The
messiness, unpredictability and complexity of context that do not square is more
of a disturbance. Techniques that simplify and sanitise by dispensing with the
contextual noise are therefore often preferred even if they distort and bias the
images of the specific situation (Givoni 2016; Bargues-Pedreny 2019). The overall
effect is to keep the dangerous environment at a distance and out of the picture.
More than this, the emphasis on the DoC for security is itself becoming an
obstacle to local anchoring of security knowledge. Insurance requirements,
administrative regulations and security procedures are effectively rendering it
exceedingly difficult to gather the kind of information that would be necessary
to anchor such security policies (Peter and Strazzari 2017; Russo and Strazzari this volume). Some areas become nothing short of "black holes" in terms
of information gathered by journalists or researchers working at a distance as
required by security professionals. No outsider can or will venture in. By
implication, the security thinking humanitarians are most likely to work into
their conduct toward the surroundings is one formulated at a distance, where
generalised suspicion and defensiveness takes the place of closer engagement.
The consequences are palpable and have been well described in the literature
on the evolving relationship of humanitarians to security. Trust is hollowed
out and increasingly replaced with a sense of looming danger. The physical
morphology of humanitarian work itself comes to reflect these transformations and reinforce them. Humanitarians circulate in armoured vehicles and
confine themselves to well-guarded compounds and hotels serviced on an
international level (Smirl 2015). They therefore become cut off from their
surroundings, protected from its potentially risky intrusions and end up
exchanging ideas mainly with themselves and other outsiders in an increasingly
"bunkerised" environment (Duffield 2010). To be ethical and moral, to protect
themselves and their operations, humanitarians are effectively encouraged wear
a thick protective belt shielding them from the surroundings.
The DoC in sum, lends support and legal backing to practical rules
regarding the technologies through which humanitarians might work on and
re-fashion their selves. I have just discussed three such rules: rules about the
own actions (requirement to prioritise the own security), rules about the own
body (requirement to accept embodied security technologies) and rules about
the own sociability (requirement to follow guidelines in the interaction with
surroundings). However, unlike the Foucauldian technologies of the self that
allow individuals "to transform themselves in order to attain a certain state of
happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection, or immortality" (Foucault 1988: 18),
here these technologies feed into technologies of production, of signs and of
power. 19 The commercial-professional rules regarding the own actions, body
and sociability deepens the dependence on commercial security professionals.
It accentuates the awareness of the own mortality and imperfections, the
limits to the own wisdom, and the impurity of humanitarian missions. For the
humanitarian worker the consequence seems more likely to be frustration
than a state of happiness. For the account here, this matters. This likely frustration tells us something about how the performative effects of the DoC on
the humanitarian politics of life. It expresses the deepening aporia they deal
with not only because the DoC is reframing their work from without but
because it is transforming the technologies of the self they themselves work
with from within. To understand the evolving humanitarian politics of life we
in clear need to focus not only how socio-material dispositives such as the
DoC frame this politics ever more as a souci de soi, but also how it works
through a souci de soi.
Conclusion
The above account of how the DoC generates a humanitarian politics of life
working both as souci de soi and through the souci de soi is discomforting.
The first section sketched the improbable ascent of the DoC as a socio-material
dispositive governing humanitarian security. It related it to an increasingly
commercialised professional security context where the possibilities to consolidate and expand military/security related activities are welcome and seized
upon. This includes the possibility of reading the Norwegian court case Dennis
v NRC case as if it revolved around the DoC when it only mentions it in passing as part of a citation and then mobilising this reading to prioritise a focus
28
Le souci de soi
A. Leander
on humanitarian security. The second section deepens the discomfort by
detailing how this unlikely ascent came to inscribe the care for the own security
as a technology of the humanitarian self This not only perpetuates and deepens the humanitarian souci de soi. It turns the care for the own security into a
matter of moral and ethical import. Caring for the own security becomes a
matter of self-improvement for humanitarians and a condition for the completion and success of their missions. This is discomforting. However, as should
also be clear from the above, this argument is not an ideological critique of
humanitarian. Rather, I could readily borrow (again) from Fassin in formulating its intent:
Far from the ideological criticisms traditionally aimed at humanitarian
organisations-which their agents in any case readily take up themselves-this critical perspective stresses the contradictions that exist in
contemporary moral economies, well beyond the sphere of intervention
of humanitarian organisations themselves, in what characterises the political disorder of the world: the inequality of lives.
(Fassin 2007: 520)
However, while Fassin concludes pos1tmg the aporia of the humanitarian
politics of life characterising it as an expression of the political disorder of the
world more broadly, I wish to move the discussion into the realm of agency.
Is there any scope for influencing the humanitarian politics of life and its
aporia? The account provided here offers some pointers. By providing a
micro-level account of how the DoC has contributed to perpetuating and
deepening the aporia it also suggests how such perpetuation and deepening
might be countered. The unlikely ascent of the dispositive could have been
(and can be) countered by alternative i11.terpretations of the significance
Dennis v. NRC. Instead of emphasizing the centrality of the Duty of Care, the
case could have been read as showing the import of more clearly establishing
accountability in networks of commercial security professionals. Also the
inscription through the DoC of security as a technology of the self could have
been differently framed. It could have been articulated as resting more on the
kind of networked security knowledge often advocated by local security
managers and area studies specialists (Hansen in this volume and elsewhere).
Pointing to possibilities for political agency such as these requires focussing
attention on the aporia is generated at the micro level, through socio-material
dispositives-such as the DoC discussed here-associating meaning and
matter allowing for technologies of power to merge with technologies of the
self. More generally it requires a willingness to acknowledge the connection
between the anti-politics of domination and the alter politics of imagining
alternatives to borrow the terms of Hage (Hage 2015). This kind of linkage
may not offer a magic potion strong enough to infuse political agency with the
force necessary to entirely displace the aporia of the humanitarian politics of
life (let alone its place in our broader present). However, it does provide some
29
sense of where there might be scope for more modest forms of agency of the
kind De Certeau might have termed tactics as well as how such agency might
stand a realistic chance of becoming influential (De Certeau 1984). Looking
closely at the DoC is yet a way of underlining its role in deepening the domination of a specific politics of life but it is also a way of highlighting the
uncertainty and fragility of this role and hence the possibility for influence it,
and through it the politics of life. This, at least to me, is a promising beginning.
Notes
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
IO
This chapter draws on arguments I have earlier developed regarding the DoC (Leander
2018; Leander 2019a) and my work on the marketing of security technologies (Leander
2019b). Financial support from the Doc:Pro project, funded by the Norwegian
Research Council, that made this research possible is gratefully acknowledged. It also
benefited from the generous and constrnctive comments by the editors of this volume.
Aporia refers to an irresolvable difficulty, something one does not have the
resources to move beyond, a point of doubt and indecision. I will follow Fassin
and use it for this argument.
In full Fassin writes: " ... By describing these problems as an aporia, I intend to
demonstrate that these contradictions are both constitutive of the humanitarian
project and effectively insurmountable within the value systems of Western societies, particularly when considering the tension that exists between the claimed
sacredness of life (which is no more viable in the context of wartime violence than
in conditions of strnctural violence) and the expressed force of compassion (which
makes it possible to maintain up to a certain point the thread of solidarity, even at
the price of ontological inequality)." (2007: 519)
Here is I use dispositive loosely following Foucault, who played with this French
term, which banally refers to a legal statement, judgement or similar, a machine,
apparatus or mechanism intended to regulate something (Foucault 2004). This is a
way of avoiding the a momentous discussion around the concept "dispositive" e.g.
Deleuze (1988); Stengers (1995); Agamben (2007).
"What I call 'politics of life' here are politics that give specific value and meaning
to 'human life'. They differ analytically from Foucauldian biopolitics, defined as
'the regulation of population', in that they relate not to the technologies of power
and the way populations are governed but to the evaluation of human beings and
the meaning of their existence." Fassin (2007: 500, emphasis added).
See Grreger and Lindgren (2017) and Okano-Heijmans and Caesar-Gordon (2016).
It was not kept sufficiently confidential. Drivers were inexperienced. Instead of
going to the less risky IFO I, the convoy went (for no good reason according to the
reports) to the more risky IFO II. The management allowed delays in the programme (OSD 2015).
For overviews of the issues at stake see e.g. Joachim and Schneiker (2012); Spearin
(2015).
He has been security advisor for NRC and became Global Security Advisory in
October 2013. Previously he worked for Armadillo/Safer Edge in DR Congo,
Afghanistan and Rwanda conducting risk assessments, preparing and implementing security plans and procedures, conducting training, https://no.linkedin.com/in/
christopher-allen-a5896a90 accessed 29 August 2017.
The "European Interagency Security Fornm" is an independent network of Security Focal Points who currently represent 85 Europe-based humanitarian NGOs
operating internationally. EISF is conm1itted to improving the security of relief
operations and staff. It aims to increase safe access by humanitarian agencies to
30
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
A. Leander
people affected by emergencies. Key to its work is the development of research and
tools that promote awareness, preparedness and good practice.
For an analysis of its development see Beerli (2017).
For example, in the 2016 ASIS Europe programme the DoC figured prominently
as a seminar theme but also in the marketing of the companies present. ASIS is
one of the main professional security associations.
www.nrk.no/nyheter/flyktninghjelpen-domt-i-kidnappingssak-1. l 257764 7 accessed
29 August 2017.
www.vl.no/nyhet/tidligere-ansatt-krever-millionerstatning-fra-flyktninghjelpen-1.
42154l?paywall=true accessed 29 August 2017.
This is a bombastic but important comment to make. There is no space to delve on
it here but for discussions see e.g. Enloe (2007); Stavrianakis and Stem (2017).
Foucault explains that: "As a context, we must understand that there are four
major types of these 'technologies', each a matrix of practical reason: (1) technologies of production, which permit us to produce, transform, or manipulate things;
(2) technologies of sign systems, which permit us to use signs, meanings, symbols,
or signification; (3) technologies of power, which determine the conduct of individuals and submit them to certain ends or domination, an objectivising of the subject; (4) technologies of the self, which permit individuals to effect by their own
means or with the help of others a certain number of operations on their own
bodies and semis, thoughts, conduct, and way of being, so as to transform themselves in order to attain a certain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection, or
immortality. These four types of technologies hardly ever function separately,
although each one of them is associated with a certain type of domination."
(Foucault 1988: 18). Reinforcing the positive connotations Foucault attaches to
technologies of the self he explains that in earlier work "I have tried to show how
we have indirectly constituted ourselves through the exclusion of some others:
criminals, mad people, and so on. And now my present work [on technologies of
the self] deals with the question: How did we directly constitute our identity
through some ethical techniques of the self which developed through antiquity
down to now?" (Foucault, 1988: 146).
These changes and the emergence of the DoC as a regulatory dispositive
endowing commercial professional networks with authority is shifting the location of the legitimate authority over the use of force away from public authorities.
It therefore has implications for all discussions surrounding who is entitled to
public protection on what terms. This includes discussions figuring centrally in
this volume such as those concerning whether or not citizens are entitled to protection from their home states (Hansen, this volume), whether or not those
employed by armed forces can expect protection from the state of that armed
force (S0by Kristensen, this volume) and whether or not researchers will be protected when/legally allowed to carry out research in conflict areas (Russo and
Strazzari, this volume).
We see this play out also in Dennis v. N RC where one of the reasons given by the
court for its judgement was that the local security officers did not consult the
regional or Oslo security professionals but acted on their own initiative. Local
security claimed that they had tried to do so but got no response. The reasoning
and the response alike underscore the hierarchy of relationship in the security field
locating it at a distance from the field, as close as possible to the central HQ
(Leander 2019a).
Although as I insist in the main text Foucault treated technologies of the self as
emancipatory, he himself opened the kind of ambiguity I am arguing for here
when he suggests that his different kinds of technologies "hardly ever function
separately" (Foucault 1988: 18).
Le souci de soi
31
Bibliography
Agamben, Giorgio (2007) Qu'est-ce qu'un dispositij?Paris: Payot & Rivages.
ASIS (2016) "Fieldwork notes". In ASIS 15th European Security Conference, London,
6-8 April.
Bargues-Pedreny, Pol (2019) "Mapping without the world and the poverty of digital
humanitarians". In David Chandler (eds), Mapping and Politics in the Digital Age.
New York: CRC Press/Routledge.
Beerli, Monique (2017) Saving the Saviors: An International Political Sociology of the
Professionalization of Humanitarian Security. Doctoral dissertation defended at the
Institut d'Etudes Politiques, Paris.
Davies, Martin (1989) "The End of the Affair: Duty of Care and Liability Insurance".
Legal Studies, 9(1):67-83.
De Certeau, Michel (1984) The Practice of Everyday Life. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
de Guttry, Andrea (2015) "Introducing a New Set of Guidelines to Implement the
'Duty of Care' of the EU Institutions and Agencies Towards Their Internationally
Mobile Workforce". European Journal of International Management, 9(6):673-689.
Deleuze, Gilles (1988) Foucault. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Duffield, Mark (2010) "Risk management and the fortified aid compound: Everyday life in post-interventionary society". Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding,
4:453-474.
Duffield, Mark (2016) "The Resilience of the Ruins: Towards a Critique of Digital
Humanitarianism". Resilience, 4(3):147-165.
Enloe, Cynthia H. (2007) Globalization and Militarism: Feminists Make the Link.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Fassin, Didier (2007) "Humanitarianism as a Politics of Life". Public Culture,
19(3):499--520.
Fassin, Didier (2011) Humanitarian Reason: A Moral History of the Present. California: University of California Press.
Foucault, Michel (2004) Securite, territoire, population. Cours au College de France
(1977-1978). Paris: Gallimard, Seuil.
Foucault, Michel (1988) Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault.
Massachusetts, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
Givoni, Michal (2016) "Between Micro Mappers and Missing Maps: Digital Humanitarianism and the Politics of Material Participation in Disaster Response".
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 34(6):1025-1043.
Gneger, Nina and Wrenn Yennie Lindgren (2017) "The Duty of Care for Citizens
Abroad: Security and Responsibility in the In Amenas and Fukushima Crises". The
Hague Journal of Diplomacy, [online] 12(1):1-23.
Hage, Ghassan (2015) Alter-Politics. Critical Anthropology and the Radical Imagination. Melbourne, Australia: Melbourne University Press.
Haggerty, Kevin D. and Ericson, Richard V. (2000) "The Surveillant Assemblage".
British Journal of Sociology, 51(4):605-622.
Hansen, Stig Jarle (2012) 'The Dynamics of Somali Piracy". Studies in Conflict &
Terrorism, 35(7-8):523-530.
Hoppe, Kelsey and Christine Williamson (2016) "Dennis vs Norwegian Refugee
Council: Implications for duty of care". [online] The Humanitarian Practice Network (HPN).
32
A. Leander
Joachim, Jutta and Andrea Schneiker (2012) "Warum so freundlich? Der Umgang von
NGOs mit Privaten Sicherheits- und Militarfirmen". In Christopher Daase, Philipp
Offermann and Valentin Rauer (eds), Sicherheitsku!tur. Analysen zur sozialen Praxis
der Gefahrenabwehr. Frankfurt, Germany: Campus Verlag, pp. 277-300.
Krahmann, Elke (2014) "The UN Guidelines on the Use of Armed Guards:
Recommendations for Improvement". International Community Law Review,
16(4):475-491.
Krahmann, Elke and Anna Leander (forthcoming) Contracting Security: Markets in
the Making of Monusco Peacekeeping.
Leander, Anna (2018) "The Politics of Legal Arrangements: The 'Duty of Care' Justifying, Extending and Perpetuating Public in the Private Forms of Protection".
Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies, 25(1):265-290.
Leander, Anna (2019) "Making markets responsible: Revisiting the state monopoly on
the legitimate use of force". In Tom Crosbie and Ori Swed (eds), Sociology, Privatization, Global Conflicts. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave, pp. 137-171.
Leander, Anna (forthcoming) Composing Control: Sensing Security through Tracking
Devices.
Merkelbach, Maarten (2017) "Voluntary Guidelines on the Duty of Care to Seconded
Civilian Personnel". [online] Available at: www.gov.uk/government/publications/
voluntary-guidelines-on-the-duty-of-care.
Merkelbach, Maarten and Edward Kemp (2016) "Duty of Care: A Review of the
Dennis vs Norwegian Refugee Council Ruling and Its Implications". [online] Available at: www.eisf.eu/library/duty-of-care-a-review-of-the-dennis-v-norwegian-refugeecouncil-ruling-and-its-implications/.
Muller, Benjamin J. (2010) Security, Risk and the Biometric State: Governing Borders
and Bodies. London: Routledge.
Munro, Ann and Angus WM. Turner (2010) "Pushing the Envelope: Whose Duty of
Care?". Journal of the Intensive Care Society, 11(1):5-8.
O'Reilly, Connor (2011) "'From Kidnaps to Contagious Diseases': Elite Rescue and
the Strategic Expansion of the Transnatronal Security Consultancy Industry".
International Political Sociology, 5(2): 178-197.
Okano-Heijmans, Maaijke and Matthew Caesar-Gordon (2016) "Protecting the WorkerCitizen Abroad: Duty of Care Beyond the State?", Global Affairs, 2(4):431-440.
Oslo District Court (OSD) (2015) Stephen Patrick Dennis vs. Norwegian Refugee
Council Oslo: Case no. 15-032886TVI-OTI R/05 (25 November).
Peter, Mateja and Francesco Strazzari (2017) "Securitization of Research: Fieldwork under New Restrictions in Darfur and Mali". Third World Quarterly,
38(7): 1531-1550.
SCTX (2016) "Fieldwork notes". In Security and Counter Terrorism Expo, London,
19-20 April.
Sevenhuijsen, Selma (2003) "The Place of Care. The Relevance of the Feminist Ethic
of Care for Social Policy". Feminist Theory, 4(2):179-197.
Smirl, Lisa (2015) Spaces of Aid: How Cars, Compounds and Hotels Shape Humanitarianism. London: Zed Books.
Spearin, Christopher (2015) "Enduring challenges of security privatization in the
humanitarian space". In Rita Abrahamsen and Anna Leander (eds) Handbook. on
Private Military-Security Companies. London: Routledge, pp. 109-117.
Stavrianakis, Anna, and Maria Stern (2017) "Militarism and security: Dialogue, possibilities and limits". Security Dialogue, 49(1-2):3-18.
Le
souci de soi 33
Stengers, Isabelle (1995) L'invention des sciences modernes [original edition 1993].
Paris: Flammarion.
Thumala, Angelica, Goold, Benjamin and Loader, Ian (2015) "Tracking Devices: On the
Reception ofa Novel Security Good". Criminology & Criminal Justice, 15(1):3-22.
Tronto, Joan (2013) Caring Democracy. Markets, Equality and Justice. New York:
New York University Press.
Wall, Imogen (2015, 26 November) "NRC Kidnap Ruling Is 'Wake-up' Call for Aid
Industry". [online] All Africa.
Young, Holly. (2015, 7 December) "Steve Dennis and the Court Case That Sent Waves
through the Aid Industry". [online] The Guardian.