econstor
A Service of
zbw
Make Your Publications Visible.
Leibniz-Informationszentrum
Wirtschaft
Leibniz Information Centre
for Economics
Turner, Kerry
Working Paper
A pluralistic approach to ecosystem services
evaluation
CSERGE Working Paper EDM, No. 10-07
Provided in Cooperation with:
The Centre for Social and Economic Research on the Global Environment (CSERGE),
University of East Anglia
Suggested Citation: Turner, Kerry (2010) : A pluralistic approach to ecosystem services
evaluation, CSERGE Working Paper EDM, No. 10-07, University of East Anglia, The Centre for
Social and Economic Research on the Global Environment (CSERGE), Norwich
This Version is available at:
http://hdl.handle.net/10419/48825
Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen:
Terms of use:
Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen
Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden.
Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your
personal and scholarly purposes.
Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle
Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich
machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen.
You are not to copy documents for public or commercial
purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them
publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise
use the documents in public.
Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen
(insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten,
gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort
genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte.
www.econstor.eu
If the documents have been made available under an Open
Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you
may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated
licence.
A Pluralistic Approach to Ecosystem Services
Evaluation
By
Kerry Turner
CSERGE Working Paper EDM 10-07
A Pluralistic Approach to Ecosystem Services Evaluation
Kerry Turner
CSERGE, School of Environmental Sciences, UEA, Norwich.
Introduction
The purpose of this note is to contribute to the emerging common understanding between
the natural science, economic and social science perspectives on the ‘value’ of ecosystems
and biodiversity. Given the inherent complexity of nature it is not surprising that the concept
of ‘value is capable of multiple interpretation and meaning. A number of different dimensions
of nature-based value can be simply discerned and evaluated in different ways eg in
monetary terms via economic analysis; in biophysical and geochemical terms via natural
science; and in more qualitative terms via sociology, cultural geography, arts and humanities
etc. Each of these value dimensions has validity in its own domain.
Environmental philosophers have ,however, constructed a generic value typology with four
categories: anthropocentric instrumental value, which maps closely on to the economic
concepts of use and most of non-use values; anthropocentric intrinsic value, a culturally
dependant concept which is linked to human stewardship of nature motivation and which
requires a human valuer to ascribe intrinsic value to non-human nature; the economist’s idea
of existence value can overlap into this value category. The other two value categories non-anthropocentric instrumental value and non- anthropocentric intrinsic value are less
directly relevant to the NEA initiative, unless in the latter value category’s case a radical
ethical position is accepted as the societal norm, which is currently not the case (Hargrove
1992).
Existence value derives from individuals who feel a benefit from just knowing that, for
example, an ecosystem and/or its component parts, does exist and will continue to exist
somewhere on the planet. The economic valuation literature has yet to reach a
comprehensive consensus on whether use and non-use value can be formally distinguished
using standard welfare economic measures. The use of survey-based methods such as an
contingent valuation and choice experiments to elicit monetary expressions of existence
values is still open to debate on the grounds of validity and reliability. The conventional
economic assumptions about human motivations and behaviour can bee seen as quite
restrictive and findings from the behavioural economics and psychology literature have
served to ‘enrich’ our still inadequate understanding of cognitive behaviour. It seems that so
– called bequest motivations (i.e. the requirement to pass on over generational time an
‘environment’ which can yield at least a constant set of ‘opportunities’) existence value
motivations and altruistic motives may all be relevant and real in certain environmental loss
contexts.
Analysts disagree over how to interpret this set of possibly overlapping motivations and
behaviours. Some see the welfare effect as an individualised ‘warm glow’ effect connected
to the act of giving, while other insist that ‘pure altruism’ is required for existence value and
can be recognised. The debate is also further complicated by consumer-citizen distinctions
that can be made. In the latter role, individuals may hold social preference values and
motivations which may be best elicited through group discussion/involvement. If one
accepts the position that only individual values are the ‘real’ values that should be taken into
account in the policy process and that individual behaviour is dominated by self-interest and
self-regarding motives, then only a restricted version of existence value (contaminated by
the ‘warm glow’ effect) is possible. Thus value estimates derived from contingent valuation
surveys will not necessarily indicate ‘true’ economic value derived from public goals such as
the ecosystem service gain/loss under test. If, on the other hand, one is persuaded that
citizen-type motivations and behaviour can be recognised, then other regarding motives and
social preferences ‘true alturism’ exist. Group-based focus gatherings or other ‘deliberative’
processes may then offer a mechanism through which bequest and existence values can be
elicited.
To summarise, focusing on just anthropocentric instrumental and intrinsic value in nature, it
is important to note that the former value concept is usually interpreted in economic analysis
in terms of an individual person (or sometimes aggregated household) and their preferences
and motivations. The latter value concept however can also be viewed in a collectivist way,
motivations and preferences which can be assigned to groups and culturally transmitted and
assimilated over time as social norms. These cultural values may not be capable of
meaningful and full monetary expression, but nevertheless they significantly signal that
human well-being and quality of life is a function of both individual wants satisfaction and the
fulfilment of a variety of social and health related and cultural collective needs. Cultural
values are shared experiences fostered by and within ‘groups’ often over long periods of
time and often connected to specific local places and landscapes.
Environmental System Value
A concern raised by some social science and natural science communities is that ecosystem
services classifications and approaches (such as MEA & NEA) carry with them an inherent
danger that leads to complete ‘commodification’ of ecosystems and a consequent policy and
management failure. The failure manifests itself in terms of an over-concentration on those
ecosystem services and benefits of direct and indirect use / non use to humans, with the
risk of over exploitation and system change or collapse. The NEA conceptual framework
recognises that it may be the case that when the value of whole environmental systems are
concerned, conventional economic valuation ( restricted to the flow of service benefits) may
not be sufficient. The framework accepts the need to assess and conserve the structural
and process / functional value of ‘healthy’ evolving ecosystems, despite the formidable
uncertainties surrounding likely thresholds / tipping points for system change. The
fundamental life-support services, labelled ‘intermediate services’ in the conceptual
framework, clearly are valuable and the focus on the flow of assigned ecosystem benefits
values is not meant to deny this.
Healthy ecosystems, anchored to a sufficient configuration of structure and process, have
‘prior’ value (labelled primary, glue or infrastructure value) in the sense that the continued
existence of the system ‘integrity’ determines the flow of all the instrumental and intrinsic
values related to final ecosystem services and benefits. So total system value is always
greater than total economic value (Gren et al 1994; Turner 1999).
Figure 1 summarises the arguments presented so far.
Fig 1 SIMPLIFIED ECOSYSTEM VALUES TYPOLOGY
ECOSYSTEM STRUCTURE
AND PROCESSES
ECOSYSTEM FUNCTIONING
AND SERVICE PROVISION
FINAL SERVICES / BENEFITS
INDIVIDUAL BENEFIT
VALUES (Total Econ Value)
COLLECTIVE BENEFIT
SHARED VALUES
MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS OF
ECOSYSTEM VALUE
PRIMARY OR GLUE VALUE OF
OVERALL HEALTHY SYSTEM
Given the policy goal of sustainable development, it has been argued that rather than a
income flow-based approach to ecosystem valuation, a stock-based approach is more
appropriate. Such a stock-based approach could be based on the measurement concept of
‘inclusive wealth’ ( Arrow et al 2003; Dasgupta and Maler, 2001). Typically, the core
sustainable development resource allocation constraint rule has been interpreted as, that the
present value (ie discounted) of future well being (utility) linked to consumption flows must
be maintained over time. But an equivalent rule can be derived in terms of the ‘inclusive
wealth’ concept and the value of natural and other capital stocks at a given time. Value is
defined as the quantity of current stocks multiplied by their shadow prices, and ‘inclusive
wealth’ is maintained if the value of capital stocks is constant over time. The shadow price of
a capital asset today is the present value of the change in utility that would be caused by a
marginal change in the quantity of the capital asset today .
However, shadow prices must be fully inclusive ie they must reflect all relevant costs and
benefits to current and future generations. A similar proviso is also required in the income
flow value-based approach and both approaches are therefore limited by the lack of perfect
information ( natural science , social and economic). Norgaard (2009) has provided a critique
of the stock-flow ecosystem services approach in which, among other issues, he focuses on
the state of scientific/ecological knowledge. He concludes that science is far from being able
to predict smaller shifts in the delivery of ecosystem services and that there is no scientific
consensus around threshold effects which can cause ecosystems to shift from one state to
another and /or suffer stock collapse. So both risk and uncertainty problems are present
when ecosystem services are exploited for their human related benefits flows. The
maintenance of ecosystem integrity ( conditioned by some poorly understood minimum
configuration of ecosystem structure and process) can help to maintain resilience capacity ie
the ability of the ecosystem stock to withstand stress and shock without significant state
change. The resilience capacity has an economic value (price) but so far efforts to
empirically estimate it have been rare and preliminary ( Maler et al 2008).
In the light of the prevailing uncertainty surrounding ecosystem threshold effects and the
risks and consequences of ecosystem collapse, a number of pragmatic management
responses have been suggested eg the imposition of safe minimum standards etc. These
mitigation measures are reviewed later in the next section, but Norgaard (2009) concludes
that only major institutional change can provide an adequate response to current
unsustainable consumption patterns across the globe. Thus the ecosystem services
approach can only be a part of a larger solution.
Irreversibility and Related Concepts
A number of issues surround the notion of irreversibility and related concepts of threshold
effects and tipping points. While all these terms are now in use in the environmental
conservation and economics literature, we find it helpful to refer to thresholds in the context
of individual ecosystems or landscape ecology limited to the regional spatial scale. This
reserves the term, tipping points, to describe global scale system and subsystem non linear
and abrupt reactions to environmental change pressures (Rockstrom et al 2009).
Ecosystems function via feedbacks between different components of structure and process.
When the feedback effects are positive any given initial perturbation (stress or shock) of the
system will be amplified, when a positive feedback occurs the prevailing state of the system
may be such that a complete switch into a different state is triggered (a classic case is the
enrichment of shallow lakes via excessive N & P inputs from the surrounding catchment,
causing abrupt change in water quality and aquatic plant and fish etc communities). The
initial ecosystem state prior to the ‘flip’ is then a threshold or a bifurcation. The capacity of
an ecosystem to ‘absorb’ stress or shock and remain in its prevailing state is known as
resilience. It is still a matter of scientific debate whether greater diversity in ecosystems
provides a buffering capacity (greater stability or resilience) and in which specific contexts
(Tisdell, 2009 and Worm et al 2006). A further degree of uncertainty surrounds the question
of whether the ecosystem state change is reversible or irreversible in the future. This is a far
from straightforward question and we currently lack sufficient scientific and other knowledge
to be able to offer robust prescriptions. In the shallow lake example cited earlier, it is the
case that remedial management actions (such as sediment pumping, N & P abatement etc)
can restore water quality & other losses. But even in this case, the timing and extent of the
necessary abatement programme is not clear cut, with adverse consequences for the overall
costs of action. In more complex contexts, irreversibility is even more difficult to pin down,
either because of current technological / scientific data and means deficiencies, or
impracticability constraints in the form of significant cost burdens and governance limitations.
Future scientific and technological breakthroughs and socio-economic conditions and
preferences may or may not lead to less constraints, but in any case they are currently only
predictions or complete unknowns.
Given that information about ecosystem functioning and dynamics under contemporary
environmental change conditions (local through to globalisation) is incomplete, there is a
positive probability that a given ecosystem in a given change context will be pressurised into
a thresholds zone and across a point, causing it to flip to a less desirable new state. The
probability of flipping is lower as resilience is maintained / increased and management
interventions to ‘conserve’ resilience are therefore important. Resilience capacity can be
regarded as capital stock (natural capital) which yields an insurance service and benefit
(Maler et al 2007). As a stock, in principle it has an accounting price, defined as, the change
in the expected change in net present value of the expected future ecosystem services
resulting from a marginal change to resilience today (Maler et al 2007). In practice, data
(time series and other) constraints have so far precluded the monetary valuation of this
insurance service, with the one exception of an agroecosystem study in Australia.
Two different approaches have been put forward in the environmental economics literature
as coping strategies for the irreversibility problem. The first was a modified CBA method,
known as the Krutilla.Fisher (K-F) approach. It laid down that in relevant preservation versus
development situations, the benefit of the preservation option should be factored into the
CBA equation. Preservation benefits forgone should be treated as part of the costs of
development and should be assumed to increase through time because of the relative price
effect. The development benefits should have an offsetting discount factor, in addition to the
‘basic’ discount rate because of ‘technological obsolescence’. It is also the case that the
present value of development can be very sensitive to the preservation relative price effect
and the obsolescence factor (Pearce & Turner 1990). Given the prevailing information gaps,
it is recommended that the benefit of the doubt be given to preservation over development in
all cases where benefits and costs are reasonable closely balanced. The K-F strategy was
designed to cope with ecosystem and landscape asset losses characterised by uniqueness
and national / international significance. The dilemma was how to cope with possible
irreversible losses of unique assets such as designated national park lands. But it may be
the case that some potential ecosystem losses are of ‘local’ significance and ‘uniqueness’.
In these cases a conservation versus development trade-off needs to be addressed.
In these ‘local irreversibility’ situations a ‘shadow project’ approach in which sustainability
considerations are integrated into the CBA calculus may be relevant. The decision maker is
asked to consider a range of decisions about development options and impose a
sustainability constraint into the decision support system and process (ie to keep the stock of
natural capital (Kn) constant over time by suitable compensatory expenditures). The sum of
the ecosystem damage done by a whole sequence of development projects would have to
be offset by separate projects within the ‘portfolio’ of decisions being made. These
compensatory projects would not have to pass the positive B-C ratio test (Barbier,
Markandya & Pearce, 1990). The precise form of ‘acceptable’ compensation will vary from
context to context and is an under-researched area. Roach & Wade (2006) for example
have examined the use of so-called habitat equivalency analysis which estimates ecological
service loss and then scales restorative ecological compensation to offset the damage
impact.
A second line of argument if irreversibility concerns are relevant incorporates the notions of
the precautionary principle and the safe minimum standard. There is a line of reasoning that
can link ecosystem diversity and resilience maintenance (with ‘primary’ / ‘glue’ /
‘infrastructure’ values in nature, alongside the ‘insurance’ value noted earlier) together with a
support for the precautionary principle and strong sustainability (Gren et al 1994, Turner et al
2003). The precautionary principle is itself shrouded in ambiguity and CBA can provide a
useful filter for it if a ‘safe minimum standards’ (SMS) interpretation covering species,
habitats and ecosystems is accepted (Crowards, 1998). This goes back to the work of
Ciricacy-Wantrup (1952) and Bishop (1978) in which it was advocated that a project should
be rejected if irreversible losses of nature could consequently occur, unless the social costs
of doing so were prohibitive (a modified minimax rule). Thus decision makers facing the
prospect of very high preservation or conservation costs might choose to sanction a
development option even though it carries a small risk of significant ecosystem damages.
Nevertheless, judging what is or is not an “unacceptable large” or “tolerably low” social cost
can be informed by ecology, economics, risk analysis etc, but ultimately is a ‘political’ call.
Ethical and political choices will have to be made and deliberatively agreed. Over time, the
aim should be to improve our understanding of ecosystem functioning so we can move
towards more situations where we are dealing with risk rather than uncertainty.
It has recently been pointed out that, at the global spatial scale, many subsystems of Earth
are sensitive to threshold effects and if a ‘tipping point’ is crossed unacceptable
environmental change could be triggered (Rockstrom, 2009). The claim is that most of the
thresholds can be defined by a critical value for one or more control variables. Nine
processes have been identified (climate change; rate of biodiversity loss; interference with
the nitrogen and phosphorus cycles; stratospheric ozone depletion; ocean acidification;
global freshwater use; change in land use; chemical pollution and atmospheric aerosol
loading) the first three of which have already reached the threshold zone.
Rockstrom et al adopt a precautionary safe minimum standards perspective and propose
that the planet must be kept in a “safe operating space” through the observance of quantified
boundaries. In the case of biodiversity loss they advocate a boundary of ten times the
background rates of extinction. Because of the many gaps in our knowledge this boundary
should be considered as preliminary, but it seems clear that the current rate of species loss
(100 to 1,000 times more than what could be considered natural) will lead to significant
reductions in ecosystem resilience. A further concern is that globalisation has resulted in a
rate and extent of economic activity sufficient to pressurise a range of earth processes
simultaneously. This means that the planetary tipping point boundaries are tightly coupled
and piecemeal abatement strategies are unlikely to be sufficiently effective.
The implementation of this global safe minimum standards strategy will be controversial and
will require concerted and targeted science and social science research efforts to underpin it.
But most of all it requires a radical overhaul of the governance processes controlling
international trade and finance and resource exploitation etc. In the interim, recent work by
Lenton et al (2008) has proposed the use of early warning systems which identify systems
that are likely to cross ‘tipping points’ and are relevant to policy and accessed by humans
(“tipping elements”). Historical data and predictive modelling (eg degenerative fingerprinting)
may then be used to locate tipping points.
Cultural Ecosystem Service Values and Human Well Being.
Human well being ( or any given individual’s perception of well being ) is a function of a set
of social, psychological, economic and cultural factors and underpinning environmental
conditions. While mainstream economics has tended to concentrate on the individual as an
isolated being with a behaviour dominated by self-interest and material want satisfaction,
insights from psychology and behavioural studies have served to counterbalance this
perspective. They emphasise the individual as a member of groups, neighbourhoods,
communities etc (Maslow 1970; Hirsch 1977; Layard 2005 ). In this context individual
behaviour and perceptions of well being are then heavily influenced by group attitudes and
actions. Any index of psychological well being will contain personal development needs such
as good health, autonomy and purpose in life, positive social relationships and self
acceptance and spiritual and religious goal satisfaction. Personal development needs
satisfaction are enabled , among other things , through the provision of basic want
satisfaction ( food, shelter etc ), personal security and a stable and fair society with equal
opportunities.
But a key enabling condition is also a healthy environment providing for a secure and
reliable flow of ecosystem services, including valuable social and cultural services. The
psychological well being index is fundamentally conditioned by the interactions between
humans and the natural environment. Both mental and physical health are positively affected
by contact with and access to ‘green spaces’ ( in local neighbourhoods and other places,
landscapes etc ). Young peoples’ educational experiences can be enriched by
environmental exposures, both passive and active. A wide range of outdoor leisure and
recreation activities provide important well being effects through the satisfaction of a variety
of wants/needs, including culture, art and media appreciation.
The evaluation of these contributions to overall human well being provided by ecosystems
will need to encompass both the monetary and other equally valid dimensions of ‘value’. The
direct use , by individuals, of outdoor leisure, recreation, cultural heritage and local green
spaces ‘for example’ can often be valued via willingness to pay for visits measures. The
beneficial mental and physical health effects provided for through contact with the natural
environment can also be valued in monetary terms and via health related quality of life
indicators. But cultural services pose a more complex evaluation problem.
The evaluation of cultural heritage (broadly defined) must be linked to the discourse of
culture, memory and language, playing out over long periods of time. The embedded
intrinsic values are ‘shared’ values, formed and altered through groupings of people and
their collective will and sense of identity. The important role of regulatory and other
governance institutions ( e g National Park Authorities etc, etc ) in cultural services provision
, protection and interpretation must also be recognised. The values transmission
mechanisms are, among others , art, literature and media. So the ‘value’ of local places and
landscapes, for example, cannot be adequately captured just in terms of individual visit rates
and willingness to pay. This approach alone misses the more collectively based intrinsic
value of cultural identity, heritage and bequest capability.
A new set of deliberative approaches to valuation have emerged which combine stated
preference methods with the discourse-based techniques of political science (Spash, 2008).
These methods involve small groups usually of between five to 20 individuals, who are
selected to represent ‘society’ and be provided with information about ecosystem service
benefits, which they discuss and formally deliberate in transparent a process as possible.
By engaging in group discussion, individuals are believed to be exposed to a much richer set
of information, attitudes and experiences, enhancing understanding of the pertinent issues.
The deliberative component is explicitly introduced on the belief that participant individuals
will explore motivations and ethnics beyond their own personal welfare. Value results can
be expressed in individual or group willingness to pay terms, or more qualitatively. Protocols
covering group discussion procedures are also being refined (Wilson and Howard, 2002);
and the analysis of group dynamics goes back to after the 1970’s and the Symlog (System
for the Multiple Level Observance of Groups) methodology (Bales and Cohen,1979).
Happiness data, human well-being and ecosystem services
With its origins in the 1970’s (Easterlin 1977) scientific interest in the so-called ‘happiness
approach’ and empirical measures of human happiness increased significantly in the last
decade (Layard 2010; Oswall and Wu 2010). This emerging field of research offers a novel
way of valuing environmental goods which model individuals’ self-rated happiness as a
fraction of their incomes and the prevailing environmental conditions (Welsch and Kuhling
2008). The approach seeks to measure individual stated subjective well-being (happiness or
life satisfaction) through large scale survey data collected on a regular basis. The data on
subjective well-being has been used in economic research as an empirical approximation for
“experienced utility”, which is an ex post hedonic quality (satisfaction) associated with an act
of choice (Kahneman et al 1997). Some surveys use verbal categories, while others use a
numerical scale (eg 1 = dissatisfied to 10 = satisfied). Measures of happiness of life
satisfaction correlate well with each other and according to factor analysis represent a single
unitary construct (Welsch, 2010). A mix of personal and demographic characteristics as well
as socio-economic factors are significantly correlated with happiness. Both the degree of
urbanisation and the provision of environmental amenities, for example, are significant
variables (negative and positive respectively). So using happiness data for environmental
valuation we may be able to estimate the value of ecosystem service benefits in a different
way to standard cost-benefit analysis and willingness to pay methods. By correlating
people’s reported subjective well-being with ecosystem service benefits and personal
income (including lagged individual income and other people’s income) it is possible to
identify the environmental quality and income utility traction and to estimate the implied
utility-constant trade-off between them (eg the increase in income necessary to compensate
individuals for any decline in environmental benefit provision). So far air pollution, water
pollution, noise, climate conditions and natural hazards have been valued using the
happiness approach. To the extent that ecosystem functioning contributes to the
maintenance/improvement of air and water quality etc, valuation of ecosystem service
benefits is possible via this ‘happiness approach’.
References
Arrow K,J, Dasgupta P and Maler K-G (2003) Evaluating projects and assessing sustainable
development in imperfect economies, Environmental and resource Economics 26:647-685.
Bales R,F and Cohen S,P (1979) SYMLOG: A system for the multiple level observance of
groups, Free Press, N York.
E.B. Barbier et al (1990) Environmental sustainability and cost-benefit analysis, Environment
and Planning A 22: 1259-1266.
R. Bishop (1978) Endangered species and uncertainty: the economics of a safe minimum
standard, American Journal of Agricultural Economics 60: 10-18.
S.Ciracy-Wantrup (1952) Resource Conservation: Economics and Policies, University of
California Press, Berkeley.
T.Crowards (1998) Safe minimum standards: costs and opportunities, Ecological Economics
25: 303-314.
Dasgupta P and Maler K-G (2001) wealth as a criterion for sustainable development, World
Economy 2:19-44.
Easterlin R (1974) Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical
evidence. In P A David and M W Reder etc Nations and Households in Economic Growth:
Essays in Honour of Moses Abramovits, NY. Academic Press 89-125.
Gren, I-M et al (1994) Primary and secondary values of wetland ecosystems, Environmental
and Resource Economics,4:55-74;
Hargrove,C. (1992) Weak anthropocentric intrinsic value, The Monist 75:183-207.
Hirsch, F. (1977) Social Limits to Growth, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
Kahneman D, Walker P and Sarin R (1997) Back to Bentham Exploration of experienced
utility, Quarterly Journal of Economics 112: 373-405.
Layard,R.(2005) Happiness :Lessons from a New Science, Penguin Books, London.
T. Lenton et al (2008) Tipping elements in The Earth’s climate system PNAS 105: 17861793.
K.G. Maler et al (2007) Accounting for ecosystem services as a way to understand the
requirements for sustainable development, PNAS 105: 9501-9506.
Maslow, A. (1970) Motivation and Personality, Harper and Row, New York.
Norgaard R. (2009) Ecosystem services: From eye-opening metaphor to complexity blinder,
Ecological Economics doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2009.11.009.
D.W. Pearce & R.K. Turner (1990) Economics of Natural Reserves and The Environment,
Harvester Wheatsheaf, Hemel Hempstead.
B. Roach & W Wade (2006) Policy evaluation of natural resource injuries, using habitat
equivalency analysis, Ecological Economics 58: 421-433.
J. Rockstrom et al (2009) A safe operating space for humanity, Nature 461: 472-475.
Spash C,C (2008) Deliberative monetary valuation and the evidence for a new value theory,
Land Economics 84: 469-488.
Turner, R.K.(1999) The place of economic values in environmental valuation. In I.J. Bateman
and K.G. Willis eds Valuing Environmental Preferences, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
R.K. Turner et al (2003) Valuing nature: lessons learned and future research directions,
Ecological Economics 46: 492-510.
Welsh H and Kuhling J (2008) Using happiness data for environmental valuation: issues
and applications, Journal of Economic Surveys 23: 385-406.
Welsh, H (2009) Implications of happiness research for environmental economics,
Ecological Economics 68: 2735-2742.
Wilson M,A and Howarth R,B (2002) Discourse-based valuation of ecosystem services:
establishing fair outcomes through group deliberation, Ecological Economics 41: 431-443.