ARTICLE IN PRESS
European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
European Economic Review
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/eer
Tax progressivity, income distribution and tax non-compliance
Tatiana Damjanovic , David Ulph 1
University of St. Andrews, St Salvator’s College, KY16 9AL, UK
a r t i c l e i n f o
abstract
Article history:
Received 27 July 2007
Accepted 23 September 2009
Available online 30 September 2009
This article examines the determinants of tax non-compliance when we recognise the
existence of an imperfectly competitive ‘‘tax advice’’ industry supplying schemes which
help taxpayers reduce their tax liability. We apply a traditional industrial organisation
framework to model the behaviour of this industry. This tells us that an important factor
determining the equilibrium price and hence, the level of non-compliance, is the
convexity of the demand schedule. We show that in this context, this convexity is
affected by the distribution of pre-tax income, the progressivity of the tax-schedule and
the way in which monitoring and penalties vary with income. It is shown that lower
pre-tax income inequality as well as a less progressive tax code may cause more tax
minimisation activities. Therefore, the frequently advocated policy of reducing the
highest tax rate may fail as a policy directed at improving tax discipline. One way of
offsetting the possible harm to tax compliance from a less progressive tax could be an
adjustment of the penalty and monitoring functions.
& 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
JEL classification:
H21
H23
H26
Keywords:
Tax compliance
Tax administration
Inequality
Tax progressivity
Tax monitoring
Penalty function
1. Introduction
Tax non-compliance—avoidance and evasion—is a problem of great importance for many countries. For example, the US
Internal Revenue Service estimated that about 17% of due income taxes are not paid (IRS, 2007), while according to the HMTreasury report (HMRC, 2007), the VAT gap is about 14.2% in the UK.
Tax non-compliance does not only reduce tax revenue (ceteris paribus) but also has a number of other welfare-reducing
consequences.2
The loss of tax revenue means that governments either have to spend less on desirable publicly provided goods and
services or else are forced to increase the tax burdens on compliant tax payers, thus amplifying the deadweight loss.3
The government’s inability to collect sufficient tax revenue may result in a higher deficit and a deterioration of the
financial environment. In extreme cases, it may cause financial crises, as in Russia in 1998 a1nd Argentina in 2002.
Significant amounts of real resources are devoted to both devising tax reducing schemes and to the monitoring and
enforcement of tax compliance.
Corresponding author.
E-mail addresses:
[email protected] (T. Damjanovic),
[email protected] (D. Ulph).
David Ulph is also Senior External Research Fellow, Centre for Business Taxation, University of Oxford.
2
For a detailed overview of the main problems related to tax compliance, see Andreoni et al. (1998).
3
Feldstein (1999) estimates the deadweight loss from income tax in the US to be more than 12 times larger than it would have been without tax
avoidance.
1
0014-2921/$ - see front matter & 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.euroecorev.2009.09.003
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
595
Non-compliance typically results in otherwise identical taxpayers facing arbitrarily different effective marginal tax
rates—which violates a standard condition of efficient taxation and thus increases the distortions of the tax system.
Since rich individuals are probably more likely to employ avoidance practices,4 the government levies heavier taxes on
those who are less well-off, which will not only increase vertical inequality but may also slow down the development of
small businesses and economic growth.
It is also important to recognise that non-compliance can have a multiplier effect to the extent that non-compliance by a
small group of individuals diminishes the social norm of tax compliance in the wider population of otherwise compliant
taxpayers. The importance of such norms has been emphasised in a number of behavioural and experimental studies
(Gordon, 1989; Cowell, 1992; Myles and Naylor, 1996; Kim, 2003).
While it is thus important to more fully understand the drivers of tax non-compliance, much of the literature has focused
on taxpayer behaviour—the demand side of non-compliance—using either the conventional Allingham–Sandmo model or
some other decision-theoretic approach. It is now generally recognised that non-compliance has both a supply side and a
demand side, and that more attention needs to be paid to the supply side. Indeed, Slemrod (2004) considers the ignorance
of the supply side of tax non-compliance to be a significant shortcoming of traditional economic models, especially in
relation to corporate tax behaviour, and points out that the market for tax abusive schemes has grown substantially in
recent years.5
One aspect of the supply side that has been widely studied is the role of agents/tax preparers who may inform the
clients of tax saving opportunities. For example, Erard (1993) shows that the non-compliance on returns prepared by
certified public accountant and lawyers is approximately 4.5 times larger than it would have been had their clients
prepared their own tax returns. Another aspect focuses on how taxes could be evaded by bribing the tax inspector6 or even
a member of parliament to issue the right tax exemption.7
In this paper, the focus is on another aspect of supply—the existence of an imperfectly competitive industry that
devises and sells tax minimisation schemes. Certainly, in many advanced economies, the market seems to be
dominated by a relatively small number of large players. For instance, in the UK, this would be the ‘‘Big Four’’
accountancy firms (KPMG, Ernst and Young, PricewaterhouseCoopers and Deloitte), which often face criticism for the provision
of tax shelters for wealthy individuals and business corporations (see, for example, The Financial Times, May 10, 2004).
Within such a perspective, a crucial factor determining the amount of non-compliance is the equilibrium price for these
schemes. Now, it is well known from the traditional Industrial Organization literature that the equilibrium price depends on
certain features of the industry demand curve. For example, Anderson and Régis (2003) show that the more convex is the industry
demand function, the lower will be the equilibrium price and the higher the equilibrium quantity. Similarly, Sandmo (1971) and
Coes (1977) have shown that the supplier reduces the quantity when facing higher uncertainty/inequality in demand.
The aim of this paper is to explore what factors affect the shape of the demand curve for the tax minimisation industry
and hence, the equilibrium price and output. We will investigate how the shape of the demand curve depends on
(i) the progressivity of the tax schedule;
(ii) the level of inequality of the pre-tax distribution of income;
(iii) the shape of penalty and monitoring functions.
A number of important implications will be discussed.
One of the most important issues is that in a wide class of cases, a greater progressivity of the tax schedule may reduce
the supply of tax avoidance/evasion schemes. Conversely, the flatter the schedule, the lower is the equilibrium price of
tax minimisation schemes and hence, the greater is the level of non-compliance. This result is very important because
the presumption is often the other way around—the response to avoidance/evasion is to have a very flat schedule (see,
for example, Tanzi and Zee, 2000).
4
Lang et al. (1997), which is based on German data, concluded that ‘‘the difference between legislative and effective tax rate increases in gross
income up to the eight income decile and remains at the maximum difference of about 16% for the ninth and the tenth decile’’. See also Agell and Persson
(2000) for the avoidance practice within the different income groups in Sweden, while Feinstein (1991) finds a similar relation for TCMP audit findings in
1982 and 1985. Desai et al. (2006) and Desai (2005) also indicate that corporate tax avoidance activities are more likely to be undertaken by larger firms.
5
The large importance of the disclosure of the tax avoidance schemes has been recognised by HMRC and postulated in Part 7 of the Finance Act 2004.
Similarly, the Internal Revenue Service proclaimed that one of its priorities in 2009 is to combat abusive tax avoidance schemes and the individuals who
promote them (IRS, 2009).
6
Chander and Wilde (1992) and Hindriks et al. (1999) cite different sources and provide outrageous evidence of tax corruption in India, Nepal,
Thailand and Taiwan. Hindriks et al. (1999), for example, write that surveys in Taiwan ‘‘report 94% of interviewees as having been ‘led to’ bribe corrupt tax
administrators and 80% of certified public accountants as admitting to bribing tax officials’’ and ‘‘confidential survey as finding that 76% of all government
tax auditors took bribes and 68% of taxpayers had paid bribes’’. For the tax moral in Latin America, see Torgler (2005).
7
The harm from legal tax exemption could be very significant for a national tax revenue. For example, according to Åslund (1999), three tax
exemptions only cost the Russian federal budget more than 7% of GDP: the tax grant to the natural gas monopoly company Gazprom at the end of 1993
(2% of GDP); the secured tax exemptions for the metallurgical industry (2% of GDP) and the National Sports Fund’s right to import alcohol and tobacco
without tax (3% of GDP).
ARTICLE IN PRESS
596
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
In a wide class of cases, there will be greater tax compliance in economies with a higher level of inequality in pre-tax
income.
Finally, we will show how, given the tax code and pre-tax income distribution, the government can influence the shape
of the demand curve for tax evasion and hence, the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers by suitably designing the
shape of the monitoring and penalty functions.
The intuition behind these first two results is the following. The more equal are tax duties—which can arise by having
either a more progressive tax schedule or a more equal distribution of pre-tax income—the more elastic is demand and
thus, the greater is the incentive of suppliers of tax schemes to cut prices to attract a larger share of the population to buy
their tax scheme. Conversely, the more unequal are tax duties, the more can be gained by targeting the rich (or those who
are ready to pay much more) at a higher price.
We will show that the main results are robust to different assumptions about the nature of market structure.
The rest of the paper is organised as follows. Section 2 presents a general model and characterises the equilibrium price
and output of tax reduction schemes. Section 3 derives the main comparative static results and, in particular, the link
between tax compliance and both the progressivity of the tax schedule and the degree of income inequality. Section 4
considers two extensions of the previous analysis: first we show how a tax authority can influence the level of compliance
through the design of its monitoring and penalty regimes and second we show how the analysis can be generalised to
different forms of payment schedules. Section 5 concludes the paper.
2. The model
2.1. The demand side
We begin by exploring the demand side of the tax minimisation industry and investigate how this is affected by factors
such as the distribution of pre-tax income, the tax code, and the shape of the audit probability and penalty functions.
2.1.1. Individual demand
There is a continuum of taxpayers that differs in only the pre-tax level, x, of some tax base, which could be earned
income, profit, bequest, etc. We will refer to x as income in the rest of the text. While the income earned by a particular
household is private information, we assume the cumulative distribution function of income, FðxÞ, to be common
knowledge. For simplicity, we assume that income is distributed over the finite interval ½a; b. We assume that FðxÞ is
differentiable and strictly increasing. Let f ðxÞ ¼ F 0 ðxÞ denote the associated density function with f ðxÞ40, 8x 2 ½a; b.
The government determines the tax code, tðxÞ, which we take to be exogenous,8 a positive and increasing function
relating the level of tax duties to income. For simplicity, we will also assume it to be continuously differentiable.
There is an industry supplying a single tax scheme9 that helps taxpayers reduce the amount of tax they pay by some
constant proportion b, b 2 ½0; 1.
However, the particular method of tax reduction may not be perfectly safe, and we assume there to be some probability
p, 0rpr1, that the taxpayer will be subjected to audit and, if audited, the scheme will be deemed to constitute tax evasion
in which case the taxpayer will have to repay the tax plus a penalty. This interpretation of p enables us to encompass a
range of possible types of schemes that might be supplied by the market. At one extreme, there is the case considered in
most of the existing literature of schemes that are known to constitute pure tax evasion with certainty and, in this case, p is
just the audit probability. At the other extreme, schemes that are known to constitute tax planning or pure tax avoidance
with certainty will be perfectly legal and so p ¼ 0, irrespective of the audit probability. More generally, schemes may fall
into a grey area where their legality may be a matter of judgement, or may depend on the precise way in which they are
implemented and, in this case, p will be the product of the audit probability and the probability of being judged to be illegal
conditional on being audited. IRS (2009) provides examples of such schemes.
Following Yitzhaki (1974) and Reinganum and Wilde (1986), we assume penalties to be proportional to the tax that is
deemed to have been evaded and let f40 denote the penalty per unit of tax evaded. Consequently, compared to the
outcome under compliance, purchasing the scheme will increase disposable income by btðxÞ if the taxpayer is not deemed
to be evading tax, but will reduce it by fbtðxÞ if the taxpayer is deemed to be evading tax. Assuming that taxpayers are risk
neutral, the expected value of purchasing a scheme will be atðxÞ, where a ¼ bð1 pð1 þ fÞÞ. Obviously, we need to assume
that a40 to ensure that any scheme is purchased. Given the low coverage rates (audit probabilities) operated by most tax
authorities, this is an innocuous assumption.
8
Roine (2006) and Borck (2007) analyse the property of the affine tax code which results from a voting over redistribution when tax avoidance and
evasion are present. Damjanovic (2001) investigated the properties of the optimal tax code design in an economy with a monopolistic tax avoidance
provider.
9
In a related paper, Ulph (2008) analyses the case where the tax advice industry provides a variety of differentiated products ranging from tax
planning through avoidance to evasion.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
597
In summary, there is thus a single type of scheme available and its properties are summarised by parameter a, giving the
expected net percentage reduction in tax through purchasing a scheme.10
For the moment, we will assume that the scheme being sold is a generic/off-the-peg scheme that could be purchased
and implemented by any taxpayer. In this case, the seller of the scheme will know nothing about the characteristics of the
purchaser and, in particular, his income, x, and cannot charge different prices for different taxpayers—i.e. engage in price
discrimination. In Section 4.2 we will consider the alternative case where sellers provide a bespoke service through which
they learn the taxpayer’s income and thus can offer a schedule of prices that varies with income.
Thus, let us assume for the moment that sellers of this scheme are unable to observe the individual incomes of the taxpayers
who buy them. Therefore, schemes will be sold on the market at a common price p40 which takes the form of an up-front fee.
Clearly, they will only be bought by those taxpayers with an income above the critical threshold xðpÞ defined by
atðxðpÞÞ ¼ p:
ð1Þ
2.1.2. Aggregate demand
It follows from (1) that when the price is p, the fraction of taxpayers who buy the scheme—i.e. aggregate demand—will
be
0rQ r1:
Q ¼ 1 F½xðpÞ;
As is common, it useful to work with the inverse aggregate demand function. So, let xðQ Þ be the critical level of income
above which taxpayers will have to buy a scheme in order to give rise to aggregate demand, Q. Then, xðQ Þ is implicitly
defined by
0rQ r1
Q 1 F½xðQ Þ;
ð2Þ
and so
x 0 ðQ Þ ¼
1
:
f ðxðQ ÞÞ
ð3Þ
Consequently, the inverse aggregate demand function is
pðQ Þ atðxðQ ÞÞ
ð4Þ
with
p0 ðQ Þ ¼
at0 ðxÞ
f ðxÞ
o0:
ð5Þ
2.2. Supply side
As indicated in the Introduction, we will assume that the tax advice industry is best described as an imperfectly
competitive oligopoly, comprising a small number of large firms.
There are nZ1 identical firms supplying the given type of scheme.
The tax minimisation industry could be compared with the research and development sector. To provide an effective tax
reduction scheme, suppliers must conduct complex research into local and international tax law, devise a scheme and then
‘‘test’’ it by seeking a legal opinion as to whether it works in law. Since, by assumption, we are dealing with marketed rather
than bespoke schemes, once devised, the marginal cost of producing an additional version of the scheme is pretty
minimal.11
Accordingly, we assume that any given firm has a technology represented by the cost function
gðqÞ ¼ C þ cq;
ð6Þ
where C is the fixed cost and c is the marginal cost.
To have an interesting story, we assume that the marginal costs are sufficiently low so that, if schemes were available at
a price equal to the marginal cost, some consumers would be willing to buy them. Formally, we assume there to exist a
level of income x , aox ob, such that
atðx Þ ¼ c:
ð7Þ
Notice that x is the minimum level of income above which individuals would purchase a scheme if the tax advice industry
were perfectly competitive.
10
So far, we have assumed a to be independent of income. In Section 4, this assumption will be relaxed, and we will investigate how equilibrium tax
compliance depends on the progressivity of the tax evasion technology, bðxÞ; the audit probability, pðxÞ; and the penalty function, fðxÞ.
11
Remember that we can have the same model allowing the cost to vary with the tax duties of the customer, with the assumption that this cost will
be transferred to the tax avoider ex post.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
598
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
For later purposes, it will be helpful to re-write (7) as
c
tðx Þ ¼ k ¼ ;
a
ð8Þ
where k is the ratio of distribution costs to the expected benefit of acquiring a scheme and can be considered as measuring
the effectiveness of the tax supply industry.
In the case where the supply industry is imperfectly competitive, we assume that firms compete in quantities, let q be
the output chosen by a typical firm and q denote the output of all other firms—so that aggregate output is Q ¼ q þ q .
We do not assume a particular form of competition in the market. Rather, we adopt a conjectural variation approach12
whereby each firm assumes that if it increases output by one unit, the total output of all remaining firms will change by the
amount c,13 that is
dq
¼ c;
dq
0rco1:
ð9Þ
Cournot competition arises when c ¼ 0 and perfect/Bertrand competition when c ¼ 1. Notice, however, that we are
excluding the uninteresting Bertrand equilibrium, where the price would just be driven down to the marginal cost and no
firm would make a profit.
From (5) and (6), the profits made by a typical firm are
Pðq; q Þ ¼ qpðQ Þ C cq:
ð10Þ
From (9) and (10), it follows that the equilibrium fraction of taxpayers who purchase a scheme, Q e , is characterised by
ðpðQ e Þ cÞ þ
1
w
Q e p0 ðQ e Þ ¼ 0;
ð11Þ
where w ¼ n=ð1 cÞZ1 measures the competitiveness of the industry.
In what follows, we assume that we have a non-trivial equilibrium in which Q e 40, so there are some non-compliant
taxpayers and the equilibrium price of a scheme is above the marginal cost.
Eq. (11) is the standard result, characterising the equilibrium of a homogenous good oligopoly.
The equilibrium will depend on three factors: marginal costs, c; competitiveness of the industry, w; and the nature of the
demand schedule. Indeed, we know from Anderson and Régis (2003) that the equilibrium will depend on the convexity of
the aggregate demand function.
From (4), we can see that the aggregate demand schedule in turn depends on the nature of both the tax schedule and
the distribution of income. To more clearly bring out how these underlying factors influence the equilibrium, substitute (2),
(4), (5) into (11), and then, after some rearrangements, we can also see that the equilibrium cut-off level of income above
which taxpayers purchase a scheme, x e , is characterised by
1
1 Fðx e Þ 0
tðx e Þ ¼ k þ t0 ðx e Þ
w
f ðx e Þ
:
ð12Þ
From (7), (12) and our assumption that Q e 40, it follows that atðx e Þ4c, and that x rx e ob, with x e ¼ x in a special case of
perfect/Bertrand competition.
To derive comparative static results, it is useful to establish an alternative way of characterising the equilibrium.
Accordingly, let us define the function
HðxÞ ¼ ðtðxÞ kÞ1=w ½1 FðxÞ:
ð13Þ
Proposition 1. There exists a unique x e , which solves (12) such that x e ¼ maxðargmax HðxÞÞ. Moreover, aox e ob and
therefore Hðx e Þ40.14
Proposition 1 defines the equilibrium threshold income which splits the population into fully compliant taxpayers and
non-compliant taxpayers who use a tax minimisation scheme and, consequently, though Eq. (2) the proportion, Q, of the
taxpayer population that is non-compliant.
Q provides one measure of the amount of non-compliance in the economy.
12
The concept of conjectural variation was introduced by Bowley (1924) and since then, it has been used by economists to explain more diversified
market outcomes rather than restricted Nash equilibrium prices or outputs. To narrow down its too broad and arbitrary predictions, many researchers
have focused on the rationality and consistency of conjectural variation (see Laitner, 1980; Bresnahan, 1981; Kamien and Schwartz, 1983; Robson, 1983;
Ulph, 1983). Despite theoretical objections to the concept, empirical evidence provides widespread support for the phenomenon (see Iwata, 1974;
Appelbaum, 1979; Just and Chern, 1980; Kolstad and Wolak, 1986). Then, a natural question arises: how does conjectural variation affect market
performance? Anderson (1977), Kamien and Schwartz (1983) and Kolstad and Wolak (1986) found that higher conjectural variation leads to lower output
and higher prices.
13
In the special case of monopoly, where n ¼ 1 and there are no other firms, we make the natural assumption that c ¼ 0.
14
In general, there could be infimum solutions to problem (12) and they will all belong to argmax HðxÞ. However, we restrict our attention to the
solution that is most preferable to the government, x e ¼ maxðargmax HðxÞÞ.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
599
Another measure of non-compliance is the tax gap—the amount of uncollected tax. This can, in gross terms, be defined
as the amount of tax that taxpayers initially try not to pay and, once more expressed in absolute terms, this would be
Z b
tðxÞf ðxÞ dx:
Ggross ¼ ð1 bÞ
x
Alternatively, the tax gap can be defined in net terms as the amount of tax that taxpayers ultimately succeed in not
paying after the effects of audit and repayment are taken into account and, once more expressed in absolute terms, this
would be
Z b
tðxÞf ðxÞ dx:
Gnet ¼ ð1 pÞð1 bÞ
x
Each of these can also be measured in relative terms as a fraction of the total amount of tax that would have been
collected had all taxpayers been fully compliant.
Whatever measure is used, factors such as the risk of being found to be non-compliant, p, the shape of the tax schedule
tðxÞ and the distribution of income f ðxÞ will affect the tax gap through two channels:
there is the direct impact, treating x as constant;
there is an indirect or behavioural effect that works through the impact of these factors on x.
In all that follows, we want to purely focus on these indirect or behavioural effects and, consequently, on changes in the
value of x. So, although we will establish a series of comparative static propositions about the effects of various parameter
changes on the number of non-compliant taxpayers, these also tell us about the qualitative indirect effects of these changes
on the tax gap.15
Remark 1. From (13), it follows that there are five factors that will generate comparative static effects:
the
the
the
the
the
marginal cost per client, c;
efficiency of the tax saving scheme, a;
competitiveness of the tax advice industry, w;
nature of the tax schedule, tðxÞ;
nature of the distribution of income, f ðxÞ.
In the next section, we establish the comparative static results relating to all these five factors.
3. Comparative static results
3.1. General discussion
In this section, we establish the main comparative static results of the paper. We will make repeated use of the following
proposition:
~
Proposition 2. Suppose that HðxÞ
¼ HðxÞgðxÞ, where gðxÞ is positive, continuously differentiable and g 0 ðxÞ40, then for the
e
e
e
corresponding pair x~ , x defined as in Proposition 1, it follows that x~ e 4x e and so, Q~ oQ e .
In the rest of the paper, we will investigate how the change of one of the factors described in Remark 1 will affect the
function HðxÞ and the proportion of honest taxpayers.
In particular, we would like to establish how changes in the tax code or in the underlying distribution of income that
will affect the distribution of the tax burden affect the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers. For this purpose, we would
~
like to relate the monotonicity of the function gðxÞ ¼ HðxÞ=HðxÞ
introduced in Proposition 2 to the Lorenz dominance
criterion for the distribution of incomes.
Lorenz dominance, introduced in Atkinson (1970), is one of the most popular orderings of inequality. Atkinson
demonstrated that if the Lorenz curve (which shows the proportion of total income received by the poorest t% of the
population) for one distribution lies below the Lorenz curve associated with another, inequality in the first case is higher
for a wide class of inequality measures.
Naturally, it is somewhat cumbersome to construct the Lorenz curve every time we need to compare the inequality
resulting from different income distributions. So, we need a test whereby we can guarantee that one income distribution
Lorenz dominates another without having to compute the associated Lorenz curves. Now, one way of reducing inequality is
15
The behavioural effect is of great importance per se. A low tax discipline reduces the effectiveness of tax audit, increases the costs of tax
enforcement and, as mentioned before, undermines the social norms of tax compliance. It may even stimulate strategic tax con-compliance as discussed
in Bassetto and Phelan (2008).
ARTICLE IN PRESS
600
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
to carry out a progressive redistribution. That is, if we transform income in such a way that the rate of increase in income is
smaller for a richer than for a poorer person, the new Lorenz curve will lie above the old one and the two Lorenz curves do
not intersect.
This idea is formalised in the following lemma which was proved in Kakwani (1977) and Jakobsson (1976) for a
continuous domain and differentiable income transformation, and in Keen et al. (2000) for a discrete income distribution.
For proof in a more general set-up, see Le Breton et al. (1996) or Damjanovic (2005), which provides a simpler proof.
Lemma 1. Let yðxÞ and zðxÞ be a positive non-decreasing function transforming income x. Then, yðxÞ is more equally distributed
than zðxÞ iff yðxÞ=zðxÞ is a decreasing function.
Lemma 1 and Proposition 2 provide the basis for showing the conceptual relation between distributional inequality, the
function HðxÞ and hence, the equilibrium amount of tax non-compliance. We spell this out in the rest of the section.
3.2. Higher marginal costs and lower net benefit
There are many factors that can cause the marginal costs of providing schemes to vary. Like any technology, this will be
subject to technical progress and knowledge spillover. For example, ideas developed in the US for lowering tax may, with
some adaptation, be applicable to the UK. On the other hand, we could envisage a tax authority introducing legislation such
as disclosure powers, which make it more difficult for the tax advice industry to market effective schemes. This could show
up as an increase in the marginal costs of distributing a scheme, c, since it may require more effort to fine-tune the scheme
to each customer’s circumstances.
Clearly, there is a number of steps that a tax authority can take to increase the risk of successful challenge, p, and the
penalty on evasion f, both of which will reduce the net benefit of a scheme, a.
Both increases in marginal costs, c, and reductions in the net benefit, a, will show up as an increase in costs relative to
benefit k ¼ c=a and, intuitively, this will result in a higher equilibrium price for schemes and, consequently, a higher critical
income threshold above which schemes are bought, x e , and thus, a smaller number of non-compliant taxpayers. Formally,
we have:
e
~
Proposition 3. If k4k
then x~ e 4x e and so Q~ oQ e .
~ 1=w ½1 FðxÞ ¼ gðxÞHðxÞ where gðxÞ ¼ ½ðtðxÞ kÞ=ð
~ tðxÞ kÞ1=w . It is easily seen that gðxÞ is a strictly
~
Proof. HðxÞ
¼ ½tðxÞ k
increasing function and the result follows from Proposition 2. &
3.3. Increased competition
Our model of competition is very general and nests as special cases:
Monopoly: n ¼ 1, c ¼ 0.
Cournot oligopoly: n41, c ¼ 0.
Bertrand equilibrium (approximately): n41, c 1.
Therefore, it is interesting to ask how the equilibrium is affected when there is an increased degree of competition in the
sense of either an increase in the number of firms, n, serving the market, or an increase in the intensity of price
competition, c. These will both have the effect of increasing the parameter w ¼ n=ð1 cÞ and, as in conventional models of
oligopoly, these will drive down the equilibrium price and expand equilibrium output, thus leading to less compliance.16
This is confirmed in the following proposition:
Proposition 4. If the industry supplying tax advice becomes more competitive, the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers will
e
increase. Formally, if w~ 4w then x~ e ox e and so Q~ 4Q e .
~
Proof. HðxÞ
¼ HðxÞgðxÞ where gðxÞ ¼ ðtðxÞ kÞ1=w 1=w . It is easily seen that g 0 ðxÞo0 and the result follows from
Proposition 2. &
~
16
Now, a particular interpretation of our model is one in which corrupt tax organisations or officials offer tax grants and exemptions for particular
firms in return for a bribe, with the case of a monopolistic corrupt official being similar to that described in Shleifer and Vishny (1993). Proposition 3
shows that to increase compliance, the government should reduce the degree of competition in the tax minimising industry. For example, the right to
issue tax grants and tax exemptions should only be given to one authority. Our prescriptions are the opposite of those in Shleifer and Vishny (1993). This is
because Shleifer and Vishny’s paper addresses the situation where bureaucrats are bribed to provide some socially valuable goods, whilst we are
investigating the production of tax avoidance, which is a ‘‘social bad’’.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
601
3.4. Tax progressivity and compliance
In this section, we establish a link between the progressivity of the tax schedule, tðxÞ, and the proportion of taxpayers
who are non-compliant.
Now, one weak sense of progressivity relates to how unequally the tax burden is distributed. At one extreme, a poll tax
makes everyone pay the same amount of tax while, under a progressive tax system, the rich pay more tax than the poor. We
capture this idea through the following definition.
Definition 1. We will say that the tax duties t~ are less equally distributed than t if ½t~ ðxÞ=tðxÞ0 40.
Definition 1 is consistent with the Lorenz dominance criterion for the distribution of tax duties, as discussed in Section
3.1.
The first and most general proposition we can establish that connects the shape of the tax schedule to the level of
compliance relates to the distribution of the profits made by tax advisers from different taxpayers: aðtðxÞ kÞ.
Definition 2. We will say that the tax code t~ results in a less equally distributed tax adviser profit than t if g 0 ðxÞ40 where
gðxÞ ¼ ½ðt~ ðxÞ kÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ.
Then, we have the following proposition:
e
Proposition 5. Let ½ðt~ ðxÞ kÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ0 be positive so that x~ e 4x e and so that Q~ oQ e .
This is an immediate corollary of Proposition 2.
For the interesting case where all costs of producing a tax scheme are purely the fixed costs of ‘‘R&D’’ and the marginal
cost of distributing the scheme is zero—so that c ¼ k ¼ 0Fthere is an immediate link between the distribution of tax
adviser profits and the distribution of tax burdens, namely progressivity.
The following proposition shows that in this case, the proportion of compliant taxpayers is higher when the tax duties
are less equally distributed.
e
Corollary 1. Let ½t~ ðxÞ=tðxÞ0 be positive and assume that the per client cost is zero, k ¼ 0, then x~ e 4x e and so Q~ oQ e .
The intuition is the following. The move to a more progressive tax system will raise the average tax rate—and hence the
willingness to pay for a scheme—of supra marginal consumers. The industry will accordingly increase profits by increasing
the price of tax schemes and catering more for high demand consumers—thus reducing the number of schemes sold.
Remark 2. As noted above, it follows that having less equally distributed tax revenues will reduce the tax gap through the
indirect effect. Naturally, it does not follow from this proposition that the overall effect on the tax gap will be negative.
Although there are fewer non-compliant taxpayers, these will typically be liable for a larger amount of tax, so the total
amount of tax underpaid could either rise or fall.
So far, we have considered very general tax codes t~ ðxÞ and tðxÞ but we have been able to get sharp propositions relating
their relative progressivity to the levels of compliance they induce only in the case where the marginal costs are zero. When
the marginal costs are positive, Proposition 5 still allows us to establish an important link between tax progressivity and
tax compliance, provided that we confine ourselves to affine transformations of tax codes and provided that the increase in
progressivity is sufficiently high.
Definition 3. The tax code t~ ðxÞ is a progressive affine transformation of the tax code tðxÞ if t~ ðxÞ ¼ mtðxÞ s, where s40,
m41.
e
Proposition 6. A progressive affine transformation of the tax code reduces the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers ðQ~ oQ e Þ
iff s=ðm 1Þ4k.
Corollary 2. If t~ ðxÞ ¼ mtðxÞ s, where s40, m41, it is easily shown that ½ðt~ ðxÞ kÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ0 ¼ t0 ðxÞðm 1Þ=ðtðxÞ kÞ2
ðs=ðm 1Þ kÞ40. The result follows from Proposition 2.
Proposition 6 shows that an increase in tax progressivity could improve the tax discipline. As in the above remark, this
does not necessarily imply an increase in the tax gap.
The reason for having to ensure that the increase in progressivity is sufficiently large is as follows. In general, the
ratio of tax adviser profits under the two tax codes can be represented as ½ðt~ ðxÞ kÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ ¼ ððt~ ðxÞ kÞ=
t~ ðxÞÞð~t ðxÞ=tðxÞÞtðxÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ. If k40 the first term is strictly increasing in x and, following Definition 1, so is the second
term provided that the tax code t~ ðxÞ is more progressive than tðxÞFi:e. produces more unequal tax burdens. However, if
k40, the third term is strictly decreasing in x. To ensure that tax adviser profits are more unequally distributed, we have to
ensure that the increase in progressivity of the tax code as reflected in s=ðm 1Þ is high relative to k.
So far, we have compared the levels of compliance under two tax codes that differ in their degree of progressivity, but
we have made no assumptions about the amount of tax raised under these two schedules. However, often in comparing tax
codes we do so under the assumption of revenue neutrality—i.e. that they raise the same amount of tax, or at least would
ARTICLE IN PRESS
602
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
do so if all taxpayers were fully compliant. Assume now that the government carries out an affine tax reform which, if all
tax-payers were fully compliant, would be revenue neutral and would result in a more progressive tax schedule: a higher
marginal tax rate, lower taxes for the poor and higher taxes for the rich. So t~ ðxÞ ¼ mtðxÞ s, m41, s40 and
Z b
Z b
t :¼
t~ ðxÞf ðxÞ dx ¼
tðxÞf ðxÞ dx;
ð14Þ
a
a
where t is the average amount of tax that would be raised in the case of full compliance. Condition (14) would imply that
s ¼ ðm 1Þt . Therefore, in this case g 0 ðxÞ ¼ ½ðt~ ðxÞ kÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ0 ¼ ðm 1Þðt0 ðxÞ=ðtðxÞ kÞ2 Þðt kÞ which is positive if and
only if t 4k ¼ tðx Þ. This latter result requires that the average benefit from tax non-compliance exceeds the marginal cost
of supply or, equivalently, that the individual with average tax duties would be involved in tax non-compliance should the
tax avoidance market be perfectly competitive. We formulate this result in Proposition 7.
Proposition 7. The move to a more progressive tax system will reduce the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers if, had the
industry supplying tax advice been perfectly competitive, the minimum level of income above which all taxpayers are noncompliant is below the income of the individual with average tax duties. Formally, the result is
x~ e _x e
as tðx Þwt :
Note 1: Another way of stating this result is to say that the impact of an increase in tax progressivity on tax discipline
depends on how high is the marginal cost of distributing the tax scheme, c, in relation to the benefit that a taxpayer paying
the average amount of tax will obtain from acquiring a scheme to reduce taxes. If the cost is not very high, coat , then a
revenue-neutral tax reform that makes the tax system more progressive will result in better tax discipline—fewer people
engaging in non-compliance.
Note 2: Although the condition for the conclusion to hold refers to the critical threshold level of income when the supply
industry is perfectly competitive, the result holds for any degree of competitiveness.
One implication of this remark is that if the industry is imperfectly competitive, it will not always be possible to tell
whether the condition of the theorem holds just by using observations on which taxpayers are actually non-compliant in
the given situation. However, one case where we can say something more definite is as follows:
Corollary 3. If there are non-compliant taxpayers with below-average tax duties then the move to a more progressive tax system
will reduce the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers. Formally, if tðx e Þot then x~ e 4x e .
Proof. Since tðx Þotðx e Þ it follows that if tðx e Þot then tðx Þot and the conclusion follows from Proposition 7.
&
Note 3: If the assumption of Corollary 3 holds and the marginal cost is high, an increase in progressivity will tend to
increase non-compliance both in the sense that the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers increases and that the total
underpayment of taxes—the tax gap—will increase.
To conclude this subsection, note that the conclusions of both Propositions 6 and 7 question the widely held belief that
moving towards a flatter, less progressive tax code will reduce the amount of non-compliance. Thus, a reduction in the
marginal tax rate for the highest tax bracket is often recommended as a means of reducing the incentives for tax avoidance
and evasion (see, for example, Tanzi and Zee, 2000). However, the present model illustrates that this policy may result in
the completely opposite outcome,17 in the case where the marginal cost per client of supplying a scheme is relatively small.
3.5. Income inequality and compliance
In this section, we will show that in a wide class of cases, a more equal distribution of the tax base may be associated
with a higher rate of tax non-compliance.
Consider two different distributions of income on the interval ½a; b with the cumulative distribution functions FðxÞ and
F~ ðxÞ. Let us also define the survival probability ratio of these two distributions as gðxÞ ¼ ð1 F~ ðxÞÞ=ð1 FðxÞÞ. From
Proposition 2, we immediately get the following result:
Proposition 8. Consider the survival probability ratio gðxÞ ¼ ð1 F~ ðxÞÞ=ð1 FðxÞÞ. If g 0 ðxÞ40, then for any tax code tðxÞ, the
e
income distribution FðxÞ will imply a higher level of tax non-compliance than F~ ðxÞ, i.e. Q e 4Q~ .
Proof. Propositions 1 and 2 immediately give us the sufficient condition for increasing the indirect effect of tax noncompliance. &
17
Indeed, exactly such an outcome was reported in Russia in 2002. Starting from 2001, the Russian government cut the profit tax rate from 35% to 25%
and broadened the tax base by revoking investment preferences, which made the tax duties more equally distributed. By implementing this measure, the
Russian government intended to reduce the incentives for tax avoidance and tax evasion. However, the ratio of taxable profit to total profit fell from 60% to
30% in one year, as reported in Gurvitch (2002). This phenomenon is hard to explain using existing tax minimising models. This paper provides a possible
explanation—the key innovation being that we treat the price of tax reduction schemes as endogenous.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
603
~
To relate this proposition to income inequality, let hðxÞ ¼ f ðxÞ=½1 FðxÞ and hðxÞ
¼ f~ ðxÞ=½1 F~ ðxÞ be the hazard rates
~
and thus, gðxÞ has a
associated with the two distributions. Now, it is immediately obvious that g 0 ðxÞ ¼ gðxÞ½hðxÞ hðxÞ
positive first derivative if and only if, for all x, the distribution FðxÞ has a higher hazard rate than the distribution F~ ðxÞ. We
say that in this case, the distribution FðxÞ is smaller than the distribution F~ ðxÞ with respect to hazard order.18
To relate hazard-rate dominance to Lorenz dominance, we first note that in Une and Saijo (1995) it was shown that if
there are two distributions on the same interval ½a; b, then the hazard-rate dominance of the first distribution over the
second implies a first-order stochastic dominance of the first over the second. But first-order stochastic dominance implies
second-order stochastic dominance, which we know from the work of Atkinson and Bourguignon (1990) to be equivalent to
generalised Lorenz dominance. So higher hazard rates are associated with both a higher level of non-compliance and a
greater level of equality, at least as measured by the generalised Lorenz dominance criterion. This is summarised in the
following proposition.
Proposition 9. For any tax code tðxÞ if the income distribution FðxÞ hazard-rate dominates the distribution F~ ðxÞ, then FðxÞ will
exhibit both a higher level of tax non-compliance and a greater degree of equality as determined by the generalised Lorenz
dominance criterion.
Generalised Lorenz dominance is now equivalent to Lorenz dominance only if the means of the income distributions are
the same. Although there is not such a close link between hazard rate dominance and Lorenz dominance, there is
nevertheless a wide family of income distributions for which an increase in the variance will imply both an increase in
inequality as measured by the Lorenz dominance criterion and a higher hazard rate and hence, from Proposition 8, a lower
rate of tax non-compliance. Among these distributions are those commonly used in the literature for approximating actual
distributions of income: e.g. Pareto distribution, Lognormal distribution and Exponential distribution. This is summarised
in the following proposition:
Proposition 10. For any tax code tðxÞ, if the income distribution FðxÞ is either Pareto or Exponential, then an increase in the
variance will result in both higher inequality in terms of Lorenz dominance and a lower hazard rate and hence, from Proposition
8, also a higher proportion of non-compliant taxpayers. The same conclusions hold for a mean preserving increase in variance for
the Lognormal distribution.
Finally, we note that there is a link between the result of this sub-section and that of the previous sub-section. They both
demonstrate that a more equal distribution of tax duties can lead to a greater level of non-compliance. In the previous
section, the greater equality of tax duties was caused by a less progressive tax system whereas in this sub-section, the root
cause is more equal distribution of pre-tax incomes. To formalise this idea, we need the following definition:
Definition 4. An increasing income transformation yðxÞ equalises tax burdens with respect to tax code tðxÞ on interval ½a; b,
if tðyðxÞÞ=tðxÞ is decreasing on ða; bÞ.
From the definition, any income transformation which equalises tax burdens makes tax duties more equal according to
the Lorenz ordering. The following proposition states that an income transformation which is equalising with respect to tax
code would reduce the share of compliant taxpayers.
Proposition 11. Let yðxÞ equalise tax burdens with respect to tax code tðxÞ. Then, if k ¼ 0; threshold equilibrium y e is smaller
than yðx e Þ, which implies a larger number of non-compliant taxpayers.
Proof. The relation between the old and new income distributions would be as follows: Fy ðzÞ ¼ Fðy1 ðzÞÞ, where y1 is an
inverted function of y. We recall that y e ¼ argmax Hy ðzÞ ¼ ½tðzÞ1=w ½1 Fy ðzÞ. Substituting x ¼ y1 ðzÞ, we obtain
1=w
xy e ¼ argmax tðyðxÞÞ ð1 FðxÞÞ ¼ argmax HðxÞgðxÞ;
where xy e ¼ y1 ðy e Þ and gðxÞ ¼ ½tðyðxÞÞ=tðxÞ1=w . If yðxÞ equalises tax burdens, gðxÞ is a decreasing function and we may apply
Proposition 2 and conclude that xy e ox e . This means that y e rgðx e Þ and the share of non-compliant taxpayers increases. &
Proposition 11 proves that equalising tax burdens with respect to tax income transformation may reduce the number of
taxpayers. For a simple proportional tax tðyðxÞÞ=tðxÞ ¼ yðxÞ=x and thus, there is a one-to-one link between the equality of
pre-tax income i and the equality of tax burdens. Thus, increasing inequality as determined by the Lorenz dominance
criterion may improve the indirect effect of tax compliance.
As a special case, consider the linear tax schedule tðxÞ ¼ tx s, 0oto1 and suppose that we make the mean-preserving
equalising transformation of income yðxÞ ¼ ax þ ð1 aÞx, 0oao1. Then, the distribution of tax duties implied by this new
distribution of pre-tax income is equivalent to that which would have been created had we alternatively introduced a new
~ s~ , where t~ ¼ atot and s~ ¼ s tð1 aÞxosFwhich is a
revenue-neutral tax reform to produce the tax schedule t~ ðxÞ ¼ tx
less progressive tax schedule. The implications for compliance can then be determined by applying Proposition 7.
18
See Muller and Dietrich (2002) for a further discussion on hazard rate ordering.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
604
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
In summary, our model predicts that pre-tax income inequality and tax compliance can be positively related. Similar
conclusions have been obtained by Cowell (1992), albeit through a very different mechanism since in his model, inequality
affects household utility through the costs of tax evasion.
In this section, we have shown how the degree of inequality of tax duties affects the level of compliance. In particular,
we have shown that more equally distributed tax duties may reduce tax compliance. The inequality of tax duties can be
related to both the distribution of pre-tax income and the progressivity of the tax schedule. In the next section, we show
how the design of the penalty and monitoring functions can also affect the distribution of rewards to taxpayers from
purchasing tax schemes and hence, the level of compliance. This implies that any changes in compliance created by shifts
in the pre-tax distribution of income can be offset by changes in shapes of the penalty and/or monitoring functions.
4. Two extensions
4.1. Monitoring, punishment and non-compliance technology
So far, we have assumed that:
schemes offer taxpayers the opportunity to save a fraction of their tax, b, which is independent of income, x;
the probability that a scheme is subject to a successful challenge, p, is independent of income;
the fraction of tax evaded that has to be paid as a penalty if a taxpayer’s scheme, f, is effectively challenged is also
independent of income.
In principle, each of these assumptions may be invalid.
The opportunities for non-compliance may vary with income. While, in principle, this could go either way, it is likely
that the greater is a taxpayer’s income—and hence the greater the amount of tax due—the greater will be the
opportunities for tax reduction. This suggests that an alternative assumption is that the fraction of tax saved by a
scheme is an increasing function of income, b0 ðxÞ40.
The tax authorities can, in principle, choose how to deploy audit resources across different taxpayer groups and can thus
choose a challenge schedule pðxÞ that varies with income. Typically, they will target their audit resources more heavily
on taxpayer groups which offer higher potential returns. Everything else equal, this would suggest that the monitoring
function that is often used will be such that p0 ðxÞ40.
In a similar spirit, the tax authorities may often negotiate settlements with taxpayers whereby they may not impose the
full penalty f that is legally available to them. For this and other reasons, we want to recognise that there is a de facto
penalty schedule fðxÞ40 that could vary with income.
For all these reasons, the expected net fraction of tax saved by purchasing a scheme is likely to vary with income—which
we capture through the equation
aðxÞ ¼ bðxÞf1 pðxÞ½1 þ fðxÞg:
It is then an immediate implication of Proposition 2 that, ceteris paribus, tax compliance is higher when the share of
taxes saved grows with income at a faster rate. Formally, we have
e
Proposition 12. If a~ ðxÞ ¼ aðxÞgðxÞ, where g 0 ðxÞ40 then x~ e 4x e and Q~ oQ e .
Proof. Immediate application of Proposition 2.
&
This gives rise to three obvious corollaries.
Corollary 4. Ceteris paribus, the proportion of compliant taxpayers is higher when the opportunities for tax saving, b, increase
more rapidly with income.
As in some previous remarks, note that this does not imply that the tax gap will be smaller, since the higher percentage of
compliant taxpayers is being offset by the fact that the non-compliant individuals are paying a smaller proportion of their
taxes.
Corollaries 5 and 6 claim that the government can increase its tax collection by making monitoring and penalty
functions more regressive, more frequently monitoring low income tax units and more heavily punishing them for tax
evasion than the tax units with higher incomes.
Corollary 5. Ceteris paribus, for income independent punishment fðf0 ¼ 0Þ, tax compliance is higher when the probability of
audit is a more rapidly decreasing function of income, p~ 0 4p0 .
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
605
Proof. We can prove this by a direct differentiation of gðxÞ, where gðxÞ ¼ ð1 p~ ðxÞ½1 þ fÞ=ð1 pðxÞ½1 þ fÞ so that
@ðloggÞ0
ð1 þ fÞðp~ 0 p0 Þ
¼
40:
@x
ð1 p~ ½1 þ fÞð1 p½1 þ fÞ
&
Corollary 6. Ceteris paribus, for income independent audit probability pðp0 ¼ 0Þ, tax compliance is higher when the tax penalty
~ 0 4f0 .
is a more rapidly decreasing function of income, f
Proof. We can prove this by direct differentiation of gðxÞ, where gðxÞ ¼ ð1 p~ ðxÞ½1 þ fÞ=ð1 pðxÞ½1 þ fÞ so that
@ðloggÞ0
pðf~ 0 f0 Þ
¼
40:
~ Þð1 p½1 þ fÞ
@x
ð1 p½1 þ f
&
4.2. Alternative pricing behaviour
So far, we have assumed that sellers of a scheme are unable to observe the income of their clients and thus sell a scheme
at a fixed price p that takes the form of an up-front fee.
However, an alternative assumption might be that sellers can observe the taxable income of their clients, which opens
up much richer pricing possibilities. For example, sellers may charge a combination of an up-front fee plus a share of the
tax saved. But this raises the question of who bears the risk if the scheme fails and the taxpayer has to repay the tax and pay
a penalty. Buyers might reasonably argue that if sellers take a share of the gains when their schemes work, they should also
take a share of the cost when they fail to work.
Accordingly in what follows, we will assume that advisers make schemes available on a two-part tariff defined by ðp; yÞ,
p40, 0oyo1, whereby the expected amount paid for a scheme by a taxpayer with income x is pð1 yÞ þ yatðxÞ. We can
consider p as an entry fee or a reserve price that must be paid by the taxpayer to purchase the scheme, and y as the fraction
of the expected gain19 (net the reserve price) from buying the scheme that the taxpayer must share with the seller. We will
take y as fixed and determined by exogenous factors that determine the (common) bargaining power between the buyer
and the seller over how to share the gains from the scheme.
Bargaining is an extensively used model in the tax evasion literature, investigating the activities of a corrupt
tax inspector who audits the individual’s true income, but can be bribed into misreporting the audit result
to the government.20 However, we believe the introduction of a reserve price to enrich the model. The reserve
price contract can easily be written, does not require any additional effort and, since the supplier can always
set a zero reserve price, it increases the gain of the supplier. Finally, this type of contract is widely implemented as a
wage contract for high-skilled professionals. A bargaining model with a reserve price was first introduced by Wang
(1995).
We will continue to assume that all schemes are perfect substitutes and thus, in equilibrium, must be sold at the same
entry fee, p. It is easily seen that an individual will buy a scheme iff
atðxÞZp:
ð15Þ
4.2.1. Aggregate demand
If Q schemes are to be sold in aggregate then, as previously, the critical income that will create this will be xðQ Þ defined
by Q ¼ 1 F½xðQ Þ, so that x 0 ðQ Þ ¼ 1=f 0 ½xðQ Þ. Consequently, the common entry fee consistent with selling Q schemes in
aggregate is pðQ Þ ¼ atðxðQ ÞÞ. But then, the revenue earned by the scheme developer when Q schemes are sold is
Z
RðQ Þ ¼ ð1 yÞQ atðxðQ ÞÞ þ y ðQ Þb atðxÞf ðxÞ dx;
ð16Þ
x
and thus, the marginal revenue is
R0 ðQ Þ ¼ ð1 yÞatðxðQ ÞÞ
¼ atðxðQ ÞÞ
ð1 yÞat0 ðxðQ ÞÞ
þ yatðxðQ ÞÞ
f ½xðQ Þ
ð1 yÞat0 ðxðQ ÞÞ
:
f ½xðQ Þ
ð17Þ
ð18Þ
19
Thus, sellers share with buyers both the gains from the schemes when they are successful and the losses when unsuccessful. That is, there is full
risk sharing.
20
See Chander and Wilde (1992) and Hindriks et al. (1999).
ARTICLE IN PRESS
606
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
4.2.2. Firm behaviour
As previously, the first-order condition for the revenue maximisation problem (18) is equivalent to the first-order
condition of the problem
xe ¼ maxðargmax HðxÞÞ;
ð19Þ
where we define
HðxÞ ¼ ½atðxÞ1y ½1 FðxÞ;
which is exactly the same as (13) except that the concentration parameter w is replaced by the bargaining strength
parameter 1 y. We then have the following result, which is just a re-interpretation of Proposition 4.
Proposition 13. If the bargaining power of sellers increases, so will the proportion of non-compliant taxpayers.
However, there are reasons to believe that there is a significant market of tax evasion and avoidance schemes, where
suppliers have a negligible bargaining power even in the absence of competition. In many cases, the value of the bribes paid
to obtain tax exemption is significantly lower than the associated cost for the government budget. For example, in New
York, according to the Gotham Gazette (2002), some 18 current and former city tax assessors accepted millions of dollars in
bribes to improperly reduce the tax rates on at least 500 properties. Corruption costs the city as much as $1 billion. The
differences between the value of bribes and the amount of taxes not paid as a result are so huge that it may be difficult to
assume any kind of bargaining.21
5. Concluding remarks
In this paper, we have modelled the tax advice industry which adjusts the supply of tax reduction schemes in response
to changes in aggregate demand. Within this model, we have shown how levels of compliance respond to a number of
factors including the progressivity of the tax schedule and the distribution of taxable income. We have shown that it is
extremely important to take this endogenous supply into account since it produces conclusions that run counter to much of
the existing literature, but can also help explain phenomena that are otherwise hard to explain with existing models. For
example, we have argued that a reduction in inequality or a decrease in tax progressiveness may result in a fall of the share
of compliant taxpayers. Further, we have provided arguments against the reduction in the highest marginal tax rate as a
policy directed at improving tax discipline.
We have also shown that when the government is reluctant to impose a more progressive tax code, it can still make tax
evasion demand less equally distributed by designing a proper audit and punishment function. Finally, we have shown that
our results are robust to the assumption on market structure, since they have been proved for Cournot game quantity
competition with conjectural variation and a bargaining model with a reserve price.
A significant limitation of the model is the assumption that there is just one type of tax scheme. Ulph (2009) extends the
model to the case with many tax schemes ranging from tax planning through tax avoidance to tax evasion, each with very
different risk profiles and expected payoffs. However, in his model, there is perfect competition so prices are exogenous and
determined by costs.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank Charles Nolan, John Beath, Jim Jin, the editor and two anonymous referees for helpful comments
and suggestions. Tatiana Damjanovic gratefully acknowledges financial support from the May Wong Smith Foundation.
Appendix A. Proof of Proposition 2
~
Proposition 2. Suppose HðxÞ
¼ HðxÞgðxÞ where HðxÞ and gðxÞ are positive, differentiable and g 0 ðxÞ40. Suppose
~
x e ¼ argmax HðxÞ; x~ e ¼ argmax HðxÞ.
Then x~ e 4x e .
Proof. Let us assume the contrary, x~ e ox e . Since gðxÞ is a strictly increasing function, it follows that
gðx e Þ4gðx~ e Þ:
ð20Þ
~
and therefore
By definition, x~ e ¼ argmax HðxÞ
~ e Þ:
~ x~ e Þ4Hðx
Hð
ð21Þ
~ e Þ=gðx e Þ, which is exactly as Hðx~ e Þ4Hðx e Þ, which is a contradiction since,
~ x~ e Þ=gðx~ e Þ4Hðx
Inequalities (20) and (21) imply Hð
21
Another potential illustration might be the Landfill tax scandal in the UK. According to The Guardian (2000), a government appointed regulator,
which polices the probity of È 280 m in tax credits given to thousands of UK environmental bodies, paid its directors over È 100,000 in fees for two years
without authorisation.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
T. Damjanovic, D. Ulph / European Economic Review 54 (2010) 594–607
607
by definition, x e ¼ argmax HðxÞ. So the assumption is incorrect and x~ e Zx e . The equality is not possible either. Let x~ e ¼ x e .
~ 0 ðx e Þ ¼ H0 ðx e Þgðx e Þ þ Hðx e Þg 0 ðx e Þ ¼ Hðx e Þg 0 ðx e Þ40. &
~ 0 ðx e Þ shall be equal to zero. However, H
Then, H
References
Anderson, F.J., 1977. Market performance and conjectural variation. Southern Economic Journal 42, 173–178.
Anderson, S.P., Régis, R., 2003. Efficiency and surplus bounds in Cournot competition. Journal of Economic Theory 113, 253–264.
Andreoni, J., Erard, B., Feinstein, J., 1998. Tax compliance. Journal of Economic Literature XXXVI, 818–860.
Appelbaum, E., 1979. Testing price-taking behaviour. Journal of Econometric 9, 283–294.
Agell, J., Persson, M., 2000. Tax arbitrage and labor supply. Journal of Public Economics 78, 3–24.
Åslund, A., 1999. Why has Russia’s economic transformation been so arduous? CERN WEB NOTE #9.
Atkinson, A.B., 1970. On the measurement of inequality. Journal of Economic Theory 2, 244–263.
Atkinson, A.B., Bourguignon, F., 1990. The design of direct taxation and family benefits. Journal of Public Economics 41 (1), 3–29.
Bassetto, M., Phelan, C., 2008. Tax riots. Review of Economic Studies 75 (3), 649–669.
Borck, R., 2007. Voting, inequality and redistribution. Journal of Economic Surveys 21, 90–109.
Bowley, A., 1924. The mathematical groundwork of economics. Oxford University Press.
Bresnahan, T., 1981. Duopoly models with consistent conjectures. American Economic Review 71, 934–945.
Le Breton, M., Moyes, P., Trannoy, A., 1996. Inequality reducing properties of composite taxation. Journal of Economic Theory 69, 71–103.
Chander, P., Wilde, L., 1992. Corruption in tax administration. Journal of Public Economics 49, 333–349.
Coes, D.V., 1977. Firm output and charges in uncertainty. The American Economic Review 67 (2), 249–251.
Cowell, F.A., 1992. Tax evasion and inequality. Journal of Economic Psychology 13, 521–542.
Damjanovic, T., 2001. The distributional component of the price for the tax avoidance service. Stockholm School of Economics Working Paper
No. 454.
Damjanovic, T., 2005. Lorenz dominance for transformed income distributions: a simple proof. Mathematical Social Sciences 50 (2), 234–237.
Desai, M.A., 2005. The degradation of reported corporate profits. The Journal of Economic Perspective 19, 171–192.
Desai, M.A., Foley, F.C., James Jr., R.H., 2006. The demand for tax haven operations. Journal of Public Economics 90, 513–531.
Erard, B., 1993. Taxation with representation: an analysis of the role of tax practitioners in tax compliance. Journal of Public Economics 52, 163–197.
Feinstein, J.S., 1991. An econometric analysis of income tax evasion and its detection. Rand Journal of Economics 22, 14–35.
Feldstein, M., 1999. Tax avoidance and the deadweight loss of the income tax. Review of Economics & Statistics 81 (4), 674.
Financial Times, 2004. Shelters in the path of the shifting tax storm, by Amity Shlaes, May 10.
Gotham Gazette, 2002. Real property tax scandal, by Scott Stringer, April 15.
Gordon, J.P.F., 1989. Individual morality and reputation costs as deterrents to tax evasion. European Economic Review 33, 797–805.
Gurvitch, E., 2002. Taxes decrease but tax avoidance increases, an interview to Komsomolskaja pravda (in Russian).
The Guardian, 2000. Landfill regulator under fees cloud, by David Hencke, August 21.
HM Revenue and Customs, 2007. Measuring indirect tax losses.
Hindriks, J., Keen, M., Muthoo, A., 1999. Corruption, extortion and evasion. Journal of Public Economics 74, 395–430.
Internal Revenue Service, 2009. Abusive offshore tax avoidance schemes.
Internal Revenue Service, 2007. Reducing the federal tax gap: a report on improving voluntary compliance. IR-2007-137, August 2.
Iwata, G., 1974. Measurement of conjectural variations in oligopoly. Econometrica 42 (5), 947–966.
Jakobsson, U., 1976. On the measurement of the degree of progression. Journal of Public Economics 5, 161–168.
Just, R., Chern, W., 1980. Tomatoes, technology and oligopsony. Bell Journal of Economics 11 (2), 584–602.
Kakwani, N.C., 1977. Applications of Lorenz curves in economic analysis. Econometrica 45 (3), 719–727.
Kamien, M.I., Schwartz, N.L., 1983. Conjectural variations. Canadian, Journal of Economics 16 (2), 191–211.
Keen, M., Papapanagos, H., Shorrocks, A., 2000. Tax reform and progressivity. Economic Journal 110, 50–69.
Kim, Y., 2003. Income distribution and equilibrium multiplicity in a stigma-based model of tax evasion. Journal of Public Economics 87, 1591–1616.
Kolstad, C.D., Wolak, F.A., 1986. Conjectural variation and the indeterminacy of duopolistic equilibria. Canadian Journal of Economics 19 (4), 656–677.
Laitner, J., 1980. ‘‘Rational’’ duopoly equilibria. Quarterly Journal of Economics 95 641-62.R.
Lang, O., Nohrbas, K.-H., Stahl, K., 1997. On income tax avoidance: the case of Germany. Journal of Public Economics 66 (2), 327–347.
Muller, A., Dietrich, S., 2002. Comparison Methods for Stochastic Models and Risks. Wiley Series in Probability and Statistics.
Myles, G.D., Naylor, R.A., 1996. A model of tax evasion with group conformity and social customs. European Journal of Political Economy 12 (1),
49–66.
Reinganum, J., Wilde, L.L., 1986. Equilibrium verification and reporting policies in a model of tax compliance. International Economic Review 27 (3),
739–760.
Robson, A., 1983. Existence of consistent conjectures: comments. American Economic Review 73 (3), 454–456.
Roine, J., 2006. The political economics of not paying taxes. Public Choice 126 (1), 107–134.
Sandmo, A., 1971. On the theory of the competitive firm under price uncertainty. American Economic Review 61, 65–73.
Shleifer, A., Vishny, R.W., 1993. Corruption. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 108 (3), 599–617.
Slemrod, J., 2004. The economics of corporate tax selfishness. NBER Working Paper No. 10858.
Tanzi, V., Zee, H.H., 2000. Tax Policy for emerging markets: developing countries. National Tax Journal 53 (2), 299–328.
Torgler, B., 2005. Tax morale in Latin America. Public Choice 122, 133–157.
Ulph, D., 1983. Rational conjectures in theory of oligopoly. International Journal of Industrial Organization 1, 131–154.
Ulph, D., 2009. Avoidance policies—a new conceptual framework. CRIEFF Discussion Papers 0908.
Une, M., Saijo, T., 1995. On the definition of favorableness. Economics Letters 47 (1), 109–110.
Wang, R., 1995. Bargaining versus posted-price selling. European Economic Review 39, 1747–1764.
Yitzhaki, S., 1974. A note on ‘Income tax evasion: a theoretical analysis’. Journal of Public Economics 3, 201–202.