236
TELOS
necessary to do more than merely report that Croce's philosophy is now generally
discarded, and that Gramsci's ideas are widely accepted.
Nemeth's and Jacobitti's works are useful contributions. This usefulness is, however,
rather limited since the leitmotif which Nemeth chooses to extract from Gramsci —
phenomenological first philosophy — seems only marginal for the problem of
intellectual and moral reform of popular culture. On the other hand, the leitmotif
that Jacobitti emphasizes in Croce is the detached contemplativism of his avoidance of
one-sidedness (pp. 142, 145). There is little question that this is a feature of Croce's
approach (as well as a problematic one). But since Jacobitti does not suggest any more
promising alternative, even if Croce's philosophy is a failure, that would not prevent it
from being the best available one. Second, given that the motivating problem is that of
intellectual and moral reform of popular culture, it is not clear that Croce's alleged
detachment is inappropriate or ineffective. Here one should recall one of his slogans to
which Jacobitti does not pay sufficient attention: theoretical activity prepares but does
not determine action.
Maurice A. Finocchiaro
Frank Sulloway. Freud, Biologist of the Mind. New York: Basic Books, 1979.
612 pages.
A Harvard-trained historian of science, Sulloway has written a new biographical
study of Freud. It is an important book that explores the origins of Freud's thought in
19th-century evolutionary biology. Sulloway's work is based on a very wide reading of
source material and its publication has occasioned considerable critical acclaim. The
author claims to have produced "a comprehensive intellectual biography of Sigmund
Freud" and "an entirely new historical interpretation." What he has actually produced
is far less than he claims and far more than he would admit. Less, because he
exhaustively catalogues one aspect of Freud's thought and tries to make it stand for the
whole. But more, because he has produced a kind of empiricist propaganda
attempting to justify the claims of sociology (and implicitly the medical model of
psychiatry) at the expense of all other approaches.
Sulloway's thesis is clear and straightforward: Freud was essentially a
crypto-biologist who attempted to obscure the biological underpinnings of his theory
in part by claiming that psychoanalysis was a "pure psychology" arising ineluctably
from purely clinical data. Sulloway claims that subsequent Freud scholarship has
promoted the myth that psychoanalysis arose out of the sheer creative genius of its
founder. According to this myth, psychoanalysis was born not in the scientific
tradition but ex nihilo partly as a result of Freud's famous self analysis. Sulloway
claims to have uncovered no less than 26 similar myths and he attempts to present a
systematic refutation of each. These myths have presumably annihilated the
prehistory of psychoanalysis and legitimated its particular claims to originality. He
claims that his work is the first to have explained psychoanalysis in terms of the
sociology of knowledge.
Sulloway sees himself as a revisionist historian representing a minority viewpoint. In
his view, orthodox Freud scholarship, including the work of Ernest Jones and Ernst
Kris, is intent on maintaining the Freud legend to establish its claims that
psychoanalysis is a "pure psychology." Sulloway's Freud is, in contrast, a biologist of
the mind, a scientist bent on extending Darwinian evolutionary theory to new areas.
REVIEWS
237
In the first place, this is a false dichotomy since "pure psychology" is not a term that
adequately describes Freud's understanding of his project, nor have his followers in the
psychoanalytic tradition attempted to deny Freud's abiding interest in evolutionary
biology. Sulloway's dichotomy is particularly puzzling since he himself quotes Ernest
Jones as having said that "the creation of psychoanalysis signifies a contribution to
biology comparable in importance only with Darwin's" (pp. 4-5). In fact, the
insistence of Freud (and his loyal followers) on the importance of libido theory
understood as a biologically immutable fact of human existence was the major source
of disagreement within the psychoanalytic movement and led eventually to the rift
between Freud and Jung, Adler, and, later, the so-called ego psychologists. It has been
one of the most pervasive accusations brought against Freud by his critics, including
Jung and Adler, that he was overly biological in his discussion of libidinal sexual and
aggressive energy. Sulloway's effort to understand the rift solely in terms of differing
biological assumptions is therefore patently ridiculous.
Another problem is Sulloway's consistent refusal to recognize that there were at least
two aspects to Freud's work: his concern to represent a fully elaborated theory of the
mind and his effort to develop a technique of treating neurotic patients. It may well be
that many of the early psychoanalytic practitioners tended to idealize Freud and to
overestimate his originality but this phenomenon has been exhaustively — even
obsessively — documented by Paul Roazen in Freud and his Followers (1971) and
others. Indeed, Sulloway seems almost ignorant of psychoanalysis as a technique of
treatment, and focuses exclusively instead on Freud's theory of mental functioning,
which he insists on confining to evolutionary biology. As a result, several important
and original aspects of Freud's thought are overlooked, including the existence of the
unconscious and Freud's keen understanding of the limits of instrumental reason as a
guide of human action.
Yet, there is a point here. In his single-minded and often absurd reductionism,
Sulloway does provide some sobering documentation of the family resemblances
between Freud's work and that of contemporary biologists. In so doing he shows just
how great was Freud's debt to biology and how seriously he worked to maintain that
connection throughout his career. In this regard, Sulloway provides many persuasive
examples of major misconceptions regarding the origins of Freud's work. A few
examples will suffice.
It is commonly believed that Joseph Breuer broke off his famous analysis of Anna O.
(Bertha Pappenheim) and terminated his relationship with Freud because of his
inability to accept the sexual etiology of hysteria. Not so, says Sulloway. Breuer was
fully aware of the importance of sexuality and the real reason for Freud's break with
him had to do with Freud's "fanatical" claim that sexuality was the cause of every
hysteria and most other neuroses as well. Nor for that matter is it true, as Freud
claimed in his autobiography, that his insistence on the existence of male hysteria was
rudely rejected by his colleagues in Vienna and marked the beginning of his near
complete isolation from the scientific establishment.
It is commonly believed that Freud abandoned his Project for a Scientific
Psychology (1895) shortly after it had been written because he realized the
impossibility of constructing his new psychology on a purely scientific basis. What
Freud abandoned, says Sulloway, was the idea of a purely neurophysiological
psychology,but that he never abandoned the project and indeed resurrected it in a new
form on the bedrock of evolutionary biology. Sulloway insists that Darwinian biology
in general and the work of Ernst Haeckel in particular was a major influence, perhaps
238
TELOS
the major influence on Freud's mature thought. While this may be an overstatement,
Sulloway shows that Haeckel's ideas (particularly the notion that ontogeny capitulates
philogeny; that the development of a single embryo from conception to maturity
mirrors the entire evolutionary development of the species) were a unifying theme in
Freud's thought — a theme he never abandoned. To take but one example, the
Oedipus complex as an ontogenetic event was seen by Freud as having a philogenetic
complement in real events in human prehistory. The wish to murder one's father,
which every male child experiences symbolically, was an actual prehistoric event in
which bands of brothers conspired to murder the patriarchal father.
The pervasive influence of Haeckel's ideas on Freud's thought has never been as
thoroughly documented as in Sulloway's work. Whether the concept that ontogeny
capitulates philogeny had for Freud the status of a scientific law or was merely a
central organizing metaphor is, however, another matter.
Another famous piece of psychoanalytic lore concerns Freud's relationship to
Wilhelm Fliess. According to the tradition, says Sulloway, Fliess was something of a
numerological mystic whose contributions to science were marginal at best and whose
chief importance to Freud was as a source of emotional support during the period of
Freud's self-analysis. Sulloway buys none of this. In the first place, he claims Fliess was
by no means the crackpot he has been made out to be. Indeed, Fliess had a fully
developed theory of infantile sexuality including recognition of the sexually gratifying
character of oral and anal zones. Secondly, Fliess had independently arrived at the
theory that libido develops in periodic thrusts of sexuality interrupted by a latency
period. In addition, Fliess had a sophisticated notion of bisexuality which included the
idea that neurotics often suffer from unconscious homosexual impulses — an idea that
Freud reformulated in the notion that neuroses are the opposite of perversions. In
these and many other instances, Sulloway documents Freud's debt to Fliess and he
claims that Freud eventually broke with his colleague precisely because of his great
unacknowledged debt. It was because of Freud's "obsessional need for intellectual
immortality" and neurotic concerns for scientific precedence and originality and not a
rejection of Fliess' theory of periodicity which led to a break between the two.
Nor was Freud's emphasis on sexuality particularly original or indeed all that
shocking to 19th-century scientific circles. Indeed, says Sulloway, sexology had
become a respectable area of scientific inquiry and had been the subject of
comprehensive study by Krafft-Ebing, Havelock Ellis, Albert Moll and many others.
Fully 300 pages of the book are devoted to a meticulous study of scientific antecedents
to Freud's theory and the result, in spite of its reductionism, is a book that
demonstrates the full measure of Freud's debt to evolutionary biology.
Recognizing the importance of biology in Freud's thought is a blow to those who,
following Marcuse and others, have sought to interpret psychoanalysis as a critical
theory of politics and society. If Freud is to be interpreted exclusively as a
socio-biologist then the socially necessary repression which Freud discussed in his later
work remains as immutable as evolution itself and therefore changes in the social order
could be expected to occur over milennia and not, as Marcuse believed, within the
course of a lifetime. In this respect, Sulloway's work is like a cold shower, dampening,
if not extinguishing, the left's enthusiasm for Freud. While a cold shower may be
useful for temporarily diminishing desires, we will argue that the interpretive impulse
springs libidinally eternal.
Sulloway's Freud is but one partial understanding of Freud and his intellectual
heritage. There have been and will be others. David Bakan, for example, in Sigmund
REVIEWS
239
Freud and the Jewish Mystical Tradition (1958), has disclosed a surprising family
resemblance between Freud's work and Jewish mysticism. One could explore Freud's
debt to ancient Greek thought. While Freud's constant reference to Greek mythology
and Platonic thought has been widely discussed, it has never been adequately
explained. Nor has the resemblance between Freud's thought and 19th-century
German philosophy been fully explored. This is particularly true with respect to
Hegel, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche.
We might conclude that a "comprehensive" understanding of Freud or, for that
matter, of any intellectual figure, is simply not possible and that what we have instead
are particular interpretations always tied to concrete social and political interests.
Recall Freud's own thoughts on the subject: "Anyone turning biographer commits
himself to lies, to concealment, to hypocrisy, to flattery, and even to hiding his own
lack of understanding, for biographical truth is not to be had, and even if it were it
couldn't be used" (Letters, 1960, p. 430). In this sense, then, there is and can be no
such thing as a comprehensive biography; only interpretation, and any act of
interpretation can never be separated from concrete personal, social and political
interest.
What is finally at issue in the perennial struggle for the definitive interpretation of
Freud is the familiar competing interests represented by empiricist and dialectic
modes of understanding. While Sulloway clearly represents empiricist interests, his
work presents a useful and necessary criticism of the work of Marcuse and others.
Clearly Freud took science in general and evolutionary biology in particular very
seriously. Perhaps Marcuse erred in not taking seriously enough the complexity and
revolutionary importance of Freud's early discoveries and may have focused his
analysis too heavily on Freud's later speculative essays.
It can be argued that Freud's originality lay not in his discovery of the unconscious,
nor in his formulation of the antagonism between civilization and individual desire,
but in his discovery that the unconscious speaks and that it has a structure. Among
other things, Freud, with Hegel, recognized that the understanding subject
participates in the creation of its own object, that there is no simple separation
between the thinking subject and its object, as the empiricists would have it. In fact,
Freud's originality lies in his discovery of an entirely new mode of reflexivity, which
Jacques Lacan likens to the Copernican revolution. Just as Copernicus demonstrated
that the Earth is not the center of the universe, so Freud demonstrated that the
individual ego is not master in its own house.
From this viewpoint, the central issue in interpreting Freud's thought is not the
opposition between psychoanalysis and science but between an empiricist and a
dialectic conception of science. The social and political implications of this dichotomy
are clear enough. The empiricist tradition that Sulloway represents is a repressive one
whose function, as Foucault shows in Madness and Civilization, is to isolate the
experience of madness from human discourse in the triumph of instrumental reason
and capital accumulation. A dialectic conception of science, on the other hand,
proceeds historically through the explication of contradiction and, in so doing, offers
the possibility of a dialogue with madness.
Which of these two positions most clearly resembles Freud's own is, of course, a
matter of interpretation. It is important to recall, however, that Freud's model of the
mind, his theory of mental illness, and his method of treatment are all based on a
conception of conflict in which the warring parties are always dialectically related.
Secondly, Freud's account of mental illness as well as his model of the mind are
240
TELOS
historical conceptions unfolding through the ontogenetic development of the
individual and the philogenetic development of the species. The distinction between
dialectic and empiricist interpretations of Freud is a distinction from which concrete
political and social conclusions inextricably follow. In therapy, for example, an
empiricist sees a symptom to be categorized with nosological precision. As a result,
therapist and patient are forever isolated from each other, and psychoactive drugs
become necessarily the treatment of choice. A dialectic understanding, on the other
hand, poses the possibility of dialogue between therapist and patient and offers for the
patient the liberating possibility of freely choosing to give up the symptom. One
method is necessarily repressive, the other at least potentially liberating.
From the viewpoint of critical theory, it is relatively easy to understand the
necessarily repressive nature of a sociobiological reading of Freud. But, as Marcuse's
work demonstrates, a dialectic analysis is no panacea either. If nothing else, Sulloway's
book helps us to understand that Marcuse's optimistic and often extravagant claims
concerning the malleability of human nature were in part based on his overemphasis
on Freud's later speculative essays.
Thus if psychoanalysis is to be interpreted as both a clinical theory of treatment and
a critical theory of politics and society, Freud's early work and particularly his relation
to 19th-century biology must be taken seriously. Freud's later essays applying
psychoanalysis to social questions should therefore be understood as frankly
speculative, profoundly suggestive, but not necessarily definitive. Therefore, to
understand the critical content of Freud's work it is necessary to begin with what is
essential; the theory of the unconscious and the technique of treatment, and to
elaborate that theory.
As for Sulloway, his work in itself would hardly merit serious consideration if it did
not represent the voice of authority and an officially acceptable definition of the
limitations of the possible. There is, however, something particularly galling about an
orthodoxy that presents itself in the guise of radical revisionism. As a contribution to
the sociology of knowledge Sulloway's work fails by virtue of its claim to scientific
disinterestedness when in fact it is very much interested in the maintenance of the
status quo and the medical and behavioral models of mental illness. Its positive value
is that it helps us recognize that the romantic view which regarded Freud's self-analysis
as an inaugural event in world history was more correct than even Freud's most
orthodox followers understood.
Larry Fuchser
International
Journal of Politics
A Quarterly Journal of Translations
T e 1„9 7 t
ESS3
individuals: $37
Editor: Arnold C. Tovell, M. E. Sharpe, Inc.
Provides translations of material that has appeared in scholarly journals,
books, and legal documents throughout the world.
cTW-E-Sharpe inc.
80 Business Park Drive.
ArmonK. New York 10504