Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
Thomas Fuchs
Pathologies of
Intersubjectivity in
Autism and Schizophrenia
Abstract: Most mental disorders include more or less profound disturbances of intersubjectivity, that means, a restricted capacity to
respond to the social environment in a flexible way and to reach a
shared understanding through adequate interaction with others. Current concepts of intersubjectivity are mainly based on a mentalistic
approach, assuming that the hidden mental states of others may only
be inferred from their external bodily behaviour through ‘mentalizing’
or ‘mindreading’. On this basis, disorders of intersubjectivity for
example in autism or schizophrenia are attributed to a dysfunction of
Theory of Mind modules. From a phenomenological point of view,
however, intersubjectivity is primarily based on a pre-reflective
embodied relationship of self and other in an emergent bipersonal
field. Instead of a theory deficit, autistic and schizophrenic patients
rather suffer from a basic disturbance of being-with-others which
they try to compensate by explicit inferences and hypothetical
assumptions about others. The paper consequently distinguishes
three levels of intersubjectivity: (a) primary intersubjectivity or
intercorporeality, (b) secondary intersubjectivity or perspective-taking, and (c) tertiary intersubjectivity, implying a self–other metaperspective. On this basis, disturbances on these different levels in
autism and schizophrenia are described.
Correspondence:
Prof. Thomas Fuchs, MD, PhD, Karl Jaspers Professor of Philosophy and Psychiatry, Psychiatric Department, University of Heidelberg, Voss-Str.4, D-69115 Heidelberg, Germany. Email:
[email protected]
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22, No. 1–2, 2015, pp. 191–214
192
T. FUCHS
Keywords: intersubjectivity; intercorporeality; autism; schizophrenia; transitivism; delusion.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
1. Introduction
The currently predominant psychiatric paradigm is based on a conception of the patient as an enclosed individual with a clearly defined
brain dysfunction. In contrast, from a phenomenological point of
view, mental illness may not be located in the individual patient, let
alone in his brain, but always includes his relations and interactions
with others. Indeed most mental disorders imply more or less profound disturbances of intersubjectivity, that means, a restricted capacity to respond to the social environment in a flexible way and to reach
a shared understanding through adequate interaction with others.
However, the concepts of intersubjectivity currently prevailing in
psychology and psychiatry are mainly based on a mentalistic
approach: they assume a fundamental strangeness and inaccessibility
of the other whose hidden mental states, thoughts, or feelings may
only be indirectly inferred from his external bodily behaviour. This
happens in the mind of the observer by using a ‘Theory of Mind’
(ToM), ‘mentalizing’, or ‘mindreading’ procedure which allows them
to explain and predict the other’s behaviour (Carruthers, 1996;
Goldman, 2012). Neither direct perception of bodily expressions nor
the embodied interaction between social agents are assumed to play a
founding role for social cognition. On this basis, disorders of intersubjectivity for example in autism or schizophrenia are consequently
attributed to a faulty development or dysfunction of ToM modules in
the brain (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Bora et al., 2009).
In contrast, phenomenological approaches regard intersubjectivity
as being based on a pre-reflective embodied relationship of self and
other in an emergent bipersonal field. Face-to-face interactions in
shared contexts play a major and often even constitutive role for social
understanding (De Jaegher and Di Paolo, 2007; Fuchs and De
Jaegher, 2009; Gallagher, 2012). This primary intersubjectivity, based
on ‘intercorporeality’ (Merleau-Ponty, 1960) and interaction, should
be distinguished from higher levels of intersubjectivity, which include
aspects of perspective-taking, inference (‘mindreading’), or imaginary transposition (‘putting oneself in another’s shoes’). Thus, the
phenomenological approach would not deny that mindreading occurs
in rare cases, for example when we are confronted with a puzzling
behaviour. However, whether such mindreading skills are based on a
ToM mechanism or rather on a communicative and narrative practice
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
193
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
of understanding typical human behaviours is an open debate
(Gallagher, 2012; Gallagher and Hutto, 2008).1 In any case, embodied
and enactive approaches suggest a different conception of intersubjective disturbances in psychopathology: What autistic and schizophrenic patients primarily suffer from is not a theory of mind deficit
but rather a disturbance of bodily being-with-others and social attunement which they try to compensate by hypothetical constructs and
assumptions about others. As we will see, disturbances arise on the
higher level of intersubjectivity too, but they are based on the primary
disturbances of embodied interaction and attunement.
In what follows, I will first present a three-level concept of intersubjectivity; on this basis, I will describe some major pathologies of
intersubjectivity, taking autism and schizophrenia as paradigm
conditions.
2. Three Levels of Intersubjectivity
(a) Primary intersubjectivity
Primary intersubjectivity (Trevarthen, 1979) develops in the first year
of life. Imitation of facial expressions starts from birth on, that means,
newborns are already able to transpose the seen facial expressions of
others into their own proprioception and movement (Meltzoff and
Moore, 1977), thus gaining a basic sense of familiarity with others.
Being affected by each other’s expressive behaviour results in shared
states of bodily feelings and affects. Moreover, already during the first
months familiar patterns of interaction and affect attunement are
stored in the infant’s implicit or procedural memory as interactive
schemas (‘schemes of being-with’, Stern, 1985). For example,
through interacting with their caregivers, babies soon learn how to
share pleasure, elicit attention, avoid overstimulation, re-establish
contact, etc. Thus, long before the age of four, the supposed age for
acquiring a ToM (or for a presumed ToM module to become functional), the infant already acquires a primary understanding of others
through shared practices.
This is the basis of empathy in face-to-face encounters: in embodied and empathic interaction, the other is not assumed to be ‘behind’
[1]
Many ToM theorists have argued that the alleged inferences are not necessarily introspectively accessible, but remain tacit or sub-personal (Gopnik and Wellman, 1995, p. 250;
Carruthers, 2009, p. 121; Spaulding, 2010). This issue cannot be dealt with here; for a critical discussion of this claim see Gallagher (2012). It does not seem very plausible, to say
the least, that the main empirical evidence for a sub-personal ToM mechanism to exist is
based on various false-belief tasks — tasks which are certainly explicit, conscious, and
even narrative ways of inferring another’s mental state.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
194
T. FUCHS
his action, but he enacts and expresses his intentions in his conduct. In
seeing his expressive movements and actions as embedded in their
specific context, ‘…one already sees their meaning. No inference to a
hidden set of mental states is necessary’ (Gallagher and Zahavi, 2008,
p. 185). Moreover, in social interaction, one’s own body is affected by
the other in various forms of bodily resonance, leading to what may be
called ‘mutual incorporation’ (Fuchs and De Jaegher, 2009). Thus,
phenomenology denies the principal divide between the other’s mind
and body assumed by current theories of social cognition. Bodily
behaviour is expressive, intentional, and meaningful within its context, and as such it is beyond the artificial distinction of internal and
external. It constitutes a sphere of primary intercorporeality as the
basis for all forms of intersubjectivity.
(b) Secondary intersubjectivity
Around the age of one year, infants increasingly go beyond the mutual
resonance of intercorporeality and begin to refer to the shared context
explicitly, namely by joint attention, gaze-following, and pointing. By
noticing how others interact with the world, they learn the usage and
meaning that objects have for them, and they recognize others’ goals
and intentions in uncompleted actions (Baldwin and Baird, 2001;
Meltzoff and Brooks, 2001). Thus, the dyadic interaction opens up
towards objects in the surrounding field, leading to a triadic structure.
Through this ‘secondary intersubjectivity’ (Trevarthen and Hubley,
1978), infants begin to perceive others as intentional agents whose
actions and mutual interactions are purposeful in pragmatic contexts.
In the course of cooperative actions, they also experience themselves
as being perceived as intentional agents by others, in a common social
space that gradually assumes a symbolic structure.
Symbolic interaction is already present in pointing and cooperative
action, but reaches its crucial stage in language. Verbal narratives
then become the presupposition for more sophisticated modes of
understanding which develop in the third and fourth year of life. By
engaging in storytelling practices, children learn to understand others
in a meaningful way, to imagine their goals and intentions as underlying a certain course of actions (Gallagher and Hutto, 2008). Narrative
competency supports the development of the capacities of taking the
other’s perspective, of pretend playing and role-taking, and, finally,
for certain predictive capacities that underlie the typical ToM tasks
(Fuchs, 2013). These capacities are only fully developed on the next
level.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
195
(c) Tertiary intersubjectivity
Whereas infants begin to perceive others as intentional agents in joint
attention situations from around 9–12 months of age, it is not before
4–5 years of age that they become aware of others as mental agents
with thoughts and beliefs that may differ from their own and also differ from reality (Tomasello, 1999). This ‘mentalizing’ capacity is
tested in the typical false-belief tests like the Sally-Ann task. Understanding conflicting perspectives of self and other implies the capacity to flexibly shift between them, and to be aware of both
perspectives at the same time. This integration of both perspectives is
only possible from a self–other metaperspective (Laing et al., 1966)
which is the hallmark of what may be termed tertiary intersubjectivity
(Fuchs, 2013). Interpersonal perception in its full sense is thus based
on the ability to freely oscillate between an ego-centric, embodied
perspective on the one hand, and an allo-centric or decentred perspective on the other, without thereby losing one’s bodily centre of selfawareness. This decisive step of human cognitive development may
also be summarized as reaching the ‘excentric position’ (Plessner,
1981) — a third or higher-level stance from which the integration of
an ego- and allocentric point of view is possible. It means to become
aware of others as being aware of oneself as being aware of them.
These briefly presented distinctions will now aid us in understanding
pathologies of intersubjectivity in autism and in schizophrenia.
3. Disturbances of Primary Intersubjectivity in Autism
As a paradigmatic disorder of intersubjectivity, autism has become a
major topic of research in phenomenology as well as in cognitive neuroscience. The present conceptualizations of the disorder are still
dominated by a cognitive and modular approach, assuming a faulty
development of ToM modules that leads to a disturbed capacity to
attribute mental states to others (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Frith, 1989). In
recent years, however, criticism has been raised by phenomenological
psychiatrists and philosophers (Hobson, 1993; 2002; Gallagher,
2004; De Jaegher, 2013), arguing that the deficit is rather caused by
failures of early interaction and interaffectivity. This is supported by
the fact that many autistic symptoms such as lack of interest in living
beings or social stimuli, reduced emotional resonance, lacking imitation, anxiety, or agitation are already present in the first and second
year of life, that means, long before the supposed age to acquire a ToM
(Klin et al., 1992; Dawson et al., 1998; Hobson and Lee, 1999; Zahavi
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
196
T. FUCHS
and Parnas, 2003). Even when an innate ToM module is assumed, its
disturbance or failure is not suitable to explain those symptoms of
lacking bodily resonance, for the latter does not require any mentalizing capacity whatsoever. Moreover, between 15 and 60% of autistic individuals at a later age are able to pass false-belief tests
successfully, pointing out that the disorder can hardly be only due to a
lack of a ToM (Reed and Paterson, 1990).
From a phenomenological approach, autism should rather be conceived as a disorder of primary or embodied intersubjectivity. This
includes basic disturbances of embodiment found in children with
autism, namely of (a) sensory-motor integration, (b) imitation and
affect attunement, and (c) holistic perception, impairing in particular
the children’s perception and understanding of others’ expressions.
As a result, the later development of higher-order capacities such as
perspective-taking and language acquisition is compromised as well.
(a) There is evidence that autistic children show a variety of basic
sensory-motor abnormalities at the neurological level (Mari et
al., 2003; Fournier et al., 2010). In studies of videotapes, such
abnormalities could be found as early as the first year of life in
children who were later diagnosed as autistic (Teitelbaum et al.,
1998), for example problems in righting, sitting, crawling, and
walking, or other abnormal motor patterns. This points to a deficient integration of visual, kinaesthetic, vestibular, and tactile
sensations into a common experiential space (Gepner and
Mestre, 2002). Infant research has shown that early dyadic interactions are particularly based on the integration of sensory,
motor, and affective experience, allowing for affect attunement
via corresponding rhythmic and dynamic shapes in different
sensorimotor modalities (Stern, 1985). In other words, there is a
close connection between the bodily ‘sensus communis’ (i.e.
intermodal integration) and social attunement or primary ‘common sense’ (Fuchs, 2001). Hence, faulty intermodal integration
may significantly interfere with the development of embodied
social perception in autistic children.
(b) Intermodal integration of perceived movements and one’s own
kinaesthetic sensations plays a particular role for the capacity of
imitation (Meltzoff, 2002), which serves as a major instrument
for early social cognition. Not surprisingly, the literature shows a
consistent finding that children with autism do not readily imitate
the actions of others (Smith and Bryson, 1994; Hobson and Lee,
1999). There is also increasing evidence for mirror neuron
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
197
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
dysfunctions in autism spectrum disorders (Oberman et al.,
2005; Dapretto et al., 2006). Problems with imitation might then
lead to a cascade of impairments in early intercorporeality, affect
attunement, joint attention, pretend play, and, finally, acquisition
of ‘mindreading’ capacities .
(c) Moreover, autistic children show problems in establishing perceptual and situational coherence: they focus on single parts or
elements rather than perceiving the Gestalt of objects, and they
tend to treat things as decontextualized, thus missing their particular meaning provided by the situation as a whole (Frith, 1989;
Happé, 1995). While this failure of holistic cognition may have
some positive effects such as remembering unrelated or nonsensical items, it significantly interferes with the development of
social understanding. Thus, affect attunement is crucially based
on perceiving emotional cues (gestures, facial expression,
voicings) as embedded in recurrent situations. Even more, secondary intersubjectivity depends on learning how to relate gestures and actions of others to the context in order to grasp their
intentions. Correspondingly, eye tracking studies have shown
that autistic children focus on inanimate and irrelevant details of
interactive situations while missing the relevant social cues (Klin
et al., 2003). In other words, the salience of social stimuli is
reduced, because these are particularly bound to the holistic perception of expressive gestures and behaviour.
Although the question of reciprocal interaction between these different mechanisms is as yet far from being solved, it seems most likely
that they converge to a fundamental disturbance of embodied social
perception and interaction very early in life. This disturbance is then
also bound to compromise the later stages of intersubjectivity. For
these are not based on ToM modules that develop separately, but
rather on the primary sensus communis or a sense of ‘being-likeothers’ that is subsequently extended by relating to a shared context
such as in social referencing or joint attention and, finally, by understanding others as mental agents like oneself. However, if the
‘like-me’ experience is already missing in primary bodily encounters,
such that the other’s body remains but an object among others, then
the child will not be able to identify herself with other persons which
would be the presupposition for acquiring the capacity to take their
perspective (Hobson and Lee, 1999). Consequently, the development
198
T. FUCHS
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
of more abstract mentalizing capacities will be seriously retarded or
even remain impossible.
In sum, what autistic children primarily lack is not a theoretical
concept of other minds but a primary sensus communis or a sense of
bodily being-with-others. Strategies of explicit mentalizing and inferring from social cues are rather employed by high-functioning autistic
individuals as a compensation for the lacking capacities of primary
intersubjectivity (Zahavi and Parnas, 2003). Thus, Temple Grandin, a
woman with autism spectrum disorder, described her problems with
interpersonal relations to Oliver Sacks as follows:
It has to do, she has inferred, with an implicit knowledge of social conventions and codes, of cultural presuppositions of every sort. This
implicit knowledge, which every normal person accumulates and generates throughout life on the basis of experience and encounters with
others, Temple seems to be largely devoid of. Lacking it, she has instead
to ‘compute’ others’ intentions and states of mind, to try to make algorithmic, explicit, what for the rest of us is second nature. (Sacks, 1995,
p. 270)
These compensatory strategies enable functional interactions with
others to a certain degree, but fail to establish the primary sense of
being-with-others which is normally provided implicitly by intercorporeality, as a kind of ‘magical communication’:
She is now aware of the existence of these social signals. She can infer
them, she says, but she herself cannot perceive them, cannot participate
in this magical communication directly, or conceive the many-leveled
kaleidoscopic states of mind behind it. Knowing this intellectually, she
does her best to compensate, bringing immense intellectual effort and
computational power to bear on matters that others understand with
unthinking ease. This is why she often feels excluded, an alien. (Ibid., p.
272)
As we can see from Grandin’s report, the bodily sensus communis
cannot be substituted by explicit inference or rule-based knowledge
about others’ behaviour. This will be confirmed when we now look at
disturbances of intersubjectivity in schizophrenia.
4. Disturbances of Primary
Intersubjectivity in Schizophrenia
According to currently dominant theories, schizophrenia, just like
autism, involves some incapacity for meta-awareness, self-monitoring, and theory of mind. Frith (1992) has proposed that schizophrenia
can be explained by impaired meta-representation: a failure of
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
199
monitoring one’s own intentions to think or to act results in symptoms
such as thought-insertion or delusions of alien control. Moreover, the
inability to correctly infer the mental states of others by using a ToM
gives rise to paranoid delusions. A number of experimental studies
have shown that patients with schizophrenia perform badly in typical
ToM tasks (false-belief test; Frith and Corcoran, 1996; Lee et al.,
2004; see Sprong et al., 2007, for a review). However, most of these
studies were conducted with patients when they were acutely ill and
showed positive symptoms such as delusions. Moreover, studies on
real-life interactions could not confirm those results — in normal conversations even delusional patients showed intact ToM skills (Walston
et al., 2000; McCabe et al., 2004; McCabe, 2004). Obviously, the
interpretation of the results depends on how one conceives the role of
narrative and context versus abstract mentalizing abilities in understanding others (Gallagher and Hutto, 2008).
In contrast to meta-representational concepts, recent phenomenological approaches locate the main disorder in schizophrenia on a
lower level, regarding it as a fundamental disturbance of the embodied
self, or a disembodiment. This includes (1) a weakening of the basic
sense of self, (2) a disruption of implicit bodily functioning, and (3) a
disconnection from the intercorporality with others (Fuchs and
Schlimme, 2009). As a result of this disembodiment, the pre-reflective, practical immersion of the self in the world is lost.
A disturbance of the pre-reflective, embodied self must necessarily
impair the patient’s social relationships. For as we saw, it is the lived
body that conveys the practical knowledge of how to interact with others, how to understand their expressions and actions on the background of the shared situation. This tacit or enacted knowledge is also
the basis of ‘common sense’ (Blankenburg, 2001; Fuchs, 2001): it
provides a fluid, automatic, and context-sensitive pre-understanding
of everyday situations, thus connecting self and world through a basic
habituality and familiarity. If this embodied involvement in the world
is disturbed as in schizophrenia, it will result in a fundamental alienation of intersubjectivity: the basic sense of being-with-others is
replaced by a sense of detachment that may pass over into a threatening alienation.
First, schizophrenic patients have been shown to lack primary or
bodily empathy, that means, they have problems with understanding
facial and gestural expressions of others (Kington et al., 2000;
Edwards et al., 2002; Amminger et al., 2012). One could say that they
experience others’ bodies more like objects. Second, patients often
show a lack of implicit social understanding, manifesting itself in a
200
T. FUCHS
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
subtle ‘loss of natural self-evidence’, as Blankenburg (1971) has
described it. Precisely those things become a problem ‘…which cannot rationally be unequivocally defined, which are a matter of tact’:
which dress one wears, how one addresses someone, how one apologizes, and so on (ibid., p. 82). What is lacking in schizophrenic
autism, then, is not explicit social knowledge, inferential or ToM abilities, but rather an implicit understanding of the ‘rules of the game’, a
sense of proportion for what is appropriate, likely, and relevant in the
social context.2 As a result, patients report that they feel isolated and
detached, unable to grasp the natural, everyday meanings of the
shared life-world. This alienation may sometimes even date back to
the patient’s childhood:
When a child, I used to watch my little cousin in order to understand
when it was the right moment to laugh or how they managed to act without thinking of it before… It is since I was a child that I try to understand
how the others function, and I am therefore forced to play the little
anthropologist. (Stanghellini, 2004, p. 115)
I don’t really grasp what others are up to… I constantly observe myself
while I am together with people, trying to find out what I should say or
do. It’s easier when I am alone or watching TV.3
Thus, the behaviour of others comes to be observed from a distant or
third-person point of view instead of entering second-person embodied interactions. Interpersonal relationships have then to be managed
by deliberate efforts, leading to constant stress in complex social situations and finally to autistic withdrawal.
This alienation can also be felt when interacting with the patient,
leading to what has been termed praecox-feeling by the Dutch psychiatrist Ruemke (1941), derived from the former term dementia praecox
for schizophrenia (ibid.). It means the sense of an interpersonal atmosphere of unnaturalness, characterized by a lack of mutuality,
responsivity, or attunement:
I felt trapped by a peculiar kind of distress, as if, in contact with my
patient, something broke within me. (Minkowski, 1933)
Even after a very brief mental state examination it becomes clear to the
psychiatrist that his [the patient’s] empathy is lacking… it is impossible
to establish contact with his personality as a whole. (Ruemke, 1941)
One might argue that a failure of implicit or sub-personal ToM mechanisms could also
explain those deficits. However, what is at stake here is not reading other people’s minds
but rather the embodied ‘social sense’ (Bourdieu, 1990) which conveys an intuitive grasp
of social situations, interactions, and intentions-in-action. On the problem of a subpersonal ToM see also footnote 1.
[3] Quotation from a schizophrenia patient, Psychiatric Clinic, Heidelberg.
[2]
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
201
In the intercorporal encounter, the patient’s emotional expressions
and verbal utterances do not seem to correspond to each other or to the
context (parathymia); bodily movements and expressions are not integrated to form a harmonious whole through which the person could
manifest himself. As a result, one could say that others will experience
the schizophrenic patient more as an object-body than as a lived body.
This impression corresponds to the experiential disembodiment of the
schizophrenic person.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
5. Disturbances of Tertiary
Intersubjectivity in Schizophrenia
(a) Transitivism
The disturbance of basic self-awareness in schizophrenia does not
only affect primary intersubjectivity, but also the higher level of
self–other distinction or self-demarcation, resulting in a loss of experienced ego-boundaries which Bleuler (1911) termed ‘transitivism’:
When I look at somebody my own personality is in danger. I am undergoing a transformation and my self is beginning to disappear. (Chapman, 1966)
The others’ gazes get penetrating, and it is as if there was a consciousness of my person emerging around me… they can read in me like in a
book. Then I don’t know who I am any more. (Fuchs, 2000, p. 172)
Such reports show that in transitivism ‘being conscious of another
consciousness’ may threaten the schizophrenic patient with a loss of
his self. How can this be explained? In current neurocognitive
accounts, the sense of self is regarded as being generated by inferential self-monitoring processes. Corresponding explanations of symptoms such as transitivism, thought insertion, acoustic hallucinations,
or passivity experiences rely on the concept of shared representations, i.e. overlapping neuronal representations for the execution of an
action and for the observation of the same action in others (Decety and
Sommerville, 2003). A hypothetical failure of the action attribution
system (neuronal ‘who’ system, Georgieff and Jeannerod, 1998) then
leads to self–other confusion and delusional misattribution.
However, such modular explanations miss the basic disturbance of
self-awareness that precedes the acute psychotic symptoms often by
years. From a phenomenological perspective, the self–other distinction is automatically constituted in every experience as an aspect of
non-reflective self-awareness (Parnas, 2003). If this primary embodied sense of self or ipseity is disturbed, then becoming aware of others
202
T. FUCHS
as being aware of oneself will become precarious. In grasping the
other’s perspective, the patients are no more able to maintain their
own embodied centre. This is illustrated by the following case
description:
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
A young man was frequently confused in a conversation, being unable
to distinguish between himself and his interlocutor. He tended to lose
the sense of whose thoughts originated in whom, and felt ‘as if’ the
interlocutor somehow ‘invaded’ him, an experience that shattered his
identity and was intensely anxiety-provoking. When walking on the
street, he scrupulously avoided glancing at his mirror image in the windowpanes of the shops, because he felt uncertain on which side he actually was. (Parnas, 2003, p. 232)
As pointed out in the first section, the verbal interaction with others
implies a continuous oscillation between the central, embodied perspective and the decentred perspective from which I am aware of the
other as being aware of me being aware of him. It is this dialectical
tension of the ‘excentric position’ that the schizophrenic patient cannot maintain any more. The perspectives of self and other are confused instead of being integrated from a self–other meta-perspective,
resulting in a sense of being invaded and overpowered by the other.
The same confusion arises for the patient when perceiving himself in
the mirror. A similar case example is given by Kimura:
When I am looking into a mirror, I do not know any more whether I am
here looking at me there in the mirror, or whether I am there in the mirror
looking at me here… If I look at someone else in the mirror, I am not
able to distinguish him from myself any more. When I am feeling
worse, the distinction between me and a real other person gets lost, too.
While watching TV, I don’t know any more whether I am speaking in
the TV-set or whether I am hearing the words here. I don’t know
whether the inside turns outwards or the outside inwards. It is as if the
foundation of my self collapses. Are there perhaps two ‘I’s? (Kimura,
1994, p. 194, own translation)
Here it is precisely the virtuality of the mirror image that undermines
the embodied sense of self. While looking into the mirror, the patient
cannot maintain his own centre, thus confusing the embodied and the
virtual self. This is generalized to the perception of virtual others in
the mirror, and finally to the encounter with real others. As we can see,
the conditions of the possibility for the phenomenon of transitivism
are rooted in the dialectical structure of intersubjectivity. To recognize
others as mental agents, that means as persons, and to recognize oneself as a separate person among others is one and the same achievement, namely reaching and maintaining the excentric position.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
203
However, this achievement is threatened when the basic bodily sense
of self is weakened, finally resulting in a short-circuit of perspectives,
as it were, or a melting of self and other.
This short-circuit may also lead to the experience of thought-broadcasting: all the patient’s thoughts are known to others; there is no difference between his mental life and that of others any more. Thus, he
is entangled in a disembodied, self-referential, and delusional view
from the outside. It is also for this reason that the first episode of
schizophrenia frequently occurs in situations of social exposure and
emotional disclosure, that means, when the affirmation of one’s own
self against the perspective of the others is at stake: e.g. when leaving
the parents’ home, starting an intimate relationship, or entering working life. In such situations, the patient may lose his embodied perspective and start to feel observed, persecuted, and permeated from all
sides. Thus we find again what I have called a disembodiment, caused
by a loss of self in the dialectical process of intersubjective
perception.
Importantly, a lack of recognition by significant others or one’s
larger social environment may aggravate these risks. According to
recent epidemiological studies, social marginalization, minority status, migration, and other facets that define individuals as being different from their social surroundings, are potential risk factors for
schizophrenia, leading to significantly increased incidences in the
affected population (Fearon et al., 2006; Cantor-Graae and Selten,
2005; Zammit et al., 2010; Bourque et al., 2011). Although a disturbance or loss of the excentric position has to be distinguished from
psychological problems of self-assertiveness or self-worth, the challenge to one’s ipseity in social encounters may nevertheless be
increased by experiences of social exclusion, discrimination, or
deprivation.
(b) Delusion
Finally, I will turn to delusions as disorders of tertiary intersubjectivity or self–other meta-perspective. At first sight, one might think
of delusions as the mere product of faulty neuronal information processing, or of ‘broken brains’. After all, delusions misrepresent reality, so they must be somehow ‘in the head’. However, even in
present-day psychiatry, this is not the whole story, for the current definitions of delusion contain a cultural clause: even convictions that
seem bizarre from a western viewpoint may well be shared with others
in a corresponding cultural background and then give no justification
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
204
T. FUCHS
for a diagnosis of delusion (APA, 2013, p. 103). This shows that the
essence of delusion cannot be just a wrong content or representation
of reality — delusion should rather be considered an interactive phenomenon. Instead of reifying delusion as a localizable state in the
head of the patient, an enactive approach regards it as a disturbance of
intersubjectivity, arising in a social situation that is always constituted
by two or more interaction partners.
According to the enactive approach to cognition, organisms do not
passively receive information from their environment which they then
translate into internal representations; rather, they constitute or enact
the world through their sensorimotor interactions with the environment (Varela et al., 1991; Thompson, 2005; 2007). However, for
human beings this constitution is not a solitary activity but always
means an intersubjective co-creation of meaning. We live in a shared
life-world because we continuously create and enact it through our
coordinated activities and ‘participatory sense-making’ (De Jaegher
and Di Paolo, 2007). This applies in particular to the domain of the
social world, that means, to the processes of mutual understanding,
negotiation of intentions, alignment of perspectives, and reciprocal
correction of perceptions.
Figure 1. Interactive circle.
Let us look at this more closely. In social interactions, shared meanings are produced by circular processes of action and mutual perception according to the following pattern (cf. Figure 1): a person, A,
makes an utterance (upper black arrow), anticipating a certain reaction of his partner B. Now B interprets A’s utterance, thus at least
implicitly taking A’s perspective, and then gives a corresponding
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
205
reply (lower black arrow), anticipating a certain reaction of A. Now it
is A’s turn to interpret B’s reaction, to compare it with his own anticipation, and then to make a second, affirming, modifying, or correcting
utterance. B compares this with his expectation, now in turn modifies
or affirms his own reply, etc. This yields an ongoing interactive circle
which may even be better illustrated by a spiral of interactions, leading to shared or participatory sense-making (Figure 2). One could also
say that the shared meaning is generated and constantly transformed
through the interaction which implies an alignment of perspectives or
mutual perspective-taking. In successful interactions, this spiral leads
to an increasingly consensual understanding or definition of the
shared situation (as symbolized by the increasing approximation of A
and B) — even if there were differing viewpoints, attitudes, and prejudgments at the beginning.
Figure 2. Spiral of participatory sense-making.
It is important to note that there is an implicit background or framework to this process which consists of all the commonsensical
assumptions about how an interaction works, what kind of reactions
are adequate or inadequate, what presuppositions may be taken for
granted, including the meaning of words or phrases in certain contexts, the shared cultural values, and the overall view of the world.
One most important element of this background, however, is a basic
sense of trust — the underlying assumption to live in a world with
mutual expectations and obligations, and with reliable rules of the
social game. This ‘bedrock’ of unquestioned certainties
(Wittgenstein, 1969; Rhodes and Gipps, 2008) is a fundamental
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
206
T. FUCHS
presupposition of the consensual understanding of a situation. Following Erikson (1959) and others (Stern, 1985; Trevarthen and
Logotheti, 1989), we may assume that a sense of basic trust and affective attunement normally develops in the first year of life, as a presupposition for being related to others, learning from them, and thus
being socialized into the human community.
However, if there are constraining boundary conditions to these circular processes, then the joint negotiation of meaning will be disturbed and mutual understanding will fail. Such is the case, for
example, when one of the partners is deaf, or does not understand the
other’s language or cultural background. It is well known that these
are typical conditions which in vulnerable persons may lead to suspicion, paranoid ideation, and finally to delusions of persecution —
termed ‘paranoia of the hard-of-hearing’ (Cooper, 1976) or ‘paranoia
of immigrants’ (Fuchs, 1999; Fossiona et al., 2004; Cantor-Graae and
Selten, 2005). In these cases, adequate understanding of verbal utterances is compromised, leading to a disturbance of the circle of social
action and perception. The non-verbal and behavioural signals of others become ambiguous, and their reactions are no longer congruent
with the patient’s anticipation. More and more, the deaf person or the
immigrant gets entangled in situations in which the utterances or
expressions of others seem to be aimed at him in a sinister way, and he
is unable to neutralize these perceived self-references by subsequent
correcting interactions.
At a certain point in this process, the basic trust in others breaks
down and is replaced by a paranoid delusional framework which now
converts even the most harmless events and doings into all the more
insidious machinations and intrigues. The breakdown of the medium
of trust and attunement to others leads to a loss of the natural evidence
of commonsensical reality (Blankenburg, 2001). Moreover, there is a
looping effect between the arising paranoid ideation and the reaction
of the others to the patient’s altered, suspicious behaviour. Their irritated reactions contribute to his sense that there is something to be suspicious about, which in turn feeds back into their failure to make
themselves understood.
With some modifications, this description applies to schizophrenic
delusions as well. For, in the prodromal stages of the psychosis, the
alienation of perception and the resulting loss of familiar significances particularly extend to the social sphere. The faces, the gazes,
and the behaviour of others become highly ambiguous, and the interactive circles with others are fundamentally disturbed. In the delusional mood arising from this ambiguity (Jaspers, 1968; Fuchs, 2005),
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
207
the basic trust in others breaks down. The co-constitution of a shared
world fails and is replaced by the new, idiosyncratic coherence of the
delusion. Now the patient feels observed by gazes from the background, being spied at from out of anonymous cars, or secretly tested
in well-prepared situations. In other words, she takes others’ presumed perspectives even excessively, but in a way that all these perspectives seem to be directed centripetally towards herself, implying
the attribution of threatening intentions to others (this has sometimes
be termed ‘overmentalization’; see for example Montag et al., 2011).
Similar to transitivism, delusions may thus be described as a loss of
the excentric position. Deluded patients are able to take on the (supposed) perspective of others, i.e. they are aware of others being (seemingly) conscious of them. However, what they lack is the independent
position from which they could compare their own and another’s
point of view, and from which they could also relativize or question
their feeling of centrality and reference (being observed, spied at, persecuted, etc.). This independent or ‘third’ position is the excentric
position — the achievement of tertiary intersubjectivity that is lost in
delusion.
The failure of excentricity becomes manifest in particular when the
patient is confronted with doubts or objections by others. In most
cases, he will not be able to adequately respond to these; on the contrary, he will simply assume a consensually perceived situation even
though this is not at all the case from the other’s point of view. The
patient behaves as if others could only be of the same opinion and does
not justify his claims in a way that is understandable to the interlocutor
(McCabe et al., 2004). He no longer succeeds in actually taking their
perspective, in transcending his own point of view. Thus, delusions
are not mere products of a deranged brain. For their essence is not a
faulty representation of the world, but the failure of co-constituting
the world through mutually taking and aligning one’s perspectives.
An important result of this is the exclusion of chance (Berner,
1978). Chance or coincidence normally allows us to neutralize irrelevant elements of a situation by attributing it to a mere contingency, not
to another’s intention: ‘This was not meant for me’ or ‘not aimed at
me’. For the schizophrenic patient, however, the situation is reversed:
it is precisely the normally irrelevant background elements that adopt
a meaningful, sinister, and threatening character. The deluded person
no longer acknowledges the possibility of chance, and thus refuses to
treat the shared situation as an open one. This inability to take a different perspective on the situation in turn leads to a severe irritation and
worry in his interaction partners. They no longer know how to
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
208
T. FUCHS
comprehend his behaviour, nor where they stand with him. This experience corresponds, on the level of verbal interaction, to the praecoxfeeling on the intercorporeal level.
In sum, delusions may not be sufficiently described as individual
false beliefs. Rather, they correspond to an intersubjective situation
bereft of the basic trust and attunement to others that could help to
restore a consensual understanding of the situation and to co-constitute a shared, commonsensical reality. No matter what their neurobiological presuppositions and components are — no doubt that these
are of crucial importance — delusions are not just products of individual brains but disorders of the in-between, or of enacting a world
through interaction with others. Delusions are relational phenomena,
precisely because they escape our attempts towards understanding;
they manifest themselves through the negation of the established
order of sense by which we aim to grasp them. By virtue of this negation, however, delusions also remain related to the others.
6. Conclusion
From a phenomenological point of view, severe disorders of intersubjectivity as they are found in autism and schizophrenia are primarily based on a disturbance of the embodied interaction with others and
on a lack of the practical skills implied. Instead of a theory deficit,
autistic and schizophrenic patients rather suffer from a lack of sensus
communis or embodied common sense — a lack which they can only
insufficiently compensate by explicit inferences and hypothetical
assumptions about others. Lacking the tacit knowledge and familiarity which normally guides our relationships and interactions, autistic
and schizophrenic patients are also impaired in their capacity to take
the other’s perspective and to participate in processes of joint sensemaking. As a consequence, higher levels of intersubjectivity are
affected on which the shared negotiation of meaning, the mutual
alignment of perspectives, and the demarcation of oneself from others
are at stake. What is most characteristic of disorders at these levels is
the lacking capacity to flexibly switch between one’s own and
another’s point of view, a capacity that is normally enabled by a third
or excentric position on a meta-level. Its loss may result in a failure to
adequately recognize others’ beliefs as differing from one’s own, further in phenomena such as transitivism or loss of self–other boundaries, and finally in delusional beliefs. In all these cases, the
interactive constitution of a shared world is seriously compromised,
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
209
leading to a fundamental alienation, detachment, and autistic
withdrawal.
The alignment of perspectives and sharing of intentions directed
towards a common object or action goal has been termed ‘shared
intentionality’ or ‘we-intentionality’ in social philosophy and psychology (Searle, 1995; Tuomela, 2002; Elsenbroich and Gilbert,
2014). We may recognize from the psychopathological conditions
described above that this we-intentionality is ultimately based on a
primary, embodied, and practical understanding of others. Even
though higher levels of intersubjectivity may be reached by highfunctioning autistic individuals through explicit inference and similar
strategies, their primary lack of intercorporeal skills is bound to at
least impair the development of high-level mentalizing capacities.
Similarly, in patients with schizophrenia the weakening of the bodily
sense of self leads not only to disturbances of intercorporeality and
commonsensical understanding of social situations, but also to a loss
of self–other distinction and participatory sense-making on higher
levels of intersubjectivity.
In the last analysis, this shows that intersubjectivity is not a relation
or meeting of ‘pure minds’, but of embodied subjects interacting with
each other in shared situations. Correspondingly, so-called ‘mental’
illnesses should not be regarded as a malfunctioning process occurring in an individual brain but as a disturbed way of enacting a world,
and, in particular, to ‘inter-enact’ a shared world through adequate
interaction with others. Mental illness is an extended phenomenon, a
process always taking place in between the patient and others.
Acknowledgments
This paper was supported by the EU Marie Curie ITN 264828 TESIS
(Towards an Embodied Science of InterSubjectivity). I am also grateful for the valuable comments of two anonymous reviewers.
References
American Psychiatric Association (APA) (2013) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM 5, 5th ed., Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric
Association.
Amminger, G., Schafer, M.R., Papageorgiou, K., Klier, C.M., Schlogelhofer, M.,
Mossaheb, N., Werneck-Rohrer, S., Nelson, B. & McGorry, P.D. (2012) Emotion recognition in individuals at clinical high-risk for schizophrenia, Schizophrenia Bulletin, 38, pp. 1030–1039.
Baldwin, D.A. & Baird, J.A. (2001) Discerning intentions in dynamic human
action, Trends in Cognitive Science, 5, pp. 171–178.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
210
T. FUCHS
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995) Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Berner, P. (1978) Psychopathologische Wahnforschung und psychiatrische
Hypothesenbildung, Nervenarzt, 49, pp. 147–152.
Blankenburg, W. (1971) Der Verlust der natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit [The
Loss of Natural Self-evidence], Berlin: Springer.
Blankenburg, W. (2001) First steps toward a ‘psychopathology of common sense’,
Mishara, A. (trans.) Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 8, pp. 303–315.
Bleuler, E. (1911) Dementia Praecox oder Gruppe der Schizophrenien, in
Aschaffenburg, G. (ed.) Handbuch der Psychiatrie, Leipzig: Franz Deuticke.
Bora, E., Yucel, M. & Pantelis, C. (2009) Theory of mind impairment in schizophrenia: Meta-analysis, Schizophrenia Research, 109, pp. 1–9.
Bourdieu, P. (1990) The Logic of Practice, Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Bourque, F., Van der Ven, E. & Malla, A. (2011) A meta-analysis of the risk for
psychotic disorders among first- and second-generation immigrants, Psychological Medicine, 41, pp. 897–910.
Cantor-Graae, E. & Selten, J.-P. (2005) Schizophrenia and migration: A metaanalysis and review, American Journal of Psychiatry, 162, pp. 12–24.
Carruthers, P. (1996) Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of the theory-theory, in Carruthers, P. & Smith, P.K. (eds.) Theories of Theories of Mind, pp.
22–38, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2009) How we know our minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, pp. 121–182.
Chapman, J. (1966) The early symptoms of schizophrenia, British Journal of Psychiatry, 112, pp. 225–251.
Cooper, A.F. (1976) Deafness and psychiatric illness, British Journal of Psychiatry, 129, pp. 216–226.
Dapretto, M., Davies, M.S., Pfeifer, J.H., Scott, A.A., Sigman, M., Bookheimer,
S.Y. & Jacoboni, M. (2006) Understanding emotions in others: Mirror neuron
dysfunction in children with autism spectrum, Nature Neuroscience, [Online],
www.nature.com/natureneuroscience.
Dawson, G., Meltzoff, A.N., Osterling, J., Rinaldi, J. & Brown, E. (1998) Children
with autism fail to orient to naturally occurring social stimuli, Journal of Autism
and Developmental Disorders, 28, pp. 479–485.
De Jaegher, H. (2013) Embodiment and sense-making in autism, Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 7, article 15, pp. 1–14.
De Jaegher, H. & Di Paolo, E. (2007) Participatory sense-making: An enactive
approach to social cognition, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, pp.
485–507.
Decety, J. & Sommerville, J.A. (2003) Shared representations between self and
other: A social cognitive neuroscience view, Trends in Cognitive Science, 7, pp.
527–533.
Edwards, J., Jackson, H J. & Pattison, P.E. (2002) Emotion recognition via facial
expression and affective prosody in schizophrenia: A methodological review,
Clinical Psychology Review, 22, pp. 789–832.
Elsenbroich, C. & Gilbert, N. (2014) We-intentionality, in Elsenbroich, C. &
Gilbert, N., Modelling Norms, pp. 185–197, Dordrecht: Springer.
Erikson, E.H. (1959) Identity and the Life Cycle, New York: International Universities Press.
Fearon, P., Kirkbride, J.B., Morgan, C., et al. (2006) Incidence of schizophrenia
and other psychoses in ethnic minority groups: Results from the MRC AESOP
Study, Psychological Medicine, 36, pp. 1541–1550.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
211
Fossiona, P., Servais, L., Rejasa, M.-C., Ledouxa, Y., Pelca, I. & Minnera, P.
(2004) Psychosis, migration and social environment: An age-and-gender controlled study, European Psychiatry, 19, pp. 338–343.
Fournier, K., Hass, C., Naik, S., Lodha, N. & Cauraugh, J. (2010) Motor coordination in autism spectrum disorders: A synthesis and metaanalysis, Journal of
Autism and Developmental Disorders, 40, pp. 1227–1240.
Frith, C. (1992) The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia, London:
Erlbaum.
Frith, C. & Corcoran, R. (1996) Exploring ‘theory of mind’ in people with schizophrenia, Psychological Medicine, 26, pp. 521–530.
Frith, U. (1989) Autism: Explaining the Enigma, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Fuchs, T. (1999) Life events in late paraphrenia and depression, Psychopathology,
32, pp. 60–69.
Fuchs, T. (2000) Psychopathologie von Leib und Raum. Phänomenologischempirische Untersuchungen zu depressiven und paranoiden Erkrankungen,
Darmstadt: Steinkopff.
Fuchs, T. (2001) The tacit dimension: Commentary to W. Blankenburg’s ‘Steps
towards a psychopathology of common sense’, Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 8, pp. 323–326.
Fuchs, T. (2005) Delusional mood and delusional perception — A phenomenological analysis, Psychopathology, 38, pp. 133–139.
Fuchs, T. (2013) The phenomenology and development of social perspectives,
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12, pp. 655–683.
Fuchs, T. & De Jaegher, H. (2009) Enactive Intersubjectivity: Participatory
sense-making and mutual incorporation, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8, pp. 465–486.
Fuchs, T. & Schlimme, J. (2009) Embodiment and psychopathology: A phenomenological perspective, Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 22, pp. 570–575.
Gallagher, S. (2004) Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction
theory as an alternative to theory of mind, Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 11, pp. 199–217.
Gallagher, S. (2012) In defense of phenomenological approaches to social cognition: Interacting with the critics, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, pp.
187–212.
Gallagher, S. & Hutto, D. (2008) Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice, in Zlatev, J., Racine, T., Sinha, C. & Itkonen, E.
(eds.) The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity, pp. 17–38, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Gallagher, S. & Zahavi, D. (2008) The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction
to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science, London, New York: Routledge.
Georgieff, N. & Jeannerod, M. (1998) Beyond consciousness of external events: A
Who system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness, Consciousness
and Cognition, 7, pp. 465–477.
Gepner, B. & Mestre, D. (2002) Rapid visual-motion integration deficit in autism,
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, p. 455.
Goldman, A.I. (2012) Theory of mind, in Margolis, E., Samuels, R. & Stich, S.
(eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science, pp. 402–424,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gopnik, A. & Wellman, H. (1995) Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory, in Davies, M. & Stone, T. (eds.) Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind
Debate, Oxford: Blackwell.
Happé, F. (1995) Autism: An Introduction to Psychological Theory, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
212
T. FUCHS
Hobson, P. (2002) The Cradle of Thought, London: Macmillan.
Hobson, R.P. (1993) Autism and the Development of Mind, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Hobson, R.P. & Lee, A. (1999) Imitation and identification in autism, Journal of
Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 40, pp. 649–659.
Jaspers, K. (1968) General Psychopathology, 7th ed., Hoenig, J. & Hamilton,
M.W. (trans.), Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Kimura, B. (1994) Psychopathologie der Zufälligkeit oder Verlust des
Aufenthaltsortes beim Schizophrenen, Daseinsanalyse, 11, pp. 192–204.
Kington, J.M., Jones, L.A., Watt, A.A., Hopkin, E.J. & Williams, J. (2000)
Impaired eye expression recognition in schizophrenia, Journal of Psychiatric
Research, 34, pp. 341–347.
Klin, A., Volkmar, F. & Sparrow, S. (1992) Autistic social dysfunction: Some limitations of the theory of mind hypothesis, Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 33, pp. 861–876.
Klin, A., Jones, W., Schultz, R. & Volkmar, F. (2003) The enactive mind, or from
actions to cognition: Lessons from autism, Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society of London, 358, pp. 345–360.
Laing, R.D., Phillipson, H. & Lee, A.R. (1966) Interpersonal Perception, London:
HarperCollins.
Lee, K.H., Farrow, T.F.D., Spence, S.A. & Woodruff, P.W.R. (2004) Social cognition, brain networks and schizophrenia, Pychological Medicine, 34, pp.
391–400.
Mari, M., Castiello, U., Marks, D., Marraffa, C. & Prior, M. (2003) The reach-tograsp movement in children with autism spectrum disorder, Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society: Biological Sciences, 358, pp. 393–403.
McCabe, R. (2004) On the inadequacies of theory of mind explanations of schizophrenia, Theory & Psychology, 14, pp. 738–752.
McCabe, R., Leudar, I. & Antaki, C. (2004) Do people with schizophrenia display
theory of mind deficits in clinical interactions?, Psychological Medicine, 34,
pp. 401–412.
Meltzoff, A.N. (2002) Elements of a developmental theory of imitation, in
Meltzoff, A.N. & Prinz, W. (eds.) The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution,
and Brain Bases, pp. 19–41, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Meltzoff, A.N. & Moore, M.K. (1977) Imitation of facial and manual gestures by
human neonates, Science, 198, pp. 74–78.
Meltzoff, A.N. & Brooks, R. (2001) ‘Like me’ as a building block for understanding other minds: Bodily acts, attention, and intention, in Malle, B.F., Moses, L.J.
& Baldwin, D.A. (eds.) Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social
Cognition, pp. 171–191, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1960) Le philosophe et son ombre, in Signes, Paris: Éditions
Gallimard.
Minkowski, E. (1933) Etudes phénoménologiques et psychopathologiques, Paris:
Coll. de l’Evolution Psychiatrique.
Montag, C., Dziobek, I., Richter, I.S., Neuhaus, K., Lehmann, A., Sylla, R. &
Gallinat, J. (2011) Different aspects of theory of mind in paranoid schizophrenia: Evidence from a video-based assessment, Psychiatry Research, 186, pp.
203–209.
Oberman, L.M., Hubbard, E.M., McCleery, J.P., Altschuler, E.L., Ramachandran,
V.S. & Pineda, J.A. (2005) EEG evidence for mirror neuron dysfunction in
autism spectrum disorders, Cognitive Brain Research, 24, pp. 190–198.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
PATHOLOGIES OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
213
Parnas, J. (2003) Self and schizophrenia: A phenomenological perspective, in
Kircher, T. & David, A. (eds.) The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, pp.
217–241, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plessner, H. (1981) Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch (1928),
Gesammelte Schriften IV, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Reed, T. & Paterson, C. (1990) A comparative study of autistic subjects’ performance at two levels of visual and cognitive perspective taking, Journal of
Autism and Developmental Disorders, 29, pp. 555–568.
Rhodes, J. & Gipps, R.G.T. (2008) Delusions, certainty, and the background, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 15, pp. 295–310.
Ruemke, H.C. (1941) The nuclear symptoms of schizophrenia and the praecox
feeling, (English translation 1990), History of Psychiatry, 1, pp. 331–341.
Sacks, O. (1995) An Anthropologist on Mars: Seven Paradoxical Tales, New York:
Alfred Knopf.
Searle, J. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality, New York: The Free Press.
Smith, I.M. & Bryson, S.E. (1994) Imitation and action in autism: A critical
review, Psychological Bulletin, 116, pp. 259–273.
Spaulding, S. (2010) Embodied cognition and mindreading, Mind and Language,
25, pp. 119–140.
Sprong, M., Schothorst, P., Vos, E., Hox, J. & van Engeland, H. (2007) Theory of
mind in schizophrenia: Meta-analysis, British Journal of Psychiatry, 191, pp.
5–13.
Stanghellini, G. (2004) Disembodied Spirits and Deanimatied Bodies: The
Psychopathology of Common Sense, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stern, D. (1985) The Interpersonal World of the Infant, New York: Basic Books.
Teitelbaum, P., Teitelbaum, O., Nye, J., Fryman, J. & Maurer, R.G. (1998) Movement analysis in infancy may be useful for early diagnosis of autism, Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the USA, 95, pp. 13982–13987.
Thompson, E. (2005) Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to
experience, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, pp. 407–427.
Thompson, E. (2007) Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of
Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, M. (1999) The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Trevarthen, C.B. (1979) Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A
description of primary intersubjectivity, in Bullowa, M. (ed.) Before Speech,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C.B. & Hubley, P. (1978) Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence,
confiding and acts of meaning in the first year, in Lock, A. (ed.) Action, Gesture
and Symbol: The Emergence of Language, pp. 183–229, London: Academic
Press.
Trevarthen, C.B. & Logotheti, K. (1989) Child in society, and society in children:
The nature of basic trust, in Howell, S. & Willis, R. (eds.) Societies at Peace:
Anthropological Perspectives, pp. 165–186, Florence, KY: Taylor & Frances/
Routledge.
Tuomela, R. (2002) The Philosophy of Social Practices: A Collective Acceptance
View, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The Embodied Mind: Cognitive
Science and Human Experience, 6th ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Walston, F., Blennerhassett, R.C. & Charlton, B. (2000) ‘Theory of mind’,
persecutory delusions and the somatic marker mechanism, Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 5, pp. 161–174.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969) On Certainty, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
214
T. FUCHS
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
Zahavi, D. & Parnas, J. (2003) Conceptual problems in infantile autism research:
Why cognitive science needs phenomenology, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10 (9–10), pp. 53–71.
Zammit, S., Lewis, G., Rasbash, J., Dalman, C., Gustafsson, J.-E. & Allebeck, P.
(2010) Individuals, schools, and neighborhood. A multilevel longitudinal study
of variation in incidence of psychotic disorders, Archives of General Psychiatry,
67, pp. 914–922.