ABSTRACT
My dissertation attends to the embodied and relational dimensions of caring ethics and
politics. I locate my analysis in conditions in which devaluing, exploiting, and extracting the care
of multiply oppressed people is a structural component of many contemporary institutions, social
forms, and intimate realities—as is the denial of care to those most impacted by systemic harms. I
argue that prominent articulations of care as a naturalistically construed ethical good on the one
hand, or an exploited form of labor on the other, sidestep the constitutive violence of these social
structures and norms, the impact of this violence on the intimacies of caring relations themselves,
and ultimately the generative and transformational role that alternative economies and practices of
care play in movements for social change.
In particular, my project critically engages i.) feminist care ethical understandings of care
as a moral value and ii.) Marxist feminist analyses of care labor as an essential, if disavowed,
component of capitalist accumulation and extraction. Together, these orientations towards ethics
and labor speak to fundamental dimensions of care—which, insofar as it is concerned with meeting
emotional and material needs, is, in Sara Ruddick’s famous phrasing, both a form of labor and an
ethical relationship (Ruddick 1998). However, I claim that isolating these material and normative
realities poses an unworkable dualism, which ultimately occludes the intimacies of struggle and
transformation at the heart of caring ethics and politics. I find more generative approaches to these
questions in two discourses in particular: On the one hand, I discuss how intersectional feminist
methods highlight the interlocking oppressions manifest in social organizations and divisions of
caring labor, and how this violence can become engrained in the very forms of caring attention
(responsiveness, empathy, other-directedness, etc.) that care ethicists often uncritically naturalize.
On the other, I engage notions of communization and life making developed by largely
untranslated contemporary Latin American social reproduction feminists, who place affective and
intimate critique and transformation at the heart of the politics of social reproduction in ways that
transcend traditional Marxist notions of labor and labor politics.
Contradictions of Care
VIOLENCE AND REVOLUTION IN CARING RELATIONS
Kelly Gawel
June 2023
Submitted to The New School for Social Research of The New School in partial
fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy
Dissertation Committee
Dr. Jay Bernstein
Dr. Cinzia Arruzza
Dr. Linda Martín Alcoff
i Dr. Emma Park
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
At all levels, this writing would be inconceivable without the contributions of beloved
friends, collaborators, family, teachers, and mentors.
I am grateful to my mother who instilled in me my deepest values, showed me the
meaning of both care and wisdom, and taught me the humor and grit needed to persevere. To my
father, my spirit kin, for teaching me gratitude, mystery, and the art of living. To Cinzia Arruzza,
thank you for inspiring this work and showing me what I can aspire to. The power of your truth
has taught me to speak truth to power. To Jay Bernstein, you taught me to argue and to teach—
and to call on new visions of beauty and reason in doing so. Thank you for seeing me, and
believing in my work even (especially) when I lost my way. To Caffyn Jesse, my counternormative role-model for queering ethics and living in alignment with purpose and pleasure.
John Campion, thank you for encouraging me to find a work I can live in, and for showing the
way by walking it.
To Veronica Dakota Padilla, Teresa Casas Hernández, Angelica Stathopoulos—my work
needs your friendship and love, as well as your writing, thinking, and being. To B Love, the
power of your magic and healing truly weaves worlds—I can’t wait to teach and write together.
To Zhivka Valiavicharska—beloved comradess and keeper of the social reproductive temple—
thank you for inviting me into your worlds, and for teaching me to live and relate in new ways.
Esra Atamer, for showing me what is possible. Melissa Buzzeo, for teaching me radical beauty,
voice, and what it means to belong. Cassandra Troyan, for sparking this project, and the Care
Cadre for nourishing it into being.
To Sandra Stephens and Ciclón Olivares: your art, as well as our friendship,
togetherness—and above all our jouissance—have taught me what chosen family is and can be.
ii
Silvia Birklein, deepest teacher of my feminist lineage, and of my soul, I will always be grateful.
To isele phoenix harper—life pal and poly bestie, our conversations have taught me more than
any book cited herein, and they imbue every page. To Mithra Lehn and Cille Varselev—thank
you for teaching me new horizons of praxis, and new depths of communion and solidarity. To A.
Sef, your embodiment inspires cultures, may the mesh be with you always. To Sarah Kamens,
you are a star; thank you for showing me I am too. Rosalyn Temple, for the power of your voice,
presence, and art. Rima Hussein, for showing me that philosophy is worth fighting for, and for
bringing play, delight, and secure attachment to the process.
Thank you, Aaron Neber, your brilliant heart and mind (and your concrete suggestions!)
truly saved me. I can’t wait to see where our philosophical conversations, and our friendship,
take us.
Thank you to Linda Martín Alcoff, your work has made new worlds of philosophy
possible, and actual, for so many. Thank you, Emma Park, for the care, generosity, and rigor you
brought to my project. And to Drucilla Cornell, I wanted you to be the spiritual mother of my
work. May you rest in power and joy.
All of you, and many others, have transformed my writing, and my caring, beyond what
words can express.
iii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgements
ii
Introduction:
The Possibility of Radical Care
1
I.
II.
III.
IV.
V.
Beyond the Parallelism of Ethics and Labor
The Contradictions of Care
Why ‘Radical’ Care
Political and Theoretical Contexts
Organization of Chapters
2
7
9
15
19
Chapter One:
How Can a Radical Ethics of Care be Possible?
24
I.
II.
III.
IV.
V.
Introduction: Contradictions in The Ethics of Care
The Value of Care: Care Ethics’ Feminist Critique of Moral Philosophy
The Politics of Care: Care Ethical Perspectives
Naturalistic/Naturalized Epistemologies of Care: Getting the Problem into View
Conclusion: Caring Attention—Ethical Given or Situated Praxis?
Chapter Two:
There is No Universal Care: Interlocking Oppressions and the
Politics of Experience in Intersectional Theories of Care
I.
II.
III.
IV.
V.
Introduction: Caring Through Difference?
Intersectional Perspectives on Care
Engrossment and Empathy: Contradictory Manifestations of Care
The Ethics of Care in Political Context
Conclusion: New Caring Tools
Chapter Three:
How Can a Radical Politics of Social Reproduction be Possible?
I.
iv
Introduction: Contradictions in the Labor of Care
25
32
42
52
62
72
73
80
95
107
118
120
121
II. Critical and Methodological Considerations on Social Reproduction
III. Autonomist and Socialist Perspectives on Reproductive Labor
a. Autonomist Perspectives
b. Socialist Perspectives
IV. The Limits of the Labor Paradigm
V. Conclusion: Traditions of Economism and Productivism
Chapter Four:
The Ethics of Social Reproduction: Affect, Embodiment,
and the Politics of Life-Making
I.
II.
III.
IV.
V.
VI.
Introduction: Care in Crisis
Structural Contradictions of Care: Marxist Feminist Perspectives on the Care Crisis
The Ethics of Labor: Two Perspectives
Moral and Material Economies of Reproduction
The Affective Labor Debates
Conclusion: The Erotics of Life-Making
Conclusion:
Holding Contradiction
I. Opacity and Caring After
II. For the Remainder: Or a Promissory Note in the Key of Feminist Economics
a. Commons and Luchas en Defensa de la Vida
b. Transformative Justice: Abolitionist Alternatives for Care
III. Conclusion: The Call of Radical Care
Bibliography
v
126
134
135
145
153
167
173
174
178
184
196
211
223
228
229
234
235
241
247
250
Introduction:
The Possibility of Radical Care
1
Radical care is a personal devotion to shifting how we meet each other in small ways and also
how we bring that into social spaces to organize for what we believe in politically. It is a lifelong
dedication towards something bigger than yourself and knowing that you may not even see the
fruits of your labor and the structural changes in your lifetime, but still holding the hope to
organize for it anyways. Radical care is actively believing and organizing for the inevitability of a
better world.
-Moon
Radical care, to me, is having a new perspective on all of the things that we were taught to be
normal and recognizing that the oppression that comes from the devaluation of care intersects
with other types of oppression…
-Esther
I think teaching and educating my community. Teaching them how to read, where the resources
are at, how to nurture themselves, where to look for community, how to do a resume, how to
upkeep taxes, their rights, how to use Narcan, how to take care of themselves, how to apply for
Medicare/Medicaid, educating them on material, educating them on how to plant, where the
abortion clinics are, what to do if arrests happen, how to deal with conflicts collectively.
-Tecuane
Mutual aid, primarily. Mending relationships with loved ones and working on being a better
feminist. Intersectional feminist.
-Sarah
Unlearning
-Hannah1
I. Beyond the Parallelism of Ethics and Labor
Care is the social, material, and emotional weaving that sustains life and connects us to others.
From midwifing new life, nurturing the young, the work of sex, and the tending of death, trauma,
disability, and physical and mental illness, it is vital in every life stage and process. And yet,
despite its ubiquity in all aspects of life, care has been routinely neglected and even dismissed by
hegemonic and radical theorists alike. The fact that care has finally gained purchase in
mainstream political and moral theory is thus something to be celebrated, as is the labor of the
thinkers and activists, often marginalized themselves, who have long placed care at the center of
1
Student responses to the prompt: “What does radical care mean to you?” during the concluding discussion of
“Radical Care and Social Transformation”—Pratt Institute, May 2023, Brooklyn NY.
2
the moral and political universe. However, this ‘caring turn’ has yet to fully address care’s
imbrication with conditions of systemic social inequality, or the role of care in movements for
social change.
The following dissertation attends to the embodied and relational dimensions of caring
ethics and politics and does so in light of structural conditions in which devaluing, exploiting,
and extracting the care of multiply oppressed people is a structural component of many
contemporary institutions, social forms, and intimate realities—as is the denial of care to those
most impacted by systemic harms. I understand care in a broad sense as the material and
affective labor and relations through which social bonds and individuals are reproduced. Care is
thus conditioned by, and upholds, social forms (family, labor) and institutional life (civic,
religious, legal). At the heart of daily and intergenerational reproduction, it involves modes of
knowing, perceiving, and relating that are highly subtle and skilled, and culturally and
historically specific. It is thus a fundamental site of cultural reproduction: through care we learn
to embody and emotionally invest in the norms of a given social context—or resist and/or
transform them.
The argument and chapters that follow are structured around my claim that prominent
feminist articulations of care as a naturalistically construed ethical good on the one hand, or an
exploited form of labor on the other, sidestep the constitutive violence of these social structures
and norms, the impact of this violence on the intimacies of caring relations themselves, and
ultimately the generative and transformational role that alternative economies and practices of
care play in movements for social change.
My aim in juxtaposing the distinct and divergent legacies of care ethics and Marxist
feminism is not arbitrary, nor does it simply follow from Sarah Ruddick’s compelling claim
3
(1998) that ethics and labor simply are fundamental dimensions of care. Rather, a foundational
assumption of this dissertation is that the parallelism manifest in these materialist and normative
paradigms is itself reflective of institutional forms and knowledge validation processes (Collins
Black Feminist Thought) that have excluded care from ethical and political life. This division of
care-as-labor from care-as-ethics undergirding these respective traditions presents problems for
those of us striving to center and transform care, and to uproot the injustices entrenched in so
many caring relations, without re-instantiating the very forms of violence we seek to overcome.
If it is true that this division is itself an unwitting reification of moral and political economies
that foundationally invisibilize and devalue care and the ostensibly private, natural, and personal
realms of life over which it holds sway, then what avenues are left for forging new meanings and
embodiments for care? Because it is not as if the philosophers and activists who gave their hearts
and minds to these revolutionary feminist projects were content with prevalent notions and
norms. They too had such new feminist architectures (Anzaldúa 44, Lorde 112-123) in mind—
and new feminist tools in hand.
On the one hand, feminist ethicists are right to reclaim the ethical value of care, and to
situate it in its rightful place at the center of political theory and action. But the fact of care’s lifesustaining capacities does not in itself make it an unequivocal good. Indeed, it points to an
unsettling ambiguity. Particularly under conditions of widespread oppression and dominance,
caring practices and relations can themselves be shaped by, and even play a role in reproducing,
forms of violence that are anathema to the life and flourishing of many people, even the earth
itself. Exploiting and extracting the care labor of subjugated people—as well as systemically
neglecting those most in need of care—is, and has historically been, a constitutive feature of the
social reproduction of violent institutions. Nor is care given as a species activity when called
4
upon in social movements or as a collective survival strategy: transformative practices of care
play a vital role in how marginalized communities sustain themselves under these conditions,
mobilize forms of resistance against them, and nurture possibilities of living otherwise.
On the other hand, Marxist feminist theorists of social reproduction do politically center
the unequal gendered, racialized, and international divisions of caring labor and access through
which so many systemic inequalities are reproduced—as well as the centrality of caring labors in
the social reproduction of both capitalism and anti-capitalist struggle alike. By calling attention
to the devaluation, naturalization, and brutal exploitation of reproductive labors at the heart of
capitalist social life, these feminist organizers and theorists have radically shifted the terrain of
anti-capitalist political theory and praxis. However, this Marxist feminist move—particularly
from those prominent on the Western academic Left—largely reduces care to labor and thus
narrows the politics of care and social reproduction to the vision of struggle and liberation
elaborated in Marx’s critique of capitalism. But, much like traditional moral philosophy, many
Marxist critiques of political economy and liberatory imaginaries of classless society have
constitutively excluded care. Reducing the politics of social reproduction to a Marxian labor lens
thus risks stripping care—and social reproduction itself—of its ethical and political specificity:
flattening the painful dilemmas that circumscribe care and sex work, for example, as well as the
horizons of transformation they bring into view.
It is as damaging to reduce care to labor politics as it is view it as a transparent ethical
good, as neither perspective sheds light on the dimensions of harm, struggle, healing, and
transformation specific to relations and practices of care—or their essential, and essentially
contested, role in ethical and political life-making. Together, these assumptions support and
motivate my claim that care is not outside of or beyond violence and social transformation. A
5
crucial takeaway from these observations is that the harms reproduced in caring institutions and
relations are not intrinsic to care as such but features of social relations and norms that both
moralize and devalue it along multiple and intersecting axes of oppression. “Dangers” such as
paternalism and parochialism2 thus should not be construed as pathologies inherent to care, but
rather as examples of historically specific harms corresponding, in large part, to contemporary
social forms and institutions: e.g. cultural and familial chauvinism in the case of parochial care,
or, in the case of paternalistic care, the individualizing narratives of responsibilization and
deservingness at play in the allocation of ever dwindling services.
Finally, my claim that care, as a locus of struggle and transformation, cannot be
adequately brought into view or engaged within the parameters of this parallelism ultimately
stems from—and, I hope, supports—both care ethical and materialist feminist insights. To claim
that care should not be reduced to a natural, biological, instinctive, or given facticity is not to
contradict care ethicists’ claim that it is an essential component of human ethics and worldmaking. While I contest care ethicists’ move to derive the ethical value of care from a universal
species activity or set of intuitive dispositions, this does not dispute the fact of care’s necessary,
fundamental, and irreducible role in our lives—or its ethical and political stakes. Analogously,
my claim that human beings’ affective, embodied, and relational capacities for care should not be
subsumed under a historical materialist concept of labor is ultimately a historical and materialist
claim: namely, that care, like labor, is conditioned by, and generative of, material and social
relations.3
2
For Joan Tronto, parochial care is a “way to excuse the inattention of the privileged” (Moral Boundaries 146) and
paternalistic care is care “in which care givers assume that they know better than care receivers what those care
receivers need” (“Creating Caring Institutions” 161).
3
I want to acknowledge and thank Linda Alcoff and Jay Bernstein for their powerful critiques of this anti-naturalist
line in my dissertation defense. While I cannot address their criticisms here, one approach could be to strategically
bracket the question of naturalism, and, following Emma Park’s suggestion in the same defense, to highlight the
historical situatedness of human caring dispositions and norms.
6
II. The Contradictions of Care
A basic assumption of this dissertation is that care is shaped in fundamentally contradictory ways
under conditions of structural violence. By structural violence I mean relations of exploitation,
extraction, abuse, and coercion that are societally systemic, which often trace multiple and
intersecting forms of oppression, and which condition social forms, institutions, and patterns of
intimate attachment in fundamental ways. Moreover, such systemic harms are often normalized,
naturalized, and mystified by given moral and political economies of care themselves. Care is
necessary for life and world making, yet its practices and relations are also shaped by systemic
oppressions that are anathema to the life they make possible. This struggle at the heart of caring
relations is what I am addressing with the term ‘contradictions of care.’
The contradictions I address in what follows should not be understood through the
meaning of ‘structural’ implied by many Marxist uses of this term.4 The contradictions of care
also include the intimate and ethical impasses that arise when the life-giving labors and relations
of care become integral to the reproduction of violent social relations and norms. Care is often
violently and interpersonally normative: e.g. in the gendered, racialized, ethnocentric “ideologies
of care” (Dowling) mobilized by institutions and individuals alike to justify and normalize
inequalities in caring relations.
If it is true that capacities for affective and relational engagement are often differentially
shaped and attenuated vis a vis multiple and intersecting axes of oppression, this means that the
contradictions of care can, and do, show up even in attempts to address them. This is a key
4
E.g. in the notion of the contradictory “tendency of the rate of profit to fall,” the conflict between forces and
relations of production, and even the development of proletarian class consciousness itself, which are often seen by
orthodox Marxists to stem from the self-undermining tendencies intrinsic to capital’s accumulation imperative. This
tendency is by no means universal to Marxist accounts. Nancy Fraser, for example, offers a nuanced Marxist
feminist theory of structural contradiction in her discussion of the economic, political, environmental, and socialreproductive “crisis tendencies” of contemporary capitalism (“Crisis of Care?” 22-24). I discuss these arguments in
Chapter Three and Four.
7
takeaway of the notion of contradiction I develop in this dissertation. The contradictions of care
are moral and political, systemic and intimate—and as such point to the need for both ethical and
structural transformation in caring relations and norms. But this is simply to re-state the issue,
especially when it comes to organizing and praxis. In practice, this painful reality points to the
at-once collective and local nature of the problem, and radical care’s co-evolutionary relationship
with sustainable and transformational social movements.
While care is in a structural state of crisis, this plays out on the most intimate terrains of
people’s lives and thus cannot be addressed through distributive, or collectivist, approaches
alone. Unwinding the intimate and relational dimensions of these contradictions also requires
sustained and collective efforts to transform embodied patterns of relational harm and develop
new caring sensibilities as integral components of radical and liberatory social change. This is a
fraught, inevitably pluralistic, task—but one that both care ethicists and Marxist feminists have
largely, if unintentionally, avoided.
I focus on these intimate and embodied dimensions of caring contradictions, as well as
political and ethical transformation, for several reasons. First, to situate this inquiry in the
domain most proper to care itself—and thus to center lived experiences of care politically and
ethically: both the harms that characterize many caring relations, as well as the specific textures
of transformation—the sensibilities, emotions, embodiments, and relational intimacies that are
brought into play and become possible when people cultivate and mobilize care in counternormative ways. Second, to call for the respectful study of, and engagement with, the many,
often buried, practices of insurgent care that communities have developed, and continue to
deploy, in confronting, indeed contradicting, their oppression. Finally, I focus on the intimate
dimensions of caring ethics and politics to point to what legacies of feminist and intersectional
8
praxis have long taught us about the paradigm shifts and openings made possible when we
politically situate, and politicize, our lived experiences and relationships in and through
organizing against systemic harms. A politics of lived experience is indispensable to radical care:
without it, we fail to engage care on its own terms.
III. Why ‘Radical’ Care?
This dissertation argues for a radical politics of care and a radical ethics of social reproduction. I
use ‘radical’ in both the critical and revolutionary senses of the word, to name the violence at the
root of social organizations and divisions of caring labor, as well as the essential and integral role
of care in building and sustaining social change.5 And yet, caring practices and relations are
inescapably plural and particular: as care ethicists have long noted, care exceeds and confounds
theoretical abstraction and global prescription. The success of my argument thus hinges on its
ability to illuminate how historical and present inequalities in caring relations can (and do)
impact people’s lived experiences and relationships, and the specific ways they can (and do) care
in ways that resist and transform these injustices in large and small ways.
Forms of care are emergent in the sense that they are deeply engrained at psychosocial
and somatic levels and are relational and responsive—that is, unpredictable (Puig de la Bellacasa
21, 138). Our experiences of giving and receiving care, or lack thereof, shape the very contours
of our sensory worlds and embodied relations to others. And yet we can cultivate new
embodiments, sensibilities, emotions, and capacities for relationship by cultivating relational
5
A few crucial and related points I want to make clear are: i). innumerable instances of radical care already exist in
social movements and political struggles; ii). they are essential to sustaining and building these struggles; and iii).
they often constitute their most revolutionary as well as endangered edges. Caring elements of struggle are thus
often subject to brutal repression from the State and reactionary forces. J Edgar Hoover’s infamous characterization
of the Black Panther Party’s breakfast program as the greatest internal security threat to the US is a paradigmatic
case in point. See Spade 2020.
9
containers and responding in creative ways to the needs of others, ourselves, our communities,
and our struggles.
Once again this opens more questions than it answers, and points to the need for engaged
and embodied learning: learning, for example, methods of political and ethical education that
unwind the vigilance, relax the hyper-attunement, enliven the insensibility, and diffuse the
entitlement through which social inequalities shape or attenuate people’s capacities to give and
receive care. Or to notice and intervene in the often subtle and intersubjective mechanisms
through which care is extracted, denied, or coerced. In this sense, my argument about radical
care follows care ethical insights about the specific and relational nature of care, which, in its
intimate pains and joys, can only be known from the inside.
At the same time, tools forged through engaged praxis can also prove useful across
contexts—e.g. by developing, practicing, and teaching modalities for how to concretely address
such inequalities and the attendant, enduring, blindness to the labor and skills of care at the
center of human life and meaning; how to cultivate and sustain the kinds of multigenerational,
international, coalitions and processes that might actively facilitate such profound shifts in caring
relations at both structural and intimate levels; or how to honor and celebrate the horizons,
however small or fleeting, that open when we do begin to care otherwise.
In this spirit, my argument builds on the following, preliminary, assertions. First, Western
moral and political theory’s neglect and even dismissal of care as an ethical and political issue is
not superficial: it points to limitations in its foundational methods and self-conceptions. If
something is indeed rotten at the core of the normative order, then simply replacing care for
justice, or construing it as a criterion of moral judgement, for example, would amount to yet
another refusal to engage care on its own terms, or contend with how deeply it unsettles the
10
methodological centrality of foundations and principles itself (Tronto 1994, Held 2006).6 Taking
care seriously requires fundamental shifts in perception: i.e. methods and tools that are capable
of sensing and engaging care as a phenomenal and material reality. In many philosophies of care,
for example, relationships rather than individuals become the primary ontological, ethical,
political, and epistemic starting point. This brings political, ethical, and epistemic realities into
view that the political atomism and normative, ontological, and epistemic individualism of
liberal models simply cannot see. Care ethicists and (many) Marxist feminists have used similar
lines of argument in their calls for radical epistemic and practical shifts in these discourses.
Acknowledging care as an essential category of moral and political thought points to the
limits of liberalism’s foundational conceptions of individualized selfhood and agency, and also
to their extension into its procedural and distributive approaches to justice.7 As I discuss in
Chapter Four, these methods for administrating goods and services, while useful tools in their
own right, rest upon a constitutive blindness to the dependencies and interdependencies of care
(Kittay). Just as liberalism’s methodological individualism cannot perceive the ethical stakes of
caring relations, its models of contractual egalitarianism are insensible to how inequalities
condition not only the normative meaning of care, but the social forms (e.g., marriage, family)
and institutions (e.g., legal, medical, electoral, social services, etc.) that necessarily mediate such
procedural and distributive mechanisms of justice. Of course, it is so often these very
institutional mediators who regulate and maintain (if not actively exploit) blatantly unjust
distributions of caring labor and access. While it would be foolish to wholly reject these tools in
6
See my critique of Michael Slote and Stephanie Collins in Chapter Two, where I develop this point.
I develop this line of thinking in my critical and generative engagement with Asha Bhandary’s liberal theory of
care (“Conditions of Radical Care”).
7
11
a time of austerity and fascist reaction, nor can we model caring politics on institutional practices
that both perpetuate and mystify caring inequalities.8
The second assumption undergirding this dissertation follows from these observations
about the deep methodological, conceptual, and practical limitations of Western normative and
political theory when it comes to addressing inequities in caring relations. Namely, that the very
social conditions which systemically devalue, exploit, extract, and invisibilize care also make it
very difficult to see care beyond the perspectives of those who continue benefit from its
disavowal as a political and moral reality. Below I argue that, in their very attempts to do such
crucial work, the traditions of care ethicists and Marxist feminism have—understandably and
perhaps inevitably—at times inadvertently resorted to assumptions of this sort.
Care ethicists’ unequivocal valuation of naturalized caring dispositions, for example,
often fail to address the structural and interpersonal dynamics of oppression they seek to center
in their work. As I argue in Chapter One and Two, an ethics of care that relies on a universalized
and naturalistic notion of care as a moral good, like the urge to make care a new foundation or
8
While the following influential authors develop incredibly important and nuanced perspectives, they, like many
care ethicists, do not fully account for the impacts of power dynamics on people’s lived experiences of, and
capacities for, care, or the need for transformative political and ethical approaches that address them. In their Care
Manifesto, the members of the ‘Care Collective” (Andreas Chatzidakis, Jamie Hakim, Jo Littler, Catherine
Rottenberg, and Lynne Segalcall) call for a “politics that puts care at the centre of life.” Their definition is rich and
expansive, including affective, material, social, and ecological dimensions: care, for them, is “a social capacity and
activity involving the nurturing of all that is necessary for the welfare and flourishing of life. Above all, to put care
centre stage means recognising and embracing our interdependencies” (Care Collective 11). However, while they
advocate for a notion of universal care in which ‘genuine care’ and collective responsibility form the keynote of
social relations at all levels, they offer only positive definitions of care as a good, and procedural approaches (e.g.,
better distribution and education) to how we might arrive at this goal. Maria Puig de la Ballacasa articulates an
emergent, ecological, and speculative ethics of care that refuses normative and a priori notions of ethical agency in
favor of a relational ontology based on interdependence and attunement, but she often lacks a critical and
transformative, that is, political, approach to how power dynamics might fundamentally condition such coemergence and relation, and thus how we might transform them in collective and politicized ways (Matters of Care,
Emma Dowling articulates very helpful notions of the structural nature of the care crisis, the insidious austeritybased ‘care fixes’ that further externalize care work onto marginalized people (The Care Crisis 32), and the
ideologies and romanticizations of care that normalize and naturalize the allocation of care work along racialized,
gendered, and national lines (70-72). However, while crucial, her structural analysis too tends to leave out the
relational and ethical transformations that must be generated alongside and through structural changes if we are not
to reproduce new forms of oppressive and exploitative power at interpersonal and institutional levels alike.
12
criterion of moral action, risk importing the leveling normativity of liberalism and its
normalization and naturalization of social inequality. Whereas normative approaches to care—
exemplified in but not limited to feminist care ethics—rarely succeed in developing a radical
perspective capable of addressing the violence conditioning normative conceptions of care, the
Marxist feminists I engage in this dissertation often fail to address the ethical and political
textures of care itself in their radical politics of social reproduction. For their part, the socialist
feminists working under the aegis of “Social Reproduction Theory” (SRT) focus on the
structural crisis tendencies informing the contradictory realities of care, as well as the reorganizations of both reproductive and productive labor necessary to overcome them—but often
fail to attend to the dimensions of life and struggle specific to social reproduction as such.
Autonomist theories of social reproduction, on the other hand, do speak about these intimate
dimensions of violence and social transformation to some extent, but their calls for the
‘commoning’ and collectivization of social reproduction do not address the challenges that the
very dispossession and exploitation of reproductive life they place at the center of their theories
pose to such efforts. Neither Marxist feminist tradition attends to the ethical dilemmas specific to
capitalist social reproduction, nor to the qualitative transformations in caring relations upon
which the success of their feminist projects depends. Like the normative presuppositions of care
ethicists, their structural focus threatens to sideline the ways that violence shapes and ruptures
people’s relationships and capacities for care, as well as the agencies they mobilize against it.
Crucially, both positions often occlude the intersectional realities that shape people’s vastly
different experiences of care, and thus the ethical and political stakes of transforming these
intimate embodiments and attachments. Socialist and autonomist feminist calls to better
13
distribute caring labor, or reclaim the commons (respectively) are necessary, but far from
sufficient, to this task.
Radical attention to care—that is, attention to the oppression at the root of how care is
distributed both interpersonally and societally as well as the horizons of transformation that
alternative relations of care make possible—shows that, despite the massive shifts in ethics and
politics they have made possible, these feminist approaches to caring ethics and labor have
proven somewhat inadequate on their own terms. Insofar as they rely on the political economic
and normative foundations of the frameworks they seek to overcome, neither can attend to the
layers of struggle and transformation implied by their own theories.
The final grounding assumption of my radical theory of care is that reconstituting caring
practices and relations on intimate and relational levels, in and through movement building and
collective healing, is a vital component of transforming cultures of care in ways that are aligned
with social justice—and should be viewed as inseparable from the project of politically centering
care and securing its just distribution. Perhaps such radical transformations are best conceived in
terms of possibility. This thought only occurred to me recently, in a conversation with students
on the last day of “Radical Care and Social Transformation,”9 a class that centered on many of
these issues. As a way of harvesting what we had learned together, I asked the students to take a
few minutes to freewrite on the question “what is radical care.”10 In the ensuing conversation,
these young people profoundly committed to social justice and aware of the structural violence
of our world, helped me realize that the meaning of radical care might actually be bound up with
the uncertainty of its realization. Perhaps, in the words of Pratt student and artist Moon Dang,
9
I designed this course for the Social Sciences and Cultural Studies Department at Pratt Institute and taught it in
spring 2022 and spring 2023.
10
Several of these responses form the epigraph to this Introduction.
14
radical care is both “a lifelong dedication” and the “knowing that you may not even see the fruits
of your labor and the structural changes in your lifetime.” The meaning and reality of radical
care are perhaps defined in such open-ended questioning and commitment—a work of grief as
much as joy, a militant no as much as a generative yes, an embrace of failure concomitant with
“organizing for the inevitability of a better world” (Dang).
IV. Political and Theoretical Contexts
For both political and methodological reasons, I want to situate this writing in relation to the
feminist legacies I engage with below, as well as give some immediate political context for my
work on care. Autonomist feminism has deeply informed my own politics, and I consider myself
heir to its legacy. I have experienced both the revolutionary possibilities as well as the political
dilemmas of this tradition from the inside, and feel responsible for, and accountable to, it. For the
past decade and a half, I have been part of feminist, queer, and antiracist projects centered on
militant social reproduction11 in Oakland, Mexico City, and New York City. Feminist organizing
projects deployed within and against radical left movement spaces, for example, have played a
crucial part in cultural shifts in these communities, which were shockingly misogynistic even 15
years ago, and have drawn from the organizing strategies and theory of thinkers like Silvia
Federici, Mariarosa Dalla Costa, Margaret Prescod, and Selma James. Most essentially, I view
my work as connected to the tradition of witches and whores that this tradition uplifts, pays
homage to, and actively supports in both theory and practice.
Likewise, while I am not a socialist, my graduate studies and friendship with Cinzia
Arruzza—a crucial organizer of the international feminist strike and a leading voice in the
socialist tradition of social reproduction theory, have deeply informed my work. While I disagree
11
Zhivka Valiavicharska and I, to our knowledge, first used the term ‘militant social reproduction’ and later
‘militant care’ in a 2015 piece of the same name, and afterwards, in the Care Cadre project I discuss below.
15
with Sue Ferguson that this strike was an essentially socialist endeavor, it is true that its New
York, and US, contingents were overwhelmingly influenced by socialist feminist perspectives
and organizing strategies. My own work organizing for this strike, and the political alliances it
made possible, have had a transformative role on the perspectives developed here, as have my
friendships and long-standing political discussions with thinkers in this tradition, some of whom
I engage below.
My engagement with autonomist feminist theories of social reproduction in Mexico,
Chile and Argentina stems from these political contexts. My first introduction to this legacy of
social reproduction feminism was in a reading group on Autonomia facilitated by Raquel
Gutiérrez in 2010, while I was living in Mexico City. I returned to Gutierrez’s work, and the
work of political collaborators such as Susana Draper and Veronica Gago, while organizing for
the international feminist strike in 2017. Cinzia Arruzza and I discuss the leadership of these
thinkers—and the Ni Una Menos collective in particular—in the recent evolution of militant
feminist organizing and theoretical production on the terrain of social reproduction (“The Politics
of Social Reproduction”). This international organizing and cross pollination provided context
for Cristina Vega, Raquel Martínez-Buján and Myriam Paredes’s incredible edited volume
Cuidado, comunidad y común: Experiencias cooperativas en el sostenimiento de la vida (Care,
community and the commons: Cooperative experiences in the maintenance of life)12, and
Gutiérrez’s Horizontes comunitario-populares: Producción de lo común más allá de las políticas
estado-céntricas (Popular and communitarian horizons: producing the commons beyond state-
12
Unless otherwise noted, all translations from Spanish are my own.
16
centric politics) both of which I intended to write about at length in the final chapters,13 and
which significantly inform my perspectives on social reproduction below.
It is equally important to point to the limits of my thinking in relation to these Latin
American lineages of social reproduction theory, as well as the intersectional feminist
approaches that deeply inform the arguments I make below. Intersectionality is a legacy of Black
feminism that pays particular attention to the lived experiences of those impacted by multiple,
interlocking oppressions. Patricia Hill Collins, for example, contends that intersectionality is a
critical social theory grounded in the experience, knowledge, and self-definition of Black women
(Collins Black Feminist Thought).14
I have accordingly attempted to position this work at the margins of intersectional theory
and the decolonial perspectives of many Latin American social reproduction theorists—
especially since I often address difficult and intimate realities of oppression I have not
experienced as a white US citizen. For example, my argument below is that the epistemic and
political paradigm shifts inaugurated by intersectional feminists are essential for understanding
and transforming care. I also claim that intersectional approaches to centering lived experience in
theory creation and political activism provide key methodological modeling for ethical and
political considerations of care. My success in doing so hinges on my ability to center the work
and experiences of those at the frontlines of these struggles without re-inscribing the
contradictions I am attempting to elaborate and address. This poses a real danger beyond what I
13
Due to the time limitations of this writing, I was not able to write the final chapter on radical care, which was to
draw heavily on these works and put them in conversation with transformative justice traditions in the US.
14
While intersectionality has been problematically appropriated and misused in many academic contexts (Collins
Intersectionality as Critical Social Theory, Hopkins) it has also been utilized by marginalized communities in
respectful and expansive ways. For example, Eli Clare and the Sins Invalid collective draw upon intersectional
theory to analyze how white and middle class perspectives were inadvertently centered in discourses and organizing
strategies of disability rights, and call on intersectional perspectives in centering the most marginalized voices in the
radical organizing praxis of disability justice.
17
can decipher with my individual good intentions, since we cannot simply will oppression out of
our selves or relations or assume that intent or attention alone will facilitate transparency in
caring relations. My ethical and political aim is thus to heed Maria Lugones’ guidance and strive
to “imbue” the social positioning—and selves—I bring to this work with the ambiguity that
historically informs them (189-190).
My work on radical care work is also deeply informed by modalities of politicized
somatics and transformative justice. I have studied and been in community with practitioners and
teachers of the Institute for the Study of Somatic Sex Education, a radical healing modality
grounded in queer and sex-worker activism, for the past six years. I am currently finishing my
final project—which involves building curriculum on counter-normative, embodied, and erotic
ethical education—under the mentorship of Corinne Diachuck and Kai Cheng Thom. My work
developing trauma-informed, consent-based, ethical practices and peer support structures aligned
with values and practices of transformative justice with and for this institute has been crucial to
the embodied and transformative perspectives on care I develop here.
Finally, the theoretical framework I develop below has roots in my experiences
organizing with a collective devoted to radical care. My thesis concerning the non-transparency
of care and resultant need for collective and embodied approaches to its transformation
originated in the beauty and failures of a project on radical care, which we lovingly and
ironically termed the ‘Care Cadre.’ Many of the insights presented here were generated out of
conversations, inspired by collective practice, and forged in response to the possibilities and
limits of this project that I was an integral part of, and cared very deeply about. This collective
was an attempt to collectively theorize, build, and politicize structures of community care in
anarchist communities in NYC and the SF Bay Area in the aftermath of incidents of sexual
18
violence. There were crossovers with transformative justice frameworks in its orientation to
survivor centeredness and peer support, collective skill-building, anti-carceral approach, and
political orientation to care—although we rarely used the language of transformative justice to
describe it. Both the power and the failure of this collective imbue and motivate my argument
here. The seemingly inevitable ways it fell apart along the very cleavages that brought us
together, despite the presence of incredible skill and much good will, speaks to the contradictory
realities of care, the problems they pose for organizing practice, and the level of skill and
attunement needed to hold and confront them. The problems and possibilities that came out of
this project have both guided and motivated this work on care and allowed me to belong to this
inquiry.
V. Organization of Chapters
My first chapter critically engages care ethics from the perspective of the ethical contradictions
of care. Given the ways that exploitative and extractive social relations are normalized,
naturalized, and mystified by moral economies of care themselves, I argue that we cannot simply
construe care as an ethical and political good—or the violent devaluation of the work of care and
those who perform or rely upon it as simply deviations from this good. Insofar as caring
practices and relations are shaped by structural violence even in their most intimate dimensions,
grounding the ethics and politics of care in naturalized understandings of care is insufficient.
Posing a deep critique of liberal individualistic approaches, care ethics disrupts the privatization
of care, moves the agency of ethics from individual rational agents to relational ontology and
praxis, and sheds light on the essential need for moral and political education to care. However,
its reliance on what I term ‘naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care’ precludes a true
19
politicization of care, and thus ultimately runs counter to the very feminist politics of experience
that inform this tradition.
Globally and locally, social organizations and divisions of caring labor express and
reproduce racialized, colonial, and class—as well as gender—oppressions. Intersectional
feminist authors have focused on the intersectional violence at play in caring practices and
relations, showing that i.) the ideological and material devaluation of caring labor and those who
perform cannot be understood through single issue frames, and ii.) this devaluation is not
incidental but structural to systems and institutions predicated on inequality and exploitation.
My second chapter elaborates the challenges these insights pose to the naturalistic conceptions of
care presented in the prior chapter, claiming that the elements of care naturalized by care ethics15
are themselves implicated in structures of violence that generate contradictions in caring
practices—even and precisely at intimate levels. If caring relations are not only capable of
perpetuating structural harms at the most intimate levels, but of doing so even in attempts to
transform these conditions of harm, this has implications for how we collectively conceive of,
and generate, politically transformative caring practices.
My third chapter critically engages Marxist feminist social reproduction theory from the
perspective of the social and material contradictions of caring labor. In both autonomist and
socialist strains of social reproduction theory, materialist feminists have pointed to a crisis of
care defined by a contradiction between capital’s drive to accumulation and extraction on the one
hand, and the ever more thinly stretched capacities for daily and intergenerational social
reproduction on the other. However, the intimate and ethical contradictions presented in the prior
chapters pose deep problems to viewing care solely through the lens of labor. While they have
15
E.g., attention (responsiveness, empathy, other-directedness, etc.)
20
theorized these structural contradictions of care in terms of the exploitation and extraction
essential to contemporary racial capitalism and international divisions of caring labor, both
traditions of social reproduction theory have largely failed to attend to the essential role of affect
and intimacy in the politics of social reproduction—both in the sense of the violence of care in
crisis as well as care’s transformative possibilities. As with ethical formations that naturalize
caring relations shaped by and reproductive of intersectional violence, feminist theories of social
reproduction are stymied if they remain beholden to socioeconomic understandings of class and
labor politics built upon the denial of care and reproductive labor as political realities and sites of
social struggle.
My fourth and final chapter points to the need for radical ethical formations on the terrain
of social reproduction that are attentive to the intimate contradictions and possibilities specific to
care. I begin this chapter by briefly framing autonomist and socialist feminist approaches to the
crisis of care, which they each see as defined by the structural contradictions of contemporary
capitalism. Building on the arguments of the prior chapter, I then claim that the labor-centric
ethical paradigms developed by both traditions foreclose serious engagement with the crisis
conditions they themselves outline, particularly when it comes to the paradigmatically
reproductive labors of care and sex themselves. In the final section, I advance the thesis that the
‘affective labor debates’ through which Marxist feminists have attempted to address their own
historical shortcomings around care in fact point back to the limits of the labor paradigm itself.
In this sense, this chapter mirrors the argumentative structure of Chapter Two, in which I
claimed that care ethicists’ naturalistic ethics limited their ability to politically address the
multiple and intersecting oppressions at play in many caring relations. Here I elaborate on how
the labor-centric paradigms of autonomist feminism and SRT have undermined these traditions’
21
ability to contend with the ethical dilemmas and possibilities specific to social reproduction.
Moreover, valorizing care in multiple locations of struggle reveals that radical politics of care
involve more than rendering necessary services and collectivizing the privatized domains of care.
I argue we must also work, in struggle, to qualitatively transform modes of care rooted in
domination and subordination—often in ways that run counter to state and NGO logics—and
attempt to show how affective and embodied dimensions of care are essential elements of social
reproduction, pointing to “the revolutionary transformations, both psychic and ethical, that are
demanded of us” (Cornell and Seely 17).
Addressing care politically and ethically entails not only attending to the struggle at the
heart of care, but to the care at the heart of struggle. The critique of care presented in my
dissertation thus points not only to the violence socially and materially embedded in caring
practices and relations, but to the generative political and ethical possibilities of radical care
demonstrated by marginalized communities of struggle past and present. However, it also points
to the political problem posed by the fact that our very capacities for affective and relational
engagement can be differentially shaped vis a vis multiple and intersecting axes of oppression. I
conclude by pointing to traditions of transformative justice and politicized somatics, as
exemplary modalities offering resources and insights for practically, intimately, and politically
addressing the often-tragic dilemmas of learning to care otherwise in a violent world. Radical
care is, of necessity, a collective endeavor, and should be viewed as conditioned upon, as well as
a condition of, sustainable and transformational social movements. These traditions, grounded in
the work of marginalized people within diverse social movement spaces, offer concrete skills
that integrate ethical, affective, and political education to care with organizing for systemic
change.
22
The question of how to collectively care for each other and ourselves in the shadows of
structural violence is an open and living one. While it is crucial to value care and place it at the
center of moral and political thinking, addressing conditions of endemic structural and intimate
violence also requires sustained and collective efforts to transform embodied patterns of
relational harm and develop new caring sensibilities as integral components of radical and
liberatory social change.
This opens a final, perhaps perennially open-ended, question: namely, how to bring care
into the structure of theory itself.16 This question too lies at the heart of this work, and is a
horizon towards which it only manages to gesture.
16
The structure of this question is inspired by Maria Lugones’s call to imbue “plurality in the very structure of a
theory” (Perigrinajes, 174-175).
23
Chapter One:
How Can a Radical Ethics of Care be Possible? 17
17
I use the singular ‘a’ here and in the title of my third chapter to present the quasi-transcendental structure of my
argument, which claims that care is both ethical and political all the way down. However, the idea that there could
be a radical ethics of care and a radical politics of social reproduction is antithetical to the culturally and historically
specific realities of care—as well as the social emergence of radical caring practices and relations, which are
fundamentally plural and responsive to the needs of the communities who articulate them.
24
I. Introduction: Contradictions in The Ethics of Care
We each live inside the contradictions of care in multiple and often conflicting ways.
They form the social and material substance of our desires, our attachments, and the ways our
intimate labors and our selves are exploited and made invisible or enact this violence on others.
We thus cannot attend to care’s contradictions as external relations, as if they were simply forced
on us from the outside by nefarious forces rather than at the same time constituting our most
intimate bonds and private longings. Nor can we view or address them as ambiguities or
ambivalences intrinsic or natural to care, lest we strip care of its very politics—the historical
contingencies by which it is structurally devalued and exploited, as well as the historical ways in
which communities have fostered care as an element of their survival and resistance. While the
second half of this dissertation speaks to these concerns by articulating a politics of social
reproduction that centers the qualitative, ethical, transformation of caring practices and relations,
the present chapters do so through a critical discussion of care ethics in light of intersectional
analysis and politics.
My understanding of radical care differs from care ethics as it has been developed by
feminist philosophers in that I claim that we must situate the politics of care in contradictory
social and material conditions of life-making rather than naturalistic or universal understandings
of care as a value. My argument in this chapter is that care ethical appeals to ostensibly intuitive
dimensions of care as the basis of the ethics and politics of care ultimately amount to a
naturalization of care. This is problematic insofar as it posits the violence socially embedded in
caring relations to be a moral aberration external to—rather than an essential component of—
oppressive social forms, institutions, and relations. Alternatively, such naturalization risks
construing the contradictions of care as forms of ambivalence internal to practices and relations
25
of caring as such. Both positions limit our diagnoses of the political and ethical problems posed
by care’s integral relation to structural violence, and our capacities for imagining and cultivating
care’s positive, transformational role in movements for social change.
The arguments of this chapter and the next rely on problematizing what I term the
naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies that care ethicists hold to be the basis of care’s moral
value. This tradition largely shares a consensus regarding not only the moral value of care as
such, but the idea that this moral value derives from intuitive caring capacities such as attention,
other-directedness, responsiveness, and receptivity. Because these intuitive dispositions or
motivational attitudes are fundamental to care, they are taken by most care ethicists to be
naturalistically given moral goods. In the following pages I problematize this basic position,
arguing that the paradigmatic concept of caring attention is itself socially embedded and thus a
political site of contestation and struggle. In other words, I use the cumbersome language of
naturalistic/naturalized care epistemologies because of what I see as the potentially dangerous
equivocation between care ethicists’ naturalistic derivation of ethics and a naturalization of the
oppressive norms and relations that shape and distribute our capacities for care. This tendency
within care ethics runs counter to the very commitments through which this tradition has set
itself apart: its relational ontology, pluralist and situated ethics, orientation to affective education,
and ultimately the very feminist politics that inform its approach.
Joan Tronto deepens this care ethical approach with her political argument for the ethics
of care. In calling for a more caring society, Tronto re-configures traditional boundaries of moral
and political thought by centering the political as well as ethical value of care as a species
activity. I articulate my argument in conversation with Tronto because her move to bring care
from the margins to the center of politics remains grounded in such naturalistically derived
26
dimensions of care, and thus still relies on an abstract and apolitical notion of care. While Tronto
brings care into view as a constituent force of politics, she fails to engage the always already
political realities of caring practices and dispositions themselves.
Before embarking on my argument, it is important to situate it in terms of the claims of
this dissertation, and thus flesh out what I understand to be the problem that care’s contradictions
pose to the ethics of care. Care is an essential condition of human life and meaning. From the
midwifing of new life, to nurturing the young, the work of sex, and the tending of death, trauma,
disability, and physical and mental illness, care is the social, material, and emotional tie that
binds humans together and enables our survival and potential flourishing. In this general sense,
then, it is indeed necessary to ethically and politically value care, and to place care at the center
of political theory and action. But precisely insofar as it bears the burden of establishing and
sustaining social bonds and is thus a necessary condition of life and world making, care must be
understood as socially and materially constituted. Care is not outside of the social: this is a
crucial feminist point. As I have argued in the introduction to this dissertation, this means that
caring practices and relations not only constitute life, but are at the same time constitutively
shaped by, and can also reproduce, forms of violence that are anathema to it.
The specifically ethical contradiction that this chapter begins with arises from the tension
presented by the need to value care as an essential condition and component of life and meaning,
and at the same time to politically analyze and oppose the ways in which care is shaped by and
reproduces violent social forms and relations, both structurally and intimately. This ethical
contradiction is laid bare when we consider that, insofar as ideologies of care18 serve an essential
18
What Emma Dowling terms “Ideologies of Caring” (85) mystify the power relations that shape and attenuate
caring relations. “Care is deeply enmeshed within power relations, but these often disappear behind what kind of
caring, and by whom, is considered normal.” Ideologies of care naturalize, normalize, invisibize and individualize
unequal social organizations and divisions of caring labor that determine who receives and gives care. For Dowling,
27
role in maintaining structural and intimate violence, care precisely appears as a naturalized ethic
in cultural and social life. Caring practices and relations are essential conditions of life that span
cultural, intimate, and cognitive dimensions, and therefore involve modes of knowing,
perceiving, and relating that are highly subtle and skilled, and are also culturally and historically
specific. At the same time, this life sustaining capacity is structurally devalued.19 The systemic
exploitation and extraction of the care performed by marginalized individuals and groups of
people forms a fundamental condition and component of multiple forms of oppression. Crucially
for my argument here is the fact that this devaluation and harnessing of care depends upon
naturalizing and mystifying the exploitation of those who perform underpaid or free caring labor,
normalizing the institutional neglect of and violence towards those without access to caring
resources and infrastructures,20 and moralizing the subjugation of those who are, in the words of
Evelyn Nakano Glenn, forced to care (2012). Upholding care as a value without attending to the
conditions of care’s devaluation risks reproducing the material and ideological conditions of
racialized, gendered, and colonial divisions of caring labor, and thus the moral justifications for
exploitative and oppressive relations of care that rest upon racialized, colonial and/or gendered
characteristics. In the next chapter I elaborate on his problem in conversation with intersectional
these ideologies include how women have been “subordinated within the nuclear family (and elsewhere),
performing housework and care work – the “‘labours of love’ that [are] mystified as a natural female vocation.”
They also include colonial and paternalistic assumptions about culture “in which migrant workers are designated as
especially suitable carers,” as well as ableist narratives of deservingness critiqued by “mental health and disability
rights movements who have been vocal about the needs, wishes and desires of care recipients, fighting the
stigmatization of disability, as well as demanding adequate care.”
19
I discuss the interlocking racialized, international, and gendered dimensions of this devaluing and deskilling of
care labor at length in the following chapter.
20
Police and prison abolitionist calls to defund the police illustrate this point, exemplified in the rallying call made
by BLM organizers to invest in “care not cops” in handling issues such as mental health crises, domestic violence
and substance dependency which can be exacerbated by conditions of poverty and structural racism. See e.g.,
https://www.8toabolition.com/invest-in-care-not-cops. Disability Justice and Disability Rights organizers offer
crucial perspectives on the institutional violence and neglect faced not only by those who perform care labor, but
also those whose living depends on it. For example, disabled individuals are much more likely to face intimate
partner and sexual violence, due to social isolation and lack of available services and community infrastructures.
28
feminist thinkers, pointing to how apparently intuitive elements of care are themselves shaped by
and reproduce the interlocking oppressions embedded in social organizations of care. Upholding
these dimensions of care as naturalistically derived and universally accessible goods also
obscures the deeply political caring labor that so often sustains the survival and struggles of
marginalized communities.
The aim of the present chapter is to highlight the feminist revolution in ethics presented
by care ethicists, and to show how valuing naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care as the
foundation of this ethics runs counter to these feminist aims. The tradition of philosophical care
ethics is right to center the transformative dimensions of care: its role, for example, in ethical
education, or the value of relational skills such as empathy and caring attention in fostering an
ethos of recognition and understanding. But this tradition does not go far enough in critiquing
how these qualities—their forced hypertrophy in some and enabled atrophy in others, their
violent extraction as well as their sometimes-cynical deployment—are equally instrumental in
maintaining conditions of structural violence. Joan Tronto and Bernice Fischer’s famous
definition of care is paradigmatic of both these transformative and problematic dimensions of
care ethics: “On the most general level we suggest that caring be viewed as a species activity that
includes everything that we do to maintain, continue and repair our ‘world’ so that we can live in
it as well as possible. That world includes our bodies, our selves, and our environment, all of
which we seek to interweave in a complex, life sustaining web” (Moral Boundaries 103). We
can see why this definition is so commonly cited; it is very helpful in its clarity and scope. It also
summarizes many care ethical concerns in that: i.) it defines care as an essential, life generating
activity; ii.) it moves from this fact of the matter to care as a robust moral value; and iii.) it
develops an ethics and politics stemming from the feminized skills and practices of caring.
29
I want to be clear that my argument follows care ethicists’ call to value care and those
who perform it—indeed, I believe that politically, ethically, and materially valuing care the labor
and relations of caregivers is an essential component of social transformation and a condition of
planetary survival. However, this definition, which is precisely intended to be broad enough to
encompass the political as well as ethical dimensions of care, elides the very specifications of
good care that care ethicists are after. Tronto and Fischer are right that care is an essential, if not
the essential, condition of life and world making, and are also right to value care and in so doing
to demand a paradigm shift in the location and nature of political and moral philosophy. But
insofar as it is inextricably embedded in social life and its reproduction, naturalistically valuing
care as a species activity hinders this sort of critical and transformational perspective. As I argue
in the second half of this chapter and the next, valuing care in the ways that Tronto, Held, and
Kittay call for requires challenging its structural devaluation and the conditions that produced it.
My claim is that this means attending to the oppressions at the root of social organizations and
divisions of caring labor as well as the differential impacts they can have on the very caring
dispositions that care ethicists see as the naturalistic source of good care as such.
In Forced to Care: Coercion and Caregiving in America, Nakano Glenn outlines what
she terms the “material and ideological underpinnings of the social organization of care” in the
US context.21 She terms these material and ideological dimensions of care coercive because they
have forced women, and especially poor, racialized, and migrant women, into the work of care.
21
“The social organization of care has been rooted in diverse forms of coercion that have induced women to assume
responsibility for caring for family members and that have tracked poor, racial minority, and immigrant women into
positions entailing caring for others. The forms of coercion have varied in degree, directness, and explicitness but
nonetheless have served to constrain and direct women's choices; the net consequence of restricted choice has been
to keep caring labor "cheap," that is, free (in the case of family care labor) or low waged (in the case of paid care
labor)” (5).
30
Crucially, this involves forms of moralization that contribute to, and obscure, the harm caused by
these unjust distributions and social organizations of care:
In the United States the social organization of care has been characterized by reliance on the
private household, feminization and racialization of care, devaluation of care work and care
workers, and abnegation of community and state responsibility for caring. The persistence of
these characteristics, despite (or perhaps because of) the frequent lip service given to the
spiritual and moral qualities of caregiving, is rooted in fundamental philosophical principles,
social structures, and cultural practices… (6, emphasis mine).
These moral dimensions of obligation are an especially insidious form of coercion in that they
politically and economically cement the degrading feminization and racialization of care
precisely by naturalizing and privatizing it: by valuing caregiving as a virtuous obligation while
simultaneously socially and materially devaluing this work as well as those who perform it.
It is difficult to account for this coercive normativity with an ethics that values care based
on intuitive moral distinctions or an ideal of relational transparency (what Kittay terms a
“transparent self”). These naturalistic presuppositions also exist in uneasy relation to care ethics’
feminist legacy and inheritance, in particular the politics of experience and relation at the core of
its methodological innovations. But morally valuing and politicizing the lived and relational
intimacies of care has proven a difficult line to walk. While they nearly universally root their
ethics in the political philosophy of the Women’s Liberation Movement (and many were activists
themselves), they often fall on the conservative side of the dilemma—defending maternal care
with exquisite and nuanced detail, for example, yet rarely revisiting feminist critiques of the
social forms that continue to mystify and devalue it. As Frigga Haug puts it in a critique of Carol
Gilligan that also applies to care ethics more generally: “what is being suggested is that the
problem of morals—and their consequences—can be resolved in a simple change of values
31
themselves, instead of by transforming the practices which determine the meaning of what is or
is not ethical itself” (42).
II. The Value of Care: Care Ethics’ Feminist Critique of Moral Philosophy
In this section, I discuss care ethics as a feminist ethics grounded in the experience of relation
and unpack the work of care ethicists in both critiquing the Western canon of moral philosophy
and expanding feminist insights about the nature and location of ethical engagement. In doing so,
I draw out the transformative and critical dimensions of this body of work, the crucial role of
affective and relational experience to its analysis and methods and point to the resultant
paradigm shift this tradition poses to understandings of the subject, ontology, and methodologies
of traditional philosophical ethics. However, in the following sections I also argue that to take
these feminist claims seriously, care ethics cannot begin from an understanding of care as a
naturalistically or universally derived norm but rather as a location of political constitution,
transformation, and struggle.
While I ultimately do offer a political critique of care ethics, it is important to keep the
problem as we have developed it in view. Namely, that despite, perhaps because of, the
structural devaluation and systemic exploitation, extraction and invisibilization of the labor of
care and those who perform it, viewing care as a naturalized moral good is deeply socially and
culturally engrained.22 This is not to downplay the care ethical achievement of bringing care to
the center of moral thinking, but rather to affirm what many care ethicists point to as an obvious
fact: care is indeed already an, if not the, essential human value and site of ethical formation.
Thus, while I bring up the problems with this naturalized approach through a discussion of care
22
Given its centrality and necessity to social life on the one hand, and its structural privatization and devaluation on
the other, the dearth of moral and political theorizing regarding care is both shocking and not at all surprising.
32
ethics in particular, I am also aiming my critique at broader social tendencies to not only
naturalize and invisibilize the work of care, but in doing so, to uncritically value it.
Care ethics has roots in feminist insights about the political import of lived experience
(Held 23). I follow Bubek’s claim that in both its critical and generative capacities care ethics is
an essentially collective and ongoing feminist research project.23 Its founding insights regarding
the need to value and center the feminized experiences marginalized by dominant ethical
narratives, as well as the need for collective critique and ethical engagement in addressing this
problem, are methodological achievements deeply rooted in feminist politics. In these respects,
care ethics resonates with the intersectional feminist perspectives I discuss in the next chapter.
While care ethics tends to rely on a generalized (and thus often implicitly white and middle
class) conception of women, and intersectional feminism seeks to center the experiences of
multiply marginalized people, both traditions are rooted in experiences and methods—
"subjugated knowledges” (Collins, Black Feminist Thought 9)—that fundamentally question
dominant normative and political understanding.
The feminist achievement regarding the moral and political importance of lived
experience structures even many of the more conservative approaches to care ethics. In a
Different Voice, Carol Gilligan’s presentation of “a new way of thinking that begins with the
premise that we live not in separation but in relationship” (“Letter to Readers”) offered a radical
alternative to the abstract rules and principles of Western moral theory. Rather, Gilligan’s
“interest lies in the interaction of experience and thought, in different voices and the dialogues to
23
“The ethic of care is best understood as an ongoing collective research project which, based on Gilligan's classic
research presented in her book In a Different Voice, is aimed at working out the form and content of the ethic of
care, what concepts, considerations, values, and virtues would be characteristic of it, and how it relates to traditional
moral theory” (11). Note that offers a rare materialist account to account for the systemic exploitation of unpaid care
labor while still endorsing the care ethical tradition (11-12).
33
which they give rise, in the way we listen to ourselves and to others, in the stories we tell about
our lives” (Different Voice 2). In her critique of the observational bias of Lawrence Kohlberg’s
theories of moral development, which pose a suspiciously Kantian model of universal ethical
principles and autonomous moral judgment as the highest moral achievement, Gilligan
recognizes and schematizes a different moral voice grounded in historically and socially
feminized values of care, empathy, connectedness and relation. Importantly, this is a socially
embedded theory: her critique of the implicit masculinity of Western moral norms and valuation
of implicitly feminized ones empirically emerged from her discussions of moral experience with
hundreds of women and girls.
It is right, as many have done, to call attention to the largely upper middle class, white
and traditionally educated perspectives of Gilligan’s subjects24 (and thus arguably her reversion
to the same sorts of implicit bias she critiques in Kohlberg). But even given these flaws, it is
important to note the paradigm shift in ethics that Gilligan inaugurated by grounding her moral
psychology in lived experiences of care and relation. Her feminist ethics are evinced not simply
in the attention she pays to the voices of women, but in how she highlights and schematizes
feminized experiences25 of lived, embodied care as a foundation and critical anchor of moral
thought and action. Thus, when she criticizes the moral theory of Kohlberg for the observational
bias towards masculinized experiences, she does so through the different sense of ethical value
that emerges in experiences of relation. In doing so, she offers both a positive view of ethical life
and a critique of dominant moral thought and action. In her discussion of gender differences in
childhood conflict resolution, for example, Gilligan explains how the value that girls placed on
24
See Joan Tronto’s critique of Gilligan’s construal of care ethics as ideologically privileging a white and middleclass standpoint (Moral Boundaries 77-81). And Patricia Hill Collins (Black Feminist Throught 200, 6).
25
I choose to read Gilligan generously on the issue of gender essentialism, following from her claim to be attending
to these issues not according to gender as such, but to theme.
34
the continuity of relations vs. the continuity of the game forms a site of education to sensitivity
and responsiveness rather than rule following and competitive achievement (8-11). In
highlighting the moral development of the responsibility and relationality involved in feminized
caring and connection versus rights and rules, Gilligan thus elaborates not only a different moral
voice, but a different notion of what ethics is and should be.
The feminist insight into the moral value of feminized experiences of caregiving on the
one hand, and the critique of abstract, individualistic, and implicitly masculine ethical norms on
the other inform the relational commitments and social ontology of the care ethical tradition.
Women’s gendered social positions and ways of navigating the world often inform the ethics
they uphold. This of course is a painful situation not easily teased apart from gender divisions of
labor and their attendant humiliations and degradations.
It is thus no coincidence that nearly every account of care ethics also begins with a
genealogy explicitly linking this philosophical tradition to insights and struggles of the women’s
liberation movement.26 This self-conception is directly related to the prior point: care ethics can
be seen as an attempt to flesh out the ethical substance of the feminist claim to the primacy of
lived experience. As Virginia Held states: “[t]he feminist validation of women’s experience has
had important consequences in ethics. It has led to a fundamental critique of the moral theories
that were (and to a large extent still are) dominant and to the development of alternative feminist
approaches to morality” (Ethics of Care 23). Beginning from a validation of experience poses
deep challenges to moral systems based upon autonomous decision-making agents engaged in
rational disinterested calculation (which, Held notes, is common to both Kantian and Utilitarian
26
Michael Slote is an important exception. Slote does not claim to be a feminist but calls for ‘human’ morality
grounded in Western sentimentalist philosophical tradition. This papers over of the deeply feminist nature of the
paradigmatic and methodological shifts in ethics that are the subject of this chapter, as well as the self-consciously
feminist roots of this tradition.
35
approaches to morality and justice and even many accounts of the cultivation of individual
virtue). In opposition to these theories, she claims that receiving and giving care is the ur-ethical
experience. Indeed, it is this “truly universal experience of care” that makes it the “most basic
and most comprehensive value” (3, my emphasis).
Held lays out several elements that help to flesh out care ethics as a feminist moral
theory.27 Taken together, the following elements of the ethics of care also illustrate her claim that
care is best understood as both a value and a practice: a practice insofar as responding to the
needs of others in sustained ways is work, and a value insofar as caring practices involve not
only motivational orientation toward human others, but reflective engagement on the adequacy
of caring practices to their needs. While the details are contested,28 some understanding of this
inseparability of the normative and practical dimensions of care is common to many care ethical
approaches. My aim in reprising these elements of care ethics that Held presents is not only to
outline care ethicists’ feminist development of ethics in opposition to the philosophical canon,
but ultimately to show how they point beyond this tradition. That is, I want to show that
centering care in feminist ways not only re-frames the subject, location, and agency of ethics, but
necessitates feminist politics: a point that I develop in conversation with the work of Tronto in
the following section.
For Held, the ethics of care begins from the dependency needs of concrete human others.
Indeed, for Stephanie Collins the claim “that dependency relationships generate responsibilities”
constitutes the slogan and criterion uniting diverse care ethical perspectives (Core of Care Ethics
27
I have not followed the exact order of Held’s presentation and have combined her discussion of abstract moral
reasoning and care ethics’s critique of liberal individualism. See Held, pgs 9-15.
28
Tronto, for example, deemphasizes this motivational dimension and focuses on care as a practice and a
disposition, placing much more emphasis on its laboring elements. Held has been critiqued (rightly in my opinion)
for deemphasizing the labor of care and thus taking a problematic view on some forms of paid caring labor as
inadequate to her criteria of care as a value.
36
2). Held and Tronto also focus on the particularity of these demands that others place on us and
to which ethical responsiveness thus attends. This focus on dependency also forms the hinge of
Kittay’s feminist dependency critique of equality which elaborates how “a conception of society
viewed as an association of equals masks inevitable dependencies” (Love’s Labor xi). For Kittay,
insofar as liberal theories of justice focus on independence as the criterion of equality and moral
decision, they do not contend with the need to care for dependents as a foundational element of
social life, and thus preclude true social justice. As the theories Kittay, Held, Tronto, Gilligan
and others illuminate, centering on the skills and capacities involved in meeting the needs of
dependent and interdependent others deeply problematizes conceptions of moral judgment
grounded in rational and disengaged moral calculation and action.
The claim here is not only that our relation to dependency is constitutive of ethics, but
that human social life as such is grounded in the experience of responding to and competently
meeting needs (Tronto). In the first instance, care is taken as the inaugural attentive and enduring
response to these individual human needs both in and beyond intimate settings. Centering
dependency requires a paradigm shift in moral understanding by asking into the relational
conditions of moral engagement and agency. The second feature of the ethics of care that Held
draws attention to is the essential role that emotions play moral decision making, when seen from
the relational point of view of care. Competently practicing the ethics of care requires affective
ethical education: “such emotions as sympathy, empathy, sensitivity and responsiveness [as well
as anger] are seen as the kind of moral emotions that need to be cultivated not only to help in the
implementation of the dictates of reason but to better ascertain what morality recommends” (10).
Both valuing and cultivating affective competency is also central to Nel Noddings’ more
conservative approach to care ethics which I discuss below. For Noddings, our ability to cultivate
37
an ethical ideal of care is grounded in a universal sense of natural caring. Nurturing this ideal,
however, requires ethical and emotional education. Both Noddings and Held emphasize care’s
motivational as well as practical dimensions—both speak of good care as a capacity to attend
and attune to (to be engrossed with, in Noddings’ language) the needs of concrete others in
emotional as well as material ways.29
According to Held, care ethics also launches a feminist critique of the public/private
divide upon which many understanding of political and moral philosophy implicitly or explicitly
depend. Valuing care and relation as essential to and formative of ethical and political life
challenges masculinist ideas about the private, natural, and apolitical nature of domestic and
intimate life and the public, disembodied, and rational nature of politics, policy, and law.30 As
Tronto also notes, critiquing this divide requires more than morally upholding so-called
‘women’s work.’ Ethically valuing care, rather, involves a critique of how the socially necessary
labor performed by women has, within bourgeois Western culture, been socially relegated to the
private and natural: a patriarchal and capitalist maneuver that feminist insight has long reframed
as a political reality and call to social transformation. The politics of care from a care ethical
perspective is also deeply indebted to this feminist insight regarding the proper domain of the
political, which not only questions the private/public divide but draws attention to the historically
and socially embedded nature of care as a site of political contestation and agency.
Finally, Held draws attention to how care ethics shifts the agency and location of moral
and political action, problematizing the autonomous liberal individual of social contract theory
29
I return to this point below, but it is important to note that while Held actively refuses to naturalize care in the
sense of an ahistorical, private affair, Noddings conception of a feminine moral education is based on a very similar
view of returning to an ur-ethical universal memory of being cared for that Held espouses.
30
While I do not discuss them here, this point and others speak to care ethical debates about the value of care
relation to justice, and whether and how care should be construed as mutually constitutive with, ontologically prior
to, opposed, or simply in false dichotomy with justice and liberal thought more broadly. Held herself sees care as the
more fundamental category but argues for a “meshing” of care and justice.
38
and abstract moral reasoning. Against the disinterested “moral point of view” (Tronto) Held
claims that the ethics of care begins from and develops the perspective of caring relations
themselves. For Held, the values of care are exemplified in such caring relations, not in
individual decisions or judgments. Since care is a relational endeavor concerned with the needs
of particular human beings, care ethics eschews impartiality as the criterion of morality. This
point is exemplified in Kittay’s embedded and relational concept of doulia. For Kittay, doulia is
a public ethic that hinges on a social and political understanding of care. It points to the fact that
successful care is never simply an individual or dyadic relation but hinges upon broader social
networks of support (Love’s Labor 68-73). Based on the role of the doula, or assistant to the
birthing parent, the notion of doulia presents the social need to care for both dependents and
caregivers, and to thus understand care as a social and moral good located not in an exchange
relation between free and equal individuals but in linked and nested sets of caring relations in
which the needs and agency of both dependents and caretakers are centered rather than
marginalized. This not only takes care out of the private domain but presents these webs of
relations as a primary location of moral know-how and political action. Placing such a socially
embedded and relational notion at the heart of moral theory fundamentally de-centers, if not calls
into question, the very concept of the self-authenticating individual endowed with rational
decision-making capacities. Moral understanding does not primarily sprout from the detached
mind of a liberal individual making free choices: it is nurtured and developed in and through
meeting the needs of dependent and interdependent others, fortifying the material and social
context of caring relations, and dignifying the embodied work of those who perform caring labor
as well as the lives of those who depend on it.
39
Affective and embedded relational engagement is crucial to the method and practice of
care ethics as I am presenting it here. To center caring relations as a key location of moral
understanding is to call for new and different forms of theorizing and action, located in relational
understandings of human personhood and agency. Recent attempts to rationally schematize and
justify care ethics, evinced in the work of Stephanie Collins and Michael Slote in particular,
seem to miss the profundity of these changes. As noted above, Collins aims to consolidate care
ethics under the slogan that caring relations generate dependencies. Her aim in doing so is to
justify care ethics as a normative theory by specifying and synthesizing its claims with the tools
of analytic philosophy. This synthesis of the aims and scope of care ethics takes place under the
egis of decision theory: her aim is to outline the caring attitudes and decisional calculations that
can be said to have the right relation to the needs of concrete human others. As I discuss at length
below, Slote too presents a sweeping argument for care ethics as a superior moral theory, unified
and systematized through the intuitive moral distinctions involved in empathic caring for others.
For Slote, a person’s actions are wrong if they act from a deficiency of caring motivation. This
criterion forms the basis for what he understands to be a comprehensive morality grounded in
Western sentimentalist philosophy, and a compelling alternative to Kantian theories of justice.
Slote and Collins both attempt to schematize and justify care ethics as a robust moral
theory. However, the notion of dependency as a principle executed through individual action or
empathy as a criterion grounding morality as such differ dramatically from Held’s own
comprehensive presentation of care ethics as a moral philosophy, outlined in the features of care
ethics described above. But this impulse towards rational justification wholly misses how
profound a critique care ethics levies against this kind of moral judgment. For example, Slote
closely relies on Noddings’ concept of engrossment to support his argument for empathy as a
40
moral criterion but doesn’t discuss why she thought such caring attention was incompatible with
moral criteria as such. For Noddings, care ethics begins from a heightening of moral perception
and sensitivity not a return to moral judgements. Insofar as care is developed from within
relational commitments, morally theorizing it resists such systemization. This is not to say that
care ethics is categorically against normative theory or its implications: many care ethicists view
care normatively under certain lights,31 and carve out crucial roles for abstract moral thinking
especially when it comes to questions of justice. But there is a reason care ethicists developed a
relational ontology and situated feminist ethos rather than the tools provided by Western moral
philosophy to engage with the realities of care.32
The care ethical tradition offers a practical theory of ethical engagement from the
perspective of relationship rather than individual deliberation and rational criteria. In situating
ethics in caring relations rather than detached moral calculation, the ethics of care folds affect
and intersubjective attunement into the very fabric of moral thinking and action. This is an
essential point that a return to discussions of moral criteria and rational decision making elide if
not miss altogether. As Tronto notes, the ethics of care is not about developing another abstract
“moral point of view” or a “first principle of social virtue:” “After we have recognized the
complexities of care as a practice, and how completely care is implicated in structures of power
in society, it will become clear that a metaethical position that starts from the standpoint of the
‘moral point of view’ is incapable of making the kinds of judgments necessary for care” (Moral
31
Held states on this point: “I see the ethics of care from as fully a normative view as any other ethic. It addresses
questions about whether and how and why we ought to engage in activities of care, questions about how such
activities should be conducted and structured, and questions about the meanings of care and caring. It especially
evaluates relations of care” (46).
32
In her discussion (and re-working) of Tronto’s famous definition, Maria Puig de la Ballacasa puts this point
beautifully: “…the ‘ethics’ in an ethics of care cannot be about a realm of normative moral obligations but rather
about thick, impure, involvement in a world where the question of how to care needs to be posed. That is, it makes
of ethics a hands-on, ongoing process of re-creation of “as well as possible” relations and therefore one that requires
a speculative opening about what a possible involves” (6).
41
Boundaries 126). Held specifically critiques Slote on this point, arguing that his focus on an
“agent-based virtue ethics of caring… misses the centrality of caring relations for an ethic of
care” (51, my emphasis). For Held, care is a social relation rather than an individual disposition,
and the values of care are thus exemplified in caring relations rather than individual states (41).
While perhaps right in relation to its letter, attempts such as Slote’s and Collins’s to schematize
or rationally justify its claims based on individual decision-making capacities miss the spirit of
care ethics presented in its relational ontology and affect laden ethos, and thus the also miss
depth of critique it poses to moral philosophy.
It is arguably Held’s methodological grounding of moral theory in the perspective and
experience of caring relations themselves that poses the most radical critique to the ontological
and methodological individualism and abstract calculations of the Western philosophical canon.
In ethically valorizing the feminized labor and relations of care, this tradition explicitly and
implicitly elaborates and builds upon the feminist dictum regarding the political and social nature
of the so-called personal and private dimensions of human life and world making. This brings us
back to a central claim of this chapter and the next: namely, that a feminist politics of experience
is an essential component of the development, as well as the theory and method, of care ethics. It
is this feminist lineage that has allowed it to so profoundly problematize culturally masculinist
and individualistic notions of the ethical person, the social locations to which ethics are bound,
and the methods by which moral deliberation and engagement are construed and developed.
Theorizing and valuing care from the inside—from the experience of giving and receiving
care—is also what lends this tradition its moral, and political, weight.
III. The Politics of Care: Care Ethical Perspectives
42
Care ethics poses a radical critique of the subject, ontology, and method of traditional
philosophical ethics. Building on the insights outlined above regarding the roots of this tradition
in feminist praxis, I now want to turn to some key components of care ethical understandings of
the politics of care. In doing so, my aim is to present a critique of how these political
developments remain beholden to the very abstract notions of agency and relation that this
tradition ethically calls into question. My argument here is that ethically situating care requires a
thoroughly political understanding of care. Care is not only ethical but political all the way
down, and this includes the intuitive elements of caring that care ethicists by and large
uncritically valorize. Insofar as it has been socially constituted within relations of structural and
intimate violence, simply valuing care as it has been so constituted does not reach the root of the
problem. I articulate this point in conversation with Joan Tronto’s paradigmatically political
argument for an ethics of care. While Tronto brings care into view as a constituent force of
politics, and indeed offers a political argument for the ethics of care, she fails to see the always
already political realities of caring practices and dispositions themselves: an omission that marks
even the most radical care ethical positions.
While I critique the political tradition of care ethics on the grounds that even the more
radical thinkers in this tradition ultimately naturalize and universalize care, I am also building on
important analyses that have been elaborated in the collective sense outlined above. As Kittay
points out, care is itself a social and political value and the question of who performs the labor of
care is a social and political question. “Questions of who takes on the responsibility of care, who
does hands-on care, who sees to it that caring is done and is done well, and who provides support
for the relationship of care and for both parties to the caring relationship—these are social and
political questions. They are questions of social responsibility and political will” (Love’s Labor
43
1). Held likewise examines social and political questions in light of the values of care and offers
suggestions for the transformation of society based on this analysis (37).
Much of what is lacking in the political theory of care comes from the fact that we are in
many ways still working in the dark, on however belabored territory.33 As with the historical
dearth of theory concerning the ethical registers of care, the relative lack of theory concerning
the basic political realities of care points to (perhaps shocking, but not surprising) ideological
predilections of dominant political theories, or deeper still to the degradation of care and
reproductive work essential to heteropatriarchal, racial capitalist, social reproduction.34 Tronto
asks the question outright: given its central and essential role in social and material life, “why is
care not a central category of social analysis?” (Moral Boundaries 112). She uses this mode of
questioning as a basis of her critique of the power relations and norms that have excluded care
from political analysis.
Yet in some sense, political analysis has been a component of care ethics since its
inception. Many care ethicists generate a politics of care from their ethical observations, moving
from a conception of ethics to a politics of care. Ruddick for example offers an early example of
a politics of peace grounded in maternal care, and Gilligan overtly critiques the gendered
dominations that have led to masculinist biases in moral psychology. There have also been
developments in the theory, from the primacy given to dyadic, maternal caring to theorizing care
in broader political and social registers. Daniel Engster helpfully summarizes this general move
from personal, intimate relations to a social and political perspective on care:
33
Recent years have seen a potent explosion of discourse on care as political concept, however. This has been
provoked by the context of the COVID pandemic, and, in the US, the 2020 uprisings for Black Lives and attendant
popularization of frameworks of prison and police abolitionism, which often speak to the need to center the politics
of care in the process of building alternative social infrastructures for dealing with violence and its social conditions.
This work is self-consciously part of this collective endeavor to center care as a political concept and practice.
34
The third and fourth chapters of this dissertation address these social reproductive contradictions at length.
44
Most basically, personal approaches to caring fail to take into account the web of social
relationships in which any particular caring relationship necessarily exists (Kittay 1999). Since
individuals can usually only care effectively for others if provided some sort of support or
accommodation by others, theories that focus narrowly on personal caring relations fail to
recognize the important role that social institutions and policies can play in fostering good caring
relations (6-7).
In moving from personal, dyadic and maternal understandings of care—which, it must be
noted, are to a large extent located in Western, heteronormative notions of the nuclear family—to
an understanding of care in its social and political context, the discourse of care ethics has also
become more skilled at centering race, class, nationality, sexuality and ability, as well as gender,
in its understandings of the complex situatedness of care and its moral and political value.
However, even the nuanced and socially conscious perspectives offered by Held and Kittay
ultimately derive their political critique from problematically equalized or universalized notions
of caring. For Held, as noted above, a robust moral theory of care ethics is grounded in what she
understands to be the universal experience of care. This argument forms the justification for her
claim that we must center care in social relations and political institutions: what she terms the
“meshing” of care and justice. Kittay’s dependency critique of liberal theories of justice presents
an alternative to liberal theories of equality, grounded in the understanding that we are all ‘some
mother’s child’ (Love’s Labor). Indeed, this equalizing maxim forms the basic assumption
through which her concept of doulia is expressed and justified.35 Thus while both Held and
35
Kittay offers a corrective to this position in response to Rosemary Tong’s critiques of this equalizing gesture.
“Tong directs us to the terrible irony that those who have been most responsible for doing society’s dependency
work come to be the least likely to receive good care when they themselves require care. In Love’s Labor I try to
promote a notion I call doulia, the public responsibility to provide support for the caregiver so that the caregiver can
give care without depleting herself and her resources. I speak of the aphorism that might characterize the triadic
concept of reciprocity embedded here: that what goes around comes around. But the aphorism seems sadly wrong—
at least in our world. What’s worse, it is precisely because of their caregiving labor that the women about whom
Tong speaks are poor and unable to purchase the care they require as they age” (“Love’s Labor Revisited” 242)
45
Kittay theorize care in social and political registers and point to the need for political reforms
that center more just distributions of care, they both base this analysis on the assumption of a
universal experience of care that sidesteps, if not obscures, deep critical analysis of the structural
and systemic oppressions that deny people basic access to care, infuse caring relations with
abuse, and exploit and extract the labor of care workers.
Tronto takes the political analysis of care a step further than prior theories by offering an
explicitly political argument for the ethics of care. Importantly, her theory rests upon a critique
of the power relations that occlude care as a moral and political reality. Her argument rests on the
fact that care is an essential element of human life that is also systemically devalued (Moral
Boundaries 158). This means that centering care politically not only requires critiquing the
structural relations and political norms that have led to this devaluation but will itself “lead to a
profound rethinking of moral and political life” (111). In claiming that the lenses through which
moral and political life have been delimited and understood exclude questions of care, she makes
a deep methodological move not only against abstract and rule-based morality but towards the
need to center care as the basis for the political achievement of a good society (172).
Like Held and Kittay, Tronto self-consciously places her intervention within feminist
history and praxis as well as political theory. The dual needs to both view care in the political
context that devalues it, and to politically value care, form the impetus for her re-construal of the
moral boundaries that she claims preclude a genuine ethics and politics of care. A central claim
of her Moral Boundaries is that “in order to take morality seriously… we have to understand
[moral arguments] in a political context” (3). This insight drives her political view of care and
her re-construal of the moral boundaries that she claims preclude caring politics. Not only are
morals political, but valuing care requires reevaluating morals in a way that politically and
46
ethically centers an integral concept of care (101). However, rather than resort to an essentialized
‘women’s morality’ traditionally associated with feminized norms, she claims that upholding the
value of these norms requires re-construing the limits and boundary demarcating moral and
political thought: centering care requires troubling the boundaries separating morality from its
political and personal contexts, the public from the private sphere, and indeed morality and
politics themselves.
For Tronto, the analytic and practical framing of moral and political philosophy has
constitutively excluded questions of care (96). Understanding and valuing care politically and
ethically thus requires us to re-draw these boundaries in a way that puts care at the center of
moral and social life. According to Stephanie Collins, care ethics eschews the distinction
between politics and morality uberhaupt: “Building on the feminist insight that the ‘personal is
political’, care ethicists tend to believe experiences in our individual ethical lives must inform
the principles that guide our political institutions, and that the nature of our political institutions
condition possibilities within our individual ethical lives” (Core of Care Ethics 6). Tronto’s
claim is more critical and transformative: rather than merely upholding the norms of intimate life
and bringing them into conversation with questions of public and political policy, she asks the
quasi-transcendental question, “how might an ethic of care become possible,” which implies a
critique of the boundary between the ethical and the political that express relations of power such
as those that constrain care to the private sphere or recreate paternalistic and domineering
tendencies in the allocating of caring services (Moral Boundaries 175).
This analysis has implications not only for political theory but for care ethics itself.
Tronto’s argument is finally that “only if we understand care as a political idea will we be able to
change its status and the status of those who do caring work in our culture” (158). For Tronto,
47
understanding care as a political idea rests on problematizing what she terms ‘morality first’
accounts of care’s social and political value. It is not enough to simply import an unmediated
notion of care into political life: ultimately the ethics of care itself “remains incomplete without a
political theory of care” (155). Tronto is explicit in her critique of Noddings on this point, who
she, following others, views to have a dyadic, sentimentalized, and anti-procedural36 account of
care that refuses institutional and structural analysis. Ultimately, viewing the morality of care as
given prior to its political and social context is incompatible with a genuine critique and of social
structures and norms. And ultimately re-inscribes the very divisions between the private and
public, the intimate and structural, and the rational and emotional that care ethics is intent upon
dismantling.
Tronto’s aim is to place the value of care front and center in political policy and theory,
while also addressing the social inequalities and power imbalances manifest in caring relations.
Meeting both aims requires viewing care ethics through a thoroughly political lens: hence
Tronto’s “political argument for an ethics of care” (the subtitle of Moral Boundaries). Tronto
finally calls for a more caring society based on re-drawn moral boundaries grounded in the
political and moral value of care as an integral species activity. “To recognize the value of care,”
she claims, ultimately “calls into question the structure of values in our society” (180). Insofar as
care is not a secondary and parochial concern but central to, and constitutive of, human life, we
are obligated to take a critical stance on existing norms and practices, and ultimately to
implement the value of care at the center of social and political institutions.
36
I have an interesting point of contact with Noddings on this issue: while I agree that her analysis is deeply
problematic when it comes to political issues, I also have developed an anti-procedural critique of liberal
conceptions of care. Interestingly, while she does not put it in its needed political context, in its attention to the
embedded relations of care surrounding both survivor and the person who has caused harm, Noddings approach to
intimate partner violence is not unlike the forms of transformative justice that I view as an alternative to legalistic
and procedural approaches to reforming care.
48
This is true, but only half the picture. For Tronto, we must change the context in which
we think about care, but we do not have to change care itself: “in order to think about care
differently” we must simply “situate it differently as an integral moral and political concept”
(124). For Tronto, it is ultimately moral boundaries and their social and political settings that
preserve privilege and oppression, not the practices and dispositions of care itself. This means
that despite her intent to provide a political theory of care that moves away from the dyadic and
sentimentalized notions offered by “morality first” notions of caring politics, Tronto ultimately
rests on an uncritical and ahistorical acceptance of care as a value—for her specifically, the
moral qualities of attentiveness, responsibility, competence, responsiveness in meeting others’
needs and the integrity of good care (127-136). She claims that “Because the practice of care is
also a political idea, [her account does] not face the problem of trying to import a moral concept
into a political order.” Rather, she contends, “the practice of care describes the qualities
necessary for democratic citizens to live together well in a pluralistic society.” (161-162).
But Tronto’s construal of the disposition and practice of good care as a political ideal still
abstracts care from social relations that constitutively devalue and exploit it. While she explicitly
draws attention to questions of power and difference in caring relations, and indeed to how “care
is raced, gendered, classed” (112), she does not question how practices of care themselves often
reproduce or invisibilize the very power imbalances she intends to address. Despite her
compelling claims to the contrary, her call to move a holistically conceived notion of good care
from the margins to the center of politics thus still relies on an abstract and apolitical notion of
care.37
37
Tronto is right in making the following nuanced claim: “As a practice embedded in social life, care obviously will
be shaped by other practices in social life as well. In a culture that privatizes domestic relations in order to control
women’s power, we are not surprised that care is privatized and gendered. Our inability to think of care in other
terms is not a failure of care but a constraint in the social context in which caring practices occur in our society”
49
While Tronto brings care into view as a constituent force of politics, and in doing so also
draws attention to the constitutive inequalities reproduced in the boundaries that exclude care
from political and moral life, she fails to see the always already political realities of caring
practices and dispositions themselves. My intent is not to dispute Tronto and other care ethicists’
claim that care is an essential condition of life and world making, or her move to politically value
care and in so doing demand a paradigm shift in the location and nature of political and moral
philosophy. Rather, my claim is that care is inextricably embedded in and reproductive of the
constitutive inequalities of social life, which means that we also must account for the political
nature of the very forms of attention, empathy, responsiveness, receptivity, and other
directedness that the discourse of care ethics holds as foundational to its understandings of both
the ethical and political value of care.
Even in her critique of placing “morality first” in the politics of care, Tronto ultimately
relies on naturalistic capacities for good care as foundational for her valuation of care as a
political ideal. Her politics of care thus ultimately relies on naturalizing dimensions of care that
are themselves structured by violence, and which are also capable of healing it. To return to this
crucial point, the very feminist politics that care ethics draws upon and richly elaborates demand
political orientations to those layers of experience and social practice excluded by dominant
understandings of the political. The same goes for care: the epistemologies, practices and
dispositions of care are not naturalistically or universally given but rather socially and materially
constituted—in both dominant hegemonic modes, and in feminist and other forms of struggle.
To say, as I am here positing, that an ethics of care demands a politics of care is to claim
that the devaluation, exploitation, extraction, and abuse that occurs in and through caring
(154). However, while oppression is not a failure of care itself, care is deeply shaped by oppression: a claim that I
develop further in the next chapter.
50
practices and relations is not incidental but essential to the reproduction of the power relations,
antagonisms, and contradictions endemic to societies systemically structured by violence. While
the histories and present realities of structural violence are diverse and irreducible (though often
at the same time deeply intersectional), the reproduction of these systems nonetheless depends in
each case on devaluing and exploiting care. This means not only that care is political, but that it
ideologically appears as a natural morality. This is to flip the script of care ethics, but in a way
that I believe is consistent with its most radical and visionary impulses. Beginning from this
understanding, which in many ways quite simply follows from feminist politics of personal and
intimate experience, presents the issue in a clearer light by locating the ethics of care on this
already political territory.
Tronto is steadfast in her insistence that care is definitively not a master’s tool (226). I
contend that it can be, and also a revolutionary one. Elena Buch helpfully elaborates this
doubleness of care with her concept of generative labor. For Buch this concept helps illuminate
“how care can simultaneously produce forms of morality, independent persons, and social
inequality. This concept highlights two aspects of social life: first, that the everyday practices
that make and sustain life—both social and biological—are necessarily entwined with the
makings of political economy. In this sense, these practices are labor. Second, these forms of
labor determine which and how different lives matter around the world; they generate both lives
and social difference in the process” (12). To say that care is a naturalized rather than a
naturalistically or universally given ethic is to account for this complexity: the profound and
painful contradictions by which care as the labor which generates life at the same time is both
produced by and reproduces social differences grounded in inequality. Noting the generativity of
caring labor also roots it in possibilities for change and survival: just as it can generate violence
51
and deepen inequality, care can and does also generate forms of ethical and political meaning
that confront and transform them.
IV. Naturalistic/Naturalized Epistemologies of Care: Getting the Problem into View
Contrary to the feminist political commitments and relational social ontology upheld by most
thinkers in this tradition, the care ethical move of grounding the ethics and politics of care in a
naturalistically and/or universally construed notion of good care relies on a problematic
abstraction of care from its material and social conditions. In the next chapter I develop this point
in relation to Kittay’s notion of a transparent self, but at this point in the argument I also want to
note the compelling pull of this approach. If correct, a transparent concept of good care grounded
in intuitive moral distinctions would provide real insight into which interpersonal elements of
caring relations, institutions, and social practices we should value and learn to embody, and
which contribute to furthering harm and marginalization. On one level, I agree with this
approach: it is crucially important, politically, and interpersonally, for privileged individuals to
learn the skills of intuitive and affective response, and for people who are socially compelled to
perform caring labor to learn to feel and embody, as well as be given the space to enforce, the
limits and boundaries of their caring capacities. However, attention to the contradictions of care
reveals that even (and precisely) the relational attitudes and dispositions taken as normative in
both broader cultural narratives and academic theorizations of care can themselves normalize
violence and inequality and further harm. This politically implicates even the intuitive
dimensions of care that care ethicists have taken as paradigmatic and foundational for
articulating an ethics and politics of care: caring attention, attunement, empathy, responsiveness,
other-directedness and the like.
52
My aim in this final section is to wrap up the claims of this chapter through an analysis of
these naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care. My claim is that the analytic and moral
frames of care ethics foreclose political analysis of the contradictions of caring engrained in
these relational matrices and dispositions. I use the double formulation of
“naturalistic/naturalized” to point to this level of contradiction: namely, that elements of care that
appear to be natural and universal are themselves naturalized practices that are socially
constituted and mystified as such. If we simply and unequivocally value these dimensions of
care, we can only view the violence embedded and reproduced in and through them as
pathological deviations from a norm of good care, or, alternatively, as ambivalences internal to it.
This limits our perspectives on caring politics in troubling ways. The issue I see is rather how to
critique and transform these deeply naturalized dimensions of intimacy and relation, insofar as
they are themselves locations in which violence as well as healing are socially engrained and
become normative.
Put simply, I want to present the social and political problem as well as horizon posed by
forms of caring attention in the context of structural violence.38 The ideological and material
devaluation of caring labor and those who perform it is not incidental but structural to social and
institutional forms predicated on inequality and exploitation, and this shows up in our embodied
relational practices in deep and intransigent ways. Kate Manne, for example, discusses the
difficulty of confronting misogyny, or the “self-masking” (Manne 281) enforcement of
patriarchy, precisely because it relies on and preserves gendered norms of nurture, economies of
giving and taking, and emotional labor and support through invisiblized yet extreme threats of
violence and erasure against women and gender non-conforming people who don’t comply. As I
38
Here I merely point to this problem, which I develop at length in subsequent chapters.
53
discuss at length in the next chapter, women of color have long pointed to the violence
reproduced in racialized as well as gender divisions of caring labor that are rooted in histories of
slavery and colonization.
These are urgent questions that point to both structural and intimate violence. For
example, the social reproduction of contemporary racial capitalism is dependent on the
intersectional violence contained in what have come to be understood as international care
chains. The labor performed by migrant women of color from the Global South is necessary to
the functioning of contemporary capitalist reproduction and neocolonial, extractive international
relations. This is a form of structural violence, but like all structural violence it is intimately
experienced in people’s lives—in this case, the exploitation, isolation, dislocation, and abuse
women often face in the domestic spaces of predominantly white, middle class, homes in the
Global North. These issues are not solved by simply pointing to the need for more or better
caring attention on the part either those who are forced to care or those who are socially and
materially incentivized not to, or even simply pointing to the inherent value of this labor, though
this is of course necessary.39
To claim, as care ethicists do, that the social, moral, and epistemic value of care lies in its
intuitive dimensions or dispositional attitudes elides the deeply rooted social and political
problems presented by care’s at once intimate and structural relation to violence. Noddings’
work is paradigmatic here. Her phenomenology of care asks how to meet another morally
through the realm of feeling and affective response. For Noddings, we must understand and
develop care from the inside: by “heightening” the moral perception and sensitivity that for her is
39
As I address at length in another writing, merely procedural accounts developed by liberal theories also prove
inadequate to these at once intimate and structural concerns. Insofar as procedures are formulaic and abstract and
themselves enacted through carceral and other broken social institutions, they are rarely adequate to facilitate
transformation at structural or intimate levels (“Conditions of Radical Care”).
54
the ground and horizon of ethicality as such. We nurture this capacity by cultivating what she
calls an “ethical ideal” of care, the origin of which lies in “natural caring:” an instinctual “love or
natural inclination.” The ethical ideal of care is an attitude developed through memories of
(natural) caring and being cared for that she, like Held, claims are universally experienced. Her
ethic of caring is phenomenologically rooted in such “feelings, attitudes and memories” that are
“natural and accessible to all human beings” (Caring 27-28). Noddings’ ethics hinges on this
capacity to recreate or maintain our most intimate memories of care (104): “[a]n ethic of caring
has its source in human natural caring, and it seeks the maintenance of that caring” (108). While
universally accessible, the ethical ideal originates in specific memories of caring: and is thus
situational and non-universalizable (5), a guideline negotiated by specific people in specific
situations.
An example will reveal the troubling implications of Noddings’ account, and the
problems it poses to naturalistic epistemologies of care. Providing what she understands to be an
instance of the complex situatedness of ethical caring, Noddings presents a dilemma faced by an
avatar, Ms. A. The context is the Black Liberation movement of the late 60s, and a conversation
with a Black classmate, Jim, whose frustrations have led him to call for more militant action. In
reflecting on her position in relation to this struggle, Ms. A admits to herself that if it came down
to violent confrontation, she would choose the side of her racist family and protect them.
Noddings phenomenologically outlines Ms. A’s pained deliberations at great length(109-113).
Indeed, she presents them as an example of the situated complexity of care, and the effort needed
to avoid self-deception. This is a crucial point in her argument insofar as it shows how one might
navigate care in the absence of objective moral criteria: it is an example of the honest assessment
55
that goes into maintaining the ethical ideal, which, in this case, she relates as a choice on the part
of Ms. A to focus her political efforts on preventing the escalation of violence.
Noddings does not provide the resources to critique the directionality of Ms. A’s
empathy, her ethical assessments, or her potential political actions. The example is itself very
strange, given that nobody is dragging Ms. A to the barricades, and we can imagine many other
ways that she could confront her family’s racism and support civil rights and Black liberation.
One’s ability to care ethically seems to have little to do with power dynamics, or how one’s own
relational dispositions might re-entrench them—or with the historical origin of one’s ethical
ideal, which, in the case of Ms. A was nurtured in a racist, though ostensibly caring, family.
Noddings presents Ms. A as attentive and sympathetic to both Jim and her family: in her
presentation Ms. A is skilled in navigating the complexity, situatedness, and ultimately the
limitations of caring. Ms. A’s ostensibly caring attention is itself implicated in the problem. Her
attunements and sympathies themselves block critical reflection on the realities of structural
racism and open her up to paranoid musings and potentially worse.40 Noddings offers little more
to think through the ethical and political problems her example poses: how to critique social
structures and shift sympathies, cultivate antiracist ethical ideals, or center the ethicality of
political struggle itself—or how these might make someone a more ethical carer.
Most of the care ethicists surveyed in this chapter would be disturbed by this example. As
I noted above, many have critiqued Noddings for her inability to account for these structural and
institutional layers of the social or their impacts on care. Confronted with the example, they
would likely argue that Ms. A’s response is precisely not attentive and responsive to her
classmate, the broader political context of white supremacy, or her positionality as a white
40
Note that in her fantasy it is Jim who incites the violence! This projection is a part of her deliberation.
56
woman within it. But their own understandings of the ethics of care, and specifically the
naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care that form the basis of their conceptions of good
care, do not ultimately offer critical resources to address such contradictions in caring practices
and relations. They too are limited when it comes to the racism baked into in Ms. A’s caring
attention itself. The relational dispositions from which they derive the value of care offer little
more than Noddings herself when it comes to addressing these problems.
Addressing contradictions such as this—here, how Ms’ A’s caring attitude itself
reproduces racist sympathies and potentially racist political action—seems to me to be an
essential concern of caring ethics and politics. Insofar as they can themselves reproduce
structural and intimate violence, simply valuing attitudes and dispositions such as attention,
other-directedness, responsiveness, and receptivity does not provide avenues for fostering radical
care. Besides its awkwardly cloaked racism and pearl clutching sentimentality, the problem I see
posed in this example is how to politically highlight the social embeddedness of care in order to
interrogate and transform its attentive and relational elements, precisely as components of
political consciousness raising and struggle.
Noddings exemplifies the deeply naturalistic tendencies of the care ethical tradition, as
well as the problems this poses for political accounts of care aligned with social justice. While
they differ in the precise elements, nearly all care ethicists outline specific features, dispositions
or attitudes that they imagine to constitute good care, and nearly all ground and justify their
political accounts of care on the basis of these intuitive moral capacities.41 As I discussed above
41
As I outlined above, there is debate about the role that the motivational elements of care in particular play in its
social and moral value. Tronto, for example, critiques Held on this point, noting how her emphasis on self-reflective
motivation abstracts care from its laboring dimensions and even excludes some care work from Held’s definition of
care. Held, in contrast, critiques Tronto’s broad definition of care for its overemphasis on labor: she claims that it
includes many dimensions of social life that cannot properly be said to be caring. Relatedly, Kittay’s disability
perspective also outlines elements of dependency rather than relational autonomy and interdependency that adds
crucial dimensions to care ethical perspectives.
57
at length, even Tronto’s thoroughly political account grounds care’s value in such elements,
which for her constitute care as a species activity. But if these dimensions of care are
naturalistically given and good, then they can only be conceived as paradigmatically outside of
or beyond the very social relations of domination at stake. In such a framework, caring practices
and relations that contain abusive elements, are fundamentally exploitative, or, as in the example
above, contain and reproduce sympathies with oppressive relations—can only be viewed as
pathological forms of care that deviate from the norm of good care, or complexities inherent to it.
Presenting caring dispositions and practices as inherently good and naturalistically given renders
any violence contained and reproduced in them as a moral aberration or intrinsic ambiguity
rather than a constituent component of the social and political reality of care. This means that
grounding an ethics of care in intuitive attitudes or dispositions overlooks and even disallows
politically situated understandings of care.
My claim here is that rather than mere deviations from a norm of good care, what appear
as ‘pathologies’ of care must often themselves be understood to be normative. Rita Segato
powerfully speaks to this point, revealing so-called pathologies to be adaptations to, or
performative instantiations of, the world as it is that reify and reproduce its relations.42 This point
is powerfully noted in her thesis of the rapist as moralist (Contra-Pedagogias 37). Without
understanding how rape and rape cultures are not pathological deviations but rather normative
instantiations of what Segato terms the patriarchal mandate of masculinity, we fail to see the
depth of the problem and thus the scope of what is demanded by feminist praxis. A similar point
could be made about so-called pathologies of care, which are often themselves normative
dimensions of patriarchal, white supremacist and other structural oppressions. For example, the
42
Psychopathic tendencies, for example, are normative to contemporary coloniality and capitalist patriarchy
(Contra-Pedagogias de la Crueldad 5).
58
extreme and nuanced attentiveness and attunement that is required in caring for abusive partners,
domestic employers, or, in the case of many disabled individuals, in navigating relations with
abusive caregivers, is foundational to both the cohesiveness and the violence of many caring
relations. To pathologize violence (or forms of adaptation to it) as somehow deviant is,
ironically, to naturalize and normalize its structural nature and the harm it perpetuates.
Relatedly, I want to distinguish my argument from discussions of the ambivalences of
care. Ruddick, for example, poignantly relates the struggles of a young mother confronting her
screaming and inconsolable infant, and how she must contend with her radical ambivalence—
including feelings of rage, helplessness, despair, and hatred—in the face of such a harrowing
responsibility to a life dependent on her care (Maternal Thinking 66-67). For Ruddick, we cannot
understand the complexity of preservative mothering love without taking such ambivalence into
account.43 This is a deeply important point that has been taken up in recent calls, during the
pandemic, to center the mental health of parents and take a more nuanced approach to the range
of emotions that caregiving inevitably entails, especially under conditions of crisis and
institutional neglect. The recent work of The Care Collective brings these ambivalences of care
into political view, a point which it will be useful to quote at length:
The very concept ‘care ’overflows with paradoxes and ambivalence. Indeed, the distinctions
between caring for, caring about, and caring with – which feminist scholars such as Tronto have
developed – are useful, but do not account for the conflicting emotions that are inevitably part of
different forms of care. Compared with similar complex, emotive terms such as courage, love or
anger, the notion of care is rarely given due respect or attention… For instance, hands-on caring,
however rewarding, also put us in contact with what may be the most daunting, even at times the
most seemingly repellent or shameful, aspects of people’s mortal, embodied selves. It is perhaps
reassuring for many to pretend that those who perform the jobs that most disgust us, perhaps
43
As Hil Malatino notes, such preservative mothering is not particularly gendered even for Ruddick—Malatino
powerfully notes that such ‘mothering’ forms of preservative love are a component of many forms of queer and
trans care outside of and against heternormative familial structures and normative gender roles (Trans Care 67).
59
literally cleaning up our own or another’s excrement, do so because ‘that is all they are good for’.
This is another reason why caring has been traditionally relegated to the domain of women,
servants or others deemed inferior, while simultaneously serving to reinforce the notion of that
inferiority – precisely because they are thought to be more suited to handling ‘abject ’flesh, the
sign of our inescapable corporeal existence and hence of our mortality… Both positive and
negative emotions inevitably entwine with both our care practices and our very capacities to care.
It is because of the complexity and profound challenges of care, as capacity and practice, that we
must provide and ensure the necessary social infrastructure that enables us to care for others, both
proximate and distant. By this we mean, for example, ample resources and time. Parents and
other carers facing the pressures of today’s job markets routinely find they barely have time to
provide for the essential needs of their dependants, let alone to pay heed to the situation of others
in the outside world. Both more time and adequate material resources are essential to ground and
facilitate mutually fulfilling and imaginative practices of care, from the domestic to the planetary
level – and to foster the overall well-being of all creatures, human and non-human (The Care
Manifesto 28-29)
This beautiful passage captures the politics of caring emotions in their material and social
contexts and motivates the authors’ claim that “[a] caring politics must grasp both this
interdependence and the ambivalence and anxiety it inevitably generates” (30). It also points to
the need to support and develop material resources and social infrastructures that can support the
full complexity of care.
While related to and certainly supportive of this aim, my claim here is different.
Ambivalence is a complexity of caring to which caring politics must attend, but we must also
acknowledge the social and material contradictions that constitute care’s political reality. While
this is a deeper conversation that I will pick up in my discussion of affect in Chapter Three, I
imagine that care ethicists, and The Care Collective, are right in their analysis: conflicting
emotions in caring relations, while historically situated and informed, are likely best understood
as an inescapable dimension of caring relations as such. While ambivalence as an affective state
60
can certainly reflect and be exacerbated by structural violence and oppression, it is ultimately a
complex emotion (or emotional complex) internal to the very experience of care. Accounting for
ambivalence is crucial to a politically nuanced and de-romanticized notion of care, but the
concept of ambivalence cannot alone bring the social and political complexity of care into
view.44 Conflating the ambivalences of care with its social and material contradictions ultimately
reduces both concepts, as well as their relation to each other in the lived complexity of care.
Rooting caring politics in intuitive dimensions of care ultimately prevents us from
viewing care as anything but an ethical ideal. This limits our view on the violence socially
embedded in care, presenting it as either a pathological deviation from care on the one hand, or
an ambivalence internal to it on the other. If caring politics are understood to hinge upon otherdirected, attuned, and responsive caring attention as such, then examples such as that of Ms. A
seem outside the realm of politics—an instance of her moral aberration or ambivalence—and
thus distant from political deliberation and social change. Both options thus offer little help in
interrogating care’s role either in reproducing violence or in politically altering oppressive social
relations.
Taking a radical view of care in the context of structural violence requires contending
with the ways that this violence appears not only in social organizations of care, but also in its
most intimate expressions. It also presents the need to reflect on why and how care already does
tend to appear as a naturalized ethic within dominant cultural and social forms.45 Within Western
44
Of course, ambivalence can be exacerbated by structural violence and neglect, as witnessed in the bone deep
burnout of mothers during the pandemic.
45
This perspective also offers a way beyond debates that have plagued care ethics since its inception. The problem
of how to uphold feminized norms of care in the context of the structural oppression of women has largely been
construed in discourses of feminist ethics as a problem of gender essentialism: in valuing care, do we risk reifying
the very gender relations we intend to critique and transform? If care is a naturalized ethic so bound up with sexism,
how can it form the basis of a progressive or radical ethics? Allison Jaggar, for example, poses the problem as such:
“if women indeed show more concern for so-called personal relations… this is less likely to be the consequence of
some innate predisposition than to be the result of women’s culturally assignment confinement to and/or
61
cultures as they stand, valuing and sentimentalizing care is the flip side of its degradation and
devaluation. Care precisely is already valued, but in ways that often reflect and reproduce
racialized, gendered, ableist and colonial logics and relations. Crucially, this contradiction shows
up in forms of affect, attention, receptivity, and attunement as well as in social forms and
institutions. As I have maintained from the beginning of this chapter, this is not to devalue the
socially necessary, deeply skilled, and meaningful labor of care. My aim is the opposite. But, in
light of the ethical contradictions of care, dignifying and celebrating care and those who perform
it requires more than valuing its apparently intuitive dimensions.
Taking what I have termed naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care to be the basis
of caring politics limits our perspectives on the problems and possibilities of caring politics. To
question our unmediated access to such dimensions of care is not to take a nihilistic stance, but to
present the problem in a clearer light.
V. Conclusion: Caring Attention—Ethical Given or Situated Praxis?
The concept of attention has been broadly theorized by care ethicists, many of whom have used
Simone Weil’s understanding of the concept to buttress their accounts.46 Discussing Weil, Tronto
notes that the capacity for attention is exemplary of care in that it is other-directed and “crucial
for any genuinely human interaction” (Moral Boundaries 128). Noddings and Ruddick also use
responsibility for the one area of life and their relative exclusion from the other” (85). One takeaway from my
analysis here is that addressing this problem requires moving beyond a framework that either values or dismisses
care due to its imbrication with essentialized notions of gender. If we can see that care is both an essential element
of life and thriving that should be tended, valued, and transformed and at the same time a naturalized ethic that
reifies and mystifies relations of violence such as gender relations, this helps to illuminate an albeit difficult path
away from debates around the role of essentialized gender norms in the ethical valuation of care.
46
Following Weil, care ethicists have posed a direct link between attention, empathy, and moral education. As
Tronto points out, Weil claimed that attention should be the basis—the motivation and goal—of education. I will not
discuss education until the final chapter of this book, but for now I want to hold onto this claim that attention is
directly linked to questions of ethical education to care, and thus the question of how to teach and learn care under
conditions of structural insensibility to care on the part of institutions and individuals. But at this point in my
argument, I turn to the question of caring attention because it helps to illuminate where care ethicists go wrong in
their understandings and praxes of caring.
62
Weil’s understanding of attention to draw out the phenomenology of other-directedness (Caring
203) and practices of attentive love (Maternal Thinking 120). Both Noddings and Ruddick
contend that, as other-directed, such caring attention cannot be fantasy or projection. Speaking of
motherhood in particular, Ruddick points to the difficulty in to keeping “one’s attention fixed to
the real situation:” the goal in caring attention is thus to “let otherness be,” and let “difference
emerge without searching for comforting commonalities” (122).
This is a beautiful image, but one that Weil’s own thought illuminatingly complicates.
For Weil, it is precisely the capacity to be with, indeed, to embody and express, contradiction
that grants attention its transformative value. “We are beings with the faculty of knowing, willing
and loving, and as soon as we turn our attention towards the objects of knowledge, will and love,
we receive evidence that there is not one which is not impossible… Consciousness of this
impossibility forces us to long continually to grasp what cannot be grasped in all that we desire,
know and will” (Gravity and Grace 96). In attempting to shape our faculties in accordance with
reality, we precisely realize that “contradiction is the criterion of the real” (98, my emphasis).
Itself an instance of such contradiction, attention is born when we allow ourselves to be rent by
what we are attending to. For Weil this contradictory capacity is the ground and condition of
ethical action: “All true good carries with it conditions which are contradictory and as a
consequence is impossible. He who keeps his attention really fixed on this impossibility and acts
will do what is good” (98).
While Weil understands contradiction as metaphysical, and for us here it is social and
material, we can follow her in imagining that attention becomes capable of moral worth in its
capacity to attend to living contradiction—in its capacity for knowledge, desire, love, and will—
and be present to seemingly impossible complexity. Applying this insight, we might say that
63
caring attention becomes ethical not by assuming its inherent value or the well-executed motives
of the carer but in its capacity to hold, to attend or bear witness to, the contradictions of caring
under conditions in which this may be difficult if not impossible.
Perhaps even more crucial than the role of contradiction in Weil’s notion of attention is
how she conceives of its moral value and educative function as arising not from existing norms,
dispositions, or attitudes, but from a shift in perception that transforms them. Attention invokes a
kind of passivity: rather than the inherent capacity of a transparent self, attention involves a shift
in sensibility, in which we are fundamentally altered in relation to the person or situation to
which we attend. This seems to be the very thing that letting otherness be and allowing
difference to emerge requires—always in relation to the dangers of fantasy and projection
inevitable in the social complexities of caring.
Conceived in this way, the ethical stakes of attention are revealed in its capacity to hold
and attend to the complexity of what is, rather than presupposed in caring dispositions
themselves. In Weil’s own writings this is conceived as a process of being undone and changed
by the impossible demands of the world, and it is thus not an achievement we can finally claim.
Most care ethicists would agree that becoming a good carer is a life’s work—hence the central
role of ethical and affective education in many care ethical writings. However, if we do not have
unmediated access to experiences or understandings of good care prior to violence, and thus no
access to naturalistic sources of caring attention, then radically caring in, and caring for, a world
in crisis proves a much more difficult, and indeed transformative, task.
Hil Malatno’s theory of trans care offers a more generative and transformative approach
that roots of caring ethics in ongoing, collective. praxis rather than a naturalized or abstract
capacity for attention. Malatino’s account of trans care differs from the theories of care outlined
64
above in that it is not given but prefigurative, and attentive to the specificity of trans lives and
needs. In one sense, trans care comprises non-hierarchical, bottom up, forms of communization
and mutual-aid—what Dean Spade terms “social justice infrastructures”—that strive to meet
needs and distribute resources in response to state and NGO failures, and often in defiance of
their logics. But it also describes a collective and relational ethos, an “infrapolitical ethics of
care,” guided by and productive of what Amy Marvin terms “trans ethical wisdom” (Trans Care
43). Malatino points to how these multivalent practices empower trans communities to shift the
terrain of care ethics and care labor away from the white, cis, gender-normative presuppositions
that often permeate even the most radical literatures on care. And yet, he is equally attentive to
the harms that normative care can leave in its wake—the role that abuses, denials, and coercions
of care play in the “overwhelming negative affect” (43) of a transphobic world. Malatino’s
presentation of this both/and of trans care—as both a reparative response to the ruptures, harms
and withdrawals of care that trans people disproportionately face, and an instance of the
transformative power of learning to care otherwise.
Trans people are disproportionately affected by structural violence and its intimate
impacts, and often do not have recourse to the paternalistic care of the state or the parochial care
of the cis-het, Western, family form. But trans care webs do not only attend to these wounds.
They also pose radical alternatives to normative models of care. There are no dyads or
hierarchies in a web because it extends horizontally in many directions with no beginning, end,
or center; likewise, resilient networks of queer and trans care and mutual aid run counter to
exploitative and extractive logics of care economies in both the ‘private’ and ‘public’ sphere.
The “resonant traumas” that bind many trans carers together may bear the imprint of care denied
or refused. But relating through such resonant traumas also nurtures alternative forms of
65
solidarity and interdependency—changing the shape of care, and the subjects who give and
receive it.
The alternative forms of care and kinship developed in queer and trans communities are
neither normative nor given. Of course, this poses its own dangers: insofar as care, like gender, is
embodied and performed within a matrix of recognition and response. Like all forms of care,
“trans care can all too easily reproduce hierarchies of attention, aid, and deservingness.” This
means that “[a]ny care praxis worth enacting must be attentive to such tendencies to reproduce
injustice. This applies to forms of emotional support just as much as it does to forms of financial
support” (69). Citing the work of Maria Puig de la Ballacasa, Malatino argues that care is never
abstract, “but only ever manifested in practice.” This means that “practices of care are always
part of an emergent ethos” (40-41, my emphasis). “They are not a priori universal, they do not
define a moral, or social, or even natural ‘nature’: they become necessary to the maintaining and
flourishing of a relation through the process of ongoing relating.” As an ethos, an assemblage of
practices, trans care disrupts the moral and material structures—the intricate regulations of
intimacy and desire, the lines dividing public and private—that correspond with normative
conceptions of gender as a “natural attitude” (37-38). Trans care reveals that, like gender itself,
care is not a natural or universal good, but a form of embodied emergence, brushing up against
the ineffable (56) as well as the dead weight of the past.
Malatino clarifies that a, perhaps the primary aim of his book is to “think about what care
actually looks like in trans lives. This means decentering the family and beginning, instead, from
the many-gendered, radically inventive, and really, really, exhausted weavers of our webs of
care” (6-7). The question of who is doing this weaving, and how, is what he is speaking about
when he discusses ‘transing care.’ Malatino notes that the “secret power” of the care web lies in
66
what Leah Lakshmi Piepzna-Samarasinha terms a “crip femme” reworking of the anarchocommunist mutual-aid dictum (and Marxist slogan) “from each according to their ability, to each
according to their need” (Piepzna-Samarasinha, Care Work, cited in Malatino, 2). Discussing the
concept of the care web from a disability justice and QTBIPOC perspective, PiepznaSamarasinha asks what it would mean “to shift our ideas of access and care… from an individual
choice, an unfortunate cost of having an unfortunate body, to a collective responsibility that’s
maybe even deeply joyful?” (Care Work 33). Like Piepzna-Samarasinha, Malatino emphasizes
these simultaneously joyful dimensions of collective access and collective care, and the physical,
existential, and emotional toll shouldered by those with both caring abilities and care needs.
Piepzna-Samarasinha and Malatino both cite the STAR House as a historical, if mythologized,
example: “the house started by Black and Brown trans femme sex worker revolutionaries Marsha
P. Johnson and Silvia Rivera, with the rent paid by hustling and street sex work, as a safe space
for trans people of color and street trans people to be free, be with each other, and share
hormones and other supplies for healing and gender affirmation” (34).The ethical practices
undergirding resilient care web will honor such brilliant caring skills—skills that are so
systemically devalued in racialized, gender and international divisions of caring labor—as well
as mitigate against the realities of oppression that result in unjust distributions of care labor and
access in the first place. In this sense, fostering resilient networks of care requires not only
redistributing resources, but uprooting engrained expectations about who receives access to care,
and who shoulders its physical and emotional burdens.
The term ‘transing care’ has a critical component too: it “also means grappling with the
fact that the forms of family and kinship that are invoked in much of the feminist literature on
care labor and care ethics are steeped in forms of domesticity and intimacy that are both White
67
and Eurocentered, grounded in the colonial/modern gender system (Lugones, 2007).” Malatino
clarifies this tension between normative and trans care through a discussion of a syllabus on
queer and trans care that he put together with Aren Aizura. In constructing the syllabus, the two
of them were “forced to grapple with the failure of dominant articulations of care work and care
ethics to do justice to the complexities of care labor trans subjects both need and undertake” (42).
By “decentering the domestic,” Malatino and Aizura found that “[t]he terrain of what constitutes
care shifts radically…For queer and trans subjects, this is often less about exporting the
feminized values of care associated with the White, bourgeois home to the public sphere than it
is about seeking ways to make the multivalent and necessary care hustle that structures so many
of our lives more sustainable, especially as we’re often actively engaged in inventing or piecing
together the units—domestic, familial, intimate—that are just assumed a priori in much literature
on care labor and care ethics” (43).
The process of transing care is immanent and anti-utopian in the deepest and most
material sense. Trans care webs coalesce around holes in the fabric of normative care, meeting
needs that go unmet within existing care structures. But a further argument is implicit in
Malatino’s book: that, in mending the gaps and withdrawals of existing care structures, trans
carers also reveal the harmful nature—the fatal contradictions and flaws—of these care
structures themselves. In this light, it appears that it was perhaps never possible, or desirable, to
quantify care in a logic of exchange, or universalize it as a moral value. That, from this
perspective, feminist aspirations to achieve quantifiably equalized care might be seen as
reproducing the very neoliberal logics they oppose (45). Or that care ethical moves to export
socially constituted values of care as a private, family affair into the public sphere (42) seem
eerily reminiscent of the very moral a priorisms that care ethicists universally dispute.
68
Insofar as they often do not, and cannot, rely on given norms and institutions of care,
queer and trans forms of collective care and mutual-aid require the ongoing cultivation of a
situated ethos—what Caffyn Jesse terms an ‘ethics for outlaws’ that is living, embodied, and
counternormative—rather than “naturalizing a set of values from [women’s] labor, then
extrapolating and exploring the deprioritization of these values in the public sphere” (Trans Care
42). Such care, in Ballacasa’s words, “remains ambivalent in its significance and social
ontology.”47 Caring attention in this light would not be a given capacity from which we can
generate norms48 but an ongoing inquiry and practice, “The question, then, is not ‘how can we
care more? ’but instead to ask what happens to our work when we pay attention to moments
where the question of ‘how to care? ’is insistent but not easily answerable” (Atkinson-Graham et
al. 2015, cited in Ballacasa, 7).
Care is a necessary and essential component of human life. As such, it is deeply
structured by social relations and their embedded inequalities. To speak of care, and the ethics of
care, as a naturalistically derived value or set of dispositions is to resort to the very sort of
abstract moral theorizing care ethicists for decades have shown to be incompatible with our
living experiences and relations of care. If, as care ethicists maintain, there is no abstract care, we
cannot abstract care from social relations or the harms they contain and perpetuate.
47
Bellacasa opens her book with these powerful words, that resonate deeply with the questions and concerns I raise
here: “Care, caring, carer. Burdened words, contested words. And yet so common in everyday life, as if care was
evident, beyond particular expertise or knowledge. Most of us need care, feel care, are cared for, or encounter care,
in one way or another. Care is omnipresent, even through the effects of its absence. Like a longing emanating from
the troubles of neglect, it passes within, across, throughout things. Its lack undoes, allows unraveling. To care can
feel good; it can also feel awful. It can do good; it can oppress. Its essential character to humans and countless living
beings makes it all the most susceptible to convey control. But what is care? Is it an affection? A moral obligation?
Work? A burden? A joy? Something we can learn or practice? Something we just do? Care means all these things
and different things to different people, in different situations. So while ways of caring can be identified, researched,
and understood concretely and empirically, care remains ambivalent in significance and ontology” (1).
48
“The question, then, is not ‘how can we care more? ’but instead to ask what happens to our work when we pay
attention to moments where the question of ‘how to care? ’is insistent but not easily answerable” (Atkinson-Graham
et al. 2015, cited in Ballacasa, 7).
69
The very feminist politics that care ethics draws upon and richly elaborates demands a
political orientation to those layers of experience and social practice excluded by dominant
understandings of the political. To grasp the personal as political means that the so-called
personal domain is already a political site of contestation and struggle. If care, like the domestic
sphere to which it has been ideologically and materially confined, is already political to its core,
then we cannot at the same time ground the ethics and politics of care in a form of natural or
universalized care that lies prior to or beyond political articulation. Hierarchies and dominations
are reproduced in social organizations and practices of care for deep political reasons, which
render them contested sites of struggle that demand, and resist, critique and transformation.
Care’s most intimate and apparently given dimensions are already politically constituted—in
dominant modes but also in myriad forms of resistance. Contending with the gendered, as well as
racist, colonial, ableist and hetero- and cis-normative dominations characteristic of how care is
socially organized and practiced is a question of political articulation and struggle. Just as
essentially, the collective and often politicized forms of care articulated by marginalized
communities reveal care to be a site of refuge, praxis, and political and ethical education
indispensable to radical politics.
If, as I am claiming, the power dynamics of an oppressive society live on in our very
epistemologies of care—that is, if social contradiction can be embedded in our very capacities
for affective attention and intuitive response—this presents deep political problems and
possibilities. In the next chapter I present these concerns in relation to interlocking oppressions
contained and reproduced in social organizations and divisions of caring labor, and the ways that
intersectional feminists have mobilized care politically and ethically in response to this violence.
For now, I want to end with two observations. First: I hope I have been convincing in my claim
70
that what care ethicists conceive of as care’s natural or universally accessible dimensions do not
escape or even ground the politics of care but are themselves politically contested, and
generative, sites of meaning-making and praxis. This means that, rather than ethical givens, what
I have termed naturalistic/naturalizing epistemologies of care are sites of contradiction, struggle,
and transformation. My second and final point is a note on method and concerns how to think
about transforming these modes of relational engagement in alignment with social justice. A
crucial insight of care ethics bears repeating in confronting the magnitude of this question:
namely that the ethics of care cannot be grasped through an appeal to abstract norms, but are
cultivated from inside embodied, relational, and, I would add, ultimately collective, experiences.
However, insofar as this intimate and affective transformation is itself political, it must also be
conceived and enacted as an integral component of broader social movements and political
change.
While it revolutionizes ethics from the perspective of care, and even calls for radically
restructuring society based on caring politics, the care ethical tradition has not fully attended to
the role of structural violence in shaping caring practices and relations. I believe this is because
this tradition roots the ethics and politics of care in an apolitical conception of care. In the
remaining chapters, my aim will be to present the stakes of this point, which I hope I have now
earned: namely, that the elements of care naturalized by care ethics are themselves implicated in
structures of violence that generate contradictions in caring practices—even and precisely at
these intimate levels.
71
Chapter Two:
There is No Universal Care: Interlocking Oppressions and the Politics of
Experience in Intersectional Theories of Care
72
I. Introduction: Caring Through Difference?
We cannot view care as outside of or beyond violence or struggle. At the same time, people’s
creative, life-giving caring capacities exceed the violence to which care is structurally and
intimately bound and lie at the root of emergent and historical political practices and imaginaries.
Ethically speaking, this contradictory nature of care under conditions of systemic violence means
that we do not have recourse to naturalistic understandings of care as a value. Radical care ethics
are made possible not through given caring dispositions, but in relation to the politics of care:
both in a negative sense (in terms of the structural oppressions within which it is socially
embedded) as well as positively (in terms of its transformative, indeed revolutionary, role in
social struggles). Far from nullifying the ethics of care, this political view on care exposes its
necessity and weight.
In the previous chapter my intention was to motivate the ethical problems posed by the
contradictions of care, arguing that rooting care’s ethical value in naturalistically conceived
dispositions or a universal experience of care presents the violence socially embedded and
reproduced in care as either a pathological deviation from genuinely caring relations, or a form
of ambivalence inherent to them. This precisely risks naturalizing historically specific forms of
violence and their effects on intimate and communal life and depoliticizing care’s role in both
maintaining the status quo and fostering alternative ways of living and relating. The aim of the
present chapter is to show how theoretical and political insights developed by intersectional and
women of color philosophers regarding the interlocking nature of oppressions—and the
inadequacy of existing political categories and practices to this reality—challenge these
naturalistic assumptions, and indeed bring care into view in ways more in keeping with the
revolution in ethics that care ethicists call for. This chapter suggests that naturalistically
73
construing care as an ethical good sidesteps the constitutive intersectional violence at play in
many existing social structures and norms, and the impact of this violence on the intimacies of
caring relations themselves. It also occludes the transformative caring ethics and politics at play
in the ways that communities foster conditions more amenable to their collective survival and
flourishing.
Ethically and politically speaking, care is where the intimate and the structural meet. In
hetero-patriarchal, white supremacist, settler colonial, and ableist societies, care is socially
organized in ways that can render care one-sided and extractive and/or neglect the needs of those
who depend upon it. These inequalities trace distinct forms of oppression (as well as forms of
paid and unpaid exploitation) that are, at the same time, deeply interconnected in both structural
divisions of caring labor and in people’s lived experiences of giving and receiving care. Yet,
care’s political and ethical salience is equally evident in practices and networks of care and
nurturance developed by oppressed people, which not only provide refuge from this violence but
often foment resistance against it and autonomous living beyond it.
A premise of this chapter, which I develop in the first section, is that social organizations
and divisions of this caring labor49 express and reproduce gender, racialized, colonial, ableist and
class oppressions on both macro and micro scales. The ideological and material devaluation and
exploitation of caring labor and those who perform it, as well as the systemic neglect of those
most in need of care, are not incidental but structural to the maintenance of violent institutions
and social relations. Dynamics of racial capitalist exploitation, for example, perpetuate and
compound multiple, and intersecting, forms of oppression through what have come to be known
49
According to Evelyn Nakano Glenn, “The social organization of care has been rooted in diverse forms of coercion
that have…tracked poor, racial minority, and immigrant women into positions entailing caring for others” (Forced
to Care 5).
74
as international care chains.50 Capitalist accumulation depends upon reproductive labor to
support ever more endangered life conditions. Maximizing profit requires externalizing this
labor, and in doing so, exploiting it as fully as possible: naturalizing it as a female vocation or
coercing, stealing, or paying extremely little for it. And it is not a coincidence that many migrant
women of color from the Global South—who often work in isolation and without basic labor and
citizenship protections in households continents away from their own—are currently doing this
sort of labor.
I also want to clarify my claim that inequality and violence are reproduced not only
through social institutions and divisions of caring labor, but through intersubjective patterns of
attention and response that take place on intimate and emotional registers. This is a tender topic,
but one that I believe touches the heart of care. Attending to this level of social shaping and
wounding can be deeply uncomfortable and requires culturally and community specific holding
containers and modalities for interrogating power—a point that I return to in the subsequent
chapters and conclusion of this dissertation. In pointing to this terrain of intimate contradiction
and struggle, my aim is not to make a universalizing or generalizing claim about people’s
experiences. My intent, rather, is to point to how experiences of care or lack thereof shape the
very contours of our sensory worlds and embodied relations to others. In this sense, my argument
follows care ethical insights about the specific and relational nature of care, which, in its intimate
pains and joys, can only be known from the inside. Such specificities include the skills and
virtuosities of care, but also the personal and collective resistance strategies, protective
mechanisms and deflections, and strategies of endurance that people develop in the face of
50
See Rhacel Salazar Parreñas’s study of the the global migration of Filipino domestic workers for a thorough and
careful account of both the structural violence at play in international care chains (the lack of labor and citizenship
protections, the harsh exploitations of this unregulated market, migration fees, and risks of abuse, dislocation and
isolation), as well as the agency and private desires the women she interviews bring to this work.
75
intimate coercion, exploitation, and neglect—as well as the alternative political economies,
kinship networks, nurturance practices and liberatory values that individuals and communities
manifest in their cultures and practices of care.
Another premise of this chapter concerns the crucial differences, as well as relations,
between paid and unpaid forms of care and social reproductive labor. Drawing on the extensive
feminist debates on the subject, I understand these distinctions in terms of the broad categories
of: i.) caring services subsidized by the state (e.g. welfare services, public health care); ii.) caring
services in the private market economy (e.g. privately employed nurses aids and elder care
workers); iii.) unpaid domestic labor that contributes to household and community reproduction
(e.g. the ‘housewife,’ but also broader, often female, kinship networks); and iv.) paid care labor
that is de-regulated and hyper-exploited in private, domestic economies (e.g. paid domestic
laborers and nannies). I follow theorists who center the intersecting oppressions reproduced in
these social organizations and divisions of caring labor. Black feminists51 have long pointed to
the vast differences between unpaid and paid domestic labor, and the extreme forms of
exploitation and abuse, historically rooted in slavery and segregation, involved in the latter.
Evelyn Nakano Glenn points to how white feminist assumptions about the universal gendering of
reproductive labor obscure these “differences across race, ethnic, and class groups in women's
relationship to that labor” (“From Servitude” 2). She points to the continuities between the
“servitude” of paid domestic labor and the racialized divisions of labor evident in commodified
service economies, where women of color continue to disproportionately occupy lower paid,
“deskilled,” positions (“From Servitude” 3).
51
See for example Hazel Carby (1982), Audre Lorde (1979, 1980), Angela Davis (1983, 1972).
76
Political and ethical articulations of care must attend to such interlocking oppressions and
social hierarchies at play in political economies of care, as well as the specific forms of agency
and organization fostered by care workers and recipients. In this sense, I follow those who have
critiqued the care ethical tendency to value bio-familial care over commodified caring services—
a move which discounts the intensive forms of emotional and bodily labor performed by
exploited care workers, the role of paid care work in buttressing the ostensibly private home, and
the historical and actual non-primacy of the nuclear family in many people’s lives.
Together, these assumptions support and motivate my claim that care is not outside of or
beyond violence and political transformation. The flip side of this is that the harms reproduced in
caring structures and relations are not intrinsic to care as such but features of social relations and
norms that both moralize and devalue it along multiple and intersecting axes of oppression.
“Dangers” such as paternalism and parochialism52 thus should not be construed as pathologies
inherent to care, but as examples of historically specific harms corresponding, in large part, to
contemporary social forms and institutions: e.g., cultural, and familial chauvinism in the case of
parochial care, and, in the case of paternalistic care, the individualizing narratives of
responsibilization and deservingness at play in the allocation of ever dwindling assistance.
Elana Buch draws attention to how Western ideals of independence are bolstered, in
structural ways, through extractive and exploitative networks of interdependence.53 The apparent
independence of some is upheld through the entrenched and systemic exploitation of the care
52
For Joan Tronto, parochial care is a “way to excuse the inattention of the privileged” (Moral Boundaries 146) and
paternalistic care is care “in which care givers assume that they know better than care receivers what those care
receivers need” (“Creating Caring Institutions” 161).
53
Buch presents the intimate stakes of this problem through her portrait of Maria Arrelano, a Puerto Rican eldercare worker. Maria’s care labor is deeply skilled: she seamlessly creates worlds of sense, meaning and embodiment
that enable more privileged, aging women to maintain a sense of independence. She takes pride in her work and is
very good at it. However, when prompted to speak to these deep skills involved in her caring labor, Maria spoke
primarily about the skill needed to shield the recipients from the impacts of her own exploited position and its
painful costs for her and her family (Buch 1-11).
77
labor of others: a relation which often traces lines of race, class, and nationality, in addition to
gender. Such inequalities vis a vis care and reproductive labor are a central point of conflict
between feminized people and have been definitive of feminist history and theory—as Audre
Lorde famously pointed out when she asked of white academic feminists in 1979:54 “if white
american feminist theory need not deal with the differences between us, and the resulting
difference in our oppressions, then how do you deal with the fact that the women who clean your
houses and tend your children while you attend conferences on feminist theory are, for the most
part, poor women and women of Color?” (112).
Lorde’s provocation poses a problem for care ethicists, many of whom place attention to
difference at the very heart of care. Care ethics is built on the idea that, at its most elemental,
care simply is the ability to consistently meet another in their alterity and need. Paradigmatic
care ethical concepts such as empathy and engrossment with the other (both of which I discuss at
length below) are grounded in, and work to develop, this core assumption. Yet the (often
disavowed) societal expectations around care remain that poor, migrant and/or women of color
will skillfully perform the labor of care, more privileged individuals will be skillfully cared for,
and this power imbalance will be naturalized through care’s devaluation and deskilling on the
one hand, and the sentimentalized moralizing of care on the other. It is helpful to recall
Dowling’s notion of ideologies of care (Care Crisis 85), which mystify power relations and
justify unequal social organizations and divisions of caring labor. While Dowling doesn’t
mention this specifically, ideologies of care are particularly insidious when they serve to
naturalize and normalize forms of oppression that are intersectional in nature.55
54
“The Master’s Tools Will Never Dismantle the Master’s House” was presented in “The Personal Is Political”
panel at the NYU conference on Simone de Beauvior’s The Second Sex in 1979.
55
Premilla Nadasan, for example, points to the simultaneously racist and sexist stereotypes that were historically
utilized in reference to Black women's coerced domestic labor. This ideology of care served a distinct purpose: the
78
The first half of this chapter reconstructs arguments from Kimberle Crenshaw, Patricia
Hill Collins, the Combahee River Collective, bell hooks and Nakano Glenn regarding the
intersecting oppressions historically and presently manifest in social organizations and divisions
of caring labor. In the second half, I claim that these arguments trouble our ability to generate
ethics from affective and embodied dispositions of care alone.
To call upon Lorde’s riddling metaphor, we cannot dismantle a culture built on the
exploitation and devaluation of care with the tools used to build it. Although I hesitate to draw
upon an idea so frequently applied and misused, I think it is helpful for situating these problems
and possibilities of care. Lorde herself was specific about the role of intimate relational patterns
and attitudes in maintaining the dominant order, as well as fostering new and more life affirming
ways of living. For Lorde, “old blueprints of expectation and response” (123) serve as master’s
tools when they normalize violence and prevent genuine mutuality and nurturance across
differences. Given how profoundly social organizations and divisions of caring labor trace social
inequalities, I believe that we can take many existing norms and practices of care as paradigmatic
instances of how such oppressive blueprints can live in our attachments and sensibilities. Such
patterns of expectation and response are expressed—as she points out—in who cares for the
children of whom during academic conferences, but also in unconscious and somatically
engrained expectations about who should, or will, be disproportionately responsive to the needs
of others, and who’s needs should, or will, be disproportionately responded to or neglected.
Because care’s imbrication with structural violence runs so deep, such patterns can show up even
image of “a content and loyal household worker who nurtured and protected white children” was cynically invoked
to both normalize a coercive and exploitative relation of care that descended from the institution of slavery, while
attempting to mask and neutralize that history and present “a fictionalized tale of stable race relations” (Household
Workers Unite 17). “The mammy figured prominently in advertising, the arts, and literature at the beginning of the
twentieth century, as white northerners and southerners attempted to put the divisiveness and resentment of the Civil
War behind them and mask contemporary racial violence. The black mammy issued from a fictionalized tale of
stable race relations marked by mutual dependence and familial love” (16-17).
79
in earnest attempts to confront them. And yet, for the same reason, transforming embodied
practices of attention and response—forging new caring sensibilities and “new patterns of
relating across difference” (123)—is a political task of urgent proportions.
II. Intersectional Perspectives on Care
Intersectional interventions into the nature of oppression pose deep challenges to the ethics of
care. On the one hand, they show that interconnected forms of structural violence play a
determining role in the fact that many women of color are, and have historically been, forced into
deeply exploitative forms of caring labor, and that social organizations and divisions of caring
labor both mirror and reproduce this violence. This means that, far from universal and
universally accessible, the experience of care so central to care ethical theorizing is shaped in
complex and differential ways at the intersections of power.56 These differences trace axes of
structural oppression, yet they are also evident in the differential relations people have to the
intimate coercions and exploitation at play in many forms of caring labor. On the other hand,
those who are coerced into exploitative caregiving or systemically denied care are frequently the
fiercest negotiators of caring politics, and transformative practices of care play a vital role in how
marginalized communities foster conditions more amenable to their collective survival and
flourishing. My claim, developed in the next section, is that naturalistic approaches to care are
inadequate to the politics of care in both this positive and negative sense. In this section, I
discuss some implications of intersectional feminist thinking for the ethics and politics of care,
56
The violence embedded in social organizations and divisions of care also differentially and unequally affects
people who depend on care. Disability justice theorists and organizers in particular shed light on the intersectional
harms that affect disabled people of color and poor disabled people in particular, who are systemically exposed to
abuse in caring relations, and are more likely to be exposed to and stay in abusive relationships due to lack of access
to care. While I do not adequately address this form of structural harm here, it is essential to a full picture of how not
only those caring, but also those cared for, can be harmed by structural violences reproduced in caring practices and
relations. See e.g. Sins Invalid, 2019; Lakshmi Piepzna-Samarasinha 2018.
80
focusing on the intersections of race, gender, class, and nationality at play in some of the most
essentially caring dimensions of reproductive labor.
As a concept and practice that has exploded in the past three decades, there are multiple
and divergent perspectives on what it means to locate intersectional thought in its specific
contexts and modes of application. Kathryn Sophia Belle notes the importance of historically,
analytically, and politically situating the concepts and modes of thinking that women of color
have developed to address their experiences. This is not an abstract ethics of citation but an ethos
intrinsic to intersectional theorizing as such.57 As Collins theorizes at length, women of color’s
knowledge has been systemically subjugated and suppressed. Belle points to how Black feminist
concepts in particular—e.g., the notion of interlocking oppressions, identity politics, and indeed
intersectionality itself—are routinely “misused, taken out of context, misappropriated, and/or
depoliticized” (“Interlocking” 171). A respect for context is thus crucial to comprehending this
critical lineage of thought. It is also a way of mitigating against the ways in which the work of
women of color has been appropriated and abused58—cynically by the Right as well as casually
and opportunistically by the individualistic, competitive norms of academic knowledge
production. For Belle, situating the different theoretical frameworks developed by marginalized
groups is also a condition for coalition building between them.
57
A commitment to a collective ethos is a common refrain in intersectional scholarship. Belle cites Spillers: “What I
was trying to do when I wrote that essay many years ago was to find a vocabulary that would make it possible, and
not all by myself, to make a contribution to a larger project” (167). Ange Marie Hancock also places community
ethics at the center of intersectional theorizing, and views her own intersectional scholarship as informed by an
“ethic of literary stewardship” charged with fostering intersectionality as a collective literacy. Speaking of her
accountability to this community she states:“ This notion of an interpretive community being entrusted with the care
of such a precious and complicated phenomenon like intersectionality is the best way of describing my current
intellectual position. If we think of a steward as someone entrusted with caring for valuables that she does not
herself own, then my role is to not only disavow ownership of intersectionality, but to remember that while I am
permitted to use it, I must do so ethically, which entails producing projects that hopefully leave intersectionality
scholars better equipped to engage in knowledge production projects in intersectionality studies” (23).
58
She points to the misappropriations of Black feminist concepts in particular: the notion of “identity politics” first
developed by Barbara Smith, Beverley Smith, and Demita Fraizer in the Combahee River Collective Statement, as
well as the notion of intersectionality first coined by Kimberlé Crenshaw.
81
Patricia Hill Collins, who, alongside Crenshaw, is largely cited as ‘coining’ the term,
situates the concept in the specific standpoint of US Black women and their oppositional
practices of knowledge making and political engagement. In Intersectionality: An Intellectual
History, Ange Marie Hancock presents intersectionality in a broader social and international
context, while also accounting for the central role of US Black feminist thinkers and organizers
in its development. To account for its specific genesis, and pay tribute to the essential
contributions of other women of color in the US, Global South, and internationally in theorizing
the impact of multiple oppressions and struggles against them, Hancock supplements her
analysis with the term intersectionality-like thinking.
Hancock’s language is helpful in situating my discussion of the intersectionality of care
below, particularly my citation of both explicitly intersectional thinkers as well as theorists
whose insights on care are better understood as ‘intersectionality-like.’ Below I frame my
discussions of the violence as well as the politicization of care with discussions of Crenshaw and
Collins—both of whom are widely cited as seminal intersectional thinkers—and also with the
explicitly intersectional approaches of thinkers such as Belle, Deva Woodly, and Alicia Garza,
and also rely heavily on the work of Evelyn Nakano Glenn, Angela Davis, and Saidiya Hartman,
who do not always work from an explicitly intersectional framework, but whose analyses deepen
understandings of care from the perspective of multiple oppressions and/or practices of
resistance against them. My aims in doing so are to foreground i.) the interlocking oppressions
undergirding social organizations and divisions of caring labor; ii.) the irreducibility of the
oppressions involved in care to single issue frames, especially gender, and iii.) the inadequacy of
naturalistic/naturalized epistemologies of care to the intimate and relational violence perpetuated
in caring relations.
82
For Kimberlé Crenshaw, who coined the term,59 intersectionality speaks “against the
tendency to treat race and gender as mutually exclusive categories of analytics and experience”
(“Demarginalizing” 139). In her analysis of various social locations and discourses including
discrimination law, conceptions of sexual violence, and pop cultural representations of race and
gender, she interrogates how a focus on gender and race as socially and discursively discrete,
“single axis” categories limits both analytic and practical orientations to institutional racism and
sexism. To focus on the “most privileged group members” (here, Black men and white women)
“marginalizes those who are multiply-burdened and obscures claims that cannot be understood as
resulting from discrete sources of discrimination.”
In centering the “multidimensionality” of Black women’s experiences, Crenshaw’s work
inaugurates a paradigm shift in thinking about the nature of oppression itself60—revealing it to be
a “much more complex phenomenon” than single issue frames can bring into view. Crenshaw’s
move to center Black women, and the irreducibility of their life experiences to single-axis
frames, is thus at once political, methodological, and critical.61 As Alicia Garza explains,
“intersectionality is a way to understand how power operates. It is also a way to ensure that no
one, as Crenshaw states, gets left behind. It is a way of understanding both how and why people
have been left behind, and it offers a road map for change by making visible those who are
59
Collins echoes a common sentiment in intersectional discourse when she critiques this idea of individual
“coining”: “This origin story inserts intersectionality into a familiar colonial narrative that positions Crenshaw as the
intrepid explorer who, because she discovers virgin territory, gets naming rights” (Intersectionality 121). This is
certainly not a critique of Crenshaw herself, but the ways in which intersectionality, as a critical epistemology and
social practice rooted in collective intellectual labor of Black women, has been framed by and for individualizing
Western academic norms.
60
Crenshaw states that she centers Black women “in order to contrast the multidimensionality of Black women's
experience with the single-axis analysis that distorts these experiences. Not only will this juxtaposition reveal how
Black women are theoretically erased, it will also illustrate how this framework imports its own theoretical
limitations that undermine efforts to broaden feminist and antiracist analyses. With Black women as the starting
point, it becomes more apparent how dominant conceptions of discrimination condition us to think about
subordination as disadvantage occurring along a single categorical axis” (“Demarginalizing,” 139-140).
61
Crenshaw’s own categorization includes “structural intersectionality,” “political intersectionality” and
“Representational intersectionality.” See also Belle, 173.
83
currently invisible” (292). Insofar as power does not operate through discrete, single-axis
categories, understanding it requires deepening and revising conceptions of how social
inequalities are reproduced. It also requires listening to how people experience the impact of
multiple, simultaneous, oppressions on their lives, as well as drawing attention to the specific
ways that these compounding impacts have been invisibilized, marginalized, ignored.62
In offering what the Combahee River Collective (CRC) members termed an integrated
analysis of the experiences of Black women confronting multiple, interlocking oppressions,
Crenshaw’s theory of intersectionality distinctly opposes the kind of externalized, additive
thinking it is often accused of. It is helpful to quote her at some length on this issue:
I argue that Black women are sometimes excluded from feminist theory and antiracist policy
discourse because both are predicated on a discrete set of experiences that often does not
accurately reflect the interaction of race and gender. These problems of exclusion cannot be
solved simply by including Black women within an already established analytical structure.
Because the intersectional experience is greater than the sum of racism and sexism, any analysis
that does not take intersectionality into account cannot sufficiently address the particular manner
in which Black women are subordinated. Thus, for feminist theory and antiracist policy discourse
to embrace the experiences and concerns of Black women, the entire framework that has been
used as a basis for translating "women's experience" or "the Black experience” into concrete
policy demands must be rethought and recast (“Demarginalizing” 140, my emphasis).
As Belle notes, Crenshaw is precisely “not presenting an additive analysis of identity and
oppression” but showing how the “very meanings of racism and sexism need to be expanded”
(Belle 172). Belle quotes Crenshaw on this point: “because women of color experience racism in
ways that are not always the same as those experienced by men of color and sexism in ways that
are not always parallel to experiences of white women, antiracism and feminism are limited,
62
This concern to center Black women’s lives and experiences also motivated Crenshaw’s founding of the “Say Her
Name” campaign.
84
even on their own terms” (“Mapping the Margins” 1252). Crenshaw’s conception of
intersectionality as a method of thinking and political engagement is not a mathematical, external
calculus or a form of ‘oppression olympics.’ Rather, she proposes the development of new
categories, methods of thinking, and organizing strategies adequate to the complex realities of
oppression in the world and in people’s lives.
Crenshaw’s vision of intersectionality deepens and expands existing categories and
epistemic practices to better understand and work towards dismantling structural oppression. The
lived experience of multiply marginalized people is front and center to her method of critiquing
these operations of power. In an illuminating passage, Crenshaw invokes Sojourner Truth’s
paradigm shifting address at the Women’s Rights conference in Akron Ohio in 1851, during
which “white male hecklers, invoking stereotypical images of ‘womanhood,’ argued that women
were too frail and delicate to take on the responsibilities of political activity.” And yet, “when
Sojourner Truth rose to speak, many white women urged that she be silenced, fearing that she
would divert attention from women's suffrage to emancipation. Truth, once permitted to speak,
recounted the horrors of slavery, and its impact on Black women.” Crenshaw notes that by
speaking to the specific violence she endured as an enslaved Black woman, Truth’s oratory also
deeply undercut the narrative of female subordination in general. But acknowledging the weight
and power of her words and their implications for political practice equally required that white
suffragettes contended with their own racism:
Truth’s personal challenge to the coherence of the cult of true womanhood was useful only to the
extent that white women were willing to reject the racist attempts to rationalize the contradictionthat because Black women were something less than real women, their experiences had no bearing
on true womanhood. Thus, this 19th-century Black feminist challenged not only patriarchy, but she
also challenged white feminists…to relinquish their vestedness in whiteness (153-154).
85
Positing race and gender as mutually exclusive categories marginalizes women of color,
and is also inadequate to articulating the full dimensions of racism and gender violence in
general.63 However, for Crenshaw, the intersectional shift in perspective is not just about gaining
a clearer understanding of oppression—it is also a call for empowerment and social change. Like
the CRC and many other Black feminist and intersectional theorists, Crenshaw conceives of
identity not simply as a result of oppression, but also as a site of collective historical experience
and politicized agency. As Barbara and Beverly Smith and Demita Frazier articulated in their
seminal Combahee River Collective Statement over ten years prior to Crenshaw (a text which is
largely viewed to be the first written account of the much maligned and misunderstood concept
of “identity politics”)64 the fact that multiple forms of oppression were “interlocking” in their
experience and social positions required an “integrated analysis.” As they clarify, this integrated
analysis allowed them to speak to forms of violence that were both gendered and racialized, such
as the white supremacist use of rape as a weapon of political terror. But this integrated
perspective was also at play in the CRC’s expansive liberatory vision, which they rooted in the
particularity of their experience and “healthy self-love.”65 For Crenshaw, too, appreciating the
63
Davis emphasizes that: “behind this concept of intersectionality is a rich history of struggle”: “there were those of
us who by virtue of our experience, not so much by virtue of academic analysis, recognized that we had to figure out
a way to bring these issues together. They weren’t separate in our bodies but also they weren’t separate in terms of
struggles” (Freedom is a Constant Struggle 19).
64
According to Keeanga-Yamahtta Taylor, “The CRC made two key observations in their use of “identity politics.”
The first was that oppression on the basis of identity—whether it was racial, gender, class, or sexual orientation
identity—was a source of political radicalization. Black women were not radicalizing over abstract issues of
doctrine; they were radicalizing because of the ways that their multiple identities opened them up to overlapping
oppression and exploitation… But “identity politics” was not just about who you were; it was also about what you
could do to confront the oppression you were facing. Or, as Black women had argued within the broader feminist
“movement: “the personal is political.” This slogan was not just about “lifestyle” issues, as it came to be popularly
understood, rather it was initially about how the experiences within the lives of Black women shaped their political
outlook” (Taylor, 15-17). Garza also speaks to radical and political scope of the term: “…identity politics is the
radical notion that your worldview is shaped by your experiences and history and that those experiences will vary in
relationship to the power a group or an individual has in the economy, society, or democracy” (Garza 2020, 377-8)
65
“We realize that the liberation of all oppressed peoples necessitates the destruction of all the political-economic
systems of capitalism and imperialism as well as patriarchy” (CRC Statement, Re-printed in Taylor 2017).
86
differences across and within group categories—of gender, race, class, nationality, and
immigration status—specifies and deepens the possibilities of empowerment and coalition.
“Through an awareness of intersectionality, we can better acknowledge and ground the
differences among us and negotiate the means by which these differences will find expression in
constructing group politics” (“Mapping the Margins” 1299).
These paradigm shifts—regarding the need to center the experiences of those most
marginalized in society, the inadequacies of single-issue frames, the integrated perspectives
needed to confront structural oppressions, and the role of lived experience in theory creation—
are particularly relevant to the ethical and political analysis of care. First and foremost because
the oppressions endemic to social organizations and divisions of caring labor are intersectional:
they affect migrant women, poor women, and women of color in specific ways that cannot be
reduced to gender, racial, colonial or class oppression alone. However, as noted above,
intersectionality involves methodological, epistemic, and political shifts. Viewing care through
an intersectional lens thus also helps clarify the nature and impact of these inequalities on
people’s lived experiences: shedding light on the complexity and nuance of both the violence
inflicted upon, and the forms of knowledge and political agency generated by, those who are
socially designated as carers as well as those systemically denied care.
Again and again, women of color have drawn attention to the vast differences in
experience and life conditions between different feminized experiences of caring labor:
differences, for example, between those who have been societally pushed or coerced into
severely underpaid reproductive and caring labor, and those whose caring role, while often
exploitative, isolating, and demeaning, is largely limited to their own families and communities.
Indeed, racialized, and international divisions of caring and reproductive labor are indicative of
87
growing divides between women. As Premilla Nadasen notes,66 such disparities in experiences of
care work have animated the feminist movement since at least the 1970s, and distributions of
caring labor track growing material disparities among women based on race, class, nationality,
and immigration status. Black, Latina, post- and decolonial feminists have consistently pointed
to the roots of these racialized and international divisions of caring and reproductive labor in
histories of slavery and colonialism, as well as the ongoing social reproduction of racial
capitalism. They have launched deep critiques of white, Western feminists unwilling to
acknowledge and resist these realities, including their historical and actual complicities in the
sexual violence, emotional and material exploitation, and isolation of women of color performing
poorly paid—or unpaid, in the historical case of enslaved women—domestic and caring labor,
often in their very households.
As Evelyn Nakano Glenn points out in her powerful 1992 essay “From Servitude to
Service Work: Historical Continuities in the Racial Division of Paid Reproductive Labor,”
women’s relation to caring and reproductive labor is anything but universal. As she notes, “[t]he
gendered organization of reproduction is widely recognized. Less obvious, but equally
characteristic, is its racial construction: historically, racial-ethnic women have been assigned a
distinct place in the organization of reproductive labor” (6). Glenn outlines the unique forms of
coercion and exploitation faced by African American, Chicana, and Japanese American
compelled into domestic work, as well as the direct and intimate relationship between their
racialized subordination and the elevated status of the white, middle class, women who
employing them. She traces draws connections between this direct and obvious offloading of
reproductive labor and the racialized divisions that see women of color disproportionately
66
Nadasen spoke to this issue during her acceptance of the inaugural Ann Snitow prize on December 15, 2020.
https://barnard.edu/news/professor-premilla-nadasen-awarded-inaugural-ann-snitow-prize
88
performing deskilled, low paying, precarious, forms of care and service work in public and
service economies as well. In drawing attention to these continuities, Glenn highlights how
divisions of labor such as those between registered nurses and nurses’ aides reflect and sediment
these racial hierarchies between white women and women of color. She also points to how white
women’s complicity with this racialized division not only oppresses women of color but
contributes to ongoing gendered hierarchies that funnel white men into the ranks of doctors and
surgeons (23-29).
While Nakano Glenn’s focus in this piece is on the racial divisions of reproductive labor,
her work here and elsewhere also speaks to the complex ways in which gender and race (and
class and nationality) combine in the oppression and exploitation specific to paid caring labor. In
a more recent interview, she notes how racial and international divisions of caring labor further
entrench the gendering of care: the bourgeois working woman relieved to pass the burden of care
onto an underpaid immigrant women sediments her own role as head of household reproduction
and thus the private and feminized nature of care (Gender Policy Report). Meanwhile, the labor
of caring for the children and households left behind by migrant women is not generally picked
up by men but left to women in the extended family or the paid labor of even poorer women.
This means that the continued feminization of reproduction itself cannot be understood or
addressed without attention to racial and international divisions of reproductive labor, nor can
dynamics of race and nation entrenched in international care chains be grasped apart from care’s
intransigent gendering.
Nakano Glenn’s analysis sheds light on the intersectional dimensions of these material
and political economies of reproductive labor, but she also speaks to the intersecting oppressions
undergirding moral economies regarding who gives and who benefits from such labor, and the
89
naturalized subservience expected from those who perform it. The deskilling of reproductive
labor forms a crucial link between these material and ideological registers. Racialization is
reproduced in services such as elder care and nursing through this mechanism of deskilling:
“…the division between ‘skilled’ and ‘unskilled’ jobs is exactly where the racial division
typically falls” (“From Servitude 37). At the same time, systemic exploitation is naturalized and
mystified through racist ideologies of care. Thus, while different histories of racial and colonial
domination come into play in different ways with different groups of feminized care workers, the
racial stereotypes surrounding who is suited for reproductive work speak to a common logic.
“Whatever the specific context of the racial characterizations, it defined the proper place of these
groups as in service: they belonged there, just as it was the dominant group’s place to be served”
(14).
This racialized de-skilling is especially evident in the labor of care in particular:
What exactly is the nature of the reproductive labor that these largely minority and supposedly
unskilled aids and assistants perform? They do most of the day-to-day, face-to-face work of
caring for the ill and disabled…There is much “dirty” work, such as cleaning up incontinent
patients. Yet there is another, unacknowledged, mental and emotional dimension to the work:
listening to the remembrances of elderly patients…comforting frightened patients about to
undergo surgery, and providing the only human contact some patients get. This caring work is
largely invisible, and the skills required to do it are not recognized as real skills (30).
This is a crucial point: the most devalued and deskilled dimensions of reproductive labor—that
is, many of the skills most associated with care itself—are racialized in systemic ways.67 Patricia
67
Nakano Glenn compellingly presents the need to take interlocking oppressions into account in discussions of
social reproduction. While this is not immediately relevant to my argument here, she moreover points to how
attention to reproductive and caring labor deepens intersectional analysis. Racialized divisions of reproductive labor
and the racialized deskilling of care are key instances demonstrating the nature and effects of interlocking
oppressions in people’s lives, and the sorts of burdens they place on multiply marginalized people. Since multiple
oppressions are so thoroughly embedded in the social organization of reproduction, a focus on these divisions of
caring and reproductive labor provides a concrete instance of the need to move beyond additive models of race and
gender (3, 30).
90
Hill Collins makes a similar point: despite changes in the racialization of private paid domestic
work (which is now largely performed by migrant women in the US), their disproportionate
representation in service and caring economies means that “U.S. Black women still do a
remarkable share of the emotional nurturing and cleaning up after other people, often for lower
pay” (Black Feminist Thought 40).
As Nakano Glenn points out, care is seen as 'priceless' and is one of the most poorly paid
forms of labor—these points are not at odds (“The Feminization of Carework”). As I noted in the
previous chapter, the structural devaluation of this labor is rationalized and normalized through
moralized notions of care as private, natural, and instinctual. These ideologies of care cast a long
shadow in dominant moral imaginaries. The intimate and nurturing dimensions of care—which
largely map onto the modes of other-directedness, empathy, and caring attention valued by care
ethicists—-are both exploited and sentimentalized as a ‘labor of love’ in specifically
intersectional ways.
These deskilled skills of care involve deep and nuanced forms of emotional and bodily
intimacy, and some of the most painful and insidious forms of coercion and exploitation faced by
multiply marginalized caregivers (as well as underserved recipients of care) occur at these
intimate registers. As Arlie Hochschild famously elaborates in her study of flight attendants,
such emotional labor can impact the selfhood and inner experience of those performing it: over
time, the ‘deep acting’ involved in maintaining an eternally caring and attentive disposition can
blur the boundaries between one’s own desires and feelings and the demands of the job (89-90).
At the same time, the most exploited care workers are often isolated, dislocated from community
sometimes by entire continents and for decades on end, and/or lack the protections of even the
most basic labor laws (Parreñas 19-20). These are conditions highly conducive to abuse,
91
coercion and particularly insidious forms of emotional and physical manipulation and
exploitation (17).
Not only the ‘dirty work’ of care, but also many of its deepest—and most moralized—
intimacies are systemically relegated to the most marginalized people in society, predominantly
women of color. This presents urgent political and ethical questions. It is obviously right to value
and uplift the incredibly nuanced and intensive skills of care, especially since they are
systemically deskilled and devalued in racist and misogynistic ways. However, insofar as caring
relations are so thoroughly shaped by interlocking and enmeshed oppressions, we must also
contend with the structural and intimate violence of care, the relentless moralisms that ultimately
justify this violence, and the effects of both on the lived experiences of caregivers and recipients.
Care is political in its differential allocation along multiple and intersecting axes of
oppression, and in the intimate coercions and moralizing ideologies at play in who gives and
receives care. Just as crucially though, care is political in that transformative practices of care
play a vital role in how marginalized communities sustain themselves under these conditions,
mobilize forms of resistance against them, and nurture possibilities of living otherwise.
Abstracting care from its contradictory realities also limits our perspectives on these
positive, generative forms of caring politics. I want to be clear that I mean this in a political, not
moral, sense: romanticizing the role of care in people’s struggles to survive brutal forms of
oppression risks re-instantiating the contradiction. By the ‘positive’ and transformative role of
care I thus refer to how the very people systemically denied care or coerced into caring labor
have often cultivated historically specific, often collective, skills and sensibilities that support the
spiritual and physical survival of their communities and even forge alternative possibilities for
living, in however marginal and threatened ways, beyond oppressive logics. Just as we cannot
92
ignore the violence of care, we cannot practice radical care or honor its histories without also
considering the way that people’s practices of care exceed and counteract this violence.
Angela Davis’s seminal “Reflections on the Black Woman’s Role in the Community of
Slaves” provides a powerful example of the historical role of insurgent caring and social
reproductive work in the life and struggles of oppressed peoples. Highlighting the centrality of
Black women’s reproductive labor to the survival, resistance, and marronage of enslaved Black
people in the US, Davis points to how, in the face of American slavery’s intensive and focused
violence against the family life and kinship structures of Black people, Black women performed
the necessary, and deeply political, work of nurturing constantly threatened and violated intimate
and community bonds. The domestic life of enslaved people was terrorized by constant threats of
violence, but it was the only domain with any degree of material and physical separation from
the enslaver, and so formed a key location for resistance to take root. As Hortense Spillers also
notes, the brutal leveling of enslaved men and women subjected to forced labor put Black
women in a very different position to reproductive labor and its gendering. Combined with the
relative autonomy of the domestic sphere, this placed Black women in a unique political
position, which they utilized to foster forms of refuge and indeed insurgency. “As the center of
domestic life, the only life at all removed from the arena of exploitation, and thus as an important
source of survival, the black woman could play a pivotal role in nurturing the thrust towards
freedom” (96). Black women mobilized their reproductive labor—labor that was exploited and
violated in the most barbaric ways by the institution of slavery—to shape and engender forms of
harbor and resistance that ultimately abolished it.
Black women have maintained continuous lineages of resistant and insurgent care and
alternative kinship at community, individual and movement levels, which have played an
93
instrumental role in sustaining and developing Black liberation struggles. Their practices of care
are crucial survival strategies, but as Hazel Carby points out, they should not be seen as “simple
adaptive mechanisms.” Rather, they are a crucial fount of autonomous “cultures of resistance”
that “can lead to new forms of struggle, new goals” (“White Women Listen 52). As Lorde points
out in her polemic at The Second Sex conference, the “mutuality between women… systems of
shared support” and “interdependence” she had experienced and taken part in as a Black lesbian
formed a critical alternative to the “patriarchal model of nurturance” (111) which construes care
and community as a burden rather than as a condition of liberation and themselves liberatory
(112). In “Homeplace: A Site of Resistance” bell hooks celebrates the spaces of refuge, dignity,
and freedom that Black women cultivated in homes, schools, and other centers of Black cultural
life even as they navigated racist oppression and poverty. She claims that “contemporary black
struggle must honor this history of services just as it must critique the sexist definition of service
as women’s “natural” role (383-384). Like Lorde and Carby, she contends that the domestic
spaces that Black women cultivated can in no way be reduced to a sexist division of labor or
contained by a white supremacist normative and social order. Rather, the “construction of a
homeplace, however fragile and tenuous… has a radical political dimension:” passing on a
“sense of shared history” and sustaining a “community of resistance” at multiple levels,
including globally (384). “Failure to recognize the realm of choice, and the remarkable revisioning of both woman’s role and the idea of “home” that black women consciously exercised
in practice obscures the political commitment to racial uplift, to eradicating racism, which was
the philosophical core of dedication to community and home” (384-385).
Homeplace, hooks contends, is a historically rooted and self-consciously political space
that redefines gendered norms of care, enabling Black communities to “gain lost perspective
94
[and] give life new meaning” (389). Black women have practiced radical care in more
traditionally political spheres as well. And they have been instrumental in forming the alternative
movement practices whose contemporary legacies include the politics of care that Deva Woodly
places at the heart of the political philosophy guiding the Movement for Black Lives. The
revolutionary legacy of transformative justice is another example of radical care, elaborating
elaborated political strategy and practices of community accountability for addressing sexual and
domestic violence outside the state.68 Healing justice, a Southern Black tradition devoted to
“building long-term infrastructure for collective care and safety for our people outside carceral
strategies” (Healing Justice Lineages 7) also consciously roots itself in a long history of struggle.
In the introduction to their recent edited volume on the topic, Cara Paige and Erica Woodland
imagine healing justice as “a call and response to [their] ancestors who survived colonialism,
slavery, and attempted genocide, healed, and transmitted a radical legacy for collective care and
safety” (1).
These are only a few well known and contemporary examples. And of course, other
communities enduring long-term oppression have developed their own lineages of radical care
praxis. These legacies of freedom and struggle, like the forms of oppression they resist, are
obscured when we conceive of care as an unambiguous moral good rooted in naturalized
practices and dispositions. Indeed, the legacies of violence and liberation carried on through
relations and practices of care reveal that these dispositions and norms are themselves contested
sites of struggle, and of ethical and political transformation.
III. Engrossment and Empathy: Contradictory Manifestations of Care
68
I discuss the tradition of transformative justice at more length in my Conclusion.
95
As Davis and Nakano Glenn elucidate, historically unique forms of both oppression and agency
have shaped economies of care in ways that are irreducible to hegemonic, single axis
understandings of power and resistance. With the intersectionality of care now in view, my aim
in this section is to make good on my promise, made in the previous chapter, to elaborate on how
caring attention itself can be shaped by violence—and thus how it can and does involve harmful
patterns of fantasy and projection. I frame this discussion through a critique of engrossment and
empathy, arguing that these apparently unproblematic orientations toward ethical caring also
point to how ‘old blueprints of expectation and response’ can equally shape our dispositions
towards others and their needs.
The intersectional violence present in societal divisions of caring labor produces
contradictions at the heart of care. This is perhaps most immediately present in the cruel fact that
the burden of caring for a broken society is often borne by those most oppressed by it. Garza
relates the impact of this societal expectation: “As Black women, we are expected to take care of
people, and the racialized patriarchy demands that we care for you before we care for ourselves”
(294). In Lorde’s sense, this is a racist and sexist pattern of expectation, and expected response.
As I argued above, ethically centering care requires politically addressing the roots of such
patterns and how to change them, not only structurally, but in habits of attention and response
through which care is given and received. However, in pointing to these relational patterns, I
want to avoid a deterministic and reductionist approach: people react to, embody, and resist
oppressive relations in complex, nuanced, and situated ways. Indeed, my claim is that insofar as
they are shaped by both structural violence and people’s individual and collective agency, these
relational dispositions are a crucial location of political struggle.
96
bell hooks’s famous concept of ‘eating the other’ offers an example of how forms of
relational identification can take the shape of social inequalities. To eat the other is to obfuscate
difference, in the mind of the dominant group, by rendering it a fetish or fantasy. With this
concept, hooks interrogates how white Americans’ unexamined desire to identify with people of
color and their cultures can re-inscribe racist dynamics. Importantly, hooks is an avowed
multiculturalist, and believes that cross-cultural dialogue is a necessary component of radical
social change. But this remains “an unrealized political possibility” (367) insofar as the
commodification and pleasurable consumption of racialized otherness in mainstream
‘multiculturalism’ both mystifies and perpetuates the erasures and complicities of racial
capitalism. For hooks, true relation across racial differences depends upon recognizing structural
conditions of racism: only the “[m]utual recognition of racism, its impact both on those who are
dominated and those who dominate… makes possible an encounter between races that is not
based on denial and fantasy. For it is the ever present reality of racist domination, of white
supremacy, that renders problematic the desire of white people to have contact with the Other”
(371). Crucially, this extractive consumption is “… projected as a force that can disrupt and
subvert the will to dominate” (370, my emphasis).
Eating the other is a form of projective identification, a destructive and one-sided fantasy,
that, despite intentions to the contrary, further engrains and mystifies patterns of dominance. It
can thus be conceived as an instance of another famous concept: that of arrogant perception,69
69
In Frye’s conception, arrogant perception is a deep structure of the male gaze, the subtle and coercive ways its
domination uses and exploits its female others. This perception is often presented as loving attention: hence the
centrality of a kind of cognitive empathy to emotional abuse and coercive control. In Maria Lugones’s treatment, it
continues to be a violent displacement that narcissistically re-centers the self in its ostensive relations to others, this
time reinstating the primacy and domination of the white and colonial gaze, particularly in feminist relations. While
she has a complex relation to intersectional theorizing, Lugones illuminates how structures of attention and relation
reproduce intersectional violence in feminist spaces. She critiques white US feminists for the ‘boomerang’
perception (Spelman) by which they (we) are so apt at re-centering themselves and their needs and arrogantly
97
what Maryln Frye terms the “arrogation of someone else’s substance for one’s own projects”
(145). Arrogant perception describes the phenomenological shaping of perception by entitlement
and domination. Perception is key here: as theorized by Frye and Lugones, arrogant perception is
a deep structure of the male, white, and colonial gaze. It justifies and normalizes the use of one
person by another, yet it often operates unconsciously and in fiercely defensive ways: selfdeception and mystification lie at its heart. In her application of the concept to white feminist
academics’ fraught attempts to relate to women of color, Mariana Ortega illustrates this selfobfuscating duplicity of the arrogant perceiver. What Ortega terms the ‘loving knowing
ignorance’ of white feminists is precisely compatible with good intent: the loving feminist
desires knowledge of and relationship with women of color, “while at the same time using
women of color to [her] own ends” (61).
Caring dispositions themselves take on such contours of power, often in unconscious and
deeply embodied, affective, ways. It is a telling feature of contemporary Western societies that
the entitled use of another so often presents itself as appreciation or even care. Equally if not
more troubling is what Garza points out in the passage sited above: the fact that—in some
inverse relation—the most intensely embodied and affective elements of caring attention are
routinely expected from those who are most oppressed in these societies. The assumption,
whether latent or manifest, that marginalized people will not only attend to but anticipate the
needs of those more privileged can differentially shape people’s caring sensibilities—the
embodied and affective dispositions through which people become extremely attuned to others’
needs, or the equally embodied entitlements through which they become insensible to the needs
of others, and the disproportionate care they receive. Caregiving under coercive or abusive terms
perceiving women of color in feminist theory and organizing spaces, avoiding the learning and humbling necessary
to notice women of color in their differences as well as racist parts of themselves (Lugones 181-185).
98
can hijack one’s nervous system, heightening one’s sensitivity to fickle and/or potentially
dangerous others, while continually having one’s needs anticipated and catered to can dull
capacities for attuned and mutual relating and render one’s attempts at caregiving prone to the
sorts of projective distortions at play in eating the other. Persistent denials of care too can shape a
person’s embodied responses to others and strategies for meeting needs. Though always
negotiated in singular and complex ways, such imbalances in caring relations are axial, indeed
normative, to the functioning of the social order.
The skills and dispositional attitudes—the embodied patterns of expectation and
response—at play in caring relations (including, importantly, the forms of dissimulation and
subterfuge oppressed people often utilize when interfacing with oppressor groups) involve
complex adaptations to, and subversions of, dynamic interplays of power. This is not an additive
calculus, but a general observation about how social inequalities can operate in people’s lives
and shape their lived experiences, and the ways people adapt to and/or resist these imbalances of
power. To draw out the implications of this observation for the ethics and politics of care, I now
turn to a critical interrogation of what Nel Noddings and Michael Slote term the “engrossment”
of ethical care. I dwell on this concept because it phenomenologically fleshes out the notion of
caring attention that I discussed in the last chapter. As such, it illustrates the dangers of
naturalizing, universalizing, and uncritically valuing caring dispositions that are, rather, shaped
at the intersections of multiple forms of oppression, and strategies of resistance against them.
In her original formulation of the concept, Noddings conceives of engrossment as an
attitude of caring presence defined by a motivational displacement of one’s self onto another.
“Caring involves stepping out of one's own personal frame of reference into the other's. When
we care, we consider the other's point of view, his objective needs, and what he expects of us.
99
Our attention, our mental engrossment is on the cared-for, not on ourselves” (Caring 24). As
with her notion of the ethical ideal of care, the motivational attitude of engrossment is contextspecific and responsive to particular others. Nevertheless, for Noddings, engrossment is an
essential component of care: “At bottom, all caring involves engrossment” (17).70
Slote develops this concept in his theory of empathy as a criterion of moral judgment. For
Slote, empathic caring for others, based on intuitive moral distinctions, constitutes a general
criterion of right and wrong: actions are wrong insofar as they demonstrate a deficiency of such
caring attention. As discussed above, Slote claims that this criterion of empathy is sufficient not
only to unify care ethical claims, but also to warrant care ethics as a superior and encompassing
model for moral decision making, which can replace liberal justice models of rational choice
making individuals. For Slote, engrossment is an essential component of empathic identification
and thus of his encompassing moral and political theory. Discussing his adaptation of the
concept from the work of Noddings (who, as he points out, wants to distinguish the activity of
empathy with the passivity of engrossment), Slote defines engrossment as follows: “Noddings
says that caring involves a ‘displacement’ of ordinary self-interest into unselfish concern for
another person, and in Caring she also holds that someone who cares for another not only
focuses on a particular individual, but is engrossed in that other person” (12).
Both Noddings and Slote understand engrossment to be an essential component of care
and elaborate it as a way of phenomenologically deepening care ethical accounts of caring
attention, thus enriching what it means to ethically enact and morally teach care. Engrossment is
70
While Noddings points to the need for what she terms empathic accuracy (205), she erases this as a problem
through recourse to normative ideals of care and maternal caregiving. She states: “…I have put great emphasis on
attention. The capacity for attention grows along with the ethical ideal. As we are cared-for and learn to care for
others, we become more and more capable of asking the question, What are you going through?, and, through the
answers to that question, of constructing an accurate picture of what the other feels.” We will recall that Noddings’s
ethical ideal is grounded in one’s situated experience of ‘natural’ caring.
100
a component of natural or intuitive caring, but as a situated skill it can be deepened and
elaborated (for Noddings, in relation to the ethical ideal). I agree that such empathic skill
building is utterly indispensable to caring ethics and politics: indeed, my entire argument rests on
this assumption that caring skills can be learned and transformed. Ethical and political education
to care plays a vital role in countering oppression and teaching caring skills to those who have
never had to learn them is a crucial component of uprooting the injustices of racism and
misogyny. However, such education does not occur in a vacuum: questions of who develops
capacities for engrossment, and how these skills are expressed, are socially and culturally
inflected in ways that Noddings and Slote, with their unequivocal valuation of this naturalized
epistemology, cannot account for. For some, the skills of attunement and other directedness are
hyper-developed as a means of survival, and violently extracted and exploited. Many caregivers
also utilize these honed capacities to navigate power dynamics, or even render themselves
inscrutable to the oppressor’s gaze. Others are much less practiced in engrossment in the sense of
genuine attunement to the needs of others—and yet they may very well think they are or be
perceived as such by others: even utilizing skills of cognitive empathy in abusive and
manipulative ways.
I imagine that something like engrossment—in the sense of attunement and attentiveness
to the needs of concrete human others—is a fundamental component of caring attention. But this
‘is’ does not immediately imply an ‘ought.’ The intimacies of engrossment are themselves
socially and historically inflected and thus fraught with dynamics of power—the self-deception
and mystification at the heart of arrogant perception, for example, render transparency and
mutuality in caring relations exceedingly difficult. Indeed, the very notion that displacing one’s
self onto another can be conceived as straightforwardly good presupposes that such caring occurs
101
under conditions in which equal, freely entered relations between consenting and autonomous
individuals are normative and socially given.71 In other words, even though the theory of
engrossment is explicitly non-contractarian (Caring 150), conceiving of engrossed caring as a
moral ideal implicitly relies on liberal assumptions about selfhood, agency, and a freely entered
social contract. I.e., felicitous engrossment with another seems conditional on the possibility of
transparent access to their needs and one’s own intentions and thus presupposes a baseline of
social equality, autonomous agency, and good will.
Conceiving of engrossment as an ethical good—avoiding what we might term the
transference problem of engrossment—requires something like the ideal theoretical abstractions
undergirding social contract theory. This of course runs counter to the foundational assumptions
of the care ethical tradition regarding the ontological and ethical priority of (inter)dependency
and resultant critiques of liberal notions of voluntary association, contract equality and individual
autonomy.
The assumption that motivational attitude like engrossment can form a model for ethical
care sidesteps complex psychosocial realities like intergenerational trauma and structural
violence, and the genuine ethical and political problems they pose. Trauma theorists for example
maintain that even relatively minor pattens of neglect, abuse, mis-attunement, and projection on
the part of our caretakers in early childhood can play a formative role in the styles of attachment
we bring to our relationships for the rest of our lives (Mate, Vanderkolk). The problem deepens
when we bring structural violence into view. It is perhaps not surprising that many Holocaust
survivors displayed significant signs of trauma, but the fact that these effects were found to be
71
Many care ethicists, including Kittay, take dependency to be the guiding imperative of care. However, as I discuss
below, her understanding of transparency, even as a regulative ideal, is grounded in the notion of care as a
transparent moral good—which implicitly relies on the notions of liberal equality and contract that she explicitly
critiques.
102
also present in their children is a problem of deep moral and political import (Dashort et. al.).
This and other studies suggest that the effects of acute and ongoing historical trauma and
oppression linger in the neurophysiology of trauma survivors and their descendants in ways that
scientific inquiry is only barely beginning to recognize and understand.72 Findings in
neuroscience and epigenetics point to the physiological dimensions of this intergenerational
transmission of trauma, but other, more socially-rooted, thinkers as diverse as transformative
justice practitioners, medical doctors, and relational psychoanalysts point to how patterns of
traumatic response are also relationally transmitted by traumatized caregivers. For example,
renowned trauma theorist and MD Gabor Mate relates the impact of his mother’s narrow escape
from Nazi persecution during his infancy on his own attachment styles and struggles with
addiction and ADHD. One wonders how this history might continue to impact the descendants of
those who perpetrated this violence as well.
For Noddings and Slote, engrossment phenomenologically describes some of the deepest
intimacies of care. But far from ahistorical goods, these intimacies can also constitute the nexus
through which historical trauma is transmitted or coercive exploitation is reproduced.73
72
See for example the recent outpouring of work on the ‘weathering’ impacts of racism on Black women’s
pregnancy outcomes.
73
As I discussed above, these factors, combined with live-in employment and the intensive emotional and embodied
nature of the work itself, puts migrant care workers at particular risk of abuse, coercion, dislocation, and isolation.
The documentary Chain of Love presents an intimate picture of the coercion and harm inflicted through what have
come to be called international care chains. In one portrait, the filmmakers feature a live-in Filipina au pair and her
white, upper middle class, Dutch employer, whose doctor husband is notably out of the picture. The interviews
quickly reveal the au pair to be a deeply engrossed, attuned carer. According to her employer, she is skilled at
displacing her attention onto the needs of the family: she cares for the four small children as if they were her own
and can be trusted with the most intimate dimensions of household reproduction. But, as the Dutch woman goes on
to explain, the excellence of her care goes deeper than this. The au pair is an adept carer because she knows to stay
out of family affairs; she cooks the dinner but does not ask or expect to be part of the sociality of eating it. In other
words, in the eyes of her employer, the au pair is a good carer because she disappears behind her engrossment. Her
capacities for attunement and other directedness are ostensibly what make her an idealized, model, carer. But her
skills are only valued in theory: in practice they are deeply exploited and extracted. Not only does she take on the
deeply personal, deeply emotional, and embodied labor of working for another person’s family, in isolation, and
dislocated from her own, the au pair is expected to reduce her relational interactions to this care. This intimate and
extraordinarily exploited labor is the source of the “freedom” and “flexibility” of her employer, who, it should be
noted, thinks this is simply a great arrangement for both of them.
103
Abstracting caring capacities from these social and historical conditions becomes even more
troubling when we bring questions of ideology and mystification back into view, and consider
how dynamics such as those that hooks names with her concept of eating the other so often do
involve powerful forces of fantasy and projection that cover over deep histories of erasure,
extraction, exploitation. Engrossed caring can nurture and morally educate, but it can equally be
coerced and coercive. From within the intimate experiences of care, it can be hard to know the
difference.
Structural violence impacts people’s lived experiences, intimate relations, and
dispositional attunements to the world and others in ways that are not always apparent, especially
to those in positions of power and privilege. This non-transparency of care poses deep political
and ethical problems that can rarely be solved through individual intention alone. To illustrate
this point, I want to turn to a historical critique of empathy presented by Saidiya Hartman. The
example I discuss comes from her Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery and Self-Making in
Nineteenth Century America, a text which charts, in stark and intimate detail, the “quotidian”
terror that was routinized in daily life during this era of slavery and its immediate aftermath. Her
examination of these routine cruelties, and the processes through which they were normalized,
sheds unwavering light on the disavowed connections between liberal ideals of freedom and
consent and the realities of subjugation and coercion—bringing attention to the impact of white
supremacist violence not only on the public life and institutional practice of this culture, but on
private experiences of selfhood and relation.
Hartman’s critical gaze lands on the troubling ambiguities of white empathy during this
time, which she illustrates through a discussion of the Letters on American Slavery composed by
white abolitionist John Rankin. She questions the purpose and “complicated, unsettling and
104
disturbing” effect of a particular instance, where Rankin describes an imaginative identification
with the position of an enslaved person, writing himself and his family into a fantasy of
enslavement in an attempt to illustrate its moral harms. For Hartman, the “difficulty and
slipperiness” of Rankin’s empathy, his “projection of self onto another in order to better
understand the other… confounds Rankin’s efforts to identify with the enslaved because in
making the slave’s suffering his own, Rankin begins to feel for himself rather than for those
whom this exercise in imagination presumably is designed to reach” (Scenes of Subjection 1718).
Importantly, Rankin’s exercise was an attempt to mobilize empathy as a tool of
abolitionist political and moral education. His aim was to elicit care for the plight of enslaved
people, first from his slave owning brother to whom his letters were addressed, and then, with
their publication, from white Americans more broadly. But Hartman reveals how this endeavor
was “complicated… by the fact that it cannot be extricated from the economy of chattel slavery
with which it is at odds” (21). Rankin’s “facile intimacy” belies his display of solidarity, for it
also reenacts the erasure and complicity his sentiments were intended to mitigate. His gesture
fails to relate to the other as other, or bear witness to their pain. Even if that was his intent, his
care remains thick with the institutionalized violence he was attempting to use it to dismantle.
Despite his abolitionist intentions, his empathy retained the relational contours of the white
supremacy he dedicated his life to overcoming. In this sense, Rankin’s display of empathy was a
contradictory manifestation of care.
Hartman’s discussion of Rankin has more than historical relevance. In the context of the
above discussion, it demonstrates the dangers of positively valuing apparently natural attitudes of
care and provides a stark example of how emotional patterns of caring attention and response—
105
especially on the part of those in the position of oppressor—can reproduce deeply harmful
dynamics, even in attempts at repair. However, elsewhere Hartman makes clear that her
penetrating critique of the relational imprints of violence is ultimately in service of those whose
autonomous, insurgent, intimacies and desires were, and are, irreducible to it. This is most
evident in her discussion of Black women’s “coerced and freely given” care, which she locates at
the center (“the belly”) of the world (“The Belly of the World” 171). She notes that what Black
women were forced to endure as caretakers of their enslavers and oppressors exceeds available
political categories. Yet so do the freedoms they cultivated and harbored—the alternative
economies of nurturance, intimate imaginaries, and ways of living otherwise they made possible
with their “brilliant and formidable labor of care.” Most crucially, these “forms of care, intimacy,
and sustenance exploited by racial capitalism… are not reducible to or exhausted by it” (171).
The quality of Hartman’s caring attention itself reveals something profound about the
transformations at stake in learning to care in radical ways, and what this might ask of us and our
living. She has spent years in the archive and on the streets, following vanishing yet indelible
traces of the intimate lives and desires of individuals who the historical record only represents
through the violence done to them. The historical counter-narrative that she weaves is itself a
“beautiful experiment” in caring otherwise. In her attention to the vast unknowns of their living,
she hones new ethical and political sensibilities perhaps capable of meeting these others at the
limits of knowing and touching possibilities of their living which have not yet found a home in
this world. It seems, in reading her work, that she feels these histories and people, accompanies
them, and brings them into the circle of her care, while also letting them shape what that care is
and can be.
106
Capacities for caring attention cannot be taken for granted or presupposed in societies
riven by violence. Prentis Hemphill, “a leading practitioner of somatics and healing justice” in
the Movement for Black Lives, defines oppression as “the requirement that you hold another’s
center at the cost of your own” (Cited in Woodly, 49). In the tradition of politicized somatics
Hemphill is drawing upon, one’s center refers to their ability to stay present, open, and in
relation to others and the world (Haines). Care becomes oppressive when some peoples’ ability
to feel safe and held in the world comes at the expense of others’ ability to do so. For somatics
practitioners, such inequality inevitably affects the embodied shape and emotional range of those
in such a relation. And yet, from a somatic perspective, shapes change and emotions can be held,
expanded, and made more conscious. We can learn capacities for care and transform our ways of
being in relation and community.
IV. The Ethics of Care in Political Context
The care we give and receive literally shapes us: our ability to have and hold boundaries, our
understandings of where we end and the other begins, our somatic and emotional regulation or
lack thereof, our capacity to know what we desire and reach for it. And yet, this social fabric is
interwoven with intersectional violence. While necessary to robust and transformative political
articulations of care, ethical concepts alone fail to speak to this level of complexity.
In this section I return to several threads from the first two chapters of this dissertation
through a discussion of the ethics and politics of care developed by both Patricia Hill Collins and
Deva Woodly. Collins and Woodly present the ethics of care as an integral component of
intersectional political praxis. Viewed in this light, the ethics of care appear more as an emergent
property born of collective knowledge, structural critique, and a politics of lived experience than
a naturalistically rooted value and practice. This discussion will also provide context for the
107
conceptions of intimate politics and embodied ethics I discuss in the next chapters, in
conversation with social reproduction theorists.
Collins discusses the situated and relational nature of both hegemonic and “subjugated”
knowledges. The systemic subordination of Black women and their knowledge validation
processes has meant that not only their experiences, but also their methodological and critical
innovations, have been constitutively excluded from dominant knowledge production. In
ethically responding to intersecting oppressions and centering the experiences of Black women
in validating knowledge claims, her conception of Black feminist thought provides many
examples of what care-knowing looks like in practice. Woodly, in her articulation of the political
philosophy of The Movement for Black Lives (which she terms Radical Black Feminist
Pragmatism, or RBFP) explicitly develops a Black feminist and intersectional ‘margin to center’
ethics, which she defines as “[r]easoning about justice from the evidence of the lived experience
of those at the margins or exterior rather than from an abstract ideal” (Reckoning 50). In
centering the experiences of the most marginalized—both African Americans in the US, as well
as more marginalized members within BLM organizing spaces—this ethic is rooted in the Black
feminist and intersectional assertion that the realities of interlocking oppressions place ethical
demands on knowledge making and political practices. Both understanding and justice require
attention and care to the impact of oppression on those most harmed by it.
Both Woodly and Collins depart from care ethics insofar as they view the epistemic and
ethical value of care to arise not from caring practices or dispositions themselves, but from the
collective and political endeavor of struggling for social justice. In her articulations of
intersectionality as a critical social theory, Collins centers the experience of Black women and
develops political praxis, knowledge, and ethics from a Black feminist standpoint, or empowered
108
and collective self-definition. For Collins, these epistemic, ethical, and political concerns are
inseparable: she claims that Black feminist thought is a political achievement grounded in
legacies of struggle and intellectual labor (what she terms a dialectic of activism and thinking) by
Black women intellectuals. In a paradigmatic example, Collins thus opposes Black feminist
thought to positivism as a way of validating knowledge. In asking, simply, “is it objectively true
or false?” positivist methods of validating truth distance the subject and object of knowledge,
separate emotions from research, preclude statements of value or ethics, and privilege individual
winners of adversarial debate (Black Feminist Thought 255). Such an approach to knowledge
validation is inadequate to the task of understanding intersecting oppressions or engaging in
struggles against them. The complex lived realities of oppression cannot simply be quantified,
isolated from experience, disinterestedly analyzed, or captured through victories of competitive
argument.
By critically opposing such “objective generalizations” (255), Collins claims that “the
existence of a self-defined Black women’s standpoint using Black feminist epistemology calls
into question the content of what currently passes as truth and simultaneously challenges the
process of arriving at that truth” (271). In contradiction to positivist, and other “eurocentric”
methods of validating knowledge, Black feminist epistemology articulates the following criteria
of knowledge, rooted in the lived experience and material reality of Black women (256): 1.
Lived experience as a criterion of meaning; 2. The use of dialogue; 3. The ethics of caring and 4.
The ethic of personal accountability. Together, these standards elaborate the nature of the
dialectic of thought and engaged, collective practice so central to her thinking.
Collins claims that, particularly for people confronting oppression, lived experience
matters: it is the “cutting edge” dividing abstract knowing from wisdom (257). Like Crenshaw,
109
Collins invokes Sojourner Truth’s truth claims as an example of the power of lived experience as
a criterion of meaning: “By invoking examples from her own life to symbolize new meanings,
Truth deconstructed the prevailing notions of woman” (258). Moreover, this criterion of meaning
helps to elaborate the relational connections—the shared experiences as well as differences—
between Black women. The use of dialogue, the second component of Black feminist epistemic
method, is thus connected to the first. This emphasis on dialogue has roots in African and
African American oral traditions and spiritual, political, and linguistic practices that presuppose
and serve to elaborate relationships between a hearer and a speaker as an essential condition of
meaning (260-62). These two features of Black feminist epistemology in particular help to
illuminate a collective perspective on truth.74 Articulating experiences and dialogic methods
from a Black feminist standpoint offers points of contact with other partial, situated forms of
knowledge: such coalitions together allow for a more total, and more subtle, image of what is
and what can be.
Crucially for my argument here, Collins presents the ethics of care, as well as an ethic of
personal accountability, as the remaining constitutive features of Black feminist epistemology. In
the ethics of both care and personal accountability “Neither emotion nor ethics is subordinated to
reason. Instead, emotion, ethics and reason are used as interconnected, essential components in
assessing knowledge claims” (266). Her understanding of the ethics of care includes an emphasis
on individual uniqueness and expressiveness, the appropriateness of emotions in deliberating
truth and ethical courses of action, and the importance of empathy in the process of
74
For Collins, the situated theory and praxis developed by Black feminists also allows for coalition and a broader
and more articulated perspective on truth: “Although it is tempting to claim that Black women are more oppressed
than everyone else and therefore have the best standpoint from which to understand the mechanisms, processes, and
effects of oppression, this is not the case. Instead, those ideas that are validated as true by African-American women,
African-American men, Latina lesbians, Asian-American women, Puerto Rican men and other groups with
distinctive standpoints, with each group using the epistemological approaches growing up from its unique
standpoint, become the most “objective” truths” (270).
110
understanding. These largely resonate with the features of care ethics presented by Held and
others: specifically, the focus on the particularity of the other, the role of emotions in ethical
reasoning, and the emphasis on affective ethical education in fostering more responsiveness to
the needs of others. Conversely, the ethic of personal accountability requires that one be
accountable to their own knowledge claims, and that such accountability have bearing on how
we assess the claims of knowers in general. Collins notes that detaching knowledge claims from
such embedded accountability can serve as a tool of oppression by posing human suffering in
cold and quantitative terms, or the claims of interested historical actors in neutral ones. The act
of making knowledge claims, as well as assessing the validity of claims made by others, requires
situating these claims in their social and historical conditions as well as one’s own lived
experience. These latter, ethical, criteria of knowledge work together in that they condition the
validity of truth on its claimants’ capacity to be responsive and responsible to human others and
the concrete conditions of their lives (265-66).
Taken together, these four criteria lead to an alternative conception of knowledge and the
process of attaining it: “In this alternative epistemology, values lie at the heart of the knowledge
validation process such that inquiry always has an ethical aim. Moreover, when these four
dimensions become politicized and attached to a social justice project, they can form a
framework for Black feminist thought and practice” (266). In naming these features of Black
feminist thought, Collins claims that empathy, intuition, responsiveness, accountability, the
recognition of individual uniqueness, and the development of collective wisdom and dialogue are
all inseparable from intersectionality’s ongoing work of forging politicized and collective
knowledge and practice. In other words, rather than deriving the ethics of care from naturalized
caring capacities themselves, the ethics of care form an integral component of Black feminist
111
praxis, resourcing and helping to articulate its stance against oppression and for collective
empowerment.
Woodly is even more explicit about politically situating the ethics of care and provides a
concrete and recent example of the power of, and need for, politicized care in fomenting radical
social transformation. Indeed, she claims that the politics of care is the “most unique aspect” of
the political philosophy of the Movement for Black Lives (M4BL), a philosophy which she
terms Radical Black Feminist Pragmatism (RBFP). This politics is rooted in the movement’s
animating assertion that Black lives matter. Black people are hurting due to systemic racist
oppression, “and that is reason enough to care” (92). Woodly juxtaposes this politics of care to
feminist care ethics in particular: “…for those who adhere to RBFP, care is not only an ethic or a
set of moral principles, it is also a politics.” While “this notion has deep affinity with the
voluminous literature in feminist political theory” it differs from thinkers such as Tronto in that
“people in the movement do not center care because of a commitment to the idea of democracy
or the duty and value of citizenship… but because they matter to themselves and to one another”
(91). For Woodly, the politics of care is not an ethical or political ideal, but an immediate
pragmatic and ethical response to pain.
Ethics play a central role in this political theory—specifically, in what Woodly terms its
intersectional ‘margin to center’ and abolitionist ethics (which I discuss below). RBFP begins
from the Black feminist commitment to “the immanent relevance of people’s lived experience,
centering the experiences of those who are most impacted by systems of domination and
oppression” (89). RBFP’s radical methodological and political approaches stem from this
112
commitment to lived experience, which, she emphasizes, “is a key tenet of the Black feminist
intellectual tradition and has always animated the movement” (69).75
Woodly and Collins view the epistemic and ethical features of care to be inseparable
components of responding to people’s concrete, situated, needs, and view this endeavor to be
guided by and rooted in a political ethos and commitment to social justice. “A politics of care”
does not begin from the universal ethical relevance of care or an affirmation of its general
epistemic features but is generated as a response to a historical need: it “requires us to consider
what harms society ought to account for and how we should reckon with the need for reparation”
(Reckoning 88).
For Woodly, “RBFP and its most unique element, the politics of care, demands that we
attend to the conditions preventing flourishing in people’s lived experience” (207). This demand
does not stem from a commitment to abstract principles—including care itself—but arises
inductively, in a situated manner, as a response to people’s pain. At the same time, the
movement’s commitment to care has generated a profoundly visionary, yet deeply practical,
political imagination. It has put racial reckoning at the forefront of American life where it
belongs, and brought perspectives such as police and prison abolition, politicized healing, and
community care into the public domain in ways that were unthinkable before the revolutionary
uprisings in response to the police murders of George Floyd and Brionna Taylor. Moreover, the
movement models these radical changes, presenting them in their full complexity, yet also
imbuing them with a sense of joy and purpose that renders them both actionable and irresistible.
75
Woodly cites Brittney Cooper: “Black women’s knowledge production has always been motivated by a sense of
care for Black communities in a world where non- Black people did not find value in the lives and livelihoods of
these communities” (Cooper cited in Woodly, 69).
113
Woodly outlines six values that underlie the politics of care articulated by the M4BL:
oppression as social trauma, interdependence, accountability, unapologetic Blackness, a defense
of Black joy, and abolition, restoration, and repair. Rather than presupposing a naturalistic or
universal conception of care’s value, these values offer a critical lens on the systemic devaluation
of Black lives in a white supremacist culture—and are also transformative in that they help orient
collective action and inspire movement participants to live in accordance with their aspirations
for justice and liberation. In both senses, Woodly claims that a commitment to healing justice
informs and motivates these disparate values.76
The first value—that of oppression as social trauma—stems from a fundamental
assumption of healing justice, which conceives of trauma as social. Trauma is an inevitable result
of oppression: addressing it thus requires a collective and political approach to healing, and a
healing approach to movement politics.77 Finding ways to collectively navigate the
intergenerational, social, and personal complexities of this trauma is a component piece of the
culture building and ongoing “experimentation…constitutive of the movement philosophy” (98).
This politics of care has both critical and positive valences: oppression is political in its
traumatic effects on marginalized groups, and in that healing from this trauma requires fostering
interdependency in communities of struggle. This focus on interdependency as a value rests on a
critique of the liberal individual as the primary social actor, and draws from disability justice
accounts of “human beings as embodied and social” (101). Viewed through the lens of
76
Healing justice is a radical modality and political orientation to healing that has fundamentally informed the
politics developed by BLM. It has connections to Black Southern healing traditions such as midwifery and
herbalism, as well as traditions of disability justice, transformative justice, and politicized somatics.
77
Citing Iris Marion Young, Woodly claims that “[o]ppression’s harm includes but goes well beyond the unfair
distribution of rights and wealth.” Its deep effects “keep people from becoming who they might be if not so
constrained, because oppression limits people’s ability to increase their capabilities and expand their capacities
through exploration, education and experiences” (95).
114
interdependency, healing from trauma and oppression is incomplete when understood on
individual terms, and the process of organizing itself is conceived as fundamentally healing.
Such collective practices, over time, allow individuals and groups to ‘show up’
differently and be empowered and accountable in relation to each other and to a sense of purpose
and belonging. Organizers consciously practice embodying their commitments, adapting their
shape or ‘posture’ in ways that are responsive to their values and goals, as well as the needs and
expectations of interdependent others with whom they are organizing and building community.
Such shifts are an “incredibly sophisticated and difficult line to walk” (104). They are sustained
through practices that connect people not only to each other in the present, but to legacies of
struggle in the past and radical possibilities for the future—connections which are often
supported by spiritual and ritual practices.
For Woodly, the politics of care are also sustained by forms of unapologetic Blackness,
as well as refusal and animating joy. Unapologetic refusal of respectability politics—refusing to
change one’s shape to fit and accommodate or gain acceptance in the eyes of the oppressor
culture (107-108). And the joy and pleasure that she claims results from belonging in a web of
interdependent relationships and feeling capable of radically altering the conditions of one’s
existence. In this sense, collective and politicized emotional expression—of joy, and also grief
and rage—becomes an integral and empowering component of the politics of care which
empowers and nurtures the movement (111-115).
The final value underlying the politics of care is an abolitionist ethics. “For people in
movement, abolition is, at bottom, a politics of care. This is because, though contemporary
abolitionists believe in the ultimate elimination of police and prisons, that aspiration is predicated
on creating the material and social conditions in which most people do not harm others” (115).
115
Abolitionist organizers and transformative justice practitioners often point out that nobody enters
violence by causing it: as Mia Mingus puts it: “no one is born knowing how to rape or torture–
these are learned behaviors” (“Transformative Justice”). For Woodly, abolitionism is a politics of
care that pragmatically orients to these conditions under which causing harm would no longer be
an immediate way to deal with pain or meet survival needs. Few abolitionists would claim that
abolition is purely, or even primarily, a negative or destructive endeavor. Rather, it involves what
Angela Davis terms a “transformative process of decarceration:” a “constellation of alternative
strategies and institutions” (Are Prisons Obsolete 107) through which fundamentally oppressive
institutions and social relations are replaced, over time, by just and equitable ones. As I argue
later in this dissertation, this orientation to transformative justice as a component piece of
abolitionist politics involves developing emotional, logistical, and even spiritual resources
through which both survivors and perpetrators of harm can find healing and repair outside of
punitive and carceral logics.
Both Woodly and Collins develop Black feminist forms of care ethics that respond in
specific ways to the needs of African American communities and build upon legacies of Black
liberation and struggle. In her later work however, Collins explicitly poses ethics as an open and
urgent question.78 Yet if ethics are to play a component role in of intersectionality as a critical
social theory, she claims, they will be political and emerge from praxis and social action as a
way of knowing.
78
In response to its current moment of crisis and transition, Collins asks whether and how the ethical commitment to
social justice should be seen to structure intersectionality as a critical social theory. This question is a constitutive
critical horizon for Collins: “Rather than assuming that social justice is implicitly a part of intersectionality, the
question of intersectionality’s ties to social justice constitutes an important and ongoing question for theorizing
intersectionality itself” (Intersectionality 275).
116
Collins’ ambiguous position on ethics can be clarified through her reading of Simone de
Beauvior’s Ethics of Ambiguity itself. She juxtaposes Beauvior’s ethics of freedom to those of
the civil rights organizer Pauli Murray—who was Beauvior’s immediate contemporary and
equally brilliant and precocious, but whose race, class position, and commitment to social
organizing prevented her from reaching a position of parallel public prominence. For Beauvior,
“there is an ethics only if there is a problem to solve” (Ethics of Ambiguity 18). Indeed, as
Collins elaborates, her ethics of ambiguity presents ethics as an ongoing space of a problem, a
continual process of failure and questioning whose only guide comes from the ambiguous claims
of others, the world, and the commitment to freedom itself. However, as opposed to Murray,
whose own ethics of freedom were firmly rooted in concrete social justice projects, Beauvior
fails to fully inhabit this space of ethical questioning and transformation that she herself brings to
light. Rather than “embracing the ambiguity” (and the embrace of ambiguity) she claims is
constitutive of ethics itself, Beauvior’s commitment to abstract, voluntarist, notions of freedom
throw her thinking back into the false dilemmas and contradictions she hoped to sidestep with
her ethics of social action and recognition.79
I wonder whether the ethics of care, too, might be best understood as inhabiting the space
of a problem—as a question who’s call and response are forged in relation to the possibility of
social justice and our ongoing ability to respond (responsibility) even, and especially, in the face
of our inevitable failures. Like Beauvior’s ethics of freedom, an ethics of care conceived through
the lens of given norms is bound to reproduce contradictions. In opposition to this—and in many
79
A passage from her conclusion illustrates Beauvior’s own struggle to stay with, rather than “eliminate” the
ambiguity constitutive of ethics itself: “Is this kind of ethics individualistic? Yes, if one means by that that it accords
to the individual an absolute value and that it recognizes in him alone the power of laying his own existence…. But
it is not solipsistic, since the individual is defined only by his relationship to the world and other individuals; he
exists by transcending himself, and his freedom can be achieved only through the freedom of others” (156).
117
ways building on legacies of Murray and so many others—the intersectional theorists I have
cited in this chapter understand the ethics of care to emerge through both political struggle and
repair: in embracing the ambiguities, freedoms, and failures of learning to care otherwise in a
violent world.
V. Conclusion: New Caring Tools
The devaluation, exploitation, and extraction of the caring labor of marginalized people is not a
pathological deviation from an ideal of good care but an essential and fundamental condition of
the world as it is. This is an impasse that cannot be fully addressed through recourse to abstract
notions of care conceived as prior to or beyond violence, nor are political solutions to this deep
social problem likely to emerge from hegemonic forms of ethics and politics. Hartman, in
particular, brings these violent realities of care into stark and living relief. The cruel coercions
and denials of care at the heart of racial capitalism, which continue to impact the lives of Black
women. And the potential reach of racism into the very caring dispositions and empathic
capacities of white America. Her critique illustrates that we cannot take motivational structures
of care for granted from within ‘worlds of sense’ (Lugones) structured by violence and
oppression. Moral economies of care both reflect and justify the social inequalities manifest in
divisions of caring labor. This is not just an external, structural, fact, but affects our embodied
and affective capacities for care.
It is difficult to forge new caring tools. Confronting the contradictions of care and
developing new caring sensibilities requires intimate and collective learning—learning how to
cultivate new blueprints of expectation and response; to develop new capacities to attune,
discern, respond, and refuse; to unearth hidden histories of care, and to hold, again and again, the
118
devastating ways our communities of care will almost inevitably reproduce the very sorts of
harms they seek to remedy.
And yet, as Weil so powerfully articulates, such transformations in attention and response
lie at the heart of ethical engagement. In this light, we might supplement and clarify Tronto’s
‘how might an ethics of care be possible’ with Woodly’s “what is required for healing justice to
be possible?’ This penetrates to the heart of what matters about care: and what is required if we
are indeed to “maintain, continue, and repair our ‘world’ so that we can live in it as well as
possible” (Moral Boundaries 103). Such reparative and generative forms of care will be found
not in care as a “species activity” but in the material and sensible revolutions, large and small,
that could enable healing and transformative justice to be possible in our social world and
intimate relations.
Tronto insists that care is definitively not a master’s tool (“Ethics of Care” 226). I believe
that it can be—and also a revolutionary one. My argument has been that our ethical practices of
care must adequate themselves to the violent contradictions, as well as the revolutionary
possibilities, of care. This is an inevitably situated and complex affair. To once again recall a
core care ethical insight, we can only know care from the inside. Learning to care radically is not
an abstract ethics but a living and collective ethos: it involves changes that can only be grasped
in living through them. Rather than a set of naturalized dispositions, we can think of emergent
and historical forms of radical care as the development of new sensibilities, forms of awareness
and attention—ways of reaching, to paraphrase Gloria Anzaldúa, through our own wounds and
fractures to connect to others.80
80
“We are all wounded” Anzaldúa states, “but we can connect through the wound that’s alienated us from others.
When the wound forms a cicatrix, the scar can become a bridge linking people split apart” (Light in the Dark 21).
119
Chapter Three:
How Can a Radical Politics of Social Reproduction be Possible?
120
I. Introduction: Contradictions in the Labor of Care
I recently attended a political meeting convoked to address the ongoing, intransigent,
difficulty of organizing around the feminized labors of care. The announcement included the
following lines: “We are interested in the chronic invisibilization, individualization, and
institutionalization of this labor, and our ongoing challenges in communalizing care and
reproduction within our homes, spaces, and movements. Why, after years of pandemic, and
decades of organizing, are our bodies, illnesses, and expectations of a dignified and ethical life so
difficult to address and collectivize around?” The following chapters address such political and
ethical challenges, as well as opportunities, specific to caring and reproductive labor.
Placing care at the center of moral and political life fundamentally alters how we think
about both. Care ethicists, for their part, have radically re-visioned ethics—expanding feminist
claims about the politics of lived experience into ethical life, and offering new visions of
thinking and acting on the basis of care. They also make compelling political arguments for a
more caring society, which were formerly inconceivable within Western discourses of political
theory. At the same time, my argument has been that, by naturalizing historically constituted
dispositions and relations of care—relations which lie at the heart of endemic intersectional
violence—care ethicists run the risk of re-instantiating the liberal assumptions about selfhood,
social life, and moral agency they so thoroughly critique, and thus once again risk overlooking
the very different histories and experiences that condition people’s relationships to care, and
indeed their capacities to give and receive it.
I make an inverse claim about the equally prominent, and crucial, theories of care labor
developed by US and European Marxist feminists81 in recent decades. Unlike many care
81
As Zhivka Valiavicharska and Brian Whitener note, social reproduction feminism has multiple lineages, many of
them not Western or primarily Marxist: “While the idea of social reproduction is most often associated with the
121
ethicists, these feminist and queer theorists offer sustained critiques of the structural inequities at
the root of social organizations and divisions of caring labor. However, their theories are clouded
by a parallel, and equally tenacious, tendency to rely on the economistic and productivist logics
they seek to overcome. This too has led to inadequacies in politically and ethically engaging the
intimacies of violence, struggle, and healing specific to care and social reproduction as such.
While care ethicists fail to address caring politics by reducing care to a naturalized moral good,
Marxist feminist tendencies to reduce politics to labor and class shrouds the living ethical
contradictions and possibilities of care.
Marxist feminist literature from the 1970s, considerable work was done around that concept in a wide range of
rather disparate bodies of work throughout the 1960s and 1970s. In addition to Marxist feminism, social
reproduction became a main focus for Italian autonomists, anti-Stalinist socialist humanists in post-Stalinist Eastern
Europe, ‘anti-humanist’ critics of orthodox Marxism such as Louis Althusser and Michel Foucault, in studies on
slavery, race, and urban development, and in the work of postcolonial and Third-World feminists.
In these bodies of work, social reproduction has acquired a wide array of meanings and has been put to
many different uses. Some take the term to mean the material means of subsistence and survival, both immediate
and infrastructural, from water and food to housing and health care. Others use the concept to underscore
reproduction as a particular kind of labor involved in the regeneration and wellbeing of others, as in domestic, care,
emotional, affective, and sex work, which have historically fallen mostly to women. More recent literature has
focused on the commodification of reproductive labor and the global economies and transnational chains of
domestic, care, and sex work.
In these and other writings, the body has become an important focus: the body as a site of biological
reproduction, the regulation of sexuality, and the reproduction of the gender binary. The reproductive and
reproducible body figures as a kind of resource – a resource for labor but also for producing more bodies and lives,
for workers. It becomes mobilized by population control projects and by medical and administrative technologies of
regulation towards the reproduction of heteronormativity, of racial and class control, and towards social
normalization projects” (“Repression and Resistance”).
Cinzia Arruzza and I historically, socially, and geographically contextualize this concept as follows:
“Social reproduction…is a primary condition of extraction and accumulation under capitalism, and struggles on its
terrains are essential to political resistance against them. Under currently existing conditions, this work of
reproducing life is gendered, racialized, and sexualized as well as deeply inflected by social and political trends in
migration, the movement and ownership of natural resources, environmental decline and environmental racism, the
social construction of ability and disability, state policies and repression, and at the same time, social forms of
organizing care, desire, embodiment, collective and familial relations. Social reproduction spans as well as holds
together these intimate and structural dimensions of life under conditions of crisis, and under conditions of struggle.
The concept of social reproduction emerges from multiple political and theoretical lineages. These include
Workerist Italian feminism, Western European, US and Canadian socialist and Marxist feminisms, autonomous and
indigenous political currents in Latin America, Eastern European and postcolonial considerations of the socialist
transformation of everyday life, and anarchist formations in the US, Europe, and Latin America. More recently,
reflections and analyses centered on social reproduction are deeply influencing the current global tide of
anticapitalist feminist movements, particularly the international feminist strikes movement, which has joined
together countries as diverse as Argentina, Chile, Mexico, Italy, Spain, Switzerland, and Poland. Social reproduction
analyses have in turn been informed by the new feminist movement’s practical experience and political elaboration.”
(“The Politics of Social Reproduction” 2-3).
122
To recall the overall positioning of this dissertation, the feminist philosophies of care that
have emerged over the last 4-5 decades have largely centered on the concepts of ethics and
labor—which the traditions of care ethics and Marxist feminism have developed in distinct, often
divergent, ways. Chapters One and Two have been concerned with elaborating why the
naturalistic/naturalized assumptions of the care ethical paradigm fail to comprehend or address
the contradictory realities of care under conditions of structural violence. Their unambiguous
valorization of care, I have argued, obfuscates the constitutive violence of existing social
structures and norms, its impact on the intimacies of caring relations, and ultimately the ways
that communities mobilize alternative economies and practices of care towards healing and
social change.
I now turn to the labors and relations of care that Marxist feminists have theorized under
the umbrella of social reproduction. Social reproduction refers to the labor, institutions,
networks, infrastructures, etc., through which human life, social bonds, and—crucially for
Marxist feminists—labor powers, are reproduced on a daily and intergenerational basis.
Feminists have long stressed that reproductive labor is basic and fundamental to human life, and
have also stressed the vast array of highly specific tasks it performs and needs it fulfills—
feeding, cleaning, educating, tending, and “maintaining kin and community ties” (Glenn, “From
Servitude” 1). Like moral philosophy’s shocking but perhaps not surprising excision of care from
ethical life, the exclusion of these reproductive labors from political economy is ironic and
telling, as they constitute the center and foundation of the oikos in any meaningful sense of the
word. This labor of reproduction is “indispensable to society” (Fraser, “Crisis of Care?” 21) and
it also involves the entire human bodymind and its capacities: it is manual and material, yes—but
it is often also affective, intellectual, spiritual, erotic, biopolitical, and disciplinary. Capitalist
123
economies are unique in that they systemically deny this work as labor: it is thus often unpaid or
grossly underpaid, is subjected to specifically cruel and coercive forms of exploitation and
extraction, and is socially organized through gendered, racialized, and international divisions of
labor and the normative ideologies that reinforce them. Care is an essential and irreducible
component of this socially necessary, life-sustaining, yet systemically denied and invsibilized,
labor of social reproduction.
The previous chapters have argued that care ethicists have not adequately situated their
ethics vis a vis the contradictory realities of care—the fact that care is already a naturalized ethic
under conditions of structural violence, and thus ought not be unambiguously valorized as a
universally normative good. Marxist feminists, in contrast, have quite clearly articulated certain
structural contradictions shaping political and moral economies of care in such brutal ways.
Capitalist accumulation and dispossession depend on reproductive labors, and at the same time
rely on their gendered and racialized devaluation. As with the life and resources of the earth
itself, it thus functions by stealing these labors, externalizing them as a natural (female, ethnic)
vocation, or compensating them as cheaply as possible—potentially up to the point of its own
systemic collapse.82
However, in a nearly logical reversal of care ethical approaches—which articulate care as
a relational value while abstracting it from its social and material conditions—this materialist
approach evacuates care and reproductive labor of their ethical and political specificity: the
embodied, affectively laden, and intersubjective skills and sensibilities, as well as the
antagonisms and struggles, particular to them. My argument in this chapter is that reducing the
82
I discuss Marxist feminist theories about these structural, social reproductive contradictions and resultant care
crisis at length in the next chapter.
124
politics of social reproduction to the politics of labor, like limiting care to naturalized ethics,
forecloses radical perspectives on the contradictions and possibilities of care.
As Cinzia Arruzza and I show in the introduction to our co-edited Comparative
Literature and Culture special issue on the politics of social reproduction,83 the two lineages of
social reproduction feminism that I engage in this chapter are not as easily disentangled, nor their
positions as divided, as they are often presented (and present themselves) in the literature, and
indeed as I often present them here. Moreover, as Arruzza and I argue, these traditions—if they
can be simplified as such—often compliment84 and offer crucial correctives to each other. As
with care ethics, and indeed more so, I enter these debates from the inside. I am heir to, part of,
and committed to these traditions. I hope this writing contributes to these developments, as well
as to the coalitional and transformational ethos at the heart of both traditions.
In Living a Feminist Life, Sarah Ahmed speaks to the vital, life-changing role of
distinctly feminist ethical imaginaries and political praxes. Feminism is sensational for Ahmed: it
is embodied and lived. Developing sensibilities and skills to name how we have been harmed by
patriarchal violence, how others have been differently harmed, and where our own intersections
locate us on the fraught terrain of feminist movement are all elements of what it means to live in
this question, as is appreciating how patriarchal violence may have robbed us of a sense of
83
As we state there: “While our introduction highlights the multiplicity of methods and experiences presented by
our contributors, we also offer a synthetic perspective on the politics of social reproduction grounded in both mass
struggle and transformative practices of community care in the midst of crisis and possibility” (“Politics of Social
Reproduction” 1).
84
E.g. in their respective strengths and orientations to “mass struggle and transformative practices of community
care” (2) or on “mass struggle and coalition building between labor and reproductive struggle” on the one hand and
“commoning, mutual aid and community care” (5) and “autonomous life-making from below and from the margins”
(5. 2) on the other. These complement each other e.g. in thinking about “the relation between mass movements and
prefigurative practices” or the “mutual articulation of mass struggle and solidarity building on the one hand, and the
emergence of new forms of social association and subjectivities on the other” (5).
125
having a home in the world at all (7). And living a feminist life, for Ahmed, is also about asking
what it means to build new feminist dwellings (1-2).
These political questions of care exceed the moral economy of the liberal individual and
his rational choices, but they also exceed the political-economic “master frame” of class and its
corresponding politics of labor. Indeed, the difficulty of finding language and political forms
appropriate to care speaks to the tenacity of moral and political philosophies that sever ethical
life from social relations and historical context and attenuate the imaginaries of both. But it also
speaks to the intransigence of care’s devaluation—and the depth at which it marks not only our
epistemic frames of reference, but the affective and relational capacities we bring to these urgent
questions.
The task of uprooting care’s systemic devaluation from our material lives and
relationships, as well as from our hearts and our minds, equally demands modes of political
organizing, consciousness raising, ethical education, collective healing. Such (emotional,
sensible, symbolic) transformations reside at what Drucilla Cornell terms the “imaginary
domain” and Raquel Gutiérrez calls the “interior horizon of struggle.” Struggles on the terrain of
social reproduction do, and must, include them. Cultivating such political sensibilities—and the
dwelling places capable of harboring and nourishing them—is certainly possible in class and
labor politics, but such intimate horizons of politicized experience and struggle at the same time
exceed Marxist political imaginaries. Politics, of course, exceed labor and class. While it is
crucial to understand and politically engage with care as labor, this does not entail that the
politics of care should be reduced to the politics of labor.
II. Critical and Methodological Considerations on Social Reproduction
126
Like the discourse of care ethics, the socialist and autonomist theories of social reproduction I
discuss below have become prominent in care theory and offer some of the most detailed and
sustained theories of care to emerge out of Western feminism in the past fifty years. Despite their
differences, thinkers in these respective Marxist feminist traditions share a common concern with
redressing systemic omission of care and reproductive labor from Leftist theory and practice.
Politically valuing and centering this invisibilized material and emotional labor, they argue that
social reproduction is an essential and foundational economic and political reality on which
capital depends and must at the same time disavow.85 Demystifying capitalism’s reliance on
brutally extracted and exploited reproductive labor, they claim, reveals these labors to be the
beating heart of capitalist sociality, and thus also of the social relations and struggles that might
transcend it. In what follows, I largely bracket the economic,86 and focus on the political,
dimensions of these theories of social reproduction.87 That is, I focus on feminist arguments and
organizing strategies that strive to reclaim, center, understand, and reconstitute the material and
social relations, infrastructures, institutions, social forms, formal and informal networks, and
intimate bonds that constitute social reproduction as a fundamental dimension of life-making—
and to understand this as a necessary component and condition of anti-capitalist organizing.
The rich legacies of Marxist feminist social reproduction theory I discuss below have
been developed in conversation with diverse feminist, antiracist, and anti-colonial intellectual
traditions and organizing strategies. While she has long been critical of certain aspects of this
85
“Without it there could be no culture, no economy, no political organization” (Fraser 21).
The economic lens of social reproduction largely focuses on questions of whether reproductive labor itself
produces value. This question, at the heart of the infamous domestic labor debates, is outside the scope of my
expertise. However, I will venture my opinion that current discussions concerning theoretical bone of contention
might fruitfully be couched as a political disagreement between socialist and autonomist politics.
87
For recent work on the economic elements of social reproduction, see for example Veronica Gago and Luci
Cavallero’s notion of feminist economics “that is able to redefine, based on the bodies and territories in conflict,
labor and exploitation, communal and feminized modes of doing and resisting, and popular innovation in moments
of crisis” (Gago and Cavallero 2).
86
127
tradition, Angela Davis, for example, discusses how its insights regarding the reproduction of
intimate, ‘private’ life have deepened understandings of how and why the personal is political.
Connecting this insight to her own abolitionist organizing, she states that “the retributive
impulses of the state are inscribed in our very emotional responses… the political reproduces
itself through the personal. This is a feminist insight—a Marxist-inflected feminist insight…
regarding the reproduction of the relations that enable something like the prison industrial
complex” (Freedom is a Constant Struggle 106). As I discuss below, such solidarities, coalitions,
and cross-pollination—as well as divergencies—have been key to the development of social
reproduction frameworks since their inception, and the future of this tradition depends on
nurturing these coalitional legacies.
Articulating the essential and foundational role of reproductive labor to both capitalistic
social life and anti-capitalist struggles was, and is, a crucial and revolutionary move. At the same
time, I claim that this revolutionary impulse on the part of Western Marxist feminists was, and is,
also hindered by persistent overextensions of class and labor paradigms. As with care ethicists’
tendencies to rely on the kinds of moral abstraction they claim are incompatible with an ethics of
care, the Marxist feminists’ arguments I engage with tend, in the last instance, to reproduce the
productivist and economistic logics they themselves find deeply incompatible with the politics of
social reproduction. This part of my argument is not original. Nor is it intended to dismiss the
power of these arguments.88 My contribution to these debates lies in what I understand to be the
88
To be clear: the labor struggles of reproductive workers like sex- and care workers are essential and must be
supported—not only as an act of working-class solidarity, but because their campaigns exemplify the truly inclusive
and diverse class politics needed for our contemporary moment. But labor and class are not the only perspectives
that those engaged in social reproductive struggles have brought to bear on the political movements and analyses of
our times—migrants, sex workers, domestic laborers, trans people, indigenous people, peasants, disabled people,
and others have brought diverse, often intersectional, lenses to bear on the violence of social reproduction and the
political possibilities unleashed when we collectively reclaim and transform the social and material conditions of our
lives. These perspectives are equally essential when thinking about radical politics and ethics of care in the context
of social reproduction.
128
ethical takeaways of centering the intimate, caring, dimensions of paid and unpaid reproductive
labor—and the implications this has for social reproduction politics.
Drucilla Cornell and Seyla Benhabib pointed to the limits of the labor paradigm when it
comes to feminist, and particularly caring, politics over thirty years ago, noting that, in
expanding Marxist notions of labor to include its reproductive dimensions, Marxist feminists
also ran the risk of reducing the intersubjective life-making activities involved in care and
nurturance to Marxist imaginaries of labor and its emancipation that are inadequate to their
unique ethico-political registers. To quote them at some length:
Whereas orthodox Marxist theory had confined itself to an analysis of productive activity and
production relations, the task of feminists would now be to enlarge these concepts to include
reproductive activities and relations of reproduction. Of course, there were misgivings about the
use of the term "reproduction" in this context, since Marx himself had used it to mean the cyclical
continuity and persistence of production over time. The more fundamental question which could
have been raised however, was omitted: is the concept of production, which is based on the model
of an active subject transforming, making and shaping an object given to it, at all adequate for
comprehending activities like childbearing and rearing, care of the sick and the elderly? Can
nurture, care and the socialization of children be understood in the light of a subject-object model
when they are activities which are so thoroughly intersubjective? The concept of reproduction
does not challenge the primacy of production within Marxism but subsumes typically female
activities under the model of work, narrowly understood as the producing and formation of an
object” (Feminism as Critique 2).
This is not entirely fair, since social reproduction theorists have long sought to center the
elements of life-making that dominant political-economic theorists so often constitutively
dismissed as ‘merely’ cultural or personal, and have been instrumental in actively drawing out
and politicizing reproductive labor and relations.89 But their points about the limits of labor when
89
This is especially true of recent theorizing on queer social reproduction and family abolition, and recent theorizing
coming out of Latin America, which I discuss in my conclusion.
129
it comes to the agencies, relationality, and forms of subjectivation specific to the feminized
domains of care and nurturance remain pertinent to contemporary debates.
The framework of social reproduction I engage with below was first developed in the
early 70s by autonomist feminists in the Wages for Housework Campaign in iconic pamphlets
such as Mariarosa Dalla Costa and Selma James’s “The Power of Women and the Subversion of
the Community” and, ten years later, by Socialist feminist Lise Vogel in Marxism and The
Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory. For their part, early proponents of Wages for
Housework (WfH) viewed their work as a response to the parallel inadequacies of traditional
Marxism and radical feminism to account for the constitutive relation between gender oppression
and capitalist exploitation. In opposition to these positions, they elaborated a critical stance on
domestic labor as a social practice that linked gender domination and the exploitation dictated by
capitalist accumulation. If capitalist immiseration depends on extracting the greatest amount of
living labor possible from the worker, then who was responsible for keeping this worker alive,
fed, emotionally tended, and fucked—and ensuring that a new generation of workers was
available to exploit once his living labor had expired? What labor, they asked, was responsible
for reproducing productive labor—i.e., reproducing the worker—on both a daily and
intergenerational basis. And what mechanisms were in place to exploit and extract this labor, and
mystify its social origin?
The answer, they contended, was to be found in the gender divisions of labor and family
forms foundational to capitalist sociality but ideologically and materially demarcated from it—
the caretaking, cooking, cleaning, and general organization of daily life, often, but not
exclusively, taking place within the ostensibly private home. They argued that this meant that,
far from a safe-haven, the Western nuclear family—and the private ‘romances’ of love, sex, and
130
intimacy that go with it—is as coercive and extractive, as bound up with contradiction and
struggle, as the factory, the mine, or the fields. The gendered labor of reproduction and the
heterosexual bonds dictating its distribution, they claimed, were not a personal service, natural
vocation, or an act of selfless love, but labor. As Federici’s epic slogan has it: “They call it love.
We call it unwaged work” (“Wages Against Housework” 1).
A decade later, Lise Vogel offered another paradigmatic argument, which has recently
inspired a wave of socialist discussion on social reproduction. Like autonomist feminists, Vogel
claimed that the question of women’s oppression under capitalism remains underdeveloped in
Marxist thinking. But, whereas autonomist thinkers like Federici, Mies, and Fortunati were often
scathing in their critiques of Marxism and explicit in their use of specifically feminist insights
and methods, Vogel’s aim was to build from Marx by providing a unitary theory of gender
oppression and capitalist exploitation. Against socialist feminist tendencies that posed gender
and capital as ‘dual systems’ with separate logics and relations of exploitation, as well as
autonomist conceptions of reproductive labor as value productive, her position differentiated
reproductive labor from productive labor—claiming the latter reproduces use values rather than
commodities for exchange—while holding that both constitute essential components of capitalist
sociality as such. Moreover, she claims, the differentiations, as well as essential relation, between
these domains constitutes a crucial site of contradiction and tension within capitalism. In
conceiving of capitalism in this way, she relies upon Marx’s own critical categories and attempts
to reconstruct, at the level of theory, “a socio material foundation” (Ferguson and McNally xxii)
for understanding women’s oppression and thus for an expanded understanding of anti-capitalist
critique inclusive of the capitalist family form itself.
131
Marx himself roots his critique of capitalism in the materialist supposition that the labor
and relations through which human beings meet their needs90 are ontologically foundational, yet
at the same time historically conditioned by the modes of production through which the means of
producing life are appropriated and socially organized—and the specific forms of class
inequality and antagonism that result. The capitalist mode of production is, of course,
particularly cruel in this regard. Driven not by the spirit of enterprise but an imperative of
maximal exploitation made possible by the even more horrific thefts and appropriations of
slavery and settler colonialism, it dispossesses the masses of all means of survival but their
dwindling capacity to labor, and nothing to lose but their chains. For Marx, crucially, this violent
logic is also self-obfuscating: mystified by the leveling economy of exchange with its hollow,
ironic freedoms as well as the alienations dividing workers from the fruits of their labors, from
each other, and from their common humanity and struggle. Dispelling this mystification, and
revealing the fundamental class antagonism it obscures, are thus two crucial and interrelated
aims of Marx’s critical project.
Whereas traditional Marxism roots its critique of political economy in the perspective of
labor and its exploitation at the point of production, autonomist feminists took a much more
expansive view of capitalism and the conditions of its overcoming, rooted in a critique of the
home and family as much as the assembly line and factory floor. On their account, unwaged
housework performed by proletarian women was labor necessary for the waged worker’s daily
and generational reproduction. This labor circumscribed an entire regime of social and economic
exclusion and domination, which formed not only the necessary condition of capitalist
production, but also of a historical articulation of gendered violence corresponding to it. As
90
For Marx, meeting social need is a matter of survival, yet human needs are also social and historical—a
productive tension which lies at the heart of much of his thinking and critique.
132
Zhivka Valiavicharska points out, they not only made “visible the structural links between
patriarchal social orders and capitalist exploitation” but “showed that the history of workingclass struggle had effectively mirrored and reproduced patriarchal subjugation and patriarchal
gender norms under capitalism” (“Social Reproduction in the Making” 2). Insofar as it is
naturalized as a “female vocation,” the mystifications—and exploitations—of this labor are even
deeper, and crueler, than those of the wage relation.
Vogel, for her part, opposes autonomists with her claim that women are oppressed not by
domestic labor per se but by women’s structural relation to the intergenerational replacement of
labor power under capitalism. However, her point plays a similar critical and methodological
role in her argument. By locating the roots of women’s oppression in their role within a family
form geared towards the reproduction of labor power as well as the relation of this family form
to capitalism, she hoped to illuminate a more precise critique of capitalist sociality, the nature of
the violence it inflicts, and ultimately the conditions of its overcoming.
With the concept of social reproduction, Marxist feminists developed and critiqued
Marx’s understanding of capitalism as a mode of production, and with it, his core concepts of
labor and class struggle, while also historicizing second wave essentialisms and biological
determinisms regarding gender domination and the family form. They thus radicalized the
Marxist anti-capitalist project, as well as the class and labor politics it outlines, by showing that
unrecognized—largely unpaid or acutely underpaid—labors of reproduction are essential to
capitalist accumulation, and therefore a crucial site of political struggle and social
transformation. This understanding of the central role that reproductive labor played in both
capitalist production and gendered oppression revolutionized understandings of both: bringing
133
class struggle to the kitchen and the sheets,91 and revealing the reconstitution of gender and the
family to be essential components, and conditions, of its success.
III. Autonomist and Socialist Perspectives on Reproductive Labor
By including and centering the invisibilized labors of care and reproduction, both autonomist and
socialist traditions of social reproduction theory radically expand Marxist conceptions of the
category of labor, as well as the politics of labor and class struggle. However, while their
theories and organizing strategies are both centered on reproductive and caring labor, their
approaches to these questions are filtered through their respective politics. In this section, I
discuss the axial role that the category of labor plays in their respective positions. I also highlight
the radical, and often overlooked, interventions of queer and Black feminist social reproduction
theorists which fundamentally shaped these debates.
A crucial difference between autonomist and socialist Marxist feminist traditions lies in
how they understand the relationship between reproductive labor and capitalist production. Many
feminists in the former school cut their political teeth in the Italian workerist movement and were
influenced by the autonomist, grassroots politics of the Johnson-Forest Tendency in the US and
Caribbean. Fundamental to their argument is the contention that the labor of the proletarian
housewife—but also unwaged work in general, including the often-criminalized economies and
community networks of those without access to the wage—is itself productive, that is, essential
and integral to the capitalistic valorization of value. This argument grew out of the workerist
imaginary of the social factory (Federici, quoted in Toupin 267), which viewed social and
cultural life as increasingly subsumed by capitalist imperatives—rendering all life a terrain of
political struggle and potential reclamation. The claim that reproductive labor produces value
91
See for example Federici’s “Counter Planning From the Kitchen” and “Why Sexuality is Work”
134
deepens this operaist politicization of all spheres of life including the economy itself, and
autonomist feminist calls to bring political consciousness and organizing to daily life in many
ways builds upon the prefigurative, grassroots, organizing tactics developed by workerists and
other autonomist movements,92 while at the same time posing major challenges to the theory and
practice (and especially the intransigent anti-feminism) of operaists and their heirs.93
The socialist feminist argument that reproductive labor is not productive of value in this
strict sense should also be situated in relation to its political lineage. Drawing on socialist
conceptions of articulation that imagine a dialectical and strategic relationship between political
forms—e.g. the party (Mohandesi, 2020)—on the one hand, and the economy on the other, they
claim that reproductive labor must be situated in relationship to, rather than conflated with,
economically productive labor. Understanding reproductive labor as a use value that is
capitalistically organized to reproduce labor power as a commodity, but which is not directly
productive of value itself, they claim, critically situates their analysis vis a vis the fundamental
tensions and fault lines between these spheres of capitalistic life. This Marxian move offers a
corrective to economism and vangardism, while providing a theoretical foundation for political
formations capable of building and strategically mobilizing mass power.
III a. Autonomist Perspectives
The WfH Campaign was a key, and early, contribution of autonomist feminists, and utilized the
bottom-up organizing and global network building between local, militant struggles
characteristic of other autonomist movements. In demanding a wage for domestic labor, the WfH
92
In an anonymous piece written by WfH organizers for The Activist in 1974, the authors define the social factory
as such: “modern capitalist society is a factory—a social factory—the whole of which functions to reproduce capital
in an ever expanding form” (“The Social Factory,” 38). The authors argue that women’s unwaged labor constituted a
major part of the social factory.
93
See my discussion of Federici’s critique of Hardt and Negri in the following chapter.
135
movement offered an alternative to radical feminist and revolutionary Marxist views regarding
the nature of gender violence and class struggle, respectively—as well as the organizing
practices needed to confront them. Its aspirations were international94 and coalitional—and
organizers sought from the beginning to form political alliances with others working on the
terrain of social reproduction—in particular, sex workers and welfare activists. Galvanized by
the insight that largely unpaid domestic labor was an essential condition of capitalist
accumulation, activists such as Mariarosa Dalla Costa, Selma James, Silvia Federici, and
Margaret Prescod began demanding a wage for this work, and organizing internationally on this
basis. For its protagonists, this was a revolutionary and transformative demand. Transformative
in the sense that the political perspective, solidarities, relationships, and power gained through
the process of organizing for this demand were at least as important as winning it. And
revolutionary in that capitalism and the capitalist state depend upon unpaid reproductive labor
and thus could not withstand the pressure of paying for it. Against its detractors from the
women’s liberation movement and Marxist organizers alike, the aim of the WfH movement was
not to entrench the role of the housewife or the bourgeois family form,95 but to break the
isolation they engender, and in doing so systemically and directly attack the capitalistically
organized gender violence at their root.
Rather than simply a means to a political end, the demand of wages for housework was a
militant stance and rallying cry for grassroots organizers intent upon reconstituting social
reproduction and building solidarities between others organizing on this terrain. In Federici’s
94
Even after the split of the original International Feminist Collective (IFC) many former members continued this
internationalist work, including through the International Wages for Housework Campaign and the “Global
Women’s Strike” network James launched in 2000 (https://globalwomenstrike.net/)
95
Maria Mies in particular spends much time developing this argument about the nuclear family as a bourgeois
phenomenon, claiming that “…capitalism did not, as Engels and Marx believed, destroy the family; on the contrary,
with the help of the state and its police, it created the family first among the propertied classes, later in the working
class, and with it the housewife as a social category” (“Patriarchy and Accumulation” 103-104).
136
words, this perspective aimed at “revolutionizing—in the process of struggling for it—all our
family and social relations” (“Wages Against Housework” 1-2). In an ironic rejoinder to the
traditional Left, Dalla Costa and James thus begin their pamphlet by relocating the “women
question”—shorthand for the Marxist96 dismissal of feminism as a subsidiary concern that would
wither away, much like the state, in the process of proletarian struggle—in “the entire “female
role” as it has been created by the capitalist division of labor” (“The Power of Women” 40). This
stance flips the Marxist script, insofar as it claims that this “female role” is an essential condition
of capitalist accumulation and dispossession, and thus that any class perspective that does not
account for it will be fatally flawed. In a move that would prove deeply problematic, they claim
this “role” is paradigmatically encapsulated in the position and labors of the working-class
housewife.97
According to the Marxist feminist proponents of wages for housework, capitalism not
only “created the modern family and the housewife’s role in it” (40) but concealed their true
nature as a source of capital accumulation—indeed, the “very pillar of the capitalist organization
of work” (49). As Federici notes in sweeping propagandistic tone: housework is “the most subtle
and mystified form of violence that capital has ever perpetrated against any segment of the
working class” (“Wages Against Housework,” 2). Capital’s mystification of the violence,
exploitation, and stultifying isolation particular to this labor are even more insidious than the
wage relation precisely because it appears as “a personal service outside capital” (“The Power of
Women,” 44)—a natural vocation “coming from the depth of our female character” (“Wages
96
We should not forget that militant Marxist men of the New Left were especially hostile to feminism. See Mies and
Toupin.
97
Even in this early period autonomist feminists did, however, make connections between domestic work and
unwaged work in general, and linked its contemporary forms to histories of settler colonialism, witch hunts, and the
institution of slavery.
137
Against Housework,” 2)—and thus not as work at all. Like waged labor, this work is not a
choice, really. But unlike waged labor, however consuming, there is no clocking off from this
role: because it is naturalized and performed in isolation, it also never ends (“The Power of
Women,” 45). To perform it well, one must not only submit to the ‘myth of female incapacity,’
but identify with these ‘labors of love’ as one’s innermost desire and highest aspirations.
As Federici brilliantly describes, this intensive training of body, heart and mind involves
mystifications that damage a person’s lived experiences and sense of identity beyond even the
cynical equality and consent of waged work. The “combination of physical, emotional, and
sexual services” that make this work so intensively difficult are also, cruelly, what render it
invisible as work (“Wages Against Housework” 3). Moreover, these expectations are
contradictory and impossible to meet: one cannot be a sex goddess and a doting wife and mother.
And, since they are characterized as nature and not a form of work, these impossible demands
come to shape one’s deepest sense of self and personal meaning. Not only does sacrifice become
the housewife’s highest duty and the man’s pleasure the barometer of her own but performing
them well requires wholly identifying with one’s responsibility to please. An inability or refusal
to meet these impossible demands can only be seen as a personal failing: “if you don’t like it, it
is your problem, your failure, your guilt, your abnormality” (3).
This makes it difficult to know and experience desire and agency as one’s own at all. As
Federici painfully puts it in “Why Sexuality is Work,” the “[d]uty to please is so built into our
sexuality that we have learned to get pleasure out of giving pleasure” (24). At the same time, the
“need to give and receive love is turned against us as a work duty” (“Wages Against
Housework,” 6). The “impossibility to see where our work begins and ends” is at the same time
the impossibility of deciphering “where our work ends and our desires begin” (6). Moreover, to
138
the extent that men themselves are exploited and emasculated by capital, enduring abuse
becomes an integral part of the job. Tending to the man’s ego when it is broken by the boss,
managing and appeasing his rage, and submitting to his sexual aggression are cruel hazards
baked into domestic work. All of this points to a deep politics of care and sex: to reclaim them as
their own, women must break their isolation and unite with others in struggle. For the proponents
of wages for housework, the struggle for a wage—for material and emotional autonomy—was
thus also a struggle to collectively reclaim and reconstitute the terrain of social reproduction as a
place where one’s own agency and desire might find a name and a home.
From the beginning of the movement, the WfH campaign brought attention to the sexual
and emotional politics of social reproduction. Sex, like care, is a condition of social
reproduction: like care, it is work. Divorced from social context, calls for sexual liberation
further mystify and intensify this work (Federici “Why Sexuality is Work” 25). Indeed,
heterosexuality itself is “part of the discipline of work.” This is bad for queer people, but also for
heterosexuals: capital “raises heterosexuality to a religion,” yet forecloses the possibility of
genuine heterosexual intimacy (47). While I claim below that these ideas remain
underdeveloped, and ultimately reduce emotional and embodied dimensions of care to labor,
they represent a crucial advance over much Marxist and mainstream feminist politics of the time,
and the narrowly circumscribed economistic and essentialized categories they were forced into.98
Indeed, as Dalla Costa puts it, “domestic labor is not essentially ‘feminine work’” any more than
drudgery of the assembly line is “masculine” (48).
While this denaturalization of gender norms and politicization of domestic labor were
crucial developments, the singular focus on the housewife and her unpaid domestic labors, as
98
See Capper and Austin 449, and Sarah Jaffe 2018
139
well as the political perspective they developed from it, proved deeply problematic, and were
rightly critiqued by Black feminists. Federici’s contention that the housewife is the only
perspective from a feminist viewpoint or Dalla Costa’s claim that this role is the determinant for
all other women under capitalism (40) universalizes a historical and relatively privileged
position, effectively excluding the perspectives of women who’s experiences of domestic labor
were at least as informed by racism and/or colonial violence as gender and class. As I discuss
below, Hazel Carby contends that universalized notions of domestic labor, reproduction, and the
family prove not only inadequate but “contradictory when applied to the lives and experiences of
black women” (“White Women Listen” 46, my emphasis), and Angela Davis wryly notes that
“[i]n the United States, women of color, especially Black women, have been receiving wages for
housework for untold decades” (Women, Race, and Class 237). These racial divisions of paid
domestic labor, and the positive role the Black family has often played in fostering resistant,
alternative, forms of social reproduction (Carby) paint a very different picture of social
reproduction and the politics of its transformation. I return to these critiques below.
At the same time, during and especially after the mid-70s heyday of the WfH campaign,
autonomists continued to develop their theory of reproductive labor, most notably in
conversation with anti-racist, decolonial, and sex worker activists. From its inception, the
campaign was influenced by the domestic workers movement in the US, the Johnson-Forest
Tendency (James was married to CLR James, and a political collaborator throughout his life),
and the League of Revolutionary Black Workers in Detroit (S. Jaffe). As I discuss at length in
the next chapter, Federici has long made connections between the various and ongoing forms of
dispossession upon which the exploitation of labor depends, drawing connections between the
European witch hunts, the vicious theft of indigenous lands, and the ongoing dispossession at
140
play in practices as diverse as predatory structural adjustment policies and the corporate
extraction and enclosure of knowledge commons. In her 1986 Patriarchy and Accumulation on a
World Scale Maria Mies also speaks to the “underground connections” between sexual and
international divisions of labor under capitalism. Developing an integrative perspective on the
interconnected processes of ‘housewifization’ and colonization, she claims that “[w]ithout the
ongoing exploitation of external colonies - formerly as direct colonies, today within the new
international division of labour- the establishment of the ‘internal colony’ that is, a nuclear
family and a woman maintained by a male ‘breadwinner,’ would not have been possible” (110).
While both Mies and Federici at times make sweeping historical claims that are difficult to
substantiate,99 their theories have been immensely influential and have laid crucial groundwork
for meaningful solidarity, coalition, and an internationalist ethos amongst many anti-capitalist
feminist movements worldwide. Their observation that the labor, economies, and relations of
reproduction are sites not only of exploitation, but ongoing dispossession, has provided crucial
theoretical groundwork for connecting decolonial and feminist struggles, for example.
These revolutionary and coalitional aspects of autonomist feminism have been most
successfully, and radically, developed by Black, queer, and sex-working theorists and organizers
within the movement. Starting in the mid-70s, Black Women for Wages for Housework
(BWfWfH), Wages Due Lesbians (WDL), and the US PROStitutes (US PROS) Collective took
the WfH campaign in radical new directions. As Capper and Austin note in their brilliant article
on BWfWfH and Wages Due Lesbians, activists with these campaigns deeply interrogated the
narrow focus on the unpaid, heterosexual, housewife, but continued to develop an autonomist
99
Interestingly, Chandra Mohanty describes Mies’s work on lace-makers of Narsapur, India, as a notable example of
a Western feminist who did not reproduce the “discursive colonialism” of much work by Western women on the
Global South at the time (“Under Western Eyes” 344-45)
141
politics of reproductive labor. Rather than a new overarching class perspective, Capper and
Austin note that “[a]utonomy…was activated as an organizational tactic to mobilize across and
beyond existing racial, gender, sexual, and class configurations while recognizing the irreducible
differences between reproductive laborers” (449).
Co-founded by Margaret Prescod and Wilmette Brown, BWfWfH was especially
prominent in developing such coalitional strategies—initiating, for example, the collaborations
with Black sex workers from which PROS began (Prescod 2021) and working with welfare
rights organizers like Beulah Sanders in the “Coalition of Grassroots Women” (Prescod 2018).
BWfWfH was thus pivotal in the early and ongoing support of sex worker autonomy and the
decriminalization of sex work—a rare move indeed for feminists in the 1970s and 80s, as well as
working alongside members of the National Welfare Rights Organization to re-frame welfare as
a wage (Prescod 2018) and make policy demands on this basis. Bringing their experiences
organizing with domestic workers, the Black Panther Party, and for reproductive justice, Prescod
and Brown deepened and radicalized the WfH framework (Prescod 2021, S. Jaffe) by connecting
it to Black women’s experiences and struggles. Capper and Austin note the impact this had on
the theory and politics of reproductive labor in particular:
In the activist and intellectual production of BWfWfH, however, black women’s housework is
positioned in a nonidentical, and at times antagonistic, relation to the labors of the (white)
housewife. Drawing on the history of slavery and its afterlives as the basis for its analysis, the
group emphasized the racialized “divisions of labor” between white and black women, and
especially the labors black women had historically performed for white women, in ways that
interrupted (but did not render impossible) alliances over the conditions of reproductive work
(Brown 1976a: 5). At the same time, the group’s approach to “housework” as an analytic was
aimed at overwhelming this category from the inside in order to unbraid the moralistic, and
ultimately ideological, distinctions between the work of the housewife and other reproductive
workers (such as the mother on welfare, the paid domestic, and the sex worker) (451).
142
The perspectives and solidarities developed by BWfWfH problematized the role of the
housewife as the paradigmatic position of the exploited reproductive laborer while retaining the
radical critique of the family forms, sexual norms, and gendered and racialized divisions of labor
at the root of capitalist accumulation and dispossession. Crucially, this was not without its realworld tensions. Illuminating a contested chapter in this history that is rarely discussed in the
literature, Prescod claims that it was “a split on race”100 that led to the breakdown of the IFC, and
the development of different contingents of the movement.101
Unlike many radical and mainstream feminists, the WfH campaign stood in solidarity
with sex workers and organized for decriminalization—calling attention to the relation between
unpaid domestic work and paid sex work and establishing long term coalitions, campaigns, and
social centers with autonomous groups such as the US PROStitutes (US PROS) Collective,102 the
ECP (English Collective of Prostitutes), and C.O.Y.O.T.E.. In her brilliant “Hookers in the
House of the Lord”—written at the request of ECP members who needed to remain
anonymous—James chronicles the 12-day sex worker occupation of a London church in 1982, as
well as the sustained decriminalization and anti-police brutality campaigns surrounding it. “By
this action” she claims, “we were demanding that Local Authorities and society at large stand by
100
Federici denies that race was behind the split: “But after four years, the international network splintered. The
New York committee, among others, dissolved after a falling-out with James and Prescod, who claim that the
priorities of Black Women for Wages for Housework were ignored; Federici denies this, and claims the group’s
issue was with James” (Kisner, “The Lockdown”)
101
“Soon after BWWFH was founded, there were problems with the New York WFH Committee, which was white.
They accused us of being ‘too pushy,’ disagreed with our focus on mothers who were on welfare, and refused to
work with us…The WFH groups in England, Canada, and the US stood strongly with us, defending Black women’s
right to autonomy, making sure that we had the support and resources we needed to carry out our campaigning. The
New York Committee dissolved. Mariarosa Dalla Costa, who led the WFH groups in Italy, told Selma that we Black
women were ‘presumptuous,’ and the international, which was coordinated from London, broke relations with Italy”
(Prescod, Kindle ed.)
102
From the PROS website: “The US PROStitutes Collective (US PROS) is a multiracial network of women who
work or have worked in different areas of the sex industry. Founded in 1982, US PROS campaigns for the
decriminalization of prostitution and for justice, protection and resources so that no woman, young person or man is
forced into prostitution through poverty or violence.” (https://uspros.net/)
143
prostitutes in their conflict with the police. This is the choice we had been asking feminists to
make since we were formed in 1975” (110).
The political perspective on reproductive labor developed by autonomist feminists
amounted to a new conception of labor itself. They articulated this stance by not only calling
attention to the unpaid domestic labor of the housewife, but by building coalitions between
reproductive laborers, and drawing connections between the capitalist exploitation of
reproductive labor on the one hand, and land theft, slavery, and the destruction of the natural
world on the other. By applying a Marxist, materialist, approach to reproductive labor they
rebuffed the biological essentialisms and determinism baked into many second wave notions of
gender and the family. But they equally critiqued the prevailing Marxism of the time—and the
Marxist concept of labor—through a resolutely feminist lens.
Mies, for example, claims to develop a new theory of labor rooted in feminism and anticolonial politics, and is deeply critical of the “additive” approach of socialist feminists
attempting “to fit the new feminist critique and rebellion into the existing theoretical body of
Marxism” (12). Indeed, she claims that the “naturalizing process” through which Marxist
tradition, including Engels, asserted an ahistorical, essentialist, account of biological
reproduction—and ultimately of reproductive labor and the family—is antithetical to a feminist
politics of reproductive labor: “This distinction between 'natural' (that is, ahistorical) processes
related to the 'production of human beings or procreation', and historical processes related to the
development of the means of production and labour is essentially responsible for the fact that
within Marxist theory a historical materialist conception of women and their labour is not
possible” (50).103 Even Fortunati (who’s book, The Arcane of Reproduction, is often neglected
103
Like Federici, Mies outlines the role of the witch hunts in this process of housewifization. “The witch hunt had
not only the direct disciplinary effect of controlling women's sexual and reproductive behaviour, but also the effect
144
due to her esoteric value theoretical perspective) argues that Marxist categories alone are
insufficient—and that the critique of capitalist social reproduction must include feminist critical
methods (9).104
But the greatest impact of autonomist feminism has arguably been in the vision of
autonomous forms of life-making and “commoning” it makes possible. Calling for the
destruction of the “entire female role” ideologically attached to reproductive labor, autonomist
feminists challenged the capitalist organization of work traditionally conceived, and also of
intimacy, love, sex, and emotions. Pointing to the transformative visions of autonomist Black
feminists and lesbians, Capper and Austin note: “The insights of BWfWfH and WDL toward an
articulation of a queer commons reside in their twinned understanding of reproduction as a
terrain of collective maintenance and insurrection, or what Stefano Harney and Fred Moten
(2013: 76) term ‘militant preservation.’” These “twinned conceptions”—their “autonomous
nonheteronormative mode of social reproduction” on the one hand and “insurgent mode of
common world-building” on the other—were indeed part of the same struggle (450).
III b. Socialist Perspectives
The socialist tradition of social reproduction theory developed over the past forty years in the US
and Canada—recently designated under the acronym ‘SRT’ (social reproduction theory)—has
also centered on a critique of the capitalist organization of reproductive labor. Unlike
autonomists however, these feminists explicitly develop and apply Marxist categories to the
terrain of social reproduction105—specifically his concept of labor. In the following pages, I
of establishing the superiority of male productivity over female productivity. These two processes are closely
connected.” (Patriarchy and Accumulation 70).
104
Fortunati, like James, centers sex work and sex worker solidarity in her theory. For reconstructions of her work
see Maya Gonzales’s important articles.
105
Primarily the categories of Capital Volume I, but also an expansive notion of labor power rooted in Marx’s early
work.
145
focus on several, interconnected, claims that follow from their Marxian feminist, labor-centered,
analysis. First, SRT distinguishes itself from other Marxist feminist and socialist traditions
through its commitment to an expansive conception of labor: as Tithi Bhattacharya puts it: “[t]he
fundamental insight of SRT is, simply put, that human labor is at the heart of creating or
reproducing society as a whole” (2). Second, SRT is committed to a theory of differentiated
labors, which Kade Doyle Griffiths and others claim gives this tradition a critical edge over the
autonomist view of labor as value productive and enables it to engage in nuanced ways with
social reproductive labor in the public sphere—and the labor struggles of teachers, nurses, and
other essential, often underpaid, workers. Combined, these analytic commitments reveal points
of connections between diverse labor struggles on the one hand, and struggles over
infrastructures, resources, and housing on the other. Finally, I discuss how these positions on
reproductive labor answer Vogel’s call for a unitary theory of gender oppression and capitalist
exploitation. Most powerfully articulated by Cinzia Arruzza, this unitary perspective provides
the theoretical underpinning of SRT’s expanded definition of class, which centers axes of
oppression such as race, gender, ability, and sexuality—and has proven especially useful for
articulating coalitional mass movements, such as the international feminist strikes movement of
recent years.
Lise Vogel’s 1983 Marxism and the Oppression of Women argues for a theory of social
reproduction rooted in Marxist historical materialism. Intervening in the ‘domestic labor debates’
of the late 60s-early 80s, Vogel opposes both the ‘dual systems’ approach initiated by Heidi
Hartman and Maxine Molyneux in the late 1970’s and taken up by many socialist feminists, and
the influential unified positions developed separately by Iris Marion Young (1981) and the WfH
campaign—which she claims are rooted in an ahistorical notion of gendered labor. Instead, she
146
sets out to provide a theoretical justification for a unitary theory that accounts for the oppression
of women by applying Marx’s own categories and critical method to the analysis of social
reproduction. Importantly, Vogel does not claim to explain or empirically elaborate all aspects of
women’s oppression under capitalism. Rather, she aims to “establish a socio material
foundation” for understanding this oppression (Ferguson and McNally xxii). In other words, like
Marx’s own critique, which begins from the mystified abstractions of bourgeois political
economy in order to then elaborate a robust, critical picture of capitalist production, Vogel
claims to provide a theoretical basis for understanding how the relation between reproductive
and productive work has led to a systemic devaluation of this work, and thus to women’s
structural subordination.
As McNally and Ferguson elaborate in their introduction to the 2014 reprint of Marxism
and the Oppression of Women—itself as an important inaugural moment for SRT—Vogel’s
intent was to lay a historically specific, non-functionalist, and thoroughly Marxian, groundwork
for a unitary critique of capitalist exploitation and gender oppression. Unlike radical feminists,
Vogel argues that reproductive labor is not inherently gendered or oppressive but becomes so
historically through specifically capitalist family structures ensuring the ‘generational
replacement’ of labor power. For Vogel and autonomists alike, reproductive labor is socially
necessary labor that is essential to the maintenance and continuation of the capitalist mode of
production (158). Contra autonomists’ claims that this labor was itself value productive however,
Vogel contends that the differentiation between reproductive and productive is what has proven
so harmful to women. Her aim in the book is to outline the specific contradictions that follow
from this complex relation between reproductive and productive labor, as well as their
implications for women’s liberation.
147
Vogel makes particular use of Marx’s materialist concept of labor—and his labor theory
of value—in the theoretical groundwork she puts forth in Marxism and the Oppression of
Women. Marx’s claim that capital’s extraction of surplus value is what defines labor as
productive, she contends, allows us to analyze the difference, as well as the relation, between the
domains of production and reproduction. Vogel’s readers have since developed this claim into
one of the key theoretical contributions of SRT.106 Doyle Griffiths elaborates on this reasoning,
explaining that it enables us to “see social reproductive work as that which both necessarily, and
in its concrete historical form, potentiates labor-power as a commodity” (“What is Valuable” 4).
In her 2017 edited volume, Tithi Bhattacharya summarizes this position as follows: “Social
reproduction theorists perceive the relation between labor dispensed to produce commodities and
labor dispensed to produce people as part of the systemic totality of capitalism. The framework
thus seeks to make visible labor and work that are analytically hidden by classical economists
and politically denied by policy makers” (2).
Importantly for our purposes, Bhattacharya and others claim that this commitment to
Marx’s category of labor enables SRT to form a sophisticated perspective on reproductive
labor—and care107 in particular. By insisting on the difference, indeed contradiction, between
“people producing,” reproductive labors and the imperatives of capitalist production, SRT also
sheds light on their relation—and thus on the relation between oppression and exploitation under
capitalism as well. In other words, they argue, it allows us to understand the oppressive divisions
of caring labor that must be in place for capital to generate profit at the expense of life.
106
SRT, Bhattacharya claims, “is unique in the sense that it theorizes the relationship between the market and
extramarket relations rather than simply gesturing toward their distinction” (“Introduction,” 14).
107
Bhattacharya defines care, or “social care” as “the corpus of social relations involving regeneration—birth, death,
social communication, and so on…” (9)
148
Doyle Griffiths helpfully explains this theory of differentiated labors, its reliance on
Marx’s labor theory of value, and its distinction from autonomist feminist theories of
reproductive labor. To quote him at some length:
This perspective is rooted in a classical conception of value as surplus-value extraction through
waged work and rejects the assertion that unwaged social reproductive labor is value-producing
(Ferguson). By paying close attention to labor-power as profit’s source, Marxian SRT
nevertheless offers a path to retaining the strategic centrality of reproductive labor with respect to
profit. While Federici and other Autonomist feminists use Marxist terminology for their own
purposes, their project is based on the assumption that Marx’s writings systematically overlook
processes of reproduction, and productivity, beyond the factory. Building on Lise Vogel’s
Marxism and the Oppression of Women, Marxian SRT instead expands Marx’s own account of
social reproductive labor as a necessary precondition for surplus value (“What is Valuable” 3).
For Doyle Griffiths and others working in this tradition, it is this differentiated, historically
specific, account of labor that gives SRT its critical power, and allows it to make nuanced
connections between diverse labor struggles within and outside of formal labor markets and the
wage. By illuminating the differences and relations between waged, productive labor, unpaid
reproductive labor, commodified and poorly paid reproductive labor, etc., SRT can chart and
oppose the crisis conditions of capitalist social reproduction and the increasing precaritization of
life and labor they engender (Doyle Griffiths, 3, 10).108 Its theory of differentiated labors also
allows SRT to politically elaborate solidarities between these different forms of labor, and also
between labor struggles and fights over resources, housing, and social reproduction more
broadly.
108
“Marxian SRT’s close attention to the distinctions among the categories of productive and reproductive, valueproducing and unproductive, and unwaged and waged labor is best suited to an analysis of the causes and
consequences of renewed class struggle arising from social reproductive crisis. This is because it allows us to
meaningfully distinguish between the dynamics and scales of the feminization of work.”
149
Bhattacharya thus claims that “SRT is a methodology to explore labor and labor power
under capitalism and is best suited to offer a rich and variegated map of capital as a social
relation” (3). Sue Ferguson further clarifies this methodological commitment to labor in her book
Women and Work: Feminism, Labor, and Social Reproduction. Also building on Vogel, she
insists on the theoretical and political value of clarifying the differences, and relations, between
the value-generating exploitation of productive labor, and the devaluation and naturalization of
unpaid, and underpaid, social reproductive labor. “In grasping the necessary but contradictory
relationship between production and reproduction,” she claims, SRT also illuminates the
systemic relation between women’s oppression and capitalist exploitation (Pluto Press Blog).
Namely, that the structural invisibilization and degradation of reproductive work is a
fundamental condition of both. For Ferguson, a “central innovation” of SRT is thus “the
theorization of feminist struggle as an anticapitalist struggle, a class struggle” (5). This
understanding that “feminist and worker struggles are two different parts of the same class
struggle” (5)109 is echoed in the work of Arruzza, Fraser, Bhattacharya, Aaron Jaffe, and others
as well.110
SRT’s defense of a ‘unitary theory’ of class exploitation and various forms of social
oppression follows from these methodological claims about labor and its specific and
contradictory organization under capitalism. According to its proponents, by expanding Marx’s
theory of labor into capitalist reproduction, SRT provides a theoretical explanation of the relation
between capitalist exploitation and gender oppression—which in turn allows for an expansive yet
articulated notion of class, and class struggle, as well. Arruzza’s widely read and celebrated
109
Below I point to the telling semantic priority of class evinced in these statements, and its tension with SRT’s
commitment to center oppression and offer an expansive conception of social reproduction.
110
See e.g. Arruzza, Bhattacharya and Fraser; A. Jaffe, 2020.
150
“Remarks on Gender”111 set the tone for this conversation—answering Vogel’s 1983 call with a
revitalized, nuanced defense of a unified theory of gender oppression and capitalist
exploitation—grounded in an expanded conception of social reproduction.
According to Arruzza, social reproduction describes the emotional and sexual
maintenance of relations, the material provision of care and material sustenance, as well as the
institutional and social structures in which these practices are embedded, all of which sustains
life on a daily and intergenerational basis—it designates “the physical, emotional, and mental
labor necessary for the production of the population,” and thus points to how this labor is
organized on a micro and macro level. This expanded framework of social reproduction, Arruzza
contends, has the advantage of moving beyond domestic labor:
The concept of social reproduction, then, allows us to locate more precisely the mobile and
porous quality of the walls of the home: in other words, the relation between, on the one hand,
domestic life within the home, and the phenomena of commodification, the sexualization of the
division of labor, and the policies of the welfare-state on the other. Social reproduction also
enables us to more effectively analyze phenomena like the relation between the commodification
of care-work and its “racialization” by repressive migration policies, such as those that aim to
lower the costs of immigrant labor and force them to accept slave-like working conditions
(“Remarks on Gender”).
By providing clarity on these institutions and social forms organizing non-productive, human,
relations, the concept of social reproduction reveals capitalism as far more than merely a mode of
production. As an epistemic and political framework of analysis, it enables a much deeper and
nuanced understanding of capitalism as an “articulated and contradictory totality of relations of
exploitation, domination, and alienation”112—and thus enriches and specifies the “Marxian
111
It should be noted that the influence of this piece spread beyond specifically socialist radical Left circles,
influencing theorizations of communization that are more rooted in autonomist, anarchist, and anti-state communist
thinkers such as Chris Chen and Maya Gonzales.
112
As Bhattacharya also notes: “SRT treats questions of oppression (gender, race, sexuality) in distinctly
nonfunctionalist ways precisely because oppression is theorized as structurally relational to, and hence shaped by,
151
critique of capitalism” (my emphasis) as well. The lens of social reproduction thus grants
Marxist feminism the political and epistemic clarity to move beyond the determinism,
functionalism and reductionism of past and present Marxisms—as well as the politically
problematic and fragmented logics of ‘indifferent capitalism’ or ‘dual’ (or multiple) systems
theory. “Viewing them through the lens of social reproduction,” rather, shows that the relation
between oppression and class is both historically contingent and essentially conditioned by
capitalist imperatives.113
With this piece, Arruzza sought to “reopen[] the crucial debate about how we should
conceptualize the structural relationship between gender oppression and capitalism” (“Remarks
on Gender”). In the intervening years, feminist organizers have utilized this updated approach to
expand the politics of social reproduction and reveal avenues of connection between antioppression and labor struggles. Bhattarcharya and others have argued that this represents a
crucial development of social reproduction theory—moving it beyond the critique of private,
family, life that limited the politics and analysis of prior social reproduction theory. SRT’s focus
on the differentiated and internally contradictory relation between production and social
reproduction allows for an articulated yet expansive conception of class politics and indeed of
politics in general: illuminating, for example how “every battle for healthcare, water, housing”
contains a seed for antisystemic struggles (Pluto Press Blog).114
capitalist production rather than on the margins of analysis or as add-ons to a deeper and more vital economic
process” (“Mapping Social Reproduction Theory” 3).
113
Arruzza’s move to provide a non-deterministic, theoretical foundation for a unitary theory, which explains key
aspects of oppression under capitalism without thereby reducing historical contingency and struggle, is a major
advancement of Vogel’s key methodological move. Vogel explains her own reasoning as follows: “While women's
oppression in class-societies is experienced at many levels, it rests, ultimately, on these material foundations. The
specific working out of this oppression is a subject for historical, not theoretical, investigation” (117). This insight
on the relation between Arruzza’s unitary theory and Vogel’s own comes out of conversations with Arruzza over the
course of her advising.
114
See also Doyle Griffiths who claims that “SRT implies distinct but overlapping visions for class struggle and
politics as a whole.”
152
SRT is perhaps most powerful in this expanded definition of class and differentiated yet
integrated account of mass struggle. These contributions are highlighted in texts like Fraser,
Arruzza and Bhattacharya’s Feminism for the 99%—a manifesto rooted in insights of SRT that
celebrates, and attempts to further ignite, the recent wave of broad based, international, and
anticapitalist feminist struggle. Deeply influenced by the praxis and theoretical innovations
coming out of the international feminist strikes movement, which has been led both intellectually
and politically by the work of collectives such as Ni Una Menos in Argentina, Fraser, Arruzza
and Bhattacharya claim that the perspective of social reproduction radically re-situates the
meaning of the strike and instigates a “new kind of politics.” By “broadening the very idea of
what counts as “labor;” “making visible the indispensable role played by gendered, unpaid work
in capitalist society,” and revealing the connection between ostensibly private, unpaid,
reproduction and waged work, it has been instrumental in overcoming intransigent divides
between identity and class politics as well (8-9).115 Like the autonomist demand for a wage, this
changes the locations and methodologies of traditional labor politics. The feminist strike both
responds to social reproductive crises and reveals new horizons for political action and
coalitional politics: articulating broad based feminist resistance to mass femicide, for example,
while also bringing together previously divided labor sectors in mass assemblies and fostering
forms of political cooperation all but inconceivable within prior paradigms of feminism and class
struggle.
IV. The Limits of the Labor Paradigm
115
This is a crucial insight with multiple lineages politically and theoretically—drawing upon the organizing
strategies and theoretical insights of various communities including the Zapatistas and precarious workers
movements like the piqueteros in Argentina.
153
Having laid out the concept of labor and its centrality to these two lineages of social reproduction
theory in some detail, I want to return to my broader argument about Marxist feminists’ slippery
overextensions of class and labor politics, and the troubled picture of social reproduction politics
that emerge from them.
While I am critical of their naturalization of care, I believe care ethicists are right that the
labor and relations of care are irreducibly ethical. Dispositions and attunements of care—its
intersubjective, affective, sensible dimensions—are the relational, neuro-biological116 incubators
of cultural life and meaning. Emotional and embodied patterns of attention and response—the
holding and nurturance, but also the refusal, neglect, or abuse—transmitted through caring
relations quite literally stitch the contours of self and relation that make up the psychosocial
fabric of society. Both intensely particular and broadly social and cultural, they convey the felt
sense of safety and belonging, or danger and indignity, through which we experience ourselves,
each other, and the world. I have gone to great lengths to argue that these life-making, relational,
and essentially components of care are also irreducibly political. Not only social organizations
and divisions of caring labor, but also these experiential capacities, dispositions, and norms of
care constitute the life-making heart of social reproduction. For pain is not the only inheritance
116
My claim is that such “neuro-biological” components of affective relationship and nervous system attunement are
ethical, as well as historical and social. I distinguish this position from the naturalism I critique in care ethics
through the teachings of politicized somatics and transformative justice. Kai Cheng Thom, for example, draws on
Stephen Porges’s understanding of the “social engagement” branch of the nervous system and the “Window of
Tolerance” or what Caffyn Jesse terms “Neural Learning Zone” in which the nervous system is engaged and
adaptive to stress but not to an extent that it perceives as dangerous, i.e. that triggers a “Fight, Flight, Freeze,
Appease” response. Thom adopts this model in her somatic approach to transformative justice: re-naming it a
“Window of Transformation” in which we can learn to engage in generative conflict without spinning out into
habitual reaction patterns. The point that I am making here is that these somatic, even biological, dimensions of care
and attunement are embedded in social contexts (including personal and intergenerational trauma) and, as such, can
and be engaged and expanded through practice—here practices of community accountability and conflict. This
allows us to slowly build the sorts of capacities so many of us lack around staying present, open, and connected
during high-intensity moments of crisis or conflict. Note that this point is yet another perspective on my argument in
the previous chapters regarding the always already political nature of caring dispositions themselves.
154
passed on through the intimate portals of care. They are also what nurture imaginaries capable, in
the works of Drucilla Cornell, of sharing the “secret of joy across generations” (236).117
To reduce these dimension of social reproduction politics to labor, even in an expanded
sense of the word, is as one-sided and limiting as reducing them to an unambiguous moral good.
Insofar as care is an essential component of social reproduction and the politics of its
transformation, so too are these relational and intimate components of care.
In the remainder of this chapter, I motivate these concerns about the over-extension of
Marxist class and labor politics and underdevelopment of these political valences of social
reproduction vis a vis the surprisingly dismissive treatment of intersectional theory on the part of
thinkers in the SRT tradition, as well as longstanding critiques of autonomists on the part of
feminists of color. Pluto Press’s description of Bhattacharya’s 2017 edited volume is indicative
of the former concern—claiming, without further explanation or context, that SRT’s perspectives
on the relation between gender, race, and capitalist exploitation present “a more sophisticated
alternative to intersectionality.”118 This common refrain—expressed with more or less nuance
across the work of Ferguson, McNally, Jaffe, Arruzza, Bhattacharya and others—is rooted in
SRT’s Marxist commitments, and specifically its methodological and political commitment to
theorizing capitalist social relations as an articulated totality. To recall this argument in broad
strokes, the claim is that, by showing how capital socially organizes not only productive but
reproductive labor, SRT reveals the logic unifying capitalist accumulation and historically
specific forms of oppression, while avoiding recourse to the reductionism, determinism, or
economism of vulgar Marxism. In Arruzza’s words, the lens of social reproduction thus “allows
us to identify the organizing logic of these intersections without for this reason excluding the role
117
118
Cornell herself cites Alice Walker’s Possessing the Secret of Joy (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1992).
https://www.plutobooks.com/9780745399881/social-reproduction-theory/
155
played by struggle, and the existence of contingent phenomena and practices in general”
(“Remarks on Gender”).
SRT’s expanded Marxian perspective, Arruzza and others claim, sheds light on the
internal relations undergirding capitalism as a contradictory social totality yet hidden from plain
view by its fragmenting and alienating social conditions. This nuanced and non-reductive stance
on the logic of capital is what its proponents claim grants SRT its special ability to outline the
structural relation between class exploitation and various forms of social oppression. By showing
that class and oppression are not “purely accidental and contingent intersections” (“Remarks on
Gender”), and providing a unified critique of both, they also provide a theoretical groundwork
for the broad based, coalitional, politics I discussed above. In this view, various forms of
oppression—e.g., racist, misogynistic, homophobic, transphobic, xenophobic or ableist
oppressions—are contingent historical and social phenomena and thus, like class struggle itself,
are not reducible to the logic of exploitation at the heart of capitalist accumulation. But nor,
Arruzza and others claim, should they be theorized as autonomous structures with their own
inherent logics (Arruzza, 2014). Finally, proponents of SRT argue, the lens of social
reproduction—and the picture of a capitalism as an articulated social totality it brings into
view—allows us to see that capitalism itself cannot be conceived apart from its integral relation
to oppression: e.g. the gendered, racialized, and colonial relations through which reproductive
labor is devalued and distributed, or the heteronormative family forms and sexual regimes
through which it is regulated and disciplined.
SRT is motivated by a genuine commitment to center oppression and forge connections
between labor struggles and social justice movements. It aims to provide a non-reductive unitary
analysis of class exploitation and oppression under capitalism, and thus a theoretical foothold for
156
political platforms that systemically link, and confront, injustices of all kinds. However, this
promise is thwarted by a fundamental equivocation through which it extends not only
explanatory but political primacy to the Marxist project, and thereby limits its own contributions
to genuinely diverse political struggles on the terrain of social reproduction.
On the one hand, SRT’s theoretical justification for an expanded notion of capitalist
sociality, and thus class struggle, is meant to be just that: a general, abstract, account that points
to the internal logic of capital unifying the historically contingent, diverse, and contradictory
phenomena that together comprise the violent conditions of our lives. On the other, however, this
theoretical move does consistently belie a de facto politics: one of class and labor. While it aims
to center oppression and anti-oppression struggles, the capitalist class relation remains the
‘master-frame” (Fraser) for SRT’s unitary theory—from here it is hard to ignore the subtle and
overt slippages through which class and labor become the implicit referent119 not only for theory,
but for politics more broadly. While she and others in the SRT tradition are clear that their
definition of politics are not encompassed by class,120 even Arruzza—whose philosophical rigor
and political wisdom inform her pathbreaking contributions to the theory of social reproduction
and international feminist organizing efforts on the terrain of social reproduction—succumbs to
this tendency. Calling to expand the solidarities that made the international feminist strike in
2017 so remarkable, she states: “[t]he concrete experience of the women’s strike, as well as the
social reproduction theory that inspired some of its organizers, made the question of whether
class struggle should take priority over ‘identity-based’ struggles …not only obsolete but
119
I borrow the term “implicit referent” from Chandra Talpade Mohanty, who uses it to describe a fundamental
component of the “discursive colonialism” through which Western feminists render women of the so-called third
world into a monolithic “archetypal victim” whose oppression and political agency alike become legible only
through reference to their own (Mohanty).
120
See e.g. Arruzza’s 2020 preface to Jaffe’s Social Reproduction Theory, Doyle Griffiths, and Ferguson.
157
ultimately misleading.” (“From Social Reproduction” 195). While she understands class in a
distinctly non-economistic lens, encompassing subject positions, experiences, and labors
extending far beyond those of traditional labor politics,121 this semantic shift nonetheless
suggests that class is her unifying lens at a concrete and political, not merely a general and
analytical, level: for example, “…movements such as Black Lives Matter, the migrants ’strikes,
and the mobilizations against the wall at the border with Mexico; and the near-spontaneous
mobilizations against the Muslim Ban” can, she argues, be read as “various forms that class
struggle is currently taking, forms that potentially empower each other and can create the
conditions for organizing work stoppages in the workplace” (194).122
For proponents of SRT, capitalist sociality is incredibly complex, and reproduced through
practices and relations of oppression that are both integral and irreducible to exploitative
productive relations. However, precisely insofar as it is an articulated totality, they claim,
capitalist sociality does have a heart—the ruthless pursuit of accumulation, or, in Marx’s
language, the ‘valorization of value.’123 In “Remarks on Gender” Arruzza uses this metaphor of
the heart to clarify how an orientation to social reproduction can avoid reductionism and
economism while nonetheless retaining the central insights of Marx’s theory and method. Jaffe
121
“Class struggle” she contends, “should not be conflated with labor struggle in the workplace: class struggle takes
many forms” (“From Social Reproduction” 194).
122
The concluding lines of Arruzza’s chapter in Bhattacharya’s volume are illustrative of her complex position:
“…it is necessary to show the internal relations between various forms of oppression and to combine the differences
these oppressions generate in a more encompassing critique of capitalist social relations. In this process, each
political subjectivation based on a specific oppression can provide us with new insights on the various ways
capitalism, racism, and sexism affect our lives” (196).
123
By the valorization of value, Marx refers to the exploitative, yet self-obscuring, wage relation at the heart of
capitalist production. The concept of value, when contextualized as an expression of the self-obscuring process by
which labor is maximally exploited, thus not only allows us to understand the systemic exploitation and
dispossession essential to the wage relation under capitalism, but also reveals classless society to be the condition of
overcoming this immiseration. Value is both a descriptive and an essentially political category insofar as it describes
the movement of capital as a whole and in its specificity, and also points to the internal limits of capitalist
production and thus the political possibility of its destruction. It is an abstraction of the ruthlessly exploitative social
process of accumulation.
158
explains the crucial contribution Arruzza makes with this metaphor, which illuminates both “the
necessity as well as the limits of appreciating the valorizing “heart” of capitalism” (Social
Reproduction Theory 124). It clarifies, he contends, how the SRT position can attend to social
oppression while retaining its Marxist commitment to seeing “the class relation that enables
valorization as the social institution that forms the violently beating heart of any capitalist
society” (81). To quote Arruzza in full, capitalism
is a mode of production and a system of social relations, with an identifiable logic: according to
Marx, it is a process of the valorization of value. Certainly, to have identified this process as the
driving force or motor of capitalism does not say everything that needs to be said about
capitalism: this would be analogous to thinking that the explanation of the anatomy of the heart
and its functions would suffice to explain the whole anatomy of the human body. Capitalism is an
ensemble of complex processes and relations. However, understanding what its heart is and how
it works is a fundamental analytic necessity (“Remarks on Gender”)
I want to dwell for a moment with this metaphor, since it cuts to the heart, so to speak, of the
problem as I see it as well. Arruzza and Jaffe both note that, as an organic totality, the body
involves many vital processes and relations. Indeed, the heart itself is one among other essential
organ systems. We can assume, for example, that the lungs, brain, kidneys, and liver, each play
distinct and irreducible, yet fundamentally interrelated, roles in the life of the body as a whole.
However, we can also assume that understanding the body’s conditions of both sickness and
health, and promoting the latter, requires the ability to shift perspectives—depending on the
symptoms at hand. So, in this sense, the valorization of value is likely the heart of capitalism as a
mode of production fueled by the systemic and brutal exploitation of labor and ever-increasing
class inequality. This knowledge is a crucial lever of labor and class politics. However, this claim
about the logic of valorization at the heart of capitalism as “a mode of production and a system
of social relations” does not justify Arruzza’s subsequent claims about capitalism qua political
159
life, or the analytic necessity of identifying accumulation as the heart unifying the totality of
these “complex processes and relations.”
While the ‘heart’ is a meaningful human metaphor, it is only that. It does not justify
privileging one vital—or toxic—system over others. And when it comes to the living body itself,
there simply is no underlying reference point or logic unifying these complex, interrelated,
processes. Similarly with social reproduction: identifying capitalist accumulation as the unifying
vantage for social reproduction politics, even at a high level of abstraction, is ultimately akin to
saying that the physical heart can and should form the reference for understanding the body and
remedying a diversity of its ills. This is particularly relevant when other factors—in the examples
of BLM or migrant struggles cited above, systemically racist, or neocolonial state violence—are
more salient or urgent factors in a given struggle. While it is crucial to clarify the multifaceted
histories and relations that connect various forms of institutionalized violence and struggles
against them, insisting on the analytic priority of one such perspective over others, even at a high
level of abstraction, threatens to flatten the lived complexities of oppression and resistance, and
hinder the horizontal solidarities and plurality of skills needed to develop diverse and coalitional
political movements.
To reiterate, I am not contesting Arruzza and Jaffe’s claims about capital’s valorization
imperative or even the idea of a unitary theory as such (a point on which I am agnostic). What I
am contesting is their move to characterize capitalism as political life and thus to cast labor and
class as the implicit or explicit reference points for political theory and practice. To extend these
points to my larger argument: while it is crucial to recognize care as labor and organize around
the dire need for labor rights and protections for care workers and other reproductive laborers, it
160
does not follow that the politics of care or social reproduction should be encompassed within, or
understood primarily with reference to, the politics of class and labor.
The problems with this tendency to privilege class as the implicit referent for politics
become evident in SRT’s approach to intersectional theories, which are frequently cited in the
literature as instances of a theoretical and practical failure to account for this unifying logic at the
heart of various oppressions. Bhattacharya, for example, claims that “intersectionality theory
shows us a world where race, gender, and other oppressions ‘intersect,’ thereby producing a
reality that is latticed—a sum total of different parts” (17)—in other words, an additive approach
to multiple oppressions. But this accusation overlooks the foundational epistemic and political
moves of many intersectional theorists. As I discussed at length in the previous chapter,
Crenshaw and others join a long lineage of Black feminist thought in confronting the limits of
such additive approaches.124 To name just a few prominent examples: the Combahee River
Collective’s ‘integrated analysis’ in the face of ‘interlocking oppressions;’ Crenshaw’s
discussions of the inadequacy of discrimination law—which offered protections against sexism
and racism, but not their combined and compounded effects in the discrimination faced by
women of color; and Collins’s ‘matrix of oppressions,’ which Jaffe and McNally both
approvingly cite, all distinctly oppose the external, merely additive, approach to multiple
oppressions espoused in the single-issue frames of women’s liberation, Black liberation, and
Socialism.
124
It is true that Crenshaw’s spatial metaphor of the ‘intersection’—by definition, a crossroads between discrete
axes or ‘streets’—has been a topic of debate in intersectional discourse (Belle). As I discuss above, however,
intersectionality represented a paradigm shift away from external approaches to the ‘single issue frames’ (Crenshaw)
or ‘parallelisms’ (Carby) developed by white feminists, Black nationalists, Marxists, and lesbian separatists whose
prioritization of race, gender, class, and/or sexuality proved politically damaging and inadequate to the
inextricability of multiple oppressions in their lived experiences and in the world.
161
It is thus somewhat puzzling that thinkers in the SRT tradition so frequently levy this
accusation of additive (or even, in the case of McNally, “neo-Newtonian”) thinking against
intersectional theory.125 Moreover, taken on their own terms, these arguments still do not clarify
the alternative they pose to the ostensive additivism of intersectional theory: namely why class
should be regarded as the reference point, or heart, of critical understanding and the social
totality alike.
“Without centering class relations,” Jaffe contends, “social theory could recognize many
systems, social structures, physical infrastructures, and forms of social oppression, but we would
not be seeing that these oppressions are situated as parts of the constitution and social
reproduction of capitalist societies” (Social Reproduction Theory, 89). But unless we presuppose
the very Marxist framework Jaffe is attempting to justify, SRT’s superior ability to unify diverse
forms of social violence and explain the “causes of social violence” remains opaque. What, in
other words, does granting the analytic primacy of class enable us to see, beyond this very
assertion? (Namely, that valorization is the unifying heart of capitalism, therefore the
125
Many intersectional thinkers develop a pluralistic and situated approach to both theory formation and political
action. SRT’s opposition to this pluralism, combined with intersectionality’s sometimes-thin treatment of class,
seems to be one plausible explanation for this stance. Jaffe, for example, claims to offer a “generous” reading of
intersectionality, which he nonetheless claims lacks an account of “the causes of social violence.” He states: “I will
make the case that, despite intersectionality’s strengths, SRT does a better job of explaining the causes of social
violence. I consider SRT to be best suited to tackling the interwoven nature of oppressions in capitalist societies, as
SRT highlights the essential role class plays in these oppressions. To make this argument, I want to develop a
generous reconstruction of some anti-capitalist potentials that stem from the best of intersectionality” (71). He
subsequently turns to Hill Collins’s concept of the matrix of oppressions, which he claims does point to the
interconnections between oppressive institutions and social practices. He concludes, however, by offering SRT as a
“better” approach, able to make clear sense of this mesh of oppressive relations by pointing to class relations as the
cause and underlying logic organizing capitalistic societies (89). It is difficult to understand, from this claim and
elsewhere, why a unitary lens is necessary to explain the roots of social violence, or why class and labor power
should form this unifying reference point. Similarly, McNally claims that intersectional theory is “haunted” by an
“ontological atomism” or even “social Newtoninanism” i.e., “the idea that there are independently constituted
relations of oppression that, in some circumstances, crisscross each other” (96). Against this approach, he poses a
notion of social reproduction theory informed by a Marxist-Hegelian understanding of an articulated totality that he
claims offers a better model of relationality for theorizing social differences. Here too it is surprising that he doesn’t
mention the core insights of many intersectional theories regarding the inextricablity or ‘enmeshment’ (Lugones) of
oppressions in people’s lived experiences, and in the world.
162
exploitation of labor (i.e., the class relation that generates value) provides a unifying frame and
causal explanation of social violence.)
Again, I am not contesting Marx’s critique of value, the indispensability of class as a
political category, or the need for labor struggle—but asking why understanding and confronting
the complex and interrelated forms of violence structuring our world should be thought of as
contingent on centering class in particular. Because similar arguments could be made about the
violence of colonial, white supremacist, cis-heteropatriarchal, and/or ableist societies—which
are, of course, often also capitalist societies, and vice versa—without thereby claiming a logical
or political primacy for any one of them. The political as such exceeds any one of these
frameworks, including class and labor, and including capitalism itself.
SRT’s insistence on the analytic and/or political primacy of class truncates its
perspectives on the ethical and political stakes of social reproduction and limits its ability to
center oppression. This is true not only in a critical, but also a transformational sense. Collins, for
example, roots her notion of intersectionality as a critical social theory in the experiences of
Black women and their collective self-definition and empowerment in the face of multiple
systemic oppressions. Her notion of a Black feminist standpoint is exemplary of the ways in
which intersectional theorists articulate new agencies, wisdom, and ways of reproducing social
life and community. As I discussed above, Collins includes ethics—and particularly an ethics of
care and accountability—as components of Black feminist thought and action. She also
elaborates on the political dialectics of oppression and activism, theory, and practice, that clarify,
motivate, and empower Black feminist theory and practice.
163
Black feminist critiques of autonomist conceptions of domestic labor—crystallized by
Angela Davis in 1971 and a decade later by Hazel Carby126—also reveal ethical and political
stakes of social reproduction beyond the lens of labor.127 Davis for example draws attention to
the ideology of the housewife and its damaging psychological and material effects not only on
housewives, but on Black, poor, and immigrant women, who who’s ability to reproduce their
own families meant undergoing even deeper, more intensive, racialized exploitations and
divisions of paid domestic labor (Women, Race, and Class 229).128 She notes the structural and
systemic degradation of such labor and the different, yet profound, impacts this had on women
for whom the normative notions of female ‘dependency’ so central to the bourgeois ideals of
nuclear family were never an option—indeed, as I discussed last chapter, bourgeois white
women’s willingness and financial ability to foist the most unpleasant domestic labors onto
women of color and poor women was a primary social and material condition of such
‘dependency’ As Davis notes, “Women of color—and especially Black women—have been
receiving wages for housework for untold decades,” and certainly did not find anything
liberating about it (237). From their perspective, Davis contends, we can comprehend that depth
and scope of the social reproductive contradictions of capitalism, and thus the social and
psychological harms inflicted through the capitalist privatization of the home itself. By centering
the experiences and social position of the multiply marginalized domestic workers who shoulder
126
See also Spillers 1987, hooks, Hartman 2016.
As Zhivka Valiavicharska points out, “The work of Claudia Jones, and later, the work of Angela Davis, Hazel
Carby, Hortense Spillers, Jacqueline Jones, Dorothy Roberts, and others traced genealogies of social reproduction
written from Black women’s historical standpoint, from slavery to the racist politics of the welfare regimes,
revealing a very different historical picture and political terrain (Jones 1949; Davis 1981, 1983, 1998 [1971]. They
showed that the ‘home,’ the ‘family,’ domestic and care work, and other forms of social-reproductive labor had
acquired different political meanings and social value in communities surviving slavery, racist oppression and
violence, and various regimes of racial and social control” (“Social Reproduction in the Making” 2-3)
128
Ferguson notes that “Contrary to Davis’ critique of the campaign, James made racialized paid domestic work
central to the UK Wages for Housework Committee political activism from the beginning” (Women and Work 109).
127
164
its deepest contradictions, we expand and deepen our political and ethical perspectives—
revealing, ultimately, the need to abolish not only the position of the housewife, but “housework
as the private responsibility of individual women” (243).
Since the publication of “The Black Woman’s Role in the Community of Slaves” from
her incarceration in 1971, Davis has expanded and deepened the lens of social reproduction. As I
discussed in the previous chapter, she has called attention to the normative and structural role
played by social imaginaries of domesticity and divisions of caring labor in maintaining a white
supremacist, patriarchal, and capitalist social order. By centering Black and other marginalized
women’s experiences, and unearthing their insurgent, even abolitionist, traditions of struggle on
this terrain, she also takes this work in new and transformative directions.
Hazel Carby also calls attention to how notions of reproduction and the family that center
solely on the gendered and class-based exploitation of unpaid domestic and care labor have
constitutively excluded the experiences of women of color—proving not only inadequate but
“contradictory when applied to the lives and experiences of black women” (46, my emphasis).
The sole focus on unpaid reproductive labor, for example, obscures the experiences of those
doing racialized, paid, domestic work, and thus the nature of the exploitation at the heart of
divisions of caring labor themselves. Since paid domestic workers are “providing for the
reproduction of black labour in their own domestic sphere, simultaneously ensuring the
reproduction of white labour power in the ‘white household,’” the concept of unpaid domestic
labor alone “is unable to explain exactly what the relations are that need to be revealed:” I.e., the
positions of the unpaid housewife presents a partial and incomplete picture of the relation
between capitalist production and social reproduction itself, and thus also a limited vision of
struggles against it. We must also ask about “how the black women’s role in… a domestic labor
165
force affects the construction of ideologies of black female sexuality… and how this role relates
to the black woman’s struggle for control over her own sexuality” (48). Likewise, like Davis, she
problematizes white feminist imaginaries of female dependency, which obscure the experiences
and labors of those who have often quite literally provided its material support, reproducing the
lives of others at the expense of their own.
Like Davis, Carby points to how Marxist feminist (and radical feminist) notions of
domestic labor, the family, and reproduction marginalized women of color and were limited in
their capacity to provide critical and emancipatory feminist perspectives. She also points to the
role of alternative kinship and family structures, as well as non-biological cultural networks, in
nurturing revolutionary values, cultural belonging, and political resistance in migrant
communities and communities of color.129 While she does not deny that “the family can be a
source of oppression,” (46) she also de-centers the “isolated position of white women in the
Western nuclear family structure” (51), and points to how the “black family has functioned as a
prime source of resistance to oppression” (46). From the historical terrors of colonialism and
slavery to contemporary state violence, the destruction of Black and indigenous kinship
structures (which often did not contain the entrenched sexism of the capitalist nuclear family) has
played an essential role in institutionalized racism (51). And yet, female led support structures
and kinship networks have been essential to survival and resistance against these forms of
oppression. While it is “important not to romanticize the existence of such female support
networks,” she highlights their key role in the development of “survival strategies” and “cultures
of resistance.” These are “not simple adaptive mechanisms; they embody important alternative
ways of organizing production and reproduction and value systems critical of the oppressor” (52,
129
These positions align with many queer and trans theories of care and social reproduction as well. See e.g.
Malatino, 2020; Spade, 2020, Marvin, 2018.
166
my emphasis). Autonomist feminists’ failure to recognize the distinct and autonomous
‘herstories’ of women of color—and the alternative modalities of social reproduction they have
already made possible—limits both the concrete solidarities and the visionary imagination
needed to re-claim and re-constitute ethics and politics on this terrain.
V. Conclusion: Traditions of Economism and Productivism
While perhaps most revelatory of that tragicomic animus revolutionaries save for those
ideologically closest to them, the fiery accusations between autonomist and socialist feminists
also illuminate their respective blind spots when it comes to the caring dimensions of social
reproduction. For their part, contemporary autonomist dismissals of SRT as a resurgent form of
‘Marxology’ (Federici “Social Reproduction Theory”) echo accusations going back to the 70s,
when autonomists claimed that socialist feminists wanted above all to ‘save their Marx,’
ultimately at the expense of the distinct and irreducible revolutionary insights of feminist and
other struggles.130 Alessandra Mezzandri, for example, claims that SRT’s focus on care labor as
“connected yet distinct to those of capital and value-generation” (“On the Value of Social
Reproduction,” 33) re-centers waged exploitation and fails to consider the informalized laboring
conditions of most of the world’s population—maintaining a Western-centric and ultimately
economistic perspective, and sidelining the productive labors of the “majority world” working in
underground and service economies. Socialist feminist quips against autonomists’ utopian
prefigurations void of political analysis are equally harsh and historically overdetermined.
Proponents of SRT claim that autonomists fail to theorize the complex mediations at play in
differentiated labors, and the varying degrees of subsumption at the level of private experience
130
Mies for example critiqued the “additive labeling approach”—“the tendency to fit the new feminist critique and
rebellion into the existing theoretical body of Marxism” (12)—on the part of socialist feminists in the 1970’s and
80’s.
167
that together comprise capitalism as a complex totality, and thus, ironically, resort to productivist
and essentialist perspectives on gendered labor and its transformation.131
Of course, productivism and economism are precisely the specters haunting the specific
Marxist traditions that autonomist and socialist feminist traditions, respectively, sought to
escape. Rooted in Italian workerism, autonomists sought to expand the critique of capitalism, and
by extension the scope of communist transformation, well beyond the point of production.
Pointing to domestic and other reproductive labor as itself productive, they thought, could bring
feminist and anti-capitalist struggle and transformation into all spheres of life. Their focus, in the
years since, on forms of commoning that can immediately reclaim, transform, and politicize the
realms of social reproduction stem from this anti-productivist vision. However, their socialist
critics are correct in pointing to problematic overextensions and blurriness characterizing their
analysis of these myriad labors. This is evident in early work by Fortunati, for example, who
reduces nearly all aspects of domestic and family life132 to capitalist production,133 and in
tendencies on the part of Federici and Mies to make de-historicized, blanket statements about the
‘commoning’ practices of communities leading struggles over land and resources. This
ambivalence vis a vis the socially and historically contested nature of reproductive labor is also
troublingly present in the trans-exclusivity implicit, if not overt, in some of Federici’s recent
work. Cory Knudson, speaking to this point, notes that while her earlier work “is audacious,
131
This dehistoricizing, they claim, poses a false picture of totally subsumed capitalistic social relations that can
only be addressed through utopian prefigurations and alternate ways of living, and thus sidelines the intricacies and
ongoing work of mass struggle itself.
132
Fortunati claims that the separation between reproduction and production is itself a mystification upon which
capitalist exploitation depends. For her, reproductive labor is ‘indirectly mediated’ wage labor, and that posing it as
non-productive is exactly the condition for the extreme exploitation of this work. From this she extrapolates, for
example, that family relations thus only appear to be interpersonal, but are actually capitalist ones (The Arcane of
Reproduction, 129).
133
I owe this insight about Fortunati, and autonomists more broadly, to Cinzia Arruzza, who pointed it out in
personal conversations.
168
rigorous, and wildly compelling in its unrelenting demolition of what we have been conditioned
to think of as “natural,” particularly when it comes to women and women’s body-politics,” her
recent work recants on this, claiming “feminism has gone too far in its de-naturalization of the
concept and resorting to highly troubling remarks about what she terms a ““body-remake
movement”134 (“Beyond the Periphery of the Skin”).
From the SRT perspective, the disavowed productivism behind the autonomist tendency
to see reproductive labor as either wholly subsumed by or wholly outside of production
overdetermines the logic of production these feminists seek to critique, and evades the complex
political work involved in collectively struggling against capitalism (Ferguson, Women and
Work 133).135 While this accusation doesn’t account for the nuanced coalitional and international
politics at the heart of autonomist feminism, socialist critiques of their undifferentiated notions of
capitalistic subsumption on the one hand, and de-historicized notions of commoning on the other
are often valid. These binaristic approaches to oppression and political agency alike muddy
autonomists’ approaches to struggle and collective agency and thus sidestep the truly politicizing
sorts of care, commoning, and “insurgent social reproduction” (Armstrong) that define struggles
on this terrain. For example, trans and queer efforts to reclaim and redistribute medical resources
and care by cultivating chosen family, social networks, and non-hierarchal infrastructures for
material and emotional support can be thought of as forms of politicized commoning which
134
As Knudson points out, what Federici includes in this term“ rang[es from plastic surgery to surrogacy and gender
reassignment”—posing sweeping parallels between wildly divergent issues and experiences that she claims betray
an uncritical“dependence on [the medical institution] that has a long history of cooperation with capital and the
state "'(4) quoted in Knudson 2020.
135
Ferguson notes that this move “dissolves women’s oppression into the economic logic of capitalist accumulation
and dispossession:” overdeterminintg it “according to its overriding drive to create value” (Women and Work 104).
While Ferguson is at times reductive in her critique of ostensibly ahistorical notions of gender division of labor
espoused by autonomists (“Women and the Subversion of the Community,” for example, is an overt critique of
capitalist divisions of reproductive labor), she is right to critique this approach to social reproduction as either
wholly subsumed by or outside of capital. I discuss this at length in the next chapter. See also Doyle Griffiths and
Aaron Jaffe.
169
strive, in practice, to de-naturalize care and reproductive labor and re-constitute more livable
social norms and gendered embodiments for all.
Likewise, the success of the SRT project hinges on developing explicitly noneconomistic understandings of class and labor politics that not only theoretically explain, but
politically center, oppression. Yet autonomists are right in that SRT’s attempt to build from and
apply Marx’s economic categories to reproduction risks re-centering labor politics and thus
reproducing the very forms of economism it seeks to overcome. Jaffe, for example, claims that
SRT can hold onto class as the “hard logical core” of contemporary social life “without being
narrowly economistic” because “[o]ppressions conjoined with exploitation, and not ‘just
identities,’ inform what SRT can mean by class” (Social Reproduction Theory 89). To put the
scare-quotes surrounding “identity”136 to the side for a moment, what Jaffe means is that, by
systematically linking oppression and class, SRT can “offer a materialist history of social
relations, one that recognizes the changing dynamics that condition all the possibilities to work”
(24). While Jaffe’s notion of ‘economy’ is expansive, and rooted in the early Marx’s notion of
freedom and an explicit appropriation of his broad, historical materialist, understanding of labor
power,137 it is still the economic relation between capitalist and waged worker138 that lies at the
heart of his critique, and thus, in proper Marxist fashion, adumbrates both the forms of resistance
136
While it is common knowledge, it remains crucial to remember that it was the Combahee River Collective who
initially coined this term, so routinely dismissed not only by the Right but also by the socialist Left. The CRC calls
upon an identity politics rooted in their own social experience, and a “healthy self-love” as well as a love for
community.
137
Jaffe quotes Marx’s definition: “the aggregate of those mental and physical capabilities existing in a human being
which he (sic) exercises whenever he produces a use value of any description” (30)
138
Jaffe spends significant time addressing a diversity of radical movements and intellectual traditions but nearly
always with reference to the economic relation definitive of class. Paradigmatic statements on this include: “Since
trans men and women, intersex, and non-binary people have compounding and different challenges at work,
different forms of gender oppression must be considered parts of working-class experience” (113); “Gender
therefore forms an inseparable part of one’s working-class experience and living personality. As a Marxist theory,
SRT can promote emancipation from the violence of gender as part of one’s class experiences and includes in its
strategic view the need to organize around different forms of gendered class disempowerment” (114).
170
needed to overcome it, as well as the socialist horizon beyond it—a world, according to Jaffe,
defined by free and differentiated labor powers. What then are we to make of the autonomous
and distinct organizing strategies and perspectives developed in the context of other
revolutionary movements (feminist, disability justice, antiracist, decolonial, queer, and trans
movements, for example)—especially those which run counter to those of Marxism, or which
affirm the political relevance or centrality of experiences, identities, and revolutionary horizons
that are wholly irreducible to work, or labor politics, no matter how broadly conceived?
Jaffe intends to further Marx’s critique of capital by pointing to the diminishment of
human life and capacities at the heart of its ‘valorizing logic.’ But his own position becomes
viciously circular to the extent that he fails to apprehend the diversity of struggles and tactics or
the political salience of domains of life and models of organizing practice beyond the lens of
labor.139 His socialist horizon of free and differentiated labors offers a wonderful political vision
but is limited by the specter of economism to the extent that it leaves little for the autonomy and
value of distinct social movements and political visions. Another example of queer and trans
social reproduction will help illustrate this point (see footnote 60). While Jaffe pays homage to a
queer and trans inclusive politics of social reproduction, his discussion is marked by its continual
reference to SRT and its class and labor politics—this may simply be a result of the framing of
the book (which is about labor) but I wonder to what extent he considers queer organizing praxis
beyond the scope of labor to be political at all.
139
Again, Arruzza’s elegant and nuanced understanding of class is illustrative here. In her preface to Jaffe’s book,
she notes that in his treatment SRT “allows us to develop a non-economic reductionist view of class as a central
agent for the struggle for freedom, a view that – as Jaffe stresses – takes forms of lived experience inflected and
constrained by various kinds of oppression to be constitutive features of what counts as class, rather than external
add-ons to an abstract and economist notion of class” (Arruzza, xii). To perhaps belabor the point, this is a rich and
crucial definition of class. But it is still class that is apparently the ultimate determinant and reference point for
political formation, knowledge, and agency: although the “novel and solidarizing” approaches of multiply oppressed
people “foster radical potential” (Jaffe, 9) they are seldom mentioned without reference to their class character.
171
For example, Malatino presents trans and queer care webs are an interesting case in point
insofar as he presents them as multi-faceted, singular, intersectional, and responsive to a
particular community’s needs. Sustaining such threatened networks of mutual aid and emotional
sustenance requires truly learning to value the care skills so systemically devalued by the over
culture. This network of care is explicitly political in that it works to center and mitigate against
the realities of oppression which result in unjust distributions of care labor and access in the first
place, as well as to uproot engrained expectations about who receives access to care, and who
shoulders its physical and emotional burdens. In this sense, such generative caring labor is
equally what Malatino terms an “infrapolitical ethics of care” (Trans Care, 43)—it brings local
and non-generalizable forms of communing (and perhaps undercommoning (Harney and Moten))
into play, which would be diminished or reduced if understood primarily with reference to
Capital or even the early Marx.
Anti-capitalist feminist demands for a social reproductive wage and organization of
social reproduction strikes are crucial, new, and transformational forms of political articulation.
However, the life-making ethics and politics of social reproduction at stake, for example, in the
care webs and forms of mutual-aid mobilized by various marginalized communities often
involve forms of embodied and intimate praxis whose political meaning may not be best
understood with reference to labor politics, even in this expanded sense. In the following chapter,
I elaborate on why and how the labor centric ethical perspectives developed by Marxist feminist
theorists of social reproduction have proven inadequate to the contradictions and possibilities of
care at the heart of social reproduction.
172
Chapter Four:
The Ethics of Social Reproduction:
Affect, Embodiment, and the Politics of Life-making
173
I. Introduction: Care in Crisis
In their epically titled article of the same name, Drucilla Cornell and Stephen Seely claim—
contra the sexually coercive arguments of a Central Committee member in Cornell’s socialist
organization in the early 1970’s—that there is, indeed, “nothing revolutionary about a blow job.”
This disturbingly banal anecdote of Leftist culture serves as a launching point for their
expansive, haunting, ultimately joyful, attempt to place political spirituality and erotic
transformation at the center of revolutionary politics. Cornell and Seely begin the article with
this example for a reason. The very fact that this militant leader could not only openly express,
but politically justify, such sexual entitlement points to the ethical need to transform how power
imbues the most intimate dimensions of life (1-2, 12). What would it have taken for this man, or
even his many comrades (who Cornell publicly addressed in a revolutionary statement of her
own) to comprehend the need for such ethical change, let alone its relevance for revolutionary
politics? In presenting this anecdote, Cornell and Seely also problematize what they see as queer
theory’s own nihilistic turn away from revolutionary politics—and even collusion with the
cynical and “antisocial” thesis of the revolutionary blow job. Their aim in making this
connection is to “return queer theory to revolutionary possibility” (3)—the “radical
reconfiguration of bodies and pleasures” (12) that is its inheritance.
These two examples point to what Cornell and Seely see as a larger disavowal, on the
part of the Left, from the promise of revolutionary politics. Cornell and Seely’s text is an urgent
call to return to these the transformational legacies and radical imaginaries and bring them to
bear on the urgent moral and political crises of our times. I begin this chapter with Cornell and
Seely’s injunction because of a similar problem in the Marxist feminist traditions I am
addressing here, and need to return to the “radical reconfiguration” of intimacy and power,
174
feeling and relation, that forms a crucial piece of its militant history and promise.140 As Cornell
herself pointed out decades ago, the narrow focus on reproductive labor is part of the problem,
insofar as it threatens to once again sideline care as a distinct and irreducible dimension of social
and cultural life-making (Cornell and Benhabib). If reproductive labor is merely the disavowed
‘other’ and condition of waged labor, it is unclear how we might engage in ethics and politics
particular to reproduction itself. This makes it difficult to articulate distinctively feminist, queer,
antiracist, decolonial or other approaches to ethics and politics on the terrain of social
reproduction. It also marginalizes the webs of interdependency that do exist—the “new patterns
of relating across difference” (123)—which Lorde argues are foundational for any meaningful
and transformative feminist praxis.
In the last chapter I argued that the politics of social reproduction cannot be reduced to
labor politics. I now turn to my ethical argument. I begin this chapter by briefly framing
autonomist and socialist feminist approaches to the crisis of care, which they each see as defined
by the structural contradictions of contemporary capitalism. Building on the arguments of the
prior chapter, I then claim that the labor-centric ethical paradigms developed by both traditions
foreclose serious engagement with the crisis conditions they themselves outline: particularly
when it comes to the paradigmatically reproductive labors of care and sex themselves. In the
final section, I advance the thesis that the ‘affective labor debates’ through which Marxist
feminists have attempted to address their own historical shortcomings around care in fact point
back to the limits of the labor paradigm itself. In this sense, this chapter mirrors the
argumentative structure of Chapter Two, in which I claimed that care ethicists’ naturalistic ethics
limited their ability to politically address the multiple and intersecting oppressions at play in
140
The vast majority of the Marxist feminists I cite identify the need, in the words of Arruzza, Bhattacharya and
Fraser, for such “profound, far reaching social transformation” (15).
175
many caring relations. Here I elaborate on how the labor-centric paradigms of autonomist
feminism and SRT have undermined these traditions’ ability to contend with the ethical
dilemmas and possibilities presented by social reproduction in crisis.
The COVID era has brought what feminist political scholars have long termed a ‘care
crisis’ into harsh and unrelenting relief.141 If it was somehow still permissible to miss the
political stakes of this crisis in the “before times”—the dire and systemic strains on caring
relations, the multiplying and widening gaps in care, the inequality on display in who is expected
to fill them and who’s needs fall through the cracks, the high stakes culture wars over which
social forms, norms, and institutions of care will replace those on the brink of collapse—it is
clear that window has closed. While social reproduction feminists were among the first to note
the systemic nature of this crisis, their ethical imaginaries have not evolved to meet the demands
of its complex and contradictory realities. On the one hand, as sex workers and care workers
have long made abundantly clear, reproductive labor, whether paid or unpaid, is work. On the
other, the forms of subjectivation, as well as “new ethical arrangements” of “bodies and
pleasures”142 (Cornell and Seely 2) that delineate care and sex as reproductive activities often
remain in excess of the category of labor. While their positions on exploitation (socialists) and
141
Emma Dowling beautifully outlines this crisis: “Deprived of the means, time and capacity to care for ourselves
and one another, we struggle to maintain not only physical but also mental health, straining to hold on to a sense of
self-esteem in the face of multiple pressures. A crisis of care means that more and more people are unable to do
these things or to get the help they need. A crisis of care also means that those who provide care to others are unable
to do so satisfactorily and under dignified conditions. To speak of a crisis of care is to speak of the changes to the
material conditions for the provision of care – whether within households and families, in communities, by public or
social services or through the market, private corporations and agencies. To speak of a crisis of care is to point to the
growing gap between care needs and the resources made available to meet them. To speak of a crisis of care is also
to look closely and critically at the kinds of ideological assumptions about human nature that inform not only
policies, but also dominant economic theories. In an unequal world, no crisis affects everyone equally. To speak of
crisis is thus to ask the question, a crisis for whom? It means to highlight class and inequality in the way the crisis is
experienced, and in the way that care is organised to entrench division and pit us against one another. It means
asking: who is cared for and who is not?” (Dowling 16-17).
142
Cornell and Seely cite Foucault in this passage, and indeed draw upon Foucault’s own ethical concern with
revolutionary ethical transformations of this sort (which they illustrate through his engagement with the Iranian
revolution) in order to trace a counter-narrative of queer revolutionary ethics and politics through Foucault himself.
176
ongoing extraction and accumulation (autonomists) are crucial for understanding the structural
and material forces driving the care crisis, their omission of these elements of lived experience
and struggle limits their visions for social change as well.143
The care crisis is not an abstract phenomenon—it is helplessness, resentment, dread, and
despair in the face of preventable pain and death. The suffocating impossibility of adequately
caring and being cared for is multifaceted and marks countless lives, but its most cruel
contradictions are borne by those at the end of the chain.144 We do indeed need structural
analyses of the capitalist imperatives to exploit and extract reproductive labor that are stretching
social reproduction to the point of collapse—and why and how this impossible burden comes to
be overwhelmingly shouldered by poor women of color.
But it is just as dangerous to take the ethics out of this structural crisis as it is to view care
as an apolitical ethics. Like the normative presuppositions of care ethicists, this structural
focus145 occludes both the ways that violence shapes and ruptures people’s relationships and
capacities to care as well as the agencies they mobilize against it. My call for an ethics of social
reproduction is thus not a return to moralism, but a materialist point about how the deeply held
norms and affective investments of care reflect and reinforce the unjust conditions of our
world—and how revolutionary values and “different ways of living-together” (Seely and
Cornell, 18) can enhance our capacity to change them. Living in a world that guarantees care to
143
Put simply, socialists call for wage reforms and welfare programs that promote more caring services and their
just distribution, and autonomists for grassroots practices of commoning and communization.
144
Those imprisoned or deported, as well as those who continue to hold families and communities together in their
absence (see Nadine Naber, Souzan Naser, and Johnaé Strong, “Radical Mothering for Abolitionist Futures PostCOVID-19”), those without homes, or for whom ‘home ’is a prison or a death sentence; the care workers who labor
without protections; the parents who’s children are snatched from their own beds or at the border, and of course the
children left in the wake.
145
Ferguson and Arruzza do stress the experiential dimensions of labor and thus complicate this structural focus. See
e.g. Ferguson, Arruzza.
177
so very few (Hedva),146 in which care is devalued and coerced under the banner of love, shapes
the nature, experience, and meaning of care itself. To paraphrase Mariame Kaba,147 both
structural and qualitative changes are needed if we are to address intransigent societal problems
like the care crisis. Socialist and autonomist feminist calls to better distribute caring labor, or
reclaim the commons (respectively) are necessary, but not sufficient, to this task.
II. Structural Contradictions of Care: Marxist Feminist Perspectives on the Care Crisis
Nancy Fraser most succinctly expresses the SRT line on the care crisis. Like other feminist
theorists of social reproduction, Fraser claims that the labor of reproduction is essential to the
social organization and reproduction of capitalist life, yet, in both its waged and unwaged guises,
has been marginalized and devalued along gendered and racialized lines.148 Like the ecological,
political, and economic crises of our times, Fraser contends that social reproduction is defined by
a “‘social contradiction” inherent in the deep structure of capitalist society” (“Crisis of Care?”
24). In order to generate profit from waged, productive labor, capital depends upon reproductive
labor to nourish, educate, care for, workers. Maximizing profit in the productive sphere depends
upon naturalizing and externalizing this work and indeed the entire reproductive sphere—
146
In Joanna Hedva’s words, “[w]hen being sick is an abhorrence to the norm, it allows us to conceive of care and
support in the same way” (“Sick Woman Theory” 10).
147
She notes: “First, when we set about trying to transform society, we must remember that we ourselves will also
need to transform. Our imagination of what a different world can be is limited. We are deeply entangled in the very
systems we are organizing to change. White supremacy, misogyny, ableism, classism, homophobia, and transphobia
exist everywhere. We have all so thoroughly internalized these logics of oppression that if oppression were to end
tomorrow, we would be likely to reproduce previous structures…Second, we must imagine and experiment with
new collective structures that enable us to take more principled action, such as embracing collective responsibility to
resolve conflicts…Third, we must simultaneously engage in strategies that reduce contact between people and the
criminal legal system. …Fourth, as scholar and activist Ruth Wilson Gilmore notes, building a different world
requires that we not only change how we address harm, but that we change everything…Changing everything might
sound daunting, but it also means there are many places to start, infinite opportunities to collaborate, and endless
imaginative interventions and experiments to create.”
148
Like other feminists in the socialist, SRT line, she claims that the particular “social contradiction” that defines
social reproduction in our post-fordist moment of austerity and finance capital is not straightforwardly an economic
crisis. Rather, it lies “at the border that simultaneously separates and connects production and reproduction. Neither
intra-economic nor intradomestic, it is a contradiction between those two constitutive elements of capitalist society”
(24).
178
feminizing it, segregating it from production, and devaluing it as such. Capital is thus dependent
on reproductive labor, yet at the same time, and as such, disavows and degrades it. (24). As
Fraser aptly puts it: “Destroying its own conditions of possibility, capital’s accumulation
dynamic effectively eats its own tail” (24).
Fraser claims that the ‘crisis of care’ is something of misnomer an “acute expression” of
capital’s crisis tendency in its contemporary, financial, mode. Care is a breaking point in the
contradiction between the drive to increase capitalist exploitation and extraction and the need to
reproduce the basic conditions of social life and subject formation. Defined by global, escalating,
and enmeshed economic, political, and environmental crises that render life conditions ever more
precarious—this financial regime of capitalism stretches social reproduction, and indeed
reproductive labor itself to the breaking point. With public services and institutions (welfare
services, education, healthcare, parental leave, the family wage, etc.) gutted, and women
“recruited into the paid workforce,” capital’s globalized, neoliberal regime is ever more
dependent on private reproductive labors. By “externalizing care work onto families and
communities while diminishing their capacity to perform it,” this regime instigates “a new,
dualized organization of social reproduction, commodified for those who can pay for it and
privatized for those who cannot” (32). This further devalues and segments reproduction, and
immiserates reproductive workers, while at the same time exacerbating crisis conditions. “Far
from filling the care gap” such ‘solutions’ merely “displace it—from richer to poorer families,
from the Global North to the Global South” (34).149
149
In her very recent work, Fraser seems to tone this argument down, and is not as explicit in refusing the language
of care itself. See Chapter 3 of Cannibal Capitalism How Our System Is Devouring Democracy, Care, and the
Planet—and What We Can Do about It. New York: Verso Books, 2022.
179
Fraser demarcates this crisis tendency from what she characterizes as the vaguely
neoliberal and individualizing language of a care crisis precisely in order to name the structural
ways that capitalist accumulation “free-rides” off social reproductive labors. Fraser’s intention,
in this sense, is to place reproductive labor at the rightful center of material and political life by
pointing to the systemic rather than accidental nature of the care crisis (Bhattacharya 12). Rather
than an isolated or random occurrence, this “so-called crisis of care” is, she claims, rooted in a
fundamental “social-reproductive contradiction of capitalism” (22, my emphasis).
While she is right to point to the structural roots of social reproductive contradictions,
Fraser’s omission of care from this crisis is somewhat telling. Fraser rejects what she
understands to be the individualizing perspective of care, but her extreme turn in the opposite
direction—to a periodized analysis of capitalism’s accumulation imperative—speaks to a parallel
problem, and indeed to a larger tension in her work. Melinda Cooper speaks to this tension in her
discussion of Fraser’s axial distinction between redistribution and recognition, which,
considering her recriminations against second wave feminism—and, we should add, queer and
anti-racist movements (“Crisis of Care?” 33-34))—for “having colluded with neoliberalism” puts
her in unlikely company on the Marxist left (Family Values 12). Frasers’s preference for
economic solutions (and aversion to ‘cultural’ ones, I would add) helps make sense of her at
times surprisingly conservative stance on the family wage—which contradicts her longstanding
emancipatory perspective towards gender relations.
Fraser’s sharp turn away from care, and towards the economic imperatives of capital, are
marked by a similar allegiance. These allegiances, combined with her cordoning off of structural
analysis from the living fabric of care and life-making itself, inhibits her perspective of this crisis
or its potential overcoming. With her “politics of economic security,” Cooper notes, Fraser
180
“seeks to imagine an improved family wage that would in the first instance recognize and
valorize women’s reproductive labor and perhaps ultimately disrupt the gendered division of
labor itself” (Family Values 12). Cooper’s critique lines up with with Fraser’s (somewhat
speculative) discussions of a “Universal Caregiver Model,” which she claims might present an
alternative to the family wage through a model in which “all jobs would be designed for workers
who are caregivers, too” (Fortunes of Feminism 134). With this position Fraser intends to
critique the sexist ‘family values’ (Cooper) normatively baked into the Fordist notions of the
family wage. She also intends this universal caregiver model to imagine more just divisions of
the care burden across race, class, and national borders. But this wholly economic solution offers
no politics of care—let alone sexual politics (Cooper)—through which such shifts in gender
relations might be made possible, or even imaginable.150
Autonomist lineages of social reproduction feminism offer parallel, if also somewhat
limited, approaches to the care crisis. Here I juxtapose Federici’s thoughts on the topic to
Fraser’s. Like Fraser, Federici argues that capitalism fosters a permanent crisis in social
reproduction (“The Reproduction of Labor Power” 14), but she diverges in that she approaches
this structural contradiction from the perspective of capitalist dispossession rather than
accumulation. This focus on ongoing dispossession as a key component of capitalist social
150
While they are more sensitive to these nuances, the model of universal care developed by the “Care Collective”
(Andreas Chatzidakis, Jamie Hakim, Jo Littler, Catherine Rottenberg, and Lynne Segalcall) illustrates the problem
at a deeper level. In their Care Manifesto, collective members call for a “politics that puts care at the centre of life.”
Their understanding of care is rich and expansive, and includes affective, material, social, and ecological
dimensions: care, for them, is “a social capacity and activity involving the nurturing of all that is necessary for the
welfare and flourishing of life” (11). Their universal care model follows from this definition of ‘genuine care,’
making interdependency and collective responsibility the keynote of social relations at all levels. While this does
add depth for a universal caregiver model, their definition of care is wholly positive, and offers only procedural
solutions—e.g. a better distribution of the services and burdens of care, and access to education—to what they too
understand to be the systemic and structural devaluation of care. Like Tronto, they thus point to the value of care
and the need for a more caring society that recognizes it. But, like Tronto, they too lack an analysis of the need to
ethically and politically transform of the caring dispositions, norms, and capacities fostered under such violently
unjust conditions.
181
reproduction is a key autonomist contribution, and has been developed in conversation with
indigenous, autonomist, popular, and feminist movements in Latin America and served as a
crucial touchstone connecting feminist and decolonial thought and practice. Most famously
popularized in Federici’s Caliban and the Witch (2004), this perspective radically extends
Marx’s notion of ‘primitive accumulation’ by pointing to capital’s ongoing imperative to extract
and enclose land, labor, and the conditions of life-making—as well as the depth and scope of this
theft, and its impact on the material and social, as well as emotional and psychic life of
oppressed people.
Federici argues that the enclosure of European women’s autonomous forms of lifemaking and material survival, and dispossession of their forms of knowledge and healing
practice, played a crucial role in the consolidation of capitalist wage labor and industrial
production. Her materialist focus on women’s labors and bodies, and indeed gender itself,
departs from Marx’s focus on commodity production and the “waged proletariat” as well as what
she understands to be his progressivist, developmental view of human history (Caliban 12-13).
The body is central to her account. But as Knudson notes, at least in this work, Federici’s notion
of the body is essentially political: for women, she claims, it is “the primary ground of
exploitation and resistance” (16). Like Mies, she also points to the structural relation between
this ‘housewifization’ of European women and the brutal thefts of land and bodily autonomy
involved in the transatlantic slave trade and settler colonial expansion. While problematic at
times in their generality, Federici and Mies’s arguments about the centrality and impact of
colonialism, slavery, and the witch hunts in consolidating the moral and political economy of
capitalism is a crucial theoretical and political development—pointing to the connection between
these brutal, repressive, forms of violence on the one hand, and the subjectivizing, disciplinary
182
forms of power that exist alongside it, ‘enclosing’ not only material commons and land, but
desires, collective forms of knowledge and wisdom, intimate relationships, and indeed capacities
for love and care.
The autonomist theory of ongoing dispossession offers an additional perspective on the
crisis of care, which autonomist thinkers also often construe as a “crisis of the commons.”
Reproductive labor, and the sphere of social reproduction more generally, is a primary site of
dispossession. Federici’s work converges with Fraser, in that they both point to the reproductive
crises and contradiction intrinsic to capitalist social reproduction. But whereas Fraser focus on
capital’s accumulation imperative in the valorization of value, Federici sees this care crisis in
light of the contradictions generated by ongoing dispossession. They also converge on pointing
to the historical and present links that this perspective of social reproduction reveals—between
capitalist, colonial, white supremacist, and misogynistic institutions and social form—and
Federici points as well to examples like austerity regimes such as the structural adjustment
policies and predatory debt that trap women in international care chains. Like Fraser’s incisive
analysis of the exploitation specific to the ‘dualized’ caring economy characteristic of capital’s
financial era, Federici illuminates the extreme impact of contemporary extraction regimes: the
“tremendous social cost” to the communities migrant care workers leave behind in their
countries of origin for example (17), and indeed the entire“ world regions marked for near zero
reproduction” (14).
Capital’s encroachment into the most intimate spheres of life is not limited to those most
impacted by the care crisis, however. Alva Gotby’s recent work on ‘emotional reproduction’
illuminates and expands on these points. “Emotional reproduction” for Gotby, “names the ways
in which we depend not only on physical acts of care, such as cooking or cleaning, but also the
183
feeling of being cared for.” Having one’s needs met in this way can be double-edged however,
particularly under the caring scarcity of contemporary reproductive regimes: “[r]eproduction
under capitalism assumes emotional investment in this society.” Moreover, “[it] is through
normative forms of care that we come to form attachments to society as it is and learn to desire
the reproduction of the world as we know it” (Gotby, my emphasis).
Autonomists have long pointed to the moral and emotional economies absorbing capital’s
externalized reproductive burdens: from the loneliness and isolation, loss of sexual and psychic
agency, and the humiliations of uni-directional care to the “anguish” that the so-called
“globalization of care” causes for migrant women (“Reproduction of Labor Power” 17), or the
fear and despair of those—migrant people, incarcerated, houseless, mentally ill—systemically
deprived access to social care. Like sexual norms, these normative burdens and distributions of
care shape our most intimate desires and relations: subjectivizing us as properly caring subjects,
or as properly expectant of care. These are difficult bonds to transform, and to break.151
Unfortunately, for all that she offered to these debates, Federici’s response to the care crisis, like
Fraser’s, largely remains within the scope of the problems she raises.
III. The Ethics of Labor: Two Perspectives
The political and economic crisis of care is equally a moral crisis: a fracturing and reconsolidation of what it means to belong in, and to, a shared world. Cornell and Steelly’s call for
a renewed revolutionary ethos is in large part motivated by this crisis: a widespread and
“legitimate fear of ethical collapse”—a fear of “…the disintegration of anything like a shared
ethical world—including ethical forms of caring for ourselves and for others” (119). This fear,
151
Federici ends “Why Sexuality is Work” with the following words, which recall feminist consciousness raising
groups: “Indeed, it has taken a lot of struggle and a leap of power on our side to finally begin to admit that nothing
was happening” (27).
184
they claim, is shared across the political spectrum, and lies at the root of many of the terrifying
forms of reaction consolidating in the face of the escalating and interwoven crises that Fraser
points to. Indeed, as Gotby points out, the normative forms of care through which we strive for a
modicum of emotional safety in a frightening world also teach us to desire and find comfort in
this world as it is. It is a grave mistake, indeed a moral failure, to isolate these ethical dimensions
of social reproduction from the social and political ones that Marxist feminists have so astutely
outlined.
Several social reproduction theorists have indeed articulated ethical frames for thinking
about care and social reproductive crisis. But insofar as they are rooted in the labor-centric
politics I discussed in the prior chapter, their respective ethical perspectives do not, indeed
cannot, properly address the social reproductive contradictions and possibilities they claim define
the care crisis. While these critiques can be extended to these schools of thought more broadly, I
develop my argument in conversation with the work of Federici and Aaron Jaffe—two thinkers
who have developed these ethical perspectives the furthest.
Federici contextualizes her ethics in relation to capital’s ongoing subsumption of social
reproduction and calls for forms of commoning and collectivization that both reclaim and
transform reproductive labors and relations. However, indigenous, and other marginalized
women’s labors often form the normative ideal for such ethical transformations—a move which
de-historicizes and reifies ostensibly non-subsumed subsistence economies and labors. Jaffe on
the other hand approaches ethics through a Marxian, critical approach, which understands labor
as “the first premise of all human history,” but also resurrects and deepens the early, humanist,
Marx’s premise that labor powers—the productive, life-making activity that forms the flesh and
blood of this history—are limited and debilitated by capitalist accumulation. This critical
185
perspective, he claims, presents labor power itself as the “normative imperative” grounding
SRT’s political philosophy. However, by subsuming ethics under the category of labor, he
reduces social transformation to the very categories of political economy he seeks to critique.
Both Federici and Jaffe articulate their ethics through the Marxist category of labor
power. But whereas Jaffe understands labor power as itself ethically normative, Federici’s
position is largely negative: for her this “abstraction” (labor power) defines the conditions we
must overcome. While sympathetic to the feminist criticisms launched by the likes of Benhabib
and Cornell—who claimed that characterizing feminized labors in these Marxist terms robs them
of their specificity as life-making activities which produce living human beings and relations—
Federici defends her use of this category against them (“The Reproduction of Labor-Power” 8).
On the one hand, she continues to do so precisely to draw attention to reproductive labor’s unfree
nature under capitalism: “To the extent that directly or indirectly it is exchanged for a wage,
reproductive work is, at all points, subjected to the conditions imposed on it by the capitalist
organization and relations of production” (8). At the same time, she, like Jaffe, contends that it
offers a critical perspective: attending to the “duality” and “contradiction inherent in
reproductive labor” as both life-making and exploited is politically empowering and disruptive.
Understanding the tensions and antagonisms inherent to this labor can aid us in deepening and
expanding feminist struggles against these unlivable conditions, motivate us to cultivate more
life-affirming forms of kinship and community, and illuminate potential nodes of solidarity with
others struggling for the social and material re-organization of society (8-9).
As Ferguson points out, Federici is “careful not to endorse just any cooperative venture”
but “elaborates upon and qualifies the concept of a revolutionary commons” (Women and Work
131). However, when it comes to outlining the ethical dimensions of this collectivization and
186
antagonism, her discussion takes on some of the dualistic implications that socialist feminists
have accused her of.152 On the one hand, as Ferguson and Doyle-Griffiths note, she often does
not differentiate between various kinds of reproductive labors (and, for them, between productive
and reproductive labor, although I continue in my agnosticism on this distinction). In doing so,
she, like other autonomists, over-extends the Marxist concept of ‘subsumption’—which they
understand as an ironically productivist instinct to simplify and overdetermine capital’s sway
over social and life and relations. But, as Ferguson and Doyle-Griffiths point out, this logic of
subsumption implies that resistance to capital must come from “outside” it. While they do not
mention her recent work, this stance is also evident in Federici’s radical differentiation of
capitalist social reproduction from the ostensibly non-subsumed, subsistence labor of women and
others working outside formal economies, who she imagines “are not yet disconnected from the
life economy by their work” (“Reproduction of Labor Power” 1)
Federici intends to center the unwaged, subsistence, labor of women in the Global South
as the disavowed “underpinning of the world economy,” which Marxist theorists ignore at the
peril of their revolutionary project (2). However, her arguments become problematic insofar as
she re-asserts a duality between the non-subsumed reproductive activities of those who “serve
life not commodity production” (1) and subsumed reproductive labor. This move places such
‘life-economies’ at the normative heart of social reproduction, but also outside, or beyond, the
contradiction, struggle, and perhaps even coalition, pointed to above.
152
As I mentioned above, some of these accusations, like those autonomists level against SRT, tend towards strawmanning—for example, the insistence that Federici and other autonomists rely on an ahistorical notion of gender
divisions of labor when they clearly do not, and the persistent claim that they remain beholden to the concept of
domestic labor when they have spent decades engaging in anticolonial, sex worker, and other struggles on the terrain
of social reproduction.
187
Federici clearly thinks that ethics emerges in relation to the antagonisms and possibilities
of social reproductive struggles: it is only through the “re-appropriation and re-collectivization”
(20) “the ‘commoning’ of the material means of reproduction”—that “collective interest and
mutual bonds are created” (Re-enchanting the World, 108). The alternative economies through
which indigenous, migrant, and land-based communities have managed, against great odds, to
defend their land, resources, and communal forms of life from extreme forms of capitalist
dispossession and enclosure form a guide for such revolutionary activity. Those engaged in such
struggles have, she claims, cultivated alternative, and deeply ethical, forms of life-making at the
margins—forms of collective responsibility and care that must be politically recognized,
centered, and materially supported. The ‘commons’ cultivated through forms of mutual aid, land
reclamation, community access, resource and knowledge sharing, infrastructure building,
communal cooking and healthcare, etc., are not just material. They offer glimpses into what it
means to transform reproduction “from a stifling, discriminating activity into the most liberating
and creative ground of experimentation in human relations” (“Reproduction of Labor-Power”
19-20).
Such “revolutionary commons” are politically transformative and instigate a profound
shift in ethical life. These two tasks seem mutually-reinforcing in much of Federici’s work:
“cooperative forms of reproduction are so important” because “they pave the way for a world
where care for others can become a creative task rather than a burden… [and] also break down
the isolation that characterizes the process of our reproduction, creating those solidarity bonds
without which our life is an affective desert and we have no social power” (Re-enchanting the
World 184-85). By subverting capitalism’s individualization of desires and needs (184) we can
also change the “quality” of our relationships to self and others. Such forms of cooperation and
188
struggle concretely engender new forms of collective self-determination, and their
“consciousness raising effects” also bring forth new ethical horizons: requiring us to “take a
stand and define one’s principles of social and ethical behavior” (3). Our ethics are clarified and
dignified in the process of collectively reclaiming and re-organizing reproduction. But such
emergent ethics are also what motivate and inspire the struggle for collective freedom.
But the dualism that socialists note in Federici’s concept of reproductive labor bleeds into
her ethics too, and this blurs the lines of antagonism and solidarity she intends to bring into
relief. On the one hand, Federici has been an instrumental force in naming the structural forces
shaping social reproduction politics—including biological reproduction, which she claims, like
feminized labor more broadly, is a historical and social rather than natural phenomenon (23)153—and also in supporting an astonishing, and global, array of social reproductive
struggles.154 Unlike many Marxists, she does not shy away from the ethical dimensions of these
questions, remaining at once trenchant in her critique of the insidious forms of naturalization,
mystification, isolation, and sheer imperatives of survival that can inhibit revolutionary forms of
commoning, and also careful and nuanced about the complexity and cultural specificity of care
and reproductive work, as well as political agency (“Reproduction of Labor-Power” 16)
However, at other points she seems to negate this radical position—presenting idealized
notions of care and nurturance as given in the social organizations and values of subsistence
economies. When discussing the reproductive activities of those she sees at the forefront of
reproductive struggles globally, and whose ways of living and relating form the ultimate ethical
153
This tension in Federici’s work between a naturalized and ahistorical ideal of the commons and the commons as a
product of struggle (Re-Enchanting the World 87) charts with Knudson’s critique of Federici’s recent, disturbingly
TERF adjacent, discussions of gendered embodiment that I discussed in the previous chapter.
154
Anecdotally, I have witnessed her remain humbly and actively engaged in various organizations and struggles in
both NYC and the Bay Area over the last decade and a half.
189
horizon of her politics, her historically mediated understanding of resistance and social
transformation gives way to naturalized notions of care and the commons.155 By placing the
reproductive activities of indigenous women and women in the Global South outside the
subsuming logic of labor power, she also homogenizes these activities and places them outside
history and thus struggle—unlike other social reproductive labors, they appear, by her lights, to
remain untainted by capitalist forms of embodiment and relation. This is an unfortunate,
colonially inflicted move that works against the solidarities she has forged over decades of
organizing. By conceiving of reproductive labor as either wholly subsumed in the service of
capital or an unmediated, directly life-sustaining activity outside of it—and reducing ethics to
both—Federici distances her analysis from lived experiences and potential solidarities of those
who toil to sustain this world, and who can thus collectively work to reclaim it.
In posing a dichotomy between those areas of life subsumed by the dictates of capitalist
production and those that somehow escape it, Federici’s labor-based ethics pose such questions
in terms of an impossible dualism of productivism and naturalism that belies the visionary
perspectives on structural and intimate transformations that have defined autonomist feminist
approaches to the politics of social reproduction. To simply value the unwaged work of women
underpinning the world economy, is to take them out of history and thus their own ethical agency
and political struggles. And dichotomously opposing these labors to those that are subsumed by
the capitalist form of labor power repeats the same logic in reverse, equally limiting the
155
This is specifically evident in her notion that subsistence labor is “not yet disconnected from the life economy”
and serves “life not commodity production” (“The Reproduction of Labor Power” 1). In a broader sense, it is also
evident, for example, when she juxtaposes Marx’s totalizing historical moves with her own, referring for example to
“the power emerging from the communal organization of life of millions in Africa, Asia, Oceania, and the
Americas” (Re-Enchanting the World 32), or in references to the “communal outlook, that valued cooperation group
identity, and culture” she claims is common to Native American cultures (80). These points may be right on some
level, but their level of generality, combined with the generality of their application to her claims the commons and
collective life, nonetheless support my claim.
190
imaginaries we bring to the crisis conditions of care. In each case, ethics is isolated from
reproductive labors and relations themselves—seemly possible only beyond the politics of social
reproduction in its concrete and material existence, rather than integral to the sustained,
multidimensional, learning required to reproduce life and struggle in alignment with new visions
of justice and care.
I now turn to Jaffe, who, from another angle, also subsumes ethics under existing
categories of political economy without giving adequate attention to the actual complexities of
caring relations or the shifts in perspective needed to center and transform them in political
movements. Whereas Federici isolates the domain of ethics from labor power—which she
understands as a capitalistic organization of labor—and thus places the possibility of ethics in
idealized notions of subsistence economies and alternative reproductive relations, Jaffe insists on
the critical and normative power of labor power itself. Jaffe’s approach too can be seen as an
attempt to ethically address the social reproductive contradictions at the root of the crisis of care.
In her foreword to his book, Arruzza defends and clarifies his reasons for doing so: like Federici,
he aims to ethically elaborate the contradictions and fissures structural to capitalist social
reproduction, and to root this ethics in the evaluative and critical perspectives that emerge from
lived and collective experiences of struggle (Social Reproduction Theory x-xii).
Jaffe is explicit in his intention to develop, and make explicit, the ethics implicit in SRT’s
commitment to theorizing an internal relation between capitalist accumulation and structural
forms of oppression, and thus ultimately between labor struggles and social justice movements
(2-3). Drawing on the expansive vision of labor power he and others find in the early Marx, as
well as the critical method of Marx’s Capital, he sets out to critically and ethically illuminate
191
SRT’s expansive and liberatory view on labor.156 The non-reductionistic lens of social
reproduction enables both perspectives, he claims, while avoiding the pitfalls of orthodox
Marxism. Labor power, following Marx, is simply the “human capacity to satisfy needs.” SRT
expands what we mean by this both critically and generatively—by showing how the capitalistic
organization of both productive and reproductive labor violently limits these human capacities,
and pointing to an expanded, anti-oppressive, vision of class politics and socialist emancipation.
Labor power, for Jaffe, both unifies SRT’s critique of oppression and exploitation, and
illuminates its emancipatory horizon. The concept of labor power, he claims, can do this heavy
lifting because of its simultaneously descriptive, critical, and normative value. As need-satisfying
activities, labor powers form “the real basis of any social organization in the first place” (48).
According to Marx, these needs are themselves historical and social: a fact that capitalism, as a
mode of production geared to the systemic exploitation of labor power, radically profits off of,
stunting both our capacities, and our ability to meet our own and each other’s needs, at both
individual and societal levels. As opposed to a naturalistic account of human nature or a
fragmented notion of oppression, Jaffe thinks that this view on labor power offers a historical
materialist basis for critiquing and elaborating the core contradictions of capitalist production
and social reproduction, as well as an emancipatory and ethical view to liberating human
capacities and meeting human needs. As Arruzza notes, Jaffe’s book intervenes into the moral
crisis acutely manifest in the dueling ethical visions of covid era US: the far-right individualist
ethos “openly endorsing ableism and social Darwinism for the sake of “liberty” and of the
“economy” on the one hand, and “the emergence and proliferation of forms and groups of mutual
156
He quotes, and follows, Bhattacharya on this point: “the fundamental insight of Social Reproduction Theory is,
simply put, that human labor is at the heart of creating or reproducing society as a whole. The notion of labor is
conceived here in the original sense in which Karl Marx meant it as ‘the first premise of all human history’”
(“Introduction” 2).
192
aid and social reproduction from below” sustaining the historic BLM uprisings on the other (ixx). His ethical position, she claims, “addresses two key questions: first, why capitalism harms
our living personality, hence what are the grounds of our anti-capitalist critique; and second,
what is conducive to the flourishing of our individual powers and to the realization of our
potentialities in such a way that others’ living personalities are also enhanced, based on the
recognition that we are socially interdependent beings and not social monads” (xi).
In his article on the same topic, Jaffe explains that his “normative commitment to labor
power” moves beyond the “productivism, ableism, and narrow versions of workerism that are
often leveled against left commitments to labor power” (“Social Reproduction Theory and the
Form of Labor Power” 1). Rather, “Those drawing from a social reproduction analysis can hold
that the plural nature of our powers, and the scope of their free development, is valuable in itself”
(8). This full and plural development of our powers is what motivates his account of a free
society. This normative commitment, he claims, also allows us to critique “the ways capitalist
social relations produce and reproduce labor power… [in] highly disempowering ways” (9):
which speaks to the first point Arruzza notes, namely, the specific harms of capitalism and thus
the grounds of anti-capitalist critique. He develops his positive ethical position from this dual
perspective: the intrinsic value of labor powers on the one hand, and the critique of their
capitalist form on the other. The normative grounding offered by labor power “could then center
our capacities as a key to unlocking further radical political commitments” (8). Through the lens
of labor power, now expanded to include reproductive labor, the justification for a socialist
society becomes clear: “freer social relations are just those through which labor powers and the
social dynamics of their actualization would be transformed from circuits of exploitation and
oppression to causes of their greatest possible freedom” (11).
193
Whereas Federici refuses the positive normative value of labor power, locating ethics
wholly beyond it in forms of non- and anti-capitalist social reproduction, Jaffe draws on a
Marxist critical methodology combined with a broad, humanistic conception of labor derived
from the early Marx, to both critique the capitalist organization of labor and to illuminate a
socialist horizon in which basic human needs are met, and we are free to express our diverse
labor powers unencumbered by the truncating effects of capital’s accumulation imperative.
However, Jaffe’s analysis does very little to illuminate the ethical problems and possibilities
specific to social reproduction itself. Already the implicit referent for social reproduction
politics, labor is now seen to encompass its normative vision as well. Rebranded as human
capacity and power itself, it circumscribes not only critique but ethical transformation on this
terrain.
As with the labor politics I discussed in the last chapter, the problem lies not in Jaffe’s
ethical commitment to labor, but in its overextension into terrains of life and struggle that it does
little to illuminate and can even obscure. In other words, Jaffe provides a powerful, though
limited ethics, and would likely provide a helpful normative basis in organizing for participatory
union politics, for example. Or, like Fraser’s universal caregiver model, as the basis for economic
reforms aiming at more just distributions of care. It becomes problematic however, when seen as
uniquely capable of analyzing and critiquing a vast array157 of the experiences, relations,
institutions, and infrastructures that comprise social reproduction. The problem deepens when it
is conceived as the normative basis for unifying such diverse experiences. Again, labor power
may indeed be a relevant ethical perspective in certain contexts. But it might illuminate very
157
Jaffe claims SRT is well suited to issues as diverse as analyzing “family structured care work in the
contemporary context,” (4), critiquing gendered divisions of labor (4), and especially “unifying social movements
and labor struggles together” (2).
194
little that is particular about, for example, the extra-economic oppressions defining a situation of
intimate partner violence,158 or the compounding risk one faces when doing paid reproductive
labor in criminalized, unregulated, or unprotected economies. It is even possible that viewing
such instances through a labor-based normative frame might reduce the specific ethical problems
they raise, and thus obscure the racist or misogynistic logics at play.
These critical, and especially normative, limits are especially stark when it comes to care.
The powers or capacities that Jaffe includes in his understanding of labor now seem expansive
enough to encompass almost all human activity, feeling, or thought, but an expanded conception
of human labor of itself does not clarify the ethical crises unfolding in the living hearts, minds,
and relationships comprising social reproduction. Like Fraser and Federici, Jaffe’s critique of
capital’s diminishment of labor powers can point to certain structural contradictions defining the
care crisis but is limited in its capacity to address the extra- or infra- economic dimensions of
oppression or struggle playing out in and through these divisions and distributions of caring
labor. Why should labor unify our ethical understanding of issues as multifaceted as the social
and institutional imperatives that distribute caring burdens along multiple and intersecting axes
of oppression? Or on the deeply engrained entitlements and coercions that accompany structural
inequalities in caring relations, or the intimate subjectivations that make transforming these
psychosocial dimensions of life so difficult to even imagine? While Jaffe’s normative
commitment to labor power might be powerfully illuminating, and inclusive, in certain contexts
and at a high degree of abstraction, it could just as easily eclipse autonomous, liberatory, ethical
transformation on the terrain of social reproduction when it does occur—such as in the insurgent
158
The same gaps in analyzing the specific dimensions of care also characterized autonomist perspectives on
domestic labor (which reduced it to productive labor). I elaborate on this point below in my discussion of affective
labor.
195
caring economies that sustained the most important uprisings this country has seen in half a
century.
By limiting the ethics of social reproduction to the Marxist concept of labor, Federici and
Jaffe strip these dimensions of life-making of their specificity, and ultimately reiterate the social
reproductive contradictions they seek to address. Reducing ethics to labor limits our
understanding of the care crisis, but more importantly, it forecloses meaningful engagement with
the diverse traditions of struggle and healing that have made radical transformations in
reproductive relations not only possible but actual.
IV. Moral and Material Economies of Reproduction
Throughout this dissertation I have argued that affective economies and intimate distributions of
care are formative in, and reflective of, how structural violence is woven into extractive,
exploitative and oppressive social relations—and that we must therefore integrate these intimate
dimensions of care (that is, the elements of life-making and relation specific to care itself) into
the critical and transformative perspectives we develop to confront systemic harms. Neither care
ethicists nor the Marxist feminists discussed in this, and the previous chapter have managed to
get political purchase on how structural violence generates contradictions in caring relations on
intimate as well as structural registers, nor do they ethically elaborate the sorts of transformations
that may, indeed already do, confront, and heal these constitutive wounds of care.
Care workers and sex workers are at the forefront of social reproductive struggles in our
times and bring crucial knowledge and skills to these questions. I now turn to a discussion about
what makes these paradigmatically reproductive labors ethically distinct from the normative
perspectives discussed in the previous section. I center on analysis coming out of sex worker
struggles to clarify some specific features of sex work as work, and at the same distinguish
196
elements of erotic reproduction from the category of labor. Focusing on the overlap and
continuities between paid sex work and care work159 will also help to specify what I see as the
uniquely ethical dimensions of care (and sex)—and thus of social reproduction more broadly—
that remain un-subsumed by this category.
The meaning and experience of care and sex work are shaped by contradictory and
mystifying imperatives; they are overdetermined as much by the expectations of embodied and
emotional intimacy160 that connect them as by the harshly punitive moral and criminal
economies that divide them. The isolation of these labors in private dwellings, their devaluation
and deskilling, and their removal, perhaps even more than manual labor, from intellectual labor
in the cultural imaginary, are also key factors determining both their ethical specificity and their
specificity as labors. Another ethically defining feature of caring and erotic labors161 is the key
role they play in the affective and embodied transmission of culture—-a point I elaborate through
Rosemary Hennessy’s concept of “affect cultures” and Sarah Ahmed’s notion of the cultural
politics of emotion. Together, these compounding factors shoulder social reproductive workers—
and sex workers in particular—with moral and economic burdens and expose them to moral and
economic harms. Finally, the relative dearth of first-hand accounts written by and for sex
workers (and care workers but to a slightly lesser degree) itself presents unique ethical
problems.162 There are many reasons behind this silence and silencing: including stigma,
precarity, the threat of deportation or arrest, the absence of a viable platform, and indeed the
159
On the specific labor struggles of care and domestic workers, see e.g. Nadasan, the work of the domestic
worker’s alliance (https://www.domesticworkers.org/), the excellent Spanish documentary ¡Cuidado, Resbala!
(https://www.serdomas.es/documental-cuidado-resbala/) and Chang.
160
I follow Parreñas and Borris (2010), as well as the militant feminist research collective Precarias a la Deriva,
who strategically complicate the binary of sex work and care work with their concepts of ‘intimate labor’ and a
continuum of care/attention/desire, respectively.
161
The term erotic labor was coined by writer and sex worker activist Thot Scholar.
162
This is especially acute when it comes to multiply marginalized sex workers, whose voices largely
appear in academic or popular publications to support the arguments of those researching them.
197
sheer incomprehensibility of sex worker experiences to dominant moral and political narratives.
The intransigence of the mother/whore divide is itself a reminder of the contradictions
that mark even the most protected sites of reproduction. Adrienne Rich speaks of the “massacre”
of possibility (13) that historically attends women’s socially sanctified role as mother. The cruel
paradox through which one’s only possibility is that through which all others are foreclosed is
passed on and “mutilates” the caring relation between parent and child (32) as well. Multiply
marginalized maternal caretakers—including paid childcare workers—often shoulder
contradictions beyond those of gender. For example, teaching one’s children to navigate, obey,
overt, and/or resist the oppressor’s norms, to anticipate their desires and whims, sometimes at the
risk of death. For those doing paid childcare, extreme and geographical separation from one’s
own children is the condition required to materially care for them. Even conversations among the
therapized few reveals that it is difficult for mothers to win. A mother must be selfless but not a
martyr, must suckle but not suffocate. An attachment figure most present in her seamless
meeting of need, and thus in her absence, she is often compelled to teach conformity to the
norms and behaviors that have degraded her, or that degrade others. As Lugones famously relates
about her relationship to her mother: “to love her was supposed to be of a piece with both my
abusing her and with my being open to being abused” (Peregrinajes 201).
And what about the contradictions encircling the counter-position? I am not a parent, but
I have performed both paid childcare and sex work. I was surprised to discover what others have
reflected too: namely, that the work shared a certain skill set, in particular its caring dimensions.
I recall, for example, a benign working encounter with an awkward man. It was my first time
working with him and he was not immediately forthcoming, so I knew very little about him.
Towards the beginning of our session, seemingly out of nowhere, he asked me if I thought he
198
was interesting and special. In the role of provider, the answer was obvious and my performance
automatic. Yes, I told him. He asked me to be specific: what was so special about him? I don’t
remember my response to this question. I do remember it felt inadequate and feigned, yet after
that he repeatedly, almost lovingly, pointed out how caring I was. Gwyneth Montenegro, a
veteran sex worker, states that the most important thing to her clients was the “feeling of being
needed and wanted.” Perhaps the cruelest contradiction of all is that despite, or perhaps because
of, the social necessity and particular skill involved in meeting such intimate needs for those so
entitled, sex workers themselves are criminalized and morally degraded—themselves treated as
disposable and unneeded in the cultural imaginary, many literally left to die and often blamed for
it (Troyan).
As I discussed in the previous chapter, the Marxist feminist traditions I engage in this
dissertation have a long legacy of sex worker solidarity. The ideas of both traditions have been
influenced by, and influential in, sex worker organizing strategies and campaigns. Autonomist
feminists have long stood in solidarity with sex workers and have organized for the
decriminalization of sex work since the mid-1970’s—they were actively involved in and aligned
with organizations such as C.O.Y.O.T.E., PROS, and the ECP, and also organized with sexworkers in broader campaigns around social reproductive justice and autonomy. Socialist
organizers of the feminist strikes movement have centered sex worker rights and labor struggles
in their political actions and platforms. In drawing connections between paid and unpaid
reproductive labors of sex and care, as exploited forms of work, and forging solidarity between
paid and unpaid reproductive workers, as well as workers across and between sex and care work
economies, these coalitions have offered new understandings of work, labor struggles, and
indeed feminist solidarity.
199
The global demand to recognize sex work as work, to decriminalize this work and grant it
the same labor protections as other occupations, is not new. But the narratives of sex workers
themselves are often drowned out by the pathologizing and victimizing frameworks of
criminalization and the global ‘rescue industry’ (Smith and Mac 23-24). Even potential alliances
are frequently clouded by the overdetermined legacies of the feminist sex wars—whose most
vocal protagonists, as Carol Leigh has noted, rarely consulted sex workers themselves on the
matter. As Molly Smith and Juno Mac discuss, sex workers become a “symbol” representing a
stance in someone else’s struggle: “Stuck in the domain of sex and whether it is ‘good’ or ‘bad’
for women (and adamant that it could only be one or the other) it was all too easy for feminists to
think of The Prostitute only in terms of what she represented to them” (24). This
instrumentalized framing of sex work on the part of various political actors eclipses the
experiences and struggles of sex workers themselves. Sex workers become stand-ins for cliched
positions on political issues that pose a “simplified binary opposition” between e.g., “Happy
Hookers” and “Exiled Women” (58). This further mystifies the structural conditions of
criminalization and stigma (Grant, Playing the Whore 75-82) and their material effects on
people’s lives (Playing the Whore 46).
Dichotomies between trafficking victim in need of rescue vs empowered sex goddess
who loves her work (and is thus not working at all) rarely reflect the complex and diverse
perspectives of sex workers themselves. These weaponized cultural narratives also obscure the
nature of this work itself—both its particularities as well as its commonalities with other labors
and labor struggles. Leigh spoke these points when she coined the term ‘sex work’ in 1978—a
term which explicitly “acknowledges the work we do rather than defines us by our status”
(quoted in North). This push to see sex work as work, to gain rights and recognition as a labor
200
struggle, has led to a well-reasoned emphasis on the dimensions of this work that are legible and
relatable to other workers. However, it is also distinct from waged labor, even in informal
economies, in several key respects. As Melissa Gira Grant points out, “the stigma and violence
faced by sex workers are far greater than sex work itself” (7). This is a crucial point. The
criminalization of this work, its gendering and racialization, its often intimate and intensively
corporeal nature, its stigmatization, the over-representation of undocumented people and trans
people without access to formal labor markets, the fact that, like other reproductive labors, it is
often relegated to private (or semi-private) spheres—legally and physically unprotected, hidden
behind closed hotel room or car doors—all render sex workers structurally vulnerable. While
assault by a client is of course one such danger, criminalization, police violence, secrecy, stigma,
and lack of labor protections are the primary dangers that sex workers face.
Struggling against these structural conditions has required far more than traditional
workplace organizing. Indeed, the class and labor politics of sex work cannot be disentangled
from its criminalization. As Grant points out, the decriminalization movement was initially
focused not on labor rights but on the demand to end police violence (22). Patriarchal violence
also converges with the state violence of criminalization, evinced in prolific anecdotal accounts
attesting to harassment, rape, and sexual assault by police officers, and a widespread sentiment
among sex workers that the police remain the greatest threat to their safety, and are not a
trustworthy ally even in situations of immediate danger. Beyond its gendering—most clients are
cis men, and sex workers are overwhelmingly cis women, trans women, and gay men—
racialization, citizenship status, gender identity, and disability differentially condition workers’
experiences in the sex trade. Trans women, undocumented women, women of color, poor, and
disabled sex workers are much more likely to be exposed to cycles of what Dean Spade terms
201
“administrative violence”—hyper-exposed to both intimate and state violence and harassment,
incarceration, fines, evictions, and the loss of children.163
These moral, legal, and cultural forces converge into a formidable weapon of patriarchal
and state violence.164 The structural dangers of criminalization are mutually reinforced by the
normative order through which the figure of ‘The Prostitute’ becomes, in Federici’s words, the
other “onto which men discharge their repressed violence” (“Why Sexuality is Work” 24). Grant
argues that the criminalization that renders sex workers disposable and (legally and morally)
punishable is, in fact, a key driver of male violence against women and gender non-conforming
people more generally (239). In perhaps no other occupation is one’s person so reduced to one’s
labors, or so morally condemned by them. Whether seen as depraved or as a victim, one is seen
as this profession in a way that few intellectual or manual laborers could be.
The moral and legal abjection of sex workers is a foundational tenet of rape culture. As
Cassandra Troyan puts it, “The presumption that she is a whore is a metaphysical presumption: a
presumption that underlies the system of reality in which she lives.” This presumption follows
from, and justifies, the lie: “A whore cannot be raped, only used” (Freedom and Prostitution 33).
If some women are whores by nature, it is a small step to assume they all are. And if you cannot
rape someone defined as such, it is a small step to assume that virtually any autonomous
sexuality on the part of a woman (whether in the form of desire or refusal) can, in Marlyn Frye’s
163
“In New York state…90% of prostitution-related arrests are of people of color. 1 Nationwide, 9 in 10 trans sex
workers or trans people suspected of being sex workers report being harassed, attacked or assaulted by police.”
Britta Love, in “Whores are Healers” https://www.petitmort.com/post/whores-are-healers
164
As Wilmette Brown notes, this serves a disciplinary function for women too: “part of the job of being a prostitute
is to be used as a sign to other women of where the bottom is”—women who may be envious of her relative
autonomy and ability to make money off of what so many otherwise do for free. An additional “part of the work of
being a prostitute must also be living with not only the contempt but the envy of other women for having the little
bit of money, the little bit of independence, they don’t have.” (“Money for Prostitutes is Money for Black Women”)
202
words, “be taken as proof that you wanted to be raped, and hence, of course, weren’t really raped
at all” (“Oppression” 11).
The instrumental role that criminalization and stigma play in reinforcing cultures of
sexual violence and exploitation has been lost on many feminists. Early autonomist feminists
were a notable exception—their early solidarity with sex workers and theoretical emphasis on
sex work as a fundamental form of reproductive labor veered radically from the dogmas of both
feminists and Marxists at the time and were formative in constituting the discourse and praxis
around social reproduction more broadly. Wilmette Brown, Margaret Prescod, and the Black
Women for Wages for Housework Campaign led many of these solidarity efforts and were
instrumental in establishing P.R.O.S. in particular (Prescod “Introduction”). In doing so, they
theorized and organized based on connections between sex worker struggles and other
movements led by Black women, such as the welfare movement and tenants’ organizing, and
drew connections as well between the criminalization of sex work and the exploitation of
women’s reproductive labor more broadly.
In a 1977 pamphlet entitled “Money for Prostitutes is Money for Black women,”
Wilmette Brown announces BWfWfH’s endorsement of the national solidarity campaign: “AN
ATTACK ON PROSTITUTES IS AN ATTACK ON ALL WOMEN.” She urges other Black
women to do the same: “the struggles of prostitute women against police harassment on the
streets, against fines and jails, against being declared ‘unfit mothers’ in the courts and having our
children taken away… against not having any money to call our own, are struggles that we as
Black women are forced to make” (1). She also points to the threat posed by sex workers’
relative freedom to racist and patriarchal institutions, and the disciplinary function of
criminalization, which works against the autonomy not only of sex workers but of Black women,
203
indeed all women, by ensuring their reproductive labors remain free or cheap. Making
connections between unpaid reproductive labor, the criminalized reproductive labor of sex
workers, and the welfare struggles led by Black women is an empowering move for all, “as
demanding money for our work becomes the rule, not the exception” (3).
Chanelle Gallant’s recent words speak powerfully to these points:
Sex workers control access to sexual labour and reproductive labour, and I think that one of the
reasons sex workers face criminalization is because they disobey the cultural demand to provide
free sexual, emotional, and reproductive labour. The penalization of sex workers is critical in the
coercion of free sexual and reproductive labour from non-sex workers, which is why the
punishment of sex workers is so visible. It provides this scare; a terrifying potential alternative
should women refuse those terms and demand compensation or even recognition for sex as a
form of labour (Quoted by Thot Scholar “99 Things to Know”).
Federici also names connections between the stigmatization of paid sex work and the
exploitation of unpaid sexual labors in “Why Sexuality is work,” as does James in “Hookers in
the House of the Lord.”165 All these texts make clear that condemning or victimizing sex workers
is an antifeminist move that directly hurts sex workers, and further naturalizes women’s unpaid
sexual and emotional labors. For this reason, organizing alongside sex workers for
decriminalization represents a major advancement for feminist struggle and solidarity. As Brown
stated it in 1977: “when prostitutes win, all women win.”
Sex work, like care work, is marked by contradictions that are structural and endemic to
the social reproduction of an unjust world. Like the social reproductive contradictions of care,
these too exceed the analysis of capital’s crisis conditions that Fraser, Federici, and others put
165
“The ECP has argued that there are many more financial considerations in our sexual relations than most of us
are prepared to face or at least to articulate to others. This reluctance to admit the connection between sex and
money in our own lives can express itself as a prejudice against prostitutes—whose job is to connect the two. This
prejudice against the women who strip sex of some of its romantic mystique is then reinforced by their illegal status”
(Sex, Race, and Class 111).
204
forward. Like care workers, sex workers must often develop a highly specialized, skilled, and
hyper-attuned capacities of attention. These forms of attention are multi-modal: they are often
intensely physical as well as emotionally and intellectually demanding. And, as with care work,
one must adapt these honed capacities, in real time and seemingly without effort, to the specific
desires and needs of the other person—both spoken and unspoken. Grant notes the affective
nuance, the labor and skill, that goes into reading and mirroring the desires of a customer, yet
also maintaining distance from one’s performance (86). This can be very difficult, and very
emotionally and psychically taxing, work—especially when you figure in the deeply troubling
and exacting taxonomies of body types and (often racialized) fetishes that dominate the aesthetic
economy of the sex trade. The more successful one is at such fantasy fulfillment, the more one’s
labor is disavowed as labor by clients.
What Elizabeth Bernstein terms the “bounded authenticity”—“an authentic, yet bounded,
interpersonal connection” —involved in various forms of commercialized sex work is deeply
intimate, and it is also labor (“Sex Work for the Middle Classes” 1). Once again, this kind of
intimacy shares many features of care work, in that it involves the capacity to attune to and
reflect the desires and needs of the other, while seamlessly keeping one’s own hidden, often
protected, from view.166 Cassandra Troyan and Maya Gonzales sardonically describe the skills
employed by the Girlfriend who provides an ‘Experience’ for her client by “deploying her
‘inherent’ skills learned through a lifetime of compulsory heterosexuality” (“Heart of a Heartless
World”). Like the reproductive labors of care, these fine-tuned skills and sensibilities are deeply
166
Elizabeth Buch discusses a similar phenomenon in how Maria Arellano, a home care worker who she interviews
at length for her book, manages, in spite of poverty and brutal working conditions, to navigate the “moral demand
for carers to set their own needs and feelings aside in order to sustain the lives of others.” Arrellano “used her
emotional labor not only to please her clients, but to protect herself from their hollow concern. “You learn to
swallow it, take care of it. Deal with it, give a little if you can. You don’t have to give a hundred percent, but you
could show a hundred percent” (Inequalities of Aging 10-11)
205
affective and embodied. And, like caring labors, they can be coerced, extracted, and exploited—
as well as mobilized in subversive and unpredictable ways.167
Sarah Ahmed provides a useful framework for conceptualizing the ambivalence
characterizing such labors, as well as the affective elements of care and sex that exceed the
category of labor. Emotions, for Ahmed, are not private or instinctual, but rather are essential
components of social reproduction. Feelings “do not reside in subjects or objects but are
produced as effects of [their] circulation.” At once social and material as well as deeply intimate,
they constitute and express the very meaning and experience of the boundary of self and other, of
a certain vision of ‘we’ and the role of the ‘I’ in relation to it. For Ahmed, “emotions work to
shape the ‘surfaces ’of individual and collective bodies.” (Cultural Politics 1). They are at once
the agent and the marker of corporeal boundaries and relational norms: “…it is through
emotions, or how we respond to objects and others, that surfaces or boundaries are made: the ‘I’
and the ‘we’ are shaped by, and even take the shape of, contact with others” (10).
Ahmed’s “cultural politics of emotion” provides a critique of their “psychologizing and
privatization.” At the same time, she is also critical “of a model of social structure that neglects
the emotional intensities, which allow such structures to be reified as forms of being” (12). Her
analysis on the profound role of affect and embodiment in political life extends beyond the
productive or reproductive labor of individuals: emotions shape and are shaped by social
narratives, values, and norms in profound ways. Although her scope is broader—encompassing
phenomena like political hate and fear, for example—her conception of emotions as a
constitutive dimension of social institutions and structural violence brings the trans-personal yet
167
Given the ambivalence and contradiction of sex work as criminalized labor that can also provide relative
autonomy, Grant describes her position as “sex ambivalent” rather than the binary terms of ‘sex positive’ or ‘sex
negative.’
206
deeply emotional dimensions of the care crisis into view, and the limits of a Marxist, laborbased, ethics in confronting it.
Rosemary Hennessy’s concept of “affect-cultures” offers another powerful lens on the
integral role that emotion, embodiment, and ethics play in the social reproduction of dominant
and subversive cultures alike. Affect cultures, she contends, are “an integral part of the social
relations and cultural forms through which needs are met… they permeate relationships and
propel action. They also amplify perception and cognition and infuse knowledge” (Fires on the
Border xviii). The concept emerges from Hennessy’s engagement with labor struggles in the
Maquiladora factories on the US/Mexican border, and the intense affective transformations
occurring through this organizing, largely led by women navigating fear and silencing as well as
coming to collective voice and courage in confronting the extreme and imbricated violence of
neoliberal exploitation, state repression, machista social norms, union complicity, and narcoterror. She defines affect culture as “the transmission of sensation and cognitive emotion through
cultural practices.” Her inquiry is deeply ethical and emerged as she “came to realize that
relatively little is known about the values that bind affect-culture to capital and that much is still
to be learned about this dimension of social movement” (xiv, my emphasis). The materiality of
affect culture is also foremost in her understanding, “and is inflected by the social relations
through which needs are met and produced” (50). I concur with Hennessy that there is nothing
immaterial about reproductive labors, or the values that bind affect-cultures to dominant and
subversive social organizations alike.168
168
Immaterial labor, for Hardt and Negri, “creates immaterial products, such as knowledge, information,
communication, a relationship, or an emotional response.” Affective labor, as opposed to immaterial intellectual or
linguistic labor, “is labor that produces or manipulates affects such as a feeling of ease, well-being, satisfaction,
excitement, or passion” (Multitude 108)—and forms the pinnacle of the “hierarchy of laboring forms” under
postmodern, post-Fordist, ‘cognitive’ capitalism vehemently disagrees with this characterization: “‘immaterial” as a
descriptor for caring and affective labor is a misnomer. Affects have a material force in that they are integral to
207
This concept of a collective affective culture emerging around socially and historically
constituted needs enables a deeper understanding of how violent regimes of capital and state
reproduce themselves in the minds and hearts of people, as well as the deep political and even
spiritual formation and education that communities cultivate in their resistance to them.169 The
labor struggles of sex workers and care workers are crucial, perhaps even definitive, of labor
politics in our contemporary moment. But the material realities and lived experiences of these
paradigmatic reproductive labors—whether paid or unpaid—are a crucial component of affectcultures and the cultural politics of emotion as well. As such, they irreducible to the ethics and
politics of labor, or the class contradictions that Marxist feminists place at the heart of the care
crisis.
Questions of coercion and consent, for example, lie at the heart of sex worker politics,
and present ethical and political challenges that, while fundamentally conditioned by economic
imperatives, are not reducible to them. Advocate and theorist Thot Scholar offers a potent
critique of how binaristic notions of choice and coercion in sex-work narratives continues to
marginalize Black and low-income sex workers.
Calling all sex work consensual or voluntary as a rule means that any negative interaction while sex
working that is non-consensual will either be lumped into sex trafficking (which will probably involve state
intervention and/or removal of or disregard for agency of the subject) or it will be written off as “stolen
goods” or the perils of the job. This is a way that the language of “choice” is used against us. It becomes
human social relations.” Moreover, “affects enter into exchange value as a component of domestic care that
reproduces labor power for the market and does so for low wages or for free” (Fires 63).
Federici also critiques this notion of the immateriality of reproductive labor. As an autonomist feminist in
the same tradition of Hardt and Negri, she certainly has stakes in the debate. However, while she is correct about the
intensity and complexity of reproductive labor, her situation of this labor as neither material nor immaterial, in the
sense that it cannot be broken down and mechanized like other productive labors, is problematic for the same
reasons that Held’s emphasis on the inadequacy of commodified caring labor: it reifies these labors and separates
them from the social and material life she intends to critique and transform (“Reproduction of Labor Power” 16).
169
Apart from her concrete experiences organizing with Maquiladora workers, Hennessy cites many influences to
her politically radical, queer and Historical Materialist understanding of affect culture, in contradistinction to more
faddish academic flavors of affect theory: in particular she sites Audre Lorde, Gloria Anzaldua, Alexandra
Kollontai, Wilhelm Reich, the Frankfurt School thinkers, as well as feminist practices of consciousness raising (3852).
208
more dangerous when you factor in rape culture and the politics of consent, and disingenuous when you
factor in class.
She goes on to explain that “consent is an ongoing process, and once you start saying things like
‘actual sex work is consensual’ you are wading into dangerous waters and running the risk of
erasing a large demographic within the community” (“heauxthots”). These narratives are
fundamentally structured by class and point to the need for labor protections. But dismantling the
rape culture that makes consent such a fraught issue for sex workers—indeed for all people
compelled to perform what Thot Scholar terms “erotic labor”—involves ethical and political
critique and transformation in social reproductive relations that cannot be reduced to labor
politics.170
Sex workers’ criminalized status, exclusion from labor protections and formal economies,
and limited access to social services, have compelled them to rely on informal networks, forms
of mutual aid, and knowledge sharing commons like “bad date lists” to survive. But these skills
are not only negative. What Evie Vigil terms “whore wisdom” might also be understood as an
instance of what Mattie Armstrong terms “insurgent social reproduction:” describing forms of
sex worker autonomy, resilience, values, and community care. Vigil states,
Sex workers already exist and work on the edges of capitalism. We come from and survive
through resilient networks and lineages that have created shelter, infrastructure, and possibilities
for our communities despite centuries of violence and criminalization. We are shape-shifters and
we are care-givers. We are very familiar with the implications of sexual and cultural trauma on
desire and empowered choice and voice. We experience and hold space for chronically repressed
and complicated fantasies and we practice and negotiate dynamic consent on deep
and…confrontational levels (“Beyond the Edge”).
170
See for example Alcoff, who argues that the “revolutionary social movement” represented by #metoo demands
survivor centered approaches to epistemology, ethics, and politics. She calls for “new epistemologies of rape” rooted
in the complexities of survivor’s own narratives, a “norming” of sexual practices attentive to the histories of antirape politics being used for racist and homophobic ends, as well as cultural transformation that enables new forms of
sexual subjectivity and self-making and work against the structural inequalities and power relations that condition
the possibility of something like enthusiastic consent.
209
The heightened sensibilities and resilient care webs that Vigil speaks of are often born of
survival. They also hold invaluable teachings on how to care for each other outside the system
and bring the life-affirming force of the erotic (Lorde) to embodied change. Sex worker advocate
and political healer Britta Love speaks to these legacies in their article “Whores are Healers.”
Their notion of healership does not reify sex workers or their agency in the binaristic terms that
Smith and Mac, and Thot Scholar critique. Rather, their ethics of erotic labor points to an openended, emergent, and situated “reclamation” of power in relation to a community of other sex
workers as well as “a refutation of a toxic, puritanical and patriarchal culture that denies the
value and importance of pleasure, of sex, and of feminized labor” and “a celebration of the
essential and valuable work we do.” The transformative ethics that Love outlines are not a
romanticization of sex work nor an “appeal to respectability.” While founded on the material and
social premise of labor rights—the notion that “the human and labor rights of sex workers are
non-negotiable,” their ethical position is irreducible to Jaffe’s commitment to labor as a
normative horizon or Federici’s ahistorical revolutionary commons. Rather, they build from this
premise, outlining dimensions of this reproductive labor that exceed it. They state:
When we see sex workers as healers, we move away from patriarchal understandings of sexuality
and make more accessible the healing power of touch, intimacy, play and connection. We dissolve
social shame imposed upon both sex workers and their clients.… We restore sex workers to their
historical role as valuable space-holders and connectors and allow the healing capacity of sex work
to be held more consciously and intentionally. We bridge the socially constructed dualisms of body
and spirit, pleasure and healing, sacred and profane.… We open the doors to accessing the full
power and potential of sex work, for sex workers and clients alike (including for sex workers and
femmes to have more access as clients themselves) – and the full power and potential of sex for all
(“Whores are Healers”).
210
Care and sex are both essential reproductive labors, and their mutual opposition and
degradation is a foundational social, material, and normative premise of capitalism—and also of
rape culture; the nuclear family form and the coercions of care and sex at its root; and the
dehumanized othering of racialized, colonized, populations that Lugones terms the
‘modern/colonial gender system.’171 They are essential to the cultural reproduction of these
violently normative ways of living, but also of living alternatives to them.
Sex workers have long made such connections and shown that struggles for the
decriminalization and labor rights of sex workers are connected to the projects of racial, gender,
and economic justice. Legacies of sex-worker struggle are rooted in and call forth dimensions of
psycho-social life and transformation—modes of healing, kinship, pleasure, commoning, and
mutual aid—that have implications for how we understand social reproduction and its definitive
contradictions and possibilities. In honing new sensibilities and affect-cultures, they present
living critiques and alternatives at both institutional and intimate levels. To conceive of these
qualitative transformations through the lens of labor is to flatten the ethical and political life of
social reproduction—reducing it to the very categories that have excluded care and sex from the
moral and political domain. For Love, labor rights are a basic and necessary premise and
protection, but cannot encompass the longings, wisdom, skills, and desires—the “new and more
possible meetings” (Lorde) that reproductive laborers have nurtured and made possible, even
here and now.
V. The Affective Labor Debates
This section elaborates my argument against the over-extensions of labor into the specifically
ethical dimensions of care and sex through an examination of the concept of affective labor. I
171
Thank you to Sandra Stephens for the insights on this concept and its relevance to my argument.
211
take Kathi Weeks and Johanna Oksala, respectively, as representatives of autonomist and
socialist lineages of Marxist feminism. Both theorists turn to this concept as a way of elaborating
on the specific harms of submitting intimate, caring, labors, to capitalist ends. While it does
clarify certain dimensions of contemporary labor economies, the concept of affective labor
should not be used as an occasion for yet another overextension of labor. My claim in this
section is that, precisely insofar as it does clarify many of the exploitations and harms specific to
reproduction, this concept also sheds light on ethical dimensions of care and sex that exceed the
labor paradigm.
While the concept of affect172 has been central to many recent academic debates, recent
Marxist feminist debates on the topic center on the need to redress the omission of care and
intimacy from prior theories of social reproduction—both in terms of its central role in
reproducing capitalist sociality and desires, and in forging alternative models of social
reproduction. This represents a crucial, and controversial, development in theories of social
reproduction. Federici and Fraser, for example, both reject what we might term the ‘affective
turn’ in feminist political theory. As I discussed above, Fraser does so to preserve the integrity of
her structural, Marxist, analysis against the market moralism common to neoliberal refrains on
the care crisis. Federici, for her part, contends that the concept of affective labor falsely divides
the material and subjective dimensions of reproductive labor, and thus diminishes the latter’s
172
The concept of affect has many origins, some recent lineages include: critical engagements with New Left
politics (Deleuze, and especially Guattari, Massumi); materialist feminist critiques of the social politics of latecapitalism (Hochschild, Berlant); psychology and attachment theory (Silvan), and the philosophical school of
speculative realism (Puig de la Ballacasa). In each case, and from various historical and genealogical orientations,
the term is a way to think of emotions beyond individual psychology—as constitutive elements of social, material,
and cultural life that flow between and among individuals. The common experiences of “reading the room,” the
feeling of things being “tense” etc. are ways of describing affect. Hennessy notes that the notions of affect so
routinely dismissed by Leftist academics in particular were themselves mobilized as a critique of the “vacuity” of
reigning political discourse. Whether and how it can stay true to this impulse remains an open question (Fires on the
Border 37).
212
status as a feminist struggle concept (“The Reproduction of Labor Power” 9). Since affect
represents only one component of reproductive labor, parsing these elements further mystifies
this labor and limits alliances between reproductive workers.
Weeks and Oksala, in contrast, insist on the centrality of affective labor to contemporary
capitalist social reproduction, and point to the analytical and political gaps in Marxist feminist
theories that fail to account for it. In doing so, they both rely heavily on Arlie Hochschild’s
original theorization of emotional labor, presented in her 1983 masterpiece, The Managed Heart:
Commercialization of Human Feeling. In her research on flight attendants, Hochschild charts the
commodification of emotions previously reserved for private intimate life, and the impact this
has on service workers’ lived experiences of self and relation. Over time, the imperative to
identify with a company image and indeed company feeling inevitably extends into a person’s
experience of selfhood. Although she points to the subtle subversions used by workers to resist
this subjectivization, her central aim is to chart the toll of the “deep acting,” “feeling
management” and ultimately the “transmutation” that occurs when private emotional systems are
subordinated to commercial use.
Of course, the private labors of emotion are also harmful—Hochschild outlines, for
example, the role of emotions in upholding gendered and racialized power structures, such as the
requirement to enhance the status of others, the virtuosity of which, like housework, is measured
by its invisibility. But she is most attentive to the uncharted tolls that commodification has on
emotional life, and the forms of alienation specific to this labor. For Marx, famously, the
industrial proletarian is alienated from his own labors, from other workers, from the product of
his labors, and from his species being. But the estrangement of feelings is not limited to external
relations and labors—it is not simply the upkeep of an outwardly facing, sunny, disposition
213
towards grinding, belligerent customers. For Hochschild, the commodification of emotion
alienates the worker from her own self as well “…when deep and surface acting are forms of
labor to be sold, and when private capacities for emotion and warmth are put to corporate uses,
what happens to the way a person relates to her feelings or her face?” (89). The answer to this
haunting question, she contends, is that this form of exploitation ultimately disrupts one’s sense
of having a private self at all.
Kathi Weeks situates Hochschild’s work, and the concept of affective labor, in terms of
broader feminist attempts “to expand the category of labor to include more of its gendered
forms.” Understanding how affective labor is “fundamental both to contemporary models of
exploitation and to the possibility of their subversion” (“Life Within and Against Work” 233) has
been crucial to advancing Marxist feminist thinking past the impasses of the domestic labor
debates. While she notes Hochschild’s instrumental role in this feminist project, Weeks takes
issue with the model of selfhood and agency that undergird her conception of alienated
emotional labor. Hochschild points to the subjectivizing nature of this labor, and thus avoids
romanticizing the private sphere of emotion management. But Weeks contends that her concept
of alienation presupposes a private self, prior to its estrangement, and with it an ideal of a nonalienated, “unmanaged heart” (244, my emphasis)—a move that risks re-naturalizing the
gendered logics dictating private life as the proper domain of feelings.
Analogously, Weeks notes the early methodological and critical advancements put forth
by autonomist theories of domestic labor.173 However, the framework posed by the domestic
labor debates—the question, “[i]n short” of whether domestic labor was “properly inside or
173
While she critiques the WfH focus on domestic labor, Weeks draws upon and is situated within the autonomist
theoretical lineage herself, and her critique of post-Fordist laboring practices also in many ways upholds Hardt and
Negri’s concept of immaterial labor, and the merging of production and reproduction that it presupposes.
214
outside capitalist production” (235)—has not adapted well to post-Fordist transformations in
laboring practices, nor to feminist politics. This is perhaps most evident in the omission of the
affective dimensions of reproduction—the emotional dimensions of care, for example—from
early concepts of reproductive labor, and thus from feminist critical intervention. In
dichotomizing or conflating reproductive and productive labor, the various parties to these
debates failed to grasp the gendered logics specific to affective and caring labor, and thus a
crucial component of social reproduction and the politics of its transformation (236).174 Given
these limitations, Weeks offers an expanded concept of social reproduction which includes, as
Oksala puts it, all the “forms of social cooperation on which capitalist accumulation depends”
(“Affective Labor” 287). This, she thinks, might open new vantages for immanent critique that
resist the temptation to abstract subjectivity and labor from their material conditions and
possibilities. Her position on affective labor, it follows, is meant to critique the increasingly
harrowing ways that capital harnesses and exploits the affective, desirous, dimensions of lifemaking, and elaborate the antagonisms and forms of agency emerging on this contested terrain.
Weeks’s position on affective labor is an extension and specification of her broader175
critique of the capitalist work ethic, and political call for strategically launching radical, antiwork demands through an immanent critique of the moralism and metaphysics of work. While
she contends that life is increasingly mediated by post-Fordist work conditions, Weeks claims
that we can also mobilize our living against its subjectivizing regimes. Continuing this line of
thinking, we can assume that in the case of affective labor, organizing around such demands
would involve qualitative shifts in our relationship to our lives and labors: as with work more
174
I agree with this assessment, both for autonomist strains of social reproduction theory and for socialist ones. Even
such beloved slogans as “what they call love, we call unpaid work” find little development at the level of political
practice and critique, especially in early theories.
175
She develops this critique primarily in The Problem with Work.
215
broadly, we should “insist that valuing it more highly and distributing it more equitably is not
enough—the organization of unwaged reproductive labor and its relationship with waged work
must be entirely rethought” (The Problem with Work 110). Applied to affective labor, such a
situated and radical politics could involve, for example, an immanent feminist politics of
desire—a collective, politicized subjectivity forged within and against the intensive demands and
divisions of this labor. More than a struggle for valuing or re-distributing these labors, this
affective politics of social reproduction would be a mobilizing of life against this regime of work
and a “struggle for a different quality of experience” (“Life Within and Against Work” 347, my
emphasis).
Johanna Oksala also claims that affective labor is a necessary category and should be
specified and elaborated by Marxist feminist analysis and practice. In particular, she claims that
the forms of exploitation and commodification this concept describes have crucial normative
stakes that must be clarified and attended to. The expanded reach and depths of commodification
represented in global care chains, for example, demand feminist theories attentive to the
differentiations between, and specificities of, the many and varied feminized labors that this
category encompasses. Thus, rather than expanding the concept of social reproduction like
Weeks does, she claims that these specifications of affective labor demand a more granular and
specific approach. While she applauds Weeks’s poststructuralist approach to power and
immanent critique, and supplementation of Marxist concepts with a Foucauldian “microphysics
of power” (“Affective Labor” 281), she argues that “feminist politics needs theoretical
distinctions within the category of affective labor that allow us to advance a normative—political
and ethical—problematization of our current forms of work” (283).
216
Like Weeks, Oksala thus calls for developing the concept of affective—and specifically
caring—labor, not through recourse to the separate spheres or reified labors of past feminist
debates, but through immanent critique and political engagement. Prior categorizations are not
up to the task: Marxist feminists must develop critical analysis adequate to the specific political
economies of affective labors, as well as the intensive forms of exploitation and biopolitical
regulation to which they are subjected. They must, for example, theoretically, politically, and
ethically account for the material specificities involved in different kinds of affective labor:
drawing analytical and normative distinctions, for example, between care work that is not
commodified, care work that is commodified, and the productions of affects in persons and not
in persons. This is where she finds points of contention with Weeks, who, by extending
autonomist ideas about the productivity of reproductive labors and their capitalist subsumption to
affective labors, Oksala contends, misses the ethical and political crux of the matter. Like Hardt
and Negri’s amorphous and politically suspect notions176 of the ‘multitude’ and ‘immaterial’
labors, Weeks’s expanded politics of social reproduction obscures rather than clarifies the
capitalist organization of life and labor. This is especially true in the case of affective labor,
which “for ethical reasons lends itself poorly to commodification” (295).
While Oksala does not explicitly align herself with SRT, her argument shares many of its
assumptions—in particular, her stance on the non-productivity of many social reproductive and
service economies, and argument that autonomist notions of immaterial labor fail to differentiate
between different labors, and thus offer little traction for normative and political critique.177 Her
176
See note 167 above for Hardt and Negri’s definition of affective labor as it relates to these concepts, as well as
Hennessy’s critique.
177
This is not an entirely fair characterization, as many autonomist feminists explicitly positioned themselves
against the male workerist tradition, and are at least implicitly critical of Hardt and Negri, and especially the concept
of immaterial labor—which Federici explicitly rejects as antifeminist.
217
critique of Weeks aligns with this position as well. On the one hand, Weeks’s concept of life—
intended to expand social reproduction beyond the narrow frame of reproductive labor—results
in the same amorphous, at once hyper- and de-politicized, revolutionary subjectivity that Hardt
and Negri espoused. At the same time, like Ferguson, Arruzza, and others in the SRT tradition,
Oksala claims that the autonomist position on capitalist subsumption reiterates the very
productivist imaginary it intended to oppose—and views affective labor too as wholly mediated
by the imperatives of capital. Thus, rather than a Foucauldian notion of productive power
capable of accounting for many distinct discursive and institutional practices, Weeks’s notion of
capitalistically mediated and socially productive affective labor—like the notion of the social
factory itself—overextends the very logic of production she intends to interrogate, ironically
leaving no outside, or only a pure outside, from which to launch critique (280, 287). This
obscures the heterogenous and divergent normativities through which capitalism itself is socially
organized and leaves little grounds for feminists to pose their own, alternative, values of “care,
solidarity, and justice” (289).
Care is at the center of Oksala’s critical and ethical perspective on affective labor. “While
the feminist movement has had some success in socializing and ungendering reproduction, the
biggest change by far in the conditions under which we reproduce has been the commodification
and globalization of care work. The gendered nature of reproduction has not changed at all.
Reproductive labor has only been redistributed to new female subjects—to poor, immigrant, and
third-world women” (300). By merging these heterogenous labors into an undifferentiated notion
of power or agency, the autonomists who first theorized the concept of affective labor have not
helped to clarify this situation—and their feminist interlocutors, Weeks included, risk repeating
these mistakes by advancing productivist notions of reproductive labor and an amorphous
218
conception of social reproduction more broadly. Feminist political projects and advocacy must
instead find ways to interrupt the invisibilization and isolation of these heterogenous labors by
rendering them visible and demanding respect for them. However, apart from rather open-ended
calls for feminists to develop alternative values, make critical ethical distinctions around whether
certain kinds of affective labor should be commodified at all, and organize to regulate markets
accordingly, her own contributions to this project remain underdeveloped.
While she does not explicitly critique the SRT tradition, or Oksala in particular, on these
points as far as I am aware, we can extrapolate what Weeks might say in response to this critique
from her broader work. As she does elsewhere, she would likely point to the limits of the
socialist, and socialist feminist, political imaginary, and specifically its failure to incorporate the
experiential and affective transformations that constitute a crucial historical legacy, and promise,
of feminist politics. Discussing the feminist legacy of WfH, for example, she notes that “the
feminists in the wages for housework movement rejected not only the capitalist but also the
socialist remedies defended by other feminists at that time” (The Problem with Work 126).
Rather than simply socializing reproduction, she claims, the autonomist feminist vision
“mandates an interrogation of the basic structures and ethics that govern this work and the
struggle for ways to make it, as it were, unproductive” (125). Like the socialist feminists who
limit their political vision to economic reform, and indeed the socialist humanists who pose labor
itself as a value178 (86), Oksala’s calls for the normative evaluation and market regulation of
affective labors do not get to the qualitative transformation of values, indeed of psychosocial
experience itself, that affective labor brings into view and indeed demands. In this light, the
178
Jaffe would be a primary example of this tradition.
219
normative assessments, and political interventions that she calls for run the risk of reifying the
very social norms and relations Oksala intends to evaluate on feminist grounds.
Some of these concerns play out in Oksala’s recent work on surrogacy, which provides a
case study in the sorts of normative and theoretical distinctions she has in mind. The intensive,
and specific, emotional, and bodily risks involved in physically gestating, and then relinquishing,
a child, she claims, raise novel ethical and political problems, that ought not be subsumed under
the Marxist notion of labor (“Feminism against Biocapitalism” 891). Surrogacy must rather be
distinguished from labor—including commercial care and sex work—and subject to different
ethical and political criteria. The difference between surrogacy and other affective and
reproductive labors, and resultant need to treat it on a different normative and political register,
hinges on her contention that surrogacy workers aren’t selling their labor but their bodies.
Surrogacy, Oksala claims, is ruled by a logic of expropriation which she, unlike autonomist
feminists, does not view on a continuum with exploitation, but, following Fraser, as sharply
opposed to it. “Rather than being instances of gendered exploitation,” surrogacy—like the
“prison labor, transnational sex trafficking, corporate land grabs, and foreclosures on predatory
debt” that Fraser lists as contemporary examples—should instead “be viewed as gendered and
racialized expropriation” (893).
Given Oksala’s call for feminist analysis attentive to the intensive, embodied, and
“capillary” function of power at play in various kinds of affective and caring labor, as well as her
emphasis on making nuanced distinctions between them, it seems strange that she would choose
to draw such a sharp line here. The problem deepens when we consider the content of Oksala’s
normative stance itself, which she sums up as follows: “Feminists should” she claims, “demand
not the institutionalization of surrogates’ status as care workers but rather the institutionalized
220
recognition that their status is significantly different from that of other care workers due to the
specificity of their kinship tie to the child” (900). She specifies that she is calling on a
denaturalized notion of kinship, which “emphasizes the everyday affective labor involved in
forming and maintaining” these ties over genetic relations (898). But this is simply to restate the
problem: why should biological reproduction constitute the line morally distinguishing surrogacy
from the “everyday” affective and embodied labors of other reproductive labors? As a presumed
example of the sorts of ethical distinctions and feminist political reforms Oksala has in mind, her
discussion of surrogacy instead reveals its limits. By reiterating a moral hierarchy of biological
reproduction over other affective and intimate labors, she fails to interrogate critically or
ethically—indeed, appears to instantiate—the normative gendering of reproduction itself.
This is not to contest Oksala’s claims about the ethical problems raised by surrogacy in
its capitalist forms, or their irreducibility to the Marxist category of labor—this is, of course,
precisely my point! But while I concur with her call for ethical differentiations within—and
especially ethical demarcations from—the category of labor, I wonder about the deep
connections between surrogacy and the reproductive labors of paid care work and sex work—as
well as the racialized and neocolonial logics at play in who is compelled to perform them, and at
what cost. Stripped of the normative baggage of biological reproduction, the elements of kinship
that she describes seem to connect surrogacy to, rather than divide it from, commodified care and
sex work.179 Care workers, for example, are also subject to intensive bodily coercions—at times
physically confined in a closet-like room for years on end, subject to extreme regulation and
surveillance, denied wages, and forced to comply with these things under threat of deportation.
179
It seems to me that surrogacy, like sex work, should be decriminalized, and, like care and sex work, should be
granted the labor and citizenship protections historically denied it—though clearly such demands should come from
surrogates themselves. Regardless, both politically and ethically, there seems to be as much uniting surrogates with
other reproductive workers as dividing them.
221
Like surrogates, the deep and primary kinship bonds they form with the children they raise can
be broken without warning. Even the extraction—the theft of affective and embodied life, and
ultimately the disposability—that Oksala claims place surrogacy in an ethical class of its own,
also characterize the laboring conditions of many care workers and sex workers.
The ethical problems (e.g., the dangers to dignity and self-worth) as well as possibilities
(e.g., the new forms of kinship) that Oksala claims set surrogacy apart, should rather be
conceived in their kinship with the labors of care and sex—which of course does not mean
denying the differences between them. This is the most crucial point for my own argument:
namely, that the ethical dimensions of intimacy and embodiment—indeed kinship—that Oksala
claims are unique to surrogacy also unite it with care and sex.
Weeks on the other hand does point to the intimate “structures and ethics” that govern
affective labor as crucial sites of political antagonism, and their qualitative transformation as a
condition of genuine political change. She claims that this requires a multi-pronged approach:
“Feminist antiwork critique would need to accomplish several things at once: to recognize
unwaged domestic work as socially necessary labor, contest its inequitable distribution (the fact
that gender, race, class, and nation affects who does more or less), and, at the same time, insist
that valuing it more highly and distributing it more equitably is not enough—the organization of
unwaged reproductive labor and its relationship with waged work must be entirely rethought”
(The Problem With Work 110).180 As Federici points out, the question of how to do this—how, in
other words, “to construct a feminist agenda and a feminist struggle that in the words of a
contemporary feminist slogan ‘places life at the center’” remains an open question. (“Social
Reproduction Theory” 57).
180
I am not aware of Weeks position on surrogacy, but Sophie Lewis relies on her work in making their family
abolitionist argument for universal surrogacy, which assumes that surrogacy is a kind of work (Lewis).
222
However, despite her call to center and engage these caring dimensions of social
reproduction, Weeks still frames the problem as one of anti-work. Like Federici’s own ethics,
this forecloses rather than enriches this open ethical terrain. This cannot bring into view the kinds
of ethical transformation beyond work—e.g., the family abolition or the transformations of social
reproductive relations beyond wages and distribution—that she herself calls for. Like Jaffe’s
socialist humanist work ethic, her anti-work ethic still conceives both the violence and the
liberation of life-making primarily in terms of labor—or, what amounts to the same thing—its
refusal.
VI. Conclusion: The Erotics of Life-Making
Care as an ethical norm becomes contradictory when it is abstracted from the social and material
inequities at the heart of so many caring relations. The inverse, however, is true of a social
reproduction politics devoid of an ethics of care. To reduce social reproduction to a Marxist idea
of human ‘productive activity’ is not only to bypass the intimate caring and erotic dimensions of
life-making and cultural reproduction that are unique and particular to it, but also the specific
contradictions and possibilities that make political struggle on this terrain both meaningful and
necessary.
Feminists have recently sought to redress these omissions with the concept of affective
labor, calling attention to the integral role of emotional and embodied labors in sustaining the
moral and political economies of social reproduction. But re-inscribing the affective and
embodied dimensions of care and sex—and the specific ethical problems and possibilities they
raise—into the labor lens has led to further impasses in feminist imaginaries and practice. This is
no surprise, given that the practical value of labor, like any moral or political concept, is defined
by its limited scope. As I discussed above, labor is an essential and necessary touchstone for the
223
care workers and sex workers demanding that their work be recognized as such—and valued and
protected accordingly. However, this does not mean that the value, and politics, of reproduction
should be contained by this concept.
The lens of social reproduction shows that the devaluation, exploitation, and extraction of
care is structural to capitalist social life, and to the white supremacist, cisheteropatriarchal,
colonial, and ableist violence from which it is inextricable. With its structural disavowal of the
caring and erotic labors upon which it depends, the ‘life’ of capital is ruled by social death—cut
off at the root by the very social forms and institutions needed to survive. This basic
contradiction—between capitalist accumulation and dispossession on the one hand and the
reproduction of life on the other—has been well named and theorized by Marxist feminists for
decades. But the crisis of capital is just one crucial vantage on the multiple, interlocking, and
escalating crises of our times. Climate catastrophe; political reaction; a colonially inflected
migration crisis; escalating and state sanctioned racism, transphobia, and misogyny; mental
health crises; mass incarceration; food and housing insecurity, and preventable deaths of disease
and despair of epidemic proportions—to name only some—render the political, moral—indeed
spiritual—questions of reproduction, and care, trenchant and complex.
To return to Cornell and Seely’s provocation with which I began this chapter, we might
ask what it means to care in ways more amenable to collective survival and freedom—to reclaim
and transform the fundamental elements of social life and relationship, given these structural
crisis conditions. Renewed visions for labor and class politics are part of the equation. But
staying true to the coalitional and transformative visions of autonomist and socialist feminism
requires acknowledging dimensions of oppression and struggle on the terrain of social
reproduction that exceed Marxist political paradigms—that require acknowledging the autonomy
224
and irreducible diversity of liberation traditions. If there is a unified perspective on these diverse
experiences, it will not be given in the logics of oppression or exploitation that divide us, but in
the militant, and ethical, care needed to hold ourselves and each other through the present and
coming crises—and to “unite and empower” (Lorde) our disparate strands of resistance on the
side of life and struggle.
My argument about the irreducibility of care, and thus social reproduction, to labor is not
only negative. I also hope to gesture towards a shared horizon of struggle that Zapatista women
have termed a struggle for life itself. A radically caring ethics, in this sense, might also be
conceived as an erotics of life-making—not in the narrow limits of the dominant imaginary, but
as a life-generating power to discern what matters, and what it means to live in accordance with
it. Audre Lorde teaches us that, like care, the erotic must be felt, and shared, to be truly known.
By aligning our living and relations with life, we become less tolerant of the violent conditions
of our world, and more capable of undergoing the transformations required of us if we are to
relate in new ways. Thus, the continental, indeed global, tide unleashed with the collective call of
‘Ni Una Menos’ in 2017 was indeed an act of refusal—a resounding and militant NO to a social
system that rendered femicide not only possible but normative. But the “terrestrial, deep, ancient
energy” unleashed through this collective refusal (Gutierrez,) was also one of care and desire:
“vivas nos queremos,” and “nos mueve el deseo”—“we want ourselves alive” and “we are moved
by desire”—were slogans that rang through plazas and around the world. The revolution, they
said, was a sensible one: as Lorde attests, the desire to dominate, the will to use another, cannot
survive such a radical shift in perception, in feeling and relation (59). Such revolutionary, and
collective, shifts in corporeal and affective life are a crucial condition and horizon of struggle on
the terrain of social reproduction.
225
According to the feminist collective Precarias a la Deriva,181 the care crisis is attendant
upon disarticulating, and thus attenuating, human affective and intimate bonds. “Sex, care, and
attention,” as bifurcated and dichotomized logics, are not given and natural “pre-existing objects,
but rather historically determined social stratifications of affect, traditionally assigned to women”
(“Very Careful Strike” 34). This “stratification,” they claim, “materializes” in a “chain” or
“continuum” of sex-attention-care that “counterposes sex and care,” “disincarnates affective
communication,” creates “new modalities of the sexual contract” and continues to “assign the
tasks linked to this chain to women, but introducing new stratifications among them, linked,
above all, to race/ethnicity and country of origin” (“Four Hypotheses” 1). These divisions and
roles are subjectivizing and alter not only the form but the quality of human relationships.
Naming the crisis as such is thus crucial to “a social transformation that would ally care with
desire in a more just manner for each and all” (“Very Careful Strike” 37). We must see that care
is at the heart of current political economy, but in order to claim its “transformative force” and
“revolutionary potential” (42), we must also re-constellate the continuum of care-attention-desire
through “new, more liberatory and cooperative forms of affect that place care at the center [of
life] but without separating it from sex or communication” (“Four Hypotheses” 4). Re-valorizing
and enhancing the “affective virtuosity” and “collective and corporeal knowledge” (“Very
Careful Strike” 41) of care is necessary to tapping its “politically radical potential”—and a
necessary component of genuine ethical and political change on the terrain of social
reproduction.
181
Precarias a la Deriva, was a collective of precarious feminized and migrant workers coalescing in Spain in the
early 2000s, whose militant research on both social reproduction and affective politics has been influential in the
Latin American traditions of social reproduction politics I briefly discuss in my conclusion. Weeks cites them as an
example of feminist work on care that “seeks to conceive care as a social phenomenon rather than an individual attribute, and to imagine the logic of care as an immanent ethical practice as opposed to moral imperative” (The
Problem with Work, Chapter One, footnote 19).
226
Of course, to call for transformation on this level is to invite a host of new problems.
How would it even be possible, we might ask, to collectively value such “affective virtuosity”
when its systemic devaluation lies at the root of the social and material world as we know it? Or
to generate political formations which draw out and re-sensitize this “ethical element that
mediates every relation,” and whose “essential creative character is constitutive of life and the
part of labor… that cannot be codified?” How do we re-constitute this ethical ground of care that
“creates relationships” and that thus “opens the terrain of the thinkable and livable” as such?
(40). It seems that the only way beyond the contradictions opened by these questions is through.
But this riddled terrain is also the ground of an “old truth”182—with care too, to radically alter the
structural conditions of our lives, we must equally embody “the revolutionary transformations,
both psychic and ethical, that are demanded of us” (Cornell and Seely 17).
182
“The sexual crisis cannot be solved unless there is a radical reform of the human psyche, and unless man’s
potential for loving is increased. And a basic transformation of the socio-economic relationships along communist
lines is, essential if the psyche is to be re-formed. This is an “old truth” but there is no other way out.” (Kollontai
241).
227
Conclusion:
Holding Contradiction
228
I. Opacity and Caring After
This conclusion briefly addresses developments in radical care coming out of i.) the recent wave
of militant feminist social reproduction theory and organizing practice in Latin America and ii.)
police and prison abolitionism and practices of transformative justice and community
accountability in the US, which were massively popularized during the historical BLM
uprisings.183 I frame this discussion with the concepts of aftercare and opacity—two concepts
that mark the temporal beginning and end of this writing, respectively, and were each presented
to me by intimate collaborators whose attuned and generative reflection guided me through
crucial junctures, revealed openings and limitations, and supported shifts in perspective that
would otherwise remain foreclosed. I hope the container these concepts provide will lend some
concretion to the transformations in care that I only gesture towards below.
For Hil Malatino, aftercare is care that is necessary “to heal from transformative physical
and emotional experiences.” In this sense, “[t]here are two linked definitions of aftercare… It is
what needs to be provided in order to help a subject heal in the wake of massive upheaval and
transformation, and it is what facilitates and supports emergence into a radically recalibrated
experience of both bodymind and the world it encounters” (Trans Care 3). Used in the context of
social and medical transitions of various sorts as well as BDSM play, aftercare describes a deep
ontological and ethical tending that facilitates shifts in one’s reality or perception. In his own
work, Malatino presents trans care as both a response and a prefiguration, an attention to both
rupture and possibility particularly calibrated to the urgency of the present. His choice to begin
his book on with this concept of an “after,” in this sense, seems to me a potent methodological
183
I intended to engage with these traditions at much greater length and depth in this dissertation, in addition to the
counternormative ethical education being developed at the Institute for the Study of Somatic Sex Education, which I
have also been part of developing for the past five years.
229
move, exemplifying the spiraling recursivity, the ruptures and repairs, of living and caring
otherwise. “Care praxis is always within and beyond; forever prefigurative” (70): hence, the need
for aftercare as an ongoing ethico-political response.
Malatino’s definition of aftercare points to multiple registers of care—as a situated and
embodied response, as a transformational praxis, as an active refusal of care as a given, a priori,
norm or practice—without reducing or conflating them. But even this is not without dangers:
care, like gender, is embodied and performed within a matrix of recognition and response that
can harm as much as it can heal. Indeed, “trans care can all too easily reproduce hierarchies of
attention, aid, and deservingness.” This means that “[a]ny care praxis worth enacting must be
attentive to such tendencies to reproduce injustice. This applies to forms of emotional support
just as much as it does to forms of financial support” (69). The how of this ongoing attention to
injustice lies at the heart of his book and is a question it leaves open.
Several years ago, my friend and collaborator Angelica Stathopoulos and I began a
written correspondence on ethics and the erotic. A carefully orchestrated exchange of letters, we
thought, might provide the opportunity to express dimensions of our work we were struggling to
articulate through more direct and combative modes of address. The concept of aftercare became
a touchstone for our dialogue. After several rounds of exchanging letters, Angelica writes: “We
talked about it once before, and it has again been haunting me since your last letter: aftercare, or
as you so perfectly put it: the caring after…The space you address me from as burdened by the
contradiction you talk about, of things you don’t want to hold, and things that hold you.” Like
Malatino, Angelica presents aftercare as a calibrated responsiveness to an acute experience of
undoing, contradiction, even “decreation,” on the part of the lover, comrade, or friend—it is a
“solace, a groundedness, a putting-back-together that we need after the rupture.” Cultivating a
230
ritual container of care can bring presence to patterns of trauma and transmute shame. Such
caring always comes after, tending to the wounded attachments and unwanted desires that haunt
our relating even as it remains beholden to and bound within them, holding open the possibility
of healing and transformation.
In our letters, Angelica and I were attempting to articulate a language and practice of
radical relationship—something we each felt was necessary for the work we were doing but
found to be incredibly difficult to realize. Through the acute attention of our writing and
witnessing, something did begin to emerge. “When I read you,” they write in the same letter, “I
feel as if you tell-me-from-the-inside. You capture something about me that isn't yet known to
me. What my work is.” And, they continue, “If I could tell you something about your work, it
would be about the caring after. Aftercare as an example of care that manifests the contradiction
within care itself.” Reading Angelica’s letters also felt like encountering a close and secret
truth—like they were speaking things inside of me I didn’t think I knew. They told me what my
work is by showing me the caring after that is possible. Our letters ended. But, we realized, for a
moment we found a relational method to bring voice to what we most needed, and wanted, to
say.
Learning to care radically in a violent world may be a kind of caring after—a continual
caring in the wake of the wounds and contradictions within care itself that as such offers no
guarantee of repair. But even in its inevitable failure, such caring can provide an opening and a
ground for transformation. Because of course, aftercare is a kinky concept too. It equally holds
us in the aftermath of our own ambivalent desires, secret humiliations, and deepest longings
emergent and revealed through intense intimacy. It processes these things, allows them to breath
in us, allows us to live in and with them with more choice, voice, and presence. As I wrote to
231
Angelica: “I think aftercare is the praxis, how we distinguish healing from re-traumatization.”
Aftercare opens us to the wild possibility of play, to the secret chambers of our imaginary
domain. And this opening of vulnerability, this willingness to be opened and shared, is equally
what awakens the sensibilities capable of responding to these things. This space of rupture and
repair, this bringing into play and tending to unknown fears and sometimes-crushing truths at the
root of our being, is also the opening of desire, of pleasure, of change. As in the care webs
Malatino describes, the weaving and reweaving of care also prefigures a beyond.
But how do we learn to hold these contradictions, this deepest fear and deepest longing,
which Leah Lakshmi Piepzna-Samarasinha so perfectly terms “the ghost of the need for care”
(Care Work 33). How do we learn the difference between care that harms and care that heals, or
to stay present to both the non-transparency of our own care, our own desire, and the radical
alterity of the other? How do those who have never been held, who have been held down, who
have held far too much, learn to hold and transmute these contradictions, or chart new, less
traumatic paths through them?
These questions lead to opacity—the opacity of our own care, the opacity of those we
care for—which is the second concept framing this conclusion. It too became salient through the
welcome observations of a close friend and collaborator, Sandra Stephens. Another dear friend
and collaborator Ciclón Olivares, Sandra, and I had plans to spend the weekend together in the
immediate aftermath of the life-changing good news of my soon-to-be employment. I was,
however, nervous (to put it kindly) about the new, much condensed timeline for submitting this
dissertation. Suddenly, shockingly, the fatal flaws of my argument were flashing up in searing
relief, the finality of this deadline and unspeakably high stakes for my life crystallizing its
contradictions like a dialectical image. Thankfully, Sandra and other calmly dispositioned friends
232
talked me down from this ledge. As I was leaving her home, she sent me off with Glissant’s
Poetics of Relation, along with some wisdom imparted at her own defense. “What about the
remainder?” a mentor had asked her, and she now asked me—reminding me of a point she had
been making over the course of several years. Namely, that if my argument about the
contradictions of care holds, then repeating them, instantiating them, and being unaware of doing
so will be an unavoidable danger of my writing. How could I expect to be free from the reality at
the heart of my own theory? Better to do as I say and become present to the gravity of this nontransparency of care with as much grace as possible.
As Sandra taught me, Glissant places opacity is the condition of relation—and thus of
ethical and political modes beyond the logics of dominance. The opaque, he claims, “is that
which cannot be reduced, which is the most perennial guarantee of participation and confluence”
(191). Yet I have also pointed to an opacity of care that is rooted in and fosters unequal power
relations—on display, for example, in the chronic insensibility to care evident in those with the
most guaranteed access to it—those “whose importance to society is everywhere recognized and
made explicit by that society, whose importance and care dominates that society at the expense
of everyone else,” as Joanna Hedva puts it (“Sick Woman Theory” 10). This insensibility is itself
often weaponized—a socially-sanctioned entitlement shielding those so-guaranteed from the
coercions and expropriations of care they engender.184
These two forms of opacity appear to be inversely related. On the one hand, Glissant’s
non-subsumable opacity of relating through alterity, which he claims would constitute a “real
foundation of Relation, in freedoms” (190). On the other, the opacity of one-sided, coercive care
184
At multiple points I give examples of the tragic contradictions that can become embodied in people’s nontransparent care—for example, in the case of someone surviving intimate partner violence who at least sometimes
may cut themselves off from the abusive power imbalances they consistently navigate.
233
(willfully?) frozen in the shape of entitlement, closed off to the disproportionate attunement of
others, and the ‘entitled’s’ own underdeveloped ability to notice and respond to their needs.
Indeed, Glissant points to similar cynical uses of the norm of transparency, which—like the
standard of deservingness the entitled person uses to rationalize their privilege and responsibilize
and negatively judge others—is frequently called upon to justify and conceal relational
imbalances. (189-190).185
If opacity—in the form of the non-reducibility of the other—is the condition of care, then
we must also recognize this cynical opacity so often justified and maintained through ideals of
relational transparency.186 We must learn to recognize this opacity of care in ourselves and in the
institutions and social forms structuring our world, as failure to do so reduces the opacity of the
other and forecloses possibilities of caring otherwise.
What, then, are the forms of caring after through which we might learn to know and to
navigate the difference between these opacities, and thus lay the “foundation of Relation,”
which, Glissant claims, is the true horizon of freedom?
II. For the Remainder: Or a Promissory Note in the Key of Feminist Economics
As I outlined in my Introduction, I understand radical care in both a critical and a
generative sense. My original intention was to highlight three local and specific instances of
radical care, as a way of more fully elaborating on the expansive and generative possibilities of
caring praxis that I pointed to in more limited ways throughout this dissertation (in my
discussion of Woodly’s Radical Black Feminist Pragmatism and the politics of care in BLM, sex
185
“If we examine the process of “understanding” people and ideas from the perspective of Western thought, we
discover that its basis is this condition of transparency. In order to understand and thus accept you, I have to measure
your solidity with the ideal scale providing me with the ground to make comparisons and, perhaps, judgments. I
have to reduce.”
186
I made a similar point in my critique of the transference of “engrossment” in Chapter 2.
234
worker practices of mutual-aid and community care, Black radical mothering, kinship structures,
and practices of insurgent care, migrant support networks, and autonomist and socialist feminist
coalition building, for example). What follows are sketches of the first two: militant feminist
social reproduction theory coming out of Latin American autonomist traditions on the one hand,
and practices of transformative justice developed through abolitionist organizing, woman of
color anti-violence work, disability justice, youth work, healing justice, mad pride, and other
radical social movement spaces in the US over the last 20 years on the other. I wholly removed
the many (and exciting) pages I drafted on embodied and counternormative ethics in the queer,
trans, and sex-worker led radical healing modality of Somatic Sex Education. All three show that
radical, intimate, and structural transformations in caring relations are not only possible, but
actual. They provide living examples of organizing praxis centered in the knowledge that care is
what holds the world together and is therefore the foundation on which we can build it anew. I
am committed to following through on these initial thoughts in both theory and practice.
II a. Caring Commons and Luchas en Defensa de la Vida
In a potent outpouring of incredibly important, largely untranslated writings, militant feminist
theorists and organizers in Latin America—many of whom have been integral to the massive and
transformational wave of feminist movements spreading across Argentina, Chile, Brazil, Mexico,
Uruguay and elsewhere, and have inspired and led a moment of true feminist internationalism
that, while brief, opened radical new horizons for the ethics and politics of social reproduction—
have been shifting understandings about social reproduction in ways that are incredibly
generative for this project. Rather than idealize or fetishize forms of collective care and survival
or re-inscribe the politics of care in dominant modes, they claim we must begin from the caring
dimensions of reproduction in their lived and embodied contradictions and possibilities.
235
Centering indigenous and autonomist conceptions of ‘life-making’ and ‘caring commons’ rather
than labor as the horizon and terrain of social reproductive struggles, thinkers like Cristina
Vega Solís, Susana Draper, Verónica Gago, and Raquel Gutiérrez orient their analysis to
multiple and intersecting axes of social struggle and injustice. As such, they show how radical
politics of care and social reproduction essentially involve transforming caring capacities and
practices in and through movement building and autonomous organization.
The framework of care and social reproduction outlined in the recent work of Cristina
Vega Solís, Raquel Martinez Buján and Myriam Paredes Chauca’s edited volume Cuidado,
comunidad y común: Experiencias cooperativas en el sostenimento de la vida is exemplary of
such generative developments in the politics and theory of social reproduction, as well as in the
politics, and ethics, of radical care. The book addresses the relation between care and social
reproduction that, as I have mentioned, is under-theorized in other formations. Central to this
project is locating struggles around community care in what the editors term “struggles in
defense of life.” They claim that closely attending to the relation between care and reproduction,
particularly in relation to collective care and practices of commoning and life-making, is
essential to political understanding and formation around social reproduction.
I want to draw out several general components of care in relation to social reproduction
that the authors of this volume illuminate. First: we must begin from the caring dimensions of
reproduction in their lived and embodied contradictions rather than idealize or fetishize forms of
collective care and survival (23). For Veronica Gago, for example, it is not enough to idealize
care and community care as either exploited or autonomous forms: rather, caring practices
constitute ambiguous and contested political fields (campos).187
187
She discusses the infrastructures of care in migrant communities in this regard, as both sites of struggle and
reclamation and of capitalist extraction. See Valiavicharska’s (2020) beautiful article “Social Reproduction in the
236
Second: formulating a theory “in which the reproductive question of care plays a key
political role” (Gago 75, my translation) requires attending to the structural racialized and gender
divides reproduced in caring practices and relations, but also, and as such, to care’s affective
components and the ambiguities of subjectivity involved in reproducing these divides, as well as
overcoming them (23). It is crucial, in this regard, to attend to people’s lived experiences of
diversity. Indeed, this introduction of ambiguity and contradiction at both structural and intimate
levels allows Gago and others in this tradition to engage in much more specific ways with the
kinds of ambiguities Hennessy points to with her notion of affect cultures. In a move that is
deeply influenced by Federici’s thinking, but moves beyond impasses burdening it, Gago
counters the binary divisions that tend to pose (good) “autonomous” against (bad) “exploited”
communities. Rather, she claims that community care and communal life are highly ambivalent.
Centering various forms of life-making as well as caring infrastructures (e.g., migrant networks),
she points to the struggles and contestations that become salient in different ways in different
places and temporalities of social reproduction.
At the same time, such nuanced and specific attention to struggle and transformation on
the terrain of social reproduction allows for paradigmatic shifts in classic political economic
theory and organizing praxis. The perspective of “feminist economics” offers an alternative,
rooted in forms of feminist organizational praxis, which have emerged from but also radically
altered the landscape of various interconnected loci of crisis. Through militant research and
genealogy rooted in such “bodies and territories in struggle” Gago and Cavallero (2020) claim
Making: Recentering the Margins, Expanding the Directions,” in which she discusses the social reproduction of
migrant communities facing brutal immigration policies. Valiavicharska argues that the constant threat of
deportation and attacks on their means of survival is a condition for funneling migrants into regimes of extreme
exploitation and draws attention to the importance of learning from the “insurgent forms of social reproduction” (to
adopt Amanda Armstrong’s phrase) that can be found in these communities’ modalities of survival, collective care
and physical and emotional support.
237
that this alternative economics “is able to redefine labor and exploitation, communal and
feminized modes of doing and resisting, and popular innovation in moments of crisis” (“10
Theses” 1).
Finally, attending to care and life-making “from the most precarious positions” 188
obligates a transformative perspective on the conjuncture, and a transformative ethics (Gutiérrez,
Cuidados 16). According to Susana Draper, for example, we must go beyond “simply
recognizing and valorizing care” to “ask how to transform caring practices culturally and
systemically” (“Tejer Cuidados” 174). A politics of care involves more than rendering necessary
services and publicizing the privatized domain of care (174). It also calls for disarticulating care
from modes of domination and “imagining alternative forms of institutionality and social
relations,” (174). Draper is clear in pointing to the deep and crucial question of how to educate
ourselves and our communities in such qualitative and transformational dimensions of care, as
well as how difficult it is to translate such efforts to institutional or state levels.
These open questions are at the heart of Gutiérrez’s notion of political organization and
intimate struggle as well. Her theory of transformative and radical care does not begin with a
normative or general concept of ethics, or of care. Nor does it naturalize or idealize the labors of
care and reproduction (Gutiérrez). What Gago terms “cuidados como campo de disputa” (care as
a contested field) (Cuidados 76, 86) can also be understood in term of Gutiérrez’s claim that
such disputes are reproduced within the reproduction of life, and especially from the most
precarious and threatened margins. And, similarly to Draper, Gutiérrez asks how we can shift our
consciousness, affects, and experiences to facilitate the “communal strategies capable of
effecting concrete transformations in the form of reproducing care” while at the same time
188
“desde los lugares más precarios”
238
organizing to center such contested fields of care—and their transformation—as a condition of
life, and new forms of politics and ethical relation. As with Draper, she wants to protect the
generative power and creativity involved in the direct politicization of social reproduction from
state-centric politics—to resist their naturalization and subsumption into demands for state
services for example, while also finding new ways of forming coalition with those who are
organizing at those levels.
Cultivating such forms of radical communal care is a non-generalizable, ongoing process
which feminists in this tradition—following Zapatista women—call “luchas en defensa de la
vida” and others call a politics of life-making.189 Such practices of care are ethical and political
in that they seek to subvert, reclaim, and transform social reproduction according to the desires
and possibilities of what Fred Moten and Stephano Harney terms the ‘under-commons.’ Rather
than assume a transhistorical commons, such forms of insurgent social reproduction embody
outlaw ethics (Caffyn Jesse) which strive, in common and with love, to look askance at
domination and evade its encircling logics (Moten and Harney)—to thus instantiate living and
transformative visions of justice and constitute new practices and relations of care.190
In this emergent and coalescing field of militant feminist social reproduction it is lifemaking not labor that constitutes the terrain and horizon for new forms of ethics and politics of
189
See e.g. Gutiérrez 2017, 2018; Gago 2020, Hennessy 2020, Ferguson 2020.
A few examples of the movements and practices discussed by those in this tradition are: the assemblies and
organizing practices that led up to and made possible the International Feminist Strikes Movement; migrant
movement politics in Argentina, indigenous organizing in Bolivia, which Gutierrez discussies in terms of the tension
between the practices of "pachakuti” (which "refers to the subversion and transformation of social relations” in
Andean indigenous language) central to the uprisings of the early 2000s, and through which Evo Morales came to
power, and the turn to state-centric politics that also emerged through these struggles; the popular economies dating
from the 2001 crisis and the piqueteros movement (a number of these organizers were first politicized through this
movement, and were also involved in developing the militant research methods of Colectivo Situationes which are a
crucial president to many of their theoretical positions); the autonomist indigenous politics of the Zapatistas; and
feminist anti-carceral approaches emerging out of collectives of imprisoned women and their supporters in both the
US and Latin America (Gago).
190
239
care. Moreover, these theories depart from those discussed above insofar as their orientation to
struggle and transformation is attentive to these intimate and embodied dimensions of life, as
well as the structural contradictions and economic-distributive or overgeneralized notions of
commoning that has characterized so many feminist debates on social reproduction
transformations. Indeed, Federici—who’s work in many ways is itself part of this tradition—has
pointed out that such emergent forms of caring must be experienced from within. This is like
care ethicists’ claims, which I have discussed at multiple points throughout this dissertation.
However, Federici, Gago, Gutiérrez, and Draper all claim that these transformations in care are a
contested field of struggle rather than guided by a given norm.
What Gutiérrez terms the “interior horizon of struggle” (Horiontes) synthesizes many of
these points. The idea of an interior horizon of struggle is itself fascinating, shifting the
inner/outer, personal/political, domestic/economic divides that would always put the horizon
outside and beyond, and would rarely position ‘inner’ as something that applies to collectives as
well as individuals, as Gutiérrez concept does. She elaborates that this concept “refers to the
most intimate contents of struggles” (51). And, utterly crucial for the constellations I am marking
between these feminists’ work on care and my own, is the fact that these intimate yet collective
contents of struggle are themselves fraught with contradictions, and are wholly imbricated in
social transformation, in the constitution of alternate forms of subjectivity and relation. The
interior horizon—as Cornell’s notion of the imaginary domain does for individual feminists but
also feminist struggle191—holds, contains, outlines, guards, the “deepest aspirations of struggle.”
And, like the imaginary domain, it includes the symbolic, affective, embodied elements of
191
For Cornell, the imaginary domain as a psychic/affective space safeguards the possibility of freedom and is also
the terrain of its elaboration. In this sense, she claims that ethical feminism concerns the possibility of autonomous
and liberated sexuality and desire, as well as the limits of theoretical reason in determining them (The Imaginary
Domain).
240
intimate, individual, and collective experience. It thus provides the kind of intimate,
transformative, and materialist perspectives I have been calling for throughout this dissertation:
naming both the depth of the problem, as well as the scope of transformations, at stake in the
ethics and politics of care and social reproduction.
These intimate and contested zones of struggle and life-making are, she claims, “where
old morals and politics are falling apart” and where new ones are constituted (85). Like the affect
cultures which Hennessy claims “can nurture life or abuse and destroy it,” the interior horizon,
and the intimate dimensions that constitute its proper domain, are a crucial location for the
reproduction of violence and also for the individual and collective desires, joys, pleasures,
meaning that guide, motivate, and empower social movements as well as the intimate political
and ethical transformations that Gutiérrez and others call the caring commons. Both this
violence, and this liberation, Gutiérrez claims, are crucial parts of social reproduction, too. The
interior horizon is “grounded in the reproduction of collective life” and is also that most
meaningful and potent “hinge of hopes and practices of transformation” (Horizontes 59). Like
the communal care of which it is an essential and irreducible part, this horizon of collective
longing and desire, and this process of cultivating new intimacies— “new blueprints of
expectation and response” (Sister Outsider 123) as Lorde says—is how we are forged as subjects
who belong to our communities of struggle and healing, to each other, to ourselves, to life itself.
Only by including these material, social, ethical, and intimate dimensions can care be radically
ethical or radically political in the deepest and most expansive sense.
II b. Transformative Justice: Abolitionist Alternatives for Care
In placing affective and intimate transformation at the heart of the politics of social reproduction,
these contemporary Latin American thinkers have much in common with the radical practices of
241
care developed by practitioners of transformative justice in the US—practices which originate in
abolitionist, sex worker, youth, and anti-violence organizing contexts, and have largely been
developed by queer and disabled women of color. By valorizing care in multiple locations of
struggle both traditions reveal that politicizing care involves more than rendering necessary
services and collectivizing the privatized domains of care (which are of course necessary). They
also place both the affective and embodied dimensions of care at the heart of their politics while
also paying close, ethical, and practical, attention to the politics of harm, and the politics of
transforming intimate as well as structural relations. This means, they both claim, that we must
also work, in and through movement building and struggle, to qualitatively transform modes of
care rooted in domination and subordination—often in ways that run counter to state and NGO
infrastructures.
Transformative justice (TJ) is a collective and living orientation to social justice that
seeks to uproot and transform the conditions of harm rather than reproduce them. Practitioners
often trace its roots to practices of survival, healing, and community accountability long
developed by marginalized people (who, as Mingus points out, often cannot call the police even
if they want to due to threats of deportation, harassment, sexual violence, or murder
(“Transformative Justice, a Brief Description”)). TJ as it is understood today originated in the
early 2000s and has been explicitly developed and documented over the last 20 years in
movement organizing contexts such as police and prison abolitionism, women of color led antiviolence work (INCITE! Collective), disability justice, mad pride, youth work (Project NIA,
YWEP), organizing against child sexual abuse (Generation 5), healing justice (Kindred Southern
Healing Justice Collective), sex worker communities and activism, harm reduction, queer and
trans activism, and anarchist activism.
242
Transformative justice is an organizing strategy, a political healing tool, a model of antioppression political and moral education, a tool of revolutionary magic and transformative,
collective empowerment—-and so much more. Crucially, as a kind of counter-normative ethics
and intimate politics it assumes that caring relations are shaped in violent ways in our world.
And, as such, it is also rooted in practices that concretely redress these relational imbalances, and
to develop and shift sensibilities such that people (e.g., community bystanders of domestic
abuse) are more empowered to change them. Finally, it also develops concrete skills and
practices of justice and care that build both individual and community accountability and
capacity to hold and transform the conditions of harm on multiple scales—from the individual,
interpersonal, community, local, and societal levels. Transformative justice is thus a
multidimensional approach to healing, transformation, and political and ethical education that revisions care and justice by uprooting their normative and violent forms from people’s bodyminds
and relations and aligning them with emancipatory visions of these core values.
Transformative justice can thus be thought of as the generative side of abolition—from
which abolition is inseparable. If abolition involves dismantling institutional and social forms
that constitutively reproduce racism and other forms of oppression at structural and intimate
levels, then what social supports, skills, ways of addressing harm and fostering accountability, do
we need to build a different world, one that is life affirming for all? For example, how do we
uproot forms of sexual violence and abuse, given how widespread they are—and given the
grotesque failures of criminal and carceral models of justice in addressing them, and the
inseparability of such punitive notions of justice from racist, colonial, heteropatriarchal, and
ableist norms and histories? A transformative justice lens reveals that with care as with justice,
the most egregious harms as well as the most revolutionary transformations are done in its name.
243
Again, transformative justice is a way of i.) understanding the systemic roots of injustice
and ii.) working on multiple levels (social, political, interpersonal, personal) to immediately
address these harms ‘outside the system,’ while also beginning to interrupt and heal
intergenerational and societal cycles of violence. It is a collective and incredibly skilled labor of
love, and not in the capitalist sense. For example, the Creative Interventions Toolkit, which many
refer to as the “TJ Bible” is free online, an offering of over 600 pages of practical wisdom that
“builds on our connections and caring rather than looking at solutions that rely only on
separation and disconnections from our communities” (2).192
The following are some themes in the discourse and practice of transformative justice—
potential ways to speak to dilemmas and possibilities of caring for ourselves and each other this
way.
• NO experts! (Hassan and Kaba). TJ is a living, embodied, and relational praxis and process.
Nobody owns this work, and it is so important to name elders and stay humble. To respect the
sacred care-labor and skills of the people who have offered their learnings. To respect the
radicality of this work, and its distinction from, and incompatibility with, many of the
institutions and social forms we find ourselves imbricated within.
• Strategies of community and self-accountability: Deepening and de-coupling concepts of
self-responsibility and community responsibility. Normalizing accountability in self and
community. What would it mean to want to be accountable rather than fear fucking up? How
can communities develop sensibilities for understanding and holding the social nature of harm
192
To my knowledge, Creative Interventions, and Mimi Kim in particular, should be cited as instrumental in this
incredible offering.
244
and survival, and “engage in strategies that reduce contact between people and the criminal
legal system” (Kaba).
• A commitment to “just practice” given the fraught nature of community violence (Kaba and
Hassan): The pun. Given the entrenched nature of structural violence failure is inevitable. But
there are also infinite ways to practice more justly (Kaba and Gilmore). And it is
intergenerational work. For example, the Generation 5 collective, which asked about the
conditions for child sexual abuse to no longer be thinkable in five generations.
• Survivor centeredness and the commitment to center the most marginalized people in
communities of struggle. Survivors’ needs should be centered in an accountability process.
Many practitioners have moved from a survivor led model however: if a survivor wants to get
revenge on their abuser for example, this won’t be something to act upon in the process, but
can represent a need (e.g., to express rage or self-protection) that can be honored or met in
another way. This also relates to the social justice commitment to center the needs of those
most marginalized in a given community or organization. See e.g., Woodly 2020 for a
discussion of this principle in BLM and the Movement for Black Lives.
• Non-disposability: Hurt people hurt people. Nobody enters violence by causing it. (Kaba).
Punitive justice continues this cycle of violence. This doesn’t mean there shouldn’t be
consequences, or that we are obligated to be in relation with those who hurt us. But the aim is
to move beyond the individualizing and pathologizing logics of justice as punishment (Davis
Are Prisons Obsolete?) and towards a vision of justice in which those who cause harm, and
those who survive it, are held by community rather than exiled from it.
245
• Embodied and relational strategies to address harm prior to its escalation: e.g., apologies
(Mingus). So many small things to learn about how to engage conflict and reduce or intervene
in harmful behaviors before it turns dangerous (Thom, Mingus).
• A commitment to remain in critical opposition to carceral, state, corporate, and NGO logics
and institutional forms (Hassan, Kaba) and to building alternative “social justice
infrastructures” (Spade).
• Bringing revolutionary values into play: developing individual and community practices for
feeling and aligning with what we, as individuals and movements, value, and care about is a
commonality in many practices of TJ and politicized somatics.
In her “No Transformative Justice Without Harm Reduction” talk in the Just Practice TJ
Mixtape Shira Hassan shares a pledge that she asks all workshop participants to make. She asks
that “every time you are going to talk about harm reduction”—in mainstream, predominantly
white, institutional, settings in particular, that we “promise and say out loud” that harm reduction
comes from queer and trans people of color in “the sex trade and street economy, from drug
users, from people who are street based,” from “people who are fighting to survive.”
She states: “Our ancestors have been whispering survival strategies to us for at least 10,
20, 30, 40, 100 generations.” And that these modalities are just the most recent set of strategies
and come from “BIPOC, queer and trans survivors who are giving you this information so that
you can continue to practice these tools and strategies towards our collective liberation, towards
a way of caring for ourselves through the mess that is this moment and this unbelievable uprising
in the midst of a pandemic. We are so lucky to have been given these strategies and been gifted
these tools.” She notes that “many of those who have given us these tools” are no longer with us,
and that it is our “duty to pledge back to them our collective survival” and to ensure that these
246
ancestors “get acknowledged and seen as the originators of this absolutely lifesaving
movement.”
Hassan’s pledge illuminates one such situated, revolutionary, value of transformative
justice. Developing an ethical practice situating oneself and naming the individuals and
communities that originated these brilliant ideas and tools counteracts the horrors of
individualism and teaches us to be accountable to ourselves and others. As Hassan shows, it also
allows us to connect to a sense of sacredness, purpose, and commitment as we strive, and fail, in
our practices of transforming justice and uprooting harm from our relations and communities.
III. Conclusion: The Call of Radical Care
Confronting the contradictions of care and developing new caring sensibilities requires
intimate and collective learning—learning how to cultivate new blueprints of expectation and
response; to develop new capacities to attune, discern, respond, and refuse; to unearth hidden
histories of insurgent care, and to hold, again and again, the devastating ways our communities
of care will almost inevitably reproduce the very sorts of harms they seek to remedy. Though we
relate to them in so many ways, and from infinitely varied vantage points, these legacies of care
remain restless within and between us. In Sara Ahmed’s terms, they are histories not yet finished
with us. But neither the violence, nor the freedom, at their core can be deciphered if we insist on
viewing care as external to the vital struggles with which it is intimately bound.
It is necessary to value care and work for a caring society, and to name and struggle
against the institutions and social forms through which caring relations are systemically
devalued. The authors I engaged with in this dissertation provide a groundwork for such projects.
However, disentangling care from violence requires transformations in caring relations at both
systemic and intimate registers. Politically and ethically transforming care at these levels is a
247
multi-generational task perhaps inherently fraught with failure. As daunting as this is, there are
infinite ways to begin anew, which over time might deepen mutual connection, fortify collective
agency and purpose, and help to sustain the networks of mutual-aid and collective care needed
for the coming crises (Spade, Kaba). There are, for example, many resources available for white
people like myself to learn somatic awareness and relational techniques for addressing our
tendencies to lash out, collapse in shame, or once again center ourselves when faced with our
racist blindspots and complicities. We can form racial justice pods to support our transformation
and avoid overburdening our BIPOC friends and political allies. Cis men can learn to see and
acknowledge the care of feminized people, expand their capacities for feeling and expressing
emotions, and share in the burdens and pleasures of caring labor. They can form groups, and
agree to hold each other accountable to transforming rape cultures. Such endeavors can, and
already do, form integral parts of larger social movements.
The question of how to collectively care for each other and ourselves in the shadows of
structural violence is an open and living one. But there are many models to learn from. In
innumerable ways, and on massive and micro scales, people are radically responding to
individual and community needs and desires, and forging new and more survivable ways of
living at the margins. Such practices of community care are a necessary condition of sustained
and sustaining social movements, and indeed often constitute their most revolutionary, if
threatened, edges. In the US, examples such as the Black Panther Party’s Survival Programs,
AIM’s (The American Indian Movements’s) survival schools, the queer healing modalities
arising out of the AIDS crisis, the care webs developed by disability justice activists and queer
and trans communities, and the politics of care which, according to Deva Woodly, is the most
unique and radical feature of the political philosophy guiding the Movement for Black Lives, all
248
provide examples of care’s essential role in radical social transformation. These legacies of care,
too, leave their traces upon the conditions of our living. Their call is heeded in concrete and
ongoing ways by queer, BIPOC, migrant, poor, sex working, and disabled individuals and
communities—and so many others—whose radical caring, while under constant threat, reveals
glimpses of living otherwise.
My argument has been that our ethical and political practices of care must adequate
themselves to the violent contradictions, as well as the revolutionary possibilities, of care. This is
an inevitably situated and complex affair. My hope is that this writing may speak to these
problems and possibilities in caring ways that gesture beyond the limits of its author, and toward
the collective genesis and ongoing work of care so central to the survival and healing of
communities of struggle, historically and in the present.
249
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ahmed, Sarah. The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004.
---. Living a Feminist Life. Durham: Duke University Press, 2017.
Anzaldúa, Gloria. Borderlands/La Frontera. 4th edition. San Francisco: Aunt Lute Books, 2012.
---. Light in the Dark/Luz en lo Oscuro: Rewriting Identity, Spirituality, Reality. Duke University
Press, 2015.
Alcoff, Linda Martín. “Comparative Epistemology.” Philosophy East and West, vol. 69, no. 3,
2019, pp. 849–56. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/26788392. Accessed 6 June 2023.
Arruzza, Cinzia. “From Social Reproduction Feminism to the Women’s Strike.” Social
Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering Oppression, edited by Tithi
Bhattavharya, Pluto Press, 2017.
---. “Remarks on Gender.” Viewpoint Magazine, September 2, 2014,
https://viewpointmag.com/2014/09/02/remarks-on-gender/. Accessed May 22, 2023.
Arruzza, Cinzia, Tithi Bhattacharya, and Nancy Fraser. Feminism for the 99%: A Manifesto.
New York: Verso, 2020.
Arruzza, Cinzia, and Kelly Gawel. "The Politics of Social Reproduction. An Introduction.”
CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture 22.2, 2020, https://doi.org/10.7771/14814374.3836
Belle, Kathryn Sophia. “Interlocking, Intersecting, and Intermeshing: Critical Engagements with
Black and Latina Feminist Paradigms of Identity and Oppression.” Critical Philosophy of
Race, vol. 8, no. 1-2, 2020, pp. 165–198.
Benhabib, Seyla and Drucialla Cornell, eds. Feminism as Critique: On the Politics of Gender.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
Bernstein, Elizabeth. Brokered Subjects: Sex, Trafficking, and the Politics of Freedom. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2018.
---. “Sex Work for the Middle Classes.” Sexualities, vol. 10, no. 4, 10(4), 473–488.
---. Temporarily Yours: Intimacy, Authenticity, and the Commerce of Sex. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2007.
Bhattavharya, Tithi, editor. Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering
Oppression. Kindle ed., Pluto Press, 2017.
Boris, Eileen and Rhacel Salizar Parreñas, editors. Intimate Labors: Culture, Technologies, and
the Politics of Care. Stanford University Press, 2010.
Brown, Wilmette. “Money for Prostitutes is Money for Black Women.”
https://freedomarchives.org/Documents/Finder/DOC46_scans/46.GenderAndSexuality.M
oneyforProstitutes.Web.pdf
Bubeck, Diemut. Care, Gender and Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995.
250
Buch, Elana. Inequalities of Aging: Paradoxes of Independence in American Home Care. New
York University Press, 2018.
Capper, Beth and Arlin Austin. “‘Wages for housework means wages against heterosexuality’:
On the Archives of Black Women for Wages for Housework and Wages Due Lesbians.”
GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies, vol. 24, no. 4, October 2018, pp. 445-466
Carby, Hazel. “White Women Listen! Black Feminism and the Limits of Sisterhood.” Theories
of Race and Racism: A Reader, edited by J. Solomos and L. Back, Routledge, 1999, pp.
110-128.
Cavallero, Luci; and Gago, Verónica. “10 Theses on Feminist Economics (or the antagonism
between the strike and finance).” CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture 22.2
(2020)
Care Collective, The. (Chatzidakis, Andreas; Hakim, Jamie; Littler, Jo Rottenberg, Catherine and
Segal, Lynne). The Care Manifesto: The Politics of Interdependence. New York: Verso,
2020.
Chain of Love. Directed by Marije Meerman, Icarus Films, 2001.
Chang, Grace. Disposable Domestics: Immigrant Women Workers in the Global Economy.
Chicago: Haymarket: 2016.
Collins, Patricia Hill. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of
Empowerment. 2nd ed. New York, Routledge, 1999.
---. Intersectionality as Critical Social Theory. Duke University Press, 2019.
Collins, Stephanie. 2015. The Core of Care Ethics. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
Cooper, Melinda. Family Values: Between Neoliberalism and the New Social Conservatism.
Brooklyn: Zone Books, 2017.
Cornell, Drucilla. The Imaginary Domain: Abortion, Pornography, and Sexual Harassment.
New York: Oxford, 1995.
Cornell, Drucilla and Seely, Stephen D. “There’s Nothing Revolutionary about a
Blowjob.” Social Text 1 June 2014; 32 (2 (119)): 1–23.
doi: https://doi.org/10.1215/01642472-2419540
Crenshaw, Kimberlé. "Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist
Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and Antiracist Politics." U.
Chicago Legal Forum, 1989, pp. 139-167.
---. “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence against Women of
Color.” Stanford Law Review, vol. 43, no. 6, 1991, pp. 1241-1299.
Dalla Costa, Mariarosa and Selma James. “The Power of Women and the Subversion of the
Community.” Materialist Feminism: A Reader in Class, Difference, and Women’s Lives,
edited by Rosemary Hennesssy and Chrys Ingraham, Routledge, 1997, 40-53.
Dalmiya, Vrinda. Caring to Know: Comparative Care Ethics, Feminist Epistemology and the
Mahabarata. Oxford, 2016.
251
Dalmiya, Vrinda. "Caring to Know: Response to Commentators." Philosophy East and West,
vol. 69 no. 3, 2019, p. 879-899. Project MUSE, doi:10.1353/pew.2019.0070.
Dashorst P, et al. “Intergenerational consequences of the Holocaust on offspring mental health: a
systematic review of associated factors and mechanisms.” European Journal of
Psychotraumatology, vol. 10, no. 1, 2019.
Davis, Angela. “The Approaching Obsolescence of Housework.” Women, Race, and Class. New
York: Random House, 1983.
---. Freedom is a Constant Struggle: Ferguson, Palestine, and the Foundations of a Movement.
Chicago: Haymarket, 2016.
---. “Reflections on the Black Woman’s Role in the Community of Slaves.” The Black Scholar
Journal of Black Studies and Research, vol. 3, no. 4, 1971, pp. 2-15.
--- . Are Prisons Obsolete? Seven Stories Press: 2003.
Dowling, Emma. The Care Crisis: What Caused It, and How Can We End It?. New York: Verso,
2022. (Ebook).
Doyle Griffiths, Kade. "Labor Valorization and Social Reproduction: What is Valuable about the
Labor Theory of Value?." CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture 22.2, 2020,
https://doi.org/10.7771/1481-4374.3839
Engster, Daniel. The Heart of Justice: Care Ethics and Political Theory. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2007.
Federici, Silvia. Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body, and Primitive Accumulation.
Brooklyn: Autonomedia, 2004.
---. Re-Enchanting the World: Feminism and the Politics of the Commons. Oakland: PM Press,
2019.
---. “The Reproduction of Labor Power in the Global Economy: Marxist Theory and the
Unfinished Feminist Revolution.” https://caringlabor.wordpress.com/2010/10/25/silviafederici-the-reproduction-of-labour-power-in-the-global-economy-marxist-theory-andthe-unfinished-feminist-revolution/
---. “Social reproduction theory: History, issues and present challenges,” Radical
Philosophy 204, Spring 2019, pp. 55–57.
---. “Wages Against Housework.” Published jointly by the Power of Women Collective and the
Falling Wall Press, 1975.
---. “Why Sexuality is Work.” Revolution at Point Zero: Housework, Reproduction and Feminist
Struggle. Oakland: PM Press, 2012.
Federici, Silvia and Nicole Cox. “Counter Planning from the Kitchen.” Revolution at Point Zero:
Housework, Reproduction and Feminist Struggle. Oakland: PM Press, 2012.
Ferguson, Sue. “Canadian Contributions to Social Reproduction Feminism, Race and Embodied
Labor.” Race, Gender & Class, vol. 15, no. 1-2, 2008, pp. 42-57.
252
Ferguson, Sue. Women and Work: Feminism, Labor, and Social Reproduction. London: Pluto
Press, 2020.
Fortunati, Leopolina. The Arcane of Reproduction: Housework, Prostitution, Labor, and Capital.
Brooklyn: Autonomedia, 1995.
Fraser, Nancy. Cannibal Capitalism: How Our System is Devouring Democracy, Care, and the
Planet and What We Can Do About It. New York: Verso, 2022.
---. “Crisis of Care? On the Social-Reproductive Contradictions of Contemporary Capitalism.”
Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering Oppression, edited by Tithi
Bhattavharya, Kindle ed., Pluto Press, 2017.
---. Fortunes of Feminism: From State-Managed Capitalism to Neoliberal Crisis. New York:
Verso, 2013.
Frye, Marilyn,“ Oppression.” Feminist Frontiers, edited by Verta Taylor, Nancy Whittier, and
Leila Rupp. McGraw-Hill Publishing Company, 2007.
Gago, Veronica. Feminist International. New York: Verso, 2020.
Garza, Alicia. The Purpose of Power: How We Come Together When We Fall Apart. Random
House, 2020. (Ebook).
Gawel, Kelly. “Conditions of radical care: a response to Asha Bhandary’s Freedom to
Care.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 25:6, 835842, 2021. DOI: 10.1080/13698230.2021.1922863
Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993.
Glenn, Evelyn Nakano. “The Gender Policy Report: ‘The Feminization of Care Work’ A
Dialogue with Professor William P. Jones & Professor Nakano Glenn.” October 10,
2017. https://genderpolicyreport.umn.edu/the-feminization-of-carework/
Glenn, Evelyn Nakano. Forced To Care: Coercion and Caregiving in America. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 2012.
Glenn, Evelyn Nakano.“From Servitude to Service Work: Historical Continuities in the Racial
Division of Paid Reproductive Labor.” Signs, vol. 18, no. 1, 1992, pp. 1-43
Glissant, Édouard. Poetics of Relation. University of Michigan, 1997.
Gonzales, Maya and Troyan, Cassandra. “Heart of a Heartless World,” Blindfield. May 26, 2016.
https://blindfieldjournal.com/2016/05/26/3-of-a-heartless-world/
Gotby, Alva. “A capitalism of feeling: emotional reproduction, work and gender.” Autonomy
Magazine. April 14, 2021. https://autonomy.work/portfolio/gotby-emotional-repro/
Gotby, Alva. “A capitalism of feeling: emotional reproduction, work and gender.” Autonomy
Magazine. April 14, 2021.
Grant, Melissa Gira. Playing the Whore: The Work of Sex Work. New York: Verso, 2014.
Gumbs, Alexis Pauline and China Martens, editors. Revolutionary Mothering: Love on the Front
Lines. PM Press, 2016.
253
Gutiérrez Aguilar, Raquel. “Because we want ourselves alive, together we aredisrupting
everything: Notes for thinking about the pathsof social transformation today.” Viewpoint
Magazine. March 7, 2018. viewpointmag.com/2018/03/07/want-alive-togetherdisrupting-everything-notes-thinking-paths-social-transformation-today/
Gutiérrez Aguilar, Raquel. Horizontes comunitario-popularesProducción de lo común más allá
de las políticas estado-céntricas.Madrid: Traficantes de Suenos, 2017.
Haines, Staci. The Politics of Trauma: Somatics, Healing and Social Justice. North Atlantic
Books, 2019.
Hancock, Ang Marie. Intersectionality: An Intellectual History. University of Oxford Press,
2016.
Hardt, Michael and Negri, Antonio. Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire. New
York: Penguin, 2004.
Hardt, Michael. “Affective Labor.” Boundary 2, vol. 26, no. 2, 1999, pp. 89–100. JSTOR,
http://www.jstor.org/stable/303793. Accessed 28 May 2023.
Harney, Stefano and Fred Moten. The Undercommons: Fugitive Planning and Black Study.
Autonomedia, 2013.
Hartman, Saidiya. 2016. “The Belly of the World: A Note on Black Women’s Labors.” Souls: A
Critical Journal of Black Politics, Culture and Society, vol. 18, no. 1, pp. 166-173.
---. Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery and Self-Making in Nineteenth Century America.
Oxford University Press, 1997
Haug, Frigga. Beyond Female Masochism: Memory-Work and Politics. New York: Verso, 1992.
Hedva, Johanna. “Sick Woman Theory.” Johannadedva.com/SickWomanTheory_Hedva_
2020.pdf
Held, Virginia. 2006. The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political and Global. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Hennessy, Rosemary. Fires on the Border: The Passionate Politics of Labor Organizing on the
Mexican Frontera. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2013.
---. Profit and Pleasure: Sexual Identities in Late Capitalism. New York: Routledge, 2000.
Hoagland, Sarah Lucia. “Some Thoughts about Caring.” Feminist Ethics, edited by Claudia
Card. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1991.
Hochschild, Arlie. The Managed Heart: Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 2012.
hooks, bell. “Eating the other: Desire and resistance.” Black Looks: Race and Representation,
South End Press, 1992, pp. 21-39.
---. “Homeplace (a site of resistance).” Yearning: Race, Gender, and Cultural Politics, South
End Press, 1990, pp. 41-50.
Jaffe, Aaron. “Social Reproduction and the Form of Labor Power.” CLCWeb: Comparative
Literature and Culture 22.2 (2020): <https://doi.org/10.7771/1481-4374.3838>
254
---. Social Reproduction Theory and the Socialist Horizon: Work, Power and Political Strategy.
London: Pluto, 2020.
Jaffe, Sarah. “The Factory in the Family: The radical vision of Wages for Housework.” The
Nation, April 9, 2018.
James, Selma. Our Time Is Now. PM Press. Kindle ed., 2021.
---. Sex, Race, and Class: The Perspective of Winning. Oakland: PM Press, 2012.
Kaba, Mariame. “So You’re Thinking of Becoming an Abolitionist,”
https://level.medium.com/so-youre-thinking-about-becoming-an-abolitionista436f8e31894
Kisner, Jordan. “The Lockdown Showed How the Economy Exploits Women. She Already
Knew.” New York Times Magazine, Feb 22, 2021, https://www.nytimes.com/2021/02/17/
magazine/waged-housework.html
Kittay, Eva Feder. Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependency. New York:
Routledge, 1999.
---. “Love’s Labor Revisited” Hypatia Vol. 17, No. 3, Feminism and Disability, Part 2 (Summer,
2002), pp. 237-250.
Knudson, Cory. “Beyond the Periphery of the Skin” (review). Full Stop, May 28, 2020,
https://www.full-stop.net/2020/05/28/reviews/cory-austin-knudson/beyond-theperiphery-of-the-skin-silvia-federici/
Kollontai, Alexandra. “Sexual Relations and the Class Struggle.” Selected Writings. Allison &
Busby, 1977.
Lakshmi Piepzna-Samarasinha, Leah. Care Work: Dreaming Disability Justice. Arsenal Pulp
Press, 2018.
Lewis, Sophie. Full Surrogacy Now: Feminism Against Family. London: Verso, 2021. (Ebook).
Lorde, Audre. Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches. Crossing Press, 2007.
Love, Britta. “Whores are Healers.” Petit Mort Magazine. Feb, 2023. https://www.petitmort.com
post/whores-are-healers
Lugones, Maria. Perigrinajes/Pilgrimages: Theorizing Coalition Against Multiple Oppressions.
Oxford: Rowan and Littlefield, 2003. (Ebook).
Malatino, Hill. Trans Care. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2020.
Manne, Kate. Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018.
Mate, Gabor. Scattered Minds: The Origins and Healing of Attention Deficit Disorder. Vintage
Random House, 1999.
McNally, David. “Intersections and Dialectics: Critical Reconstructions in Social Reproduction
Theory.” Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering Oppression, edited
by Tithi Bhattavharya, Kindle ed., Pluto Press, 2017.
255
Mezzadri, Alessandra. “On the value of social reproduction: Informal labour, the majority world
and the need for inclusive theories and politics.” Radical Philosophy 204, Spring 2019,
pp. 33–41.
Mies, Maria. Patriarchy and Accumulation on a World Scale: Women in the International
Division of Labor. 3rd Ed. Zed Books, 2014.
Mingus, Mia. Transformative Justice: A Brief Description.” Transform Harm.
https://transformharm.org/tj_resource/transformative-justice-a-brief-description/
Modern Times Collective. “The Social Factory,” The Activist, vol. 15, no. 1–2, 1975, 38.
Mohandesi, Salar. “Party as Articulator.” Viewpoint Magazine, September 4, 2020,
https://viewpointmag.com/2020/09/04/party-as-articulator/
Mohanty, Chandra Talpade. “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial
Discourses.” boundary 2, vol. 12, no. 3, 1984, pp. 333-358.
Montenegro, Gwyneth. “Sex worker with over 10K partners reveals what men really want” NY
Post. https://nypost.com/2017/11/11/sex-worker-with-over-10000-partners-reveals-whatmen-really-want/
Naber, Nadine, Souzan Naser, and Johnaé Strong. “Radical Mothering for Abolitionist Futures
Post-COVID-19” Abolition Journal. June 18, 2020. https://abolitionjournal.org/radicalmothering/
Nadasan, Premilla. Household Workers Unite: The Untold Story of African American Women
Who Built a Movement. Beacon Press, 2015. (Ebook)
Noddings, Nel. Caring: A Relational Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 2013.
---. Starting at Home: Caring and Social Policy. Berkeley, CA: University of CA Press, 2002.
North, Anna. “The movement to decriminalize sex work, explained.” Vox News. August 12,
2019. https://www.vox.com/2019/8/2/20692327/sex-work-decriminalization-prostitutionnew-york-dc
Oksala, Johanna. “Affective Labor and Feminist Politics.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture
and Society, vol. 41, no. 2, 2016, pp. 281-303. https://doi.org/10.1086/682920
---. “Feminism against Biocapitalism: Gestational Surrogacy and the Limits of the Labor
Paradigm.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, vol. 44, no. 4, 2019 pp. 883904.
Olthuis, Gert, Helen Kohlen, and Jorma Heier, editors. Moral Boundaries Redrawn: The
Significance of Joan Tronto’s Argument for Political Theory, Professional Ethics, and
Care as a Practice. Leuven: Peeters, 2014.
Ortega, Mariana. “Being Lovingly, Knowingly Ignorant: White Feminism and Women of
Color.” Hypatia, vol. 21, no. 3, 2006, pp. 56-74.
Paige, Cara and Woodland, Erica. Healing Justice Lineages: Dreaming at the Crossroads of
Liberation, Collective Care, and Safety. North Atlantic Books, 2023.
256
Precarias a la Deriva. “A Very Careful Strike – Four hypotheses.” caring labor: an archive.
www.caringlabor.wordpress.com
Precarias a la Deriva. “Close encounters in the second phase: The communication continuum:
care-sex-attention.” caring labor: an archive www.caringlabor.wordpress.com
Prescod, Margaret. “Introduction.” Our Time Is Now. PM Press. Kindle ed., 2021.
Puig de la Ballacasa, Maria. Matters of Care: Speculative Ethics in More than Human Worlds.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 2017.
Ruddick, Sara. “Care as Labor and Relationship.” Norms and Values: Essays on the Work of
Virginia Held, edited by Mark S. Haflon and Joram C. Haber. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1998.
---. Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace. Boston: Beacon Press, 1989.
Salazar Parreñas, Rhacel. Servants of Globalization: Migration and Domestic Work. Stanford
University Press, 2015.
Segato, Rita. Contra-pedagogías de la crueldad: Actos y prácticas que enseñan, habitúan y
programan a los sujetos a transmutar lo vivo y su vitalidad en las cosas. Buenos Aires:
Prometo Libros, 2018.
Sins Invalid. Skin, Tooth and Bone: A Disability Justice Primer. Sins Invalid, 2019.
https://www.sinsinvalid.org/
Slote, Michael. The Ethics of Care and Empathy. New York: Routledge, 2007.
Smith, Molly and Mac, Juno. Revolting Prostitutes: The Fight for Sex Workers’ Rights. New
York: Verso, 2018. (Ebook)
Spade, Dean. “Solidarity Not Charity: Mutual Aid for Mobilization and Survival. Social Text 1
March 2020; 38 (1 (142)): 131–151. doi: https://doi.org/10.1215/01642472-7971139
Spillers, Hortense. “Mama's Baby, Papa's Maybe: An American Grammar Book.” Diacritics,
Vol. 17, No. 2, Culture and Countermemory: The "American" Connection. (Summer,
1987), pp. 64-81.
Taylor, Keeanga-Yamahtta. How We Get Free: Black Feminism and the Combahee River
Collective. Haymarket, 2017. (Ebook)
Ticktin, Mariam and Wijsman, Katinka. Review of Maria Puig de la Bellacasa, Matters of Care:
Speculative Ethics in More Than Human Worlds. Hypatia Reviews Online. 2017, E4,
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S2753906700002096
Thot Scholar. “99 Things to Know about Erotic Laborers.” https://www.patreon.com/posts/99things-to-35381259
---. “heauxthots: “Defined/Definers: My thoughts on common terminology around erotic labor &
trafficking.” https://medium.com/heauxthots/heauxthots-de%EF%AC%81nedde%EF%AC%81ners-my-thoughts-on-common-terminology-around-erotic-labortrafficking-f9df45ea2b9a
257
Toupin, Louise. Wages For Housework: A History of an Internationalist Feminist Movement,
1972-1977. Vancouver: Pluto Press, 2018.
Tronto, Joan. Caring Democracy: Markets, Equality and Justice. New York: New York
University Press, 2013.
---. “Ethics of Care: Present and New Directions.” in Olthuis, Gert, Helen Kohlen, and Jorma
Heier, editors. Moral Boundaries Redrawn: The Significance of Joan Tronto’s Argument
for Political Theory, Professional Ethics, and Care as a Practice. Leuven: Peeters, 2014.
---. “Creating Caring Institutions: Politics, Plurality, and Purpose,” Ethics and Social
Welfare, vol. 4, no. 2, 2010, 158-171.
---. Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge, 1994.
Troyan, Cassandra. Freedom and Prostitution. The Elephants, 2021.
Valiavicharska, Zhivka. "Social Reproduction in the Making: Recentering the Margins,
Expanding the Directions." The Politics of Social Reproduction, edited by Cinzia Arruzza
and Kelly Gawel. CLCWeb: Comparative Literature and Culture 22.2, 2020.
Tuana, Nancy and Sullivan, Shannon., eds. Race and Epistemologies of Ignoranc. State
University of New York Press: 2007. (Adobe Digital Editions).
Valiavicharska, Zhivka and Brian Whitener (under pseudonym). “Repression and Resistance on
the Terrain of Social Reproduction: Historical Trajectories, Contemporary Openings.”
Issue 5: Social Reproduction. Viewpoint Magazine, October 31, 2015,
https://viewpointmag.com/2015/11/02/issue-5-social-reproduction/
Vanderkolk, Bessel. The Body Keeps the Score: Brain, Mind, and Body in the Healing of
Trauma. Penguin, 1024.
Vega Solis, Cristina et al. Cuidado, Comunidad y Comun: Experiencias Cooperativas en el
Sostenimento de la Vida. Madrid: Traficantes de Suenos, 2018. (Creative Commons).
-Introduction, essays by Susana Draper, Vero Gago, Marta Malo.
Vigil, Evie. “Beyond the Edge.” https://institute-for-somatic-sexology.teachable.com/courses/
library/lectures/30735752
Vogel, Lise. Marxism and the Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory. Boston: Brill,
2013.
Weeks, Kathi. “Life Within and Against Work: Affective Labor, Feminist Critique, and PostFordist Politics.” Ephemera: Theory and Politics in Organization, vol. 7, no. 1, 2007, pp.
233-249.
---. The Problem with Work: Feminism, Marxism, Antiwork Politics, and Postwork Imaginaries.
Durham: Duke University Press: 2011.
Weil, Simone. Gravity and Grace. New York: Routledge, 1999.
Woodly, Deva. Reckoning: Black Lives Matter and the Democratic Necessity of Social
Movements. Oxford University Press, 2022.
258
Zapatista Women. “Zapatista Women’s Opening Address at the First International Gathering of
Politics, Art, Sport and Culture for Women in Struggle”. Enlace Zapatista, March 2018.
enlacezapatista.ezln.org.mx/2018/03/26/words-of-the-zapatista-women-at-the-closingceremony-of-the-firstinternational-gathering-of-politics-art-sport-and-culture-for-womenin-struggle-in-the-zapatista-caracol-of-thetzotz-choj-zone/. Accessed 25 March 2020.
Zapatista Women. “Words of the Zapatista women at the closing ceremony of the first
international Gathering of Politics, Art, Sport, and Culture for Women in Struggle in the
Zapatista Caracol of the Tzotz Choj Zone”. Enlace Zapatista, March 2018.
enlacezapatista.ezln.org.mx/2018/03/26/words-of-the-zapatista-women-at-theclosingceremony-of-the-first-international-gathering-of-politics-art-sport-and-culture-forwomen-in-struggle-in-thezapatista-caracol-of-the-tzotz-choj-zone/. Accessed 25 March
2020.
259