A Dialogue on
the Ethics of
Mathematics
PAUL ERNEST
A
bsalom: Welcome, Consuela, to this dialogue. You
have the unenviable task of upholding your view
that mathematics is ethical. How will you bridge the
divide between ethics and pure mathematical knowledge?
Consuela: Good morning, Absalom. I suppose it is
harder to argue that mathematics is ethical instead of the
standard view of mathematics as ethically free, because the
‘received’ absolutist view so permeates the culture of
mathematics. However, the idea that mathematics is ethical
goes back to Plato or earlier.
Abs.: And will you use Plato’s arguments to make your
case?
Con.: No. In the Republic Plato argues that mathematics
is ethical because it teaches unity, concord, order, and
proportion, and these are central features of ethics as he
understands it. In modern times we do not see these as the
core of ethics, even if they can be virtues when applied to
some behaviours and social situations.1 By the way, we
notice that the name Absalom happens to begin with the
same three letters as absolutism, the position that you will
uphold.
Abs.: Yes—just as your name begins the same as
constructivism.2
Con.: From my point of view, mathematics is ethical,
that is, pure mathematical knowledge has ethical implications. My claim is that there are intrinsic ethical elements
within mathematics itself.
Abs.: Let’s get this clear. I think it is important to distinguish: (1) the ethics of applications of mathematics, (2)
the professional ethics of mathematicians, (3) the ethics of
teaching mathematics, and (4) the ethics of pure mathematics itself, whatever that might be. We can clearly agree
that ethical obligations are entered into within all professional and applicational work, as they are with all
social practices. Any scientific application has an ethical
dimension, there are professional codes of ethics for
mathematicians, and clearly any teaching is bound by
ethical codes.3
Con.: That’s right, Absalom, we can both agree on issues
1, 2, and 3. These are not controversial. What I am claiming
is your point 4, that mathematics itself is intrinsically
ethical.
1
Not everyone rejects Plato’s (2000) position. Myles Burnyeat (2000), basing his arguments on Plato, proposes that mathematics is good for the soul by making it
receptive to higher ideas including reasoning, truth, the good, and ethics.
2
Note that, as emerges in the dialogue, Consuela espouses social constructivism, the view that mathematical knowledge and objects are constructed socially. This
should be distinguished from the foundationalist philosophy named constructivism, related to intuitionism, which proposes that all mathematical objects are constructed by finite procedures, and rejects completed infinities as well as the validity of proofs of existence by contradiction. Social constructivism has, in the past few
decades, won a growing number of philosophers and mathematicians as adherents. For example, see the collections Gold and Simons (2008) and Tymoczko (1986).
3
A number of mathematicians have written on the need for ethics for applications of mathematics, including Chandler Davis (1988) and Philip Davis (2007); Reuben
Hersh (1990, 2007) has written on mathematics and ethics and on ethics for mathematicians; and the American Mathematical Society (2005) has published Ethical
Guidelines for mathematicians including research and teaching obligations. There is also an extensive literature on ethics in mathematics education, including Atweh
(2013), Boylan (2013), and D’Ambrosio (1998).
2016 Springer Science+Business Media New York
DOI 10.1007/s00283-016-9656-z
Abs.: You are claiming that pure mathematical knowledge itself has ethical implications? This is a radical claim
that most people would find difficult to swallow. With all
due respect, I think I will have no trouble refuting it.
Con.: Well I’m, not entirely on my own with this claim.4
To make my case I have three arguments to offer.
First Argument
Con.: My first argument comes from the warranting of
mathematical knowledge. Do you agree that to establish
the validity of a mathematical claim you must display the
means of verification openly? Thus, the warrant for asserting a theorem is a proof, and the solution of a simple
problem is a calculation, and these must be offered for
inspection.
Abs.: I’m not clear why you bring up calculation.
Mathematical problems are solved by deductive proofs.
However, I agree that mathematical knowledge requires
warranting through mathematical proof.
Con.: No, calculations are important because they are
the means for warranting most mathematical knowledge.
When a shopkeeper shows you a bill, you can verify the
correctness of the total by checking the individual sums,
the components of the calculation by which the total is
derived.
Abs.: Your example is too trivial to have any place in this
discussion.
Con.: I disagree. Compared to modern research mathematics, everyday calculations are trivial, but they still
represent the most widespread mathematics in all societies,
and were once the major part of all mathematics. Jens
Høyrup finds that in ancient Mesopotamia and Egypt,
where mathematics was invented, the reliability of calculation, measures, and numerical records was understood as
part of the idea of justice, taking on an ethical value. It was
the openness and democratic checkability of accounting,
taxation, and trade calculations that enabled these activities
to be trusted and relied upon by all parties involved.5
Abs.: Please let us focus on proper mathematics, such as
theories, theorems, and proofs.
Con.: Technically every calculation can be represented
as an arithmetic proof,6 and conversely, so we can consider
them together if we want to.
Abs.: Go on then, what is the point you wish to make
about proofs?
Con.: I said that any kind of mathematical claim could
become mathematical knowledge only when it is warranted. The role of proof is to persuade its audience of the
correctness of the claim via a convincing chain of reasoning. Agreed so far?
Abs.: Yes, a mathematical proof needs to be verified by
mathematicians as a correct chain of reasoning.
4
Con.: My point is that this makes mathematics open and
democratic. Mathematical knowledge cannot be established by fiat or authoritative pronouncement. Its claims
must be made publicly and be openly available for challenge. Thus mathematics is not a secret or occult
knowledge. To qualify as knowledge at all, it needs
openness and democratic access. Whereas for difficult
abstract theorems only a limited audience can read and
validate them, for simpler mathematical claims, such as an
elementary calculation, a much broader audience can validate them. Thus mathematics embodies openness and
democracy. And these are ethical values.
Abs.: Ah! … I now see why you were keen to include
calculations as well as proofs in your claim. But aren’t the
shopkeeper’s calculations applied mathematics? Didn’t we
concede the ethical nature of applications and dismiss it
from your main claim that mathematical knowledge itself is
ethical?
Con.: We did agree that, but calculations come into my
argument not as applications, but as pure mathematics. In
checking a calculation we are not seeing how well a theory
fits with the physical world, but looking within pure
mathematics to check the correctness of an internal mathematical procedure. If I spend 17 Euros, my change from a
50-Euro note is 33 Euros because 50 – 17 = 33 is correct
within arithmetic, not because of any empirical observations or practices.
Abs.: Okay, I’ll concede that point. But you have opened
another can of worms. Because if calculation is not a
mathematical application but pure mathematics, then it is
free of value and ethics, since these are necessarily excluded from epistemology and epistemological concerns.7
Con.: To be sure, I can’t agree to that. You are presupposing the very thing I am trying to disprove. Yes, I
recognize mathematical knowledge as knowledge, an
epistemological issue, but that does not of necessity
exclude values or ethics. This is precisely the point I am
arguing.
Abs.: Whilst I cannot agree with you, I will suspend this
reservation while I hear your case. But I have another
criticism to your argument so far. A proof is presented
openly not because mathematics is intrinsically open or
democratic, but just because a warrant is needed. Mathematical knowledge is not open or democratic; it is a body
of absolute truths. Such truths need logical warranting, and
the process opens mathematics up to the human gaze, but
that is quite incidental. The proofs in themselves are purely
epistemic or epistemological.
Con.: Now here I disagree with you. If mathematical
theorems need proofs to warrant them as mathematical
knowledge, who is the intended reader of the mathematical
proof? Whom else but humans can the reasoning persuade?
A few authors have argued that mathematical knowledge is itself ethical or has ethical implications, including Ernest (1998) and Johnson (2012).
See Høyrup (1980) and Høyrup (1994). To be sure, he goes on to say that precise accounting also served to disguise exploitation by giving the illusion of justice.
6
It is easy to show that all calculations can be represented as deductive proofs (and vice versa), for example, see Ernest (2009). Gödel’s Incompleteness theorems
depend on the arithmetization of Russell-Whitehead’s first-order logic and proof, so that if t is the arithmetic representation of a theorem T, and p encodes its proof P,
there is a primitive recursive (decidable) function f such that f(p,t) = 1 iff P proves T, for any P and T. Thus any proof in the system is in fact verifiable by the calculation of
the value of f(p,t), which is decidable.
7
Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that studies knowledge and its foundations.
5
THE MATHEMATICAL INTELLIGENCER
Who is the knower of mathematical knowledge? How can
knowledge exist without a knower? If the knower were
god, why would she—all-seeing and all-knowing—need a
proof to warrant mathematical assertions? Mathematical
knowledge needs open warrants in the form of proofs, and
this makes openness and hence democracy an intrinsic part
of the epistemology of mathematics. To deny this is to deny
that the purpose of proof is to let any listeners or readers
come to know the certainty of its conclusions.
Abs.: No, not at all. The purpose of proofs is logical, to
provide an ironclad demonstration of the certainty of
mathematical theorems. Proof is purely epistemological,
and although its existence potentially opens up the reasoning to scrutiny, it is not itself democratic or open.
Human access is a fortuitous by-product of epistemology.
Con.: Here we have to differ. I do not believe there can
be knowledge without some knower, or proof without
some demonstration, warrant, or persuasive reasoning.
Furthermore, it is always the case that you demonstrate
something to someone, you warrant something to someone, and you persuade someone of something. These are
all transitive verbs, and the idea that there can be
knowledge without a knowing subject or persuasion
without a persuadee does not make sense to me. To
accept it you must, by nominalizing knowing, reasoning,
demonstrating, warranting, or persuading, believe in freefloating ideas with no connections to their originating
authors or agents.
Abs.: You are making the fallacy of slipping from the
context of justification to what Popper and Reichenbach
termed the context of discovery. These are wholly separate;
one is in the domain of logic and one in the domain of
psychology.8
Con.: I am aware of this distinction promoted by Popper
and Reichenbach. Both of these philosophers of science
were very keen to demarcate science from other domains
of knowledge. But following the philosophers Quine and
Putnam, I think it is more accurate to see all of human
knowledge and knowing as a single connected web
encompassing both a priori knowledge, such as mathematics and logic, and a posteriori knowledge including the
physical and human sciences, to use Kant’s distinction.9 Of
course some aspects of discovery in mathematics and science fall outside the domains of logic and epistemology.
But as Lakatos asserts, there are rational aspects to scientific
and mathematical discovery, which are the business of
epistemology, just as there are elements of sociology and
psychology in warranting scientific and mathematical
knowledge.10 Thus the contexts of discovery and justification are not as philosophically distinct as Popper says.
Abs.: Of course I disagree with you about the context of
discovery. As Feyerabend says, in mathematical or scientific
discovery anything goes,11 whereas the justification of
knowledge is purely about logic and epistemology. Mathematical proofs are purely logical, and scientific testing of
hypotheses is just about deducing logical consequences
from theories and testing them by observation.
Con.: Sure, that’s the official story: mathematical proofs
are purely logical. In practice, no actual proof in mathematics follows the rules of formal mathematical logic.
Published proofs are always abbreviated deductions that
make claims that are persuasive to mathematicians, compelling even, but rarely if ever fully rigorous.
Abs.: It may be that in practice almost all published
mathematical proofs are abbreviated, but they could always
be written out in full as formal logical proofs.
Con.: This is a potential promise that you will never see
fulfilled. Even if it were true, the complete proofs would be
too long for humans to check them. Even in the relatively
primitive system of Principia Mathematica, it took more
than 300 pages to derive the fact that 1 + 1 = 2.12 Imagine
the size of the proof of a nontrivial theorem: it would be
too large for a single human to comprehend. We would
need to check the proof with some aids such as computer
verification of proofs. Then we would need to check the
computer verification procedures with some other safeguard. This would send us into an infinite vicious spiral of
verification.
Abs.: Nevertheless, the brevity of proofs in practice is a
matter of convenience, not of principle.
Con.: I disagree. Mathematicians’ tacit knowledge is
brought to bear in deciding that a published proof is adequate, and this tacit knowledge is acquired experientially,
by immersion in the practices of professional mathematics.13 Thus mathematical proofs cannot be said to exist
purely in the domain of logic. We do not look solely to the
rules of logic to warrant them. We also depend on the tacit
knowledge of mathematicians, knowledge that I claim
cannot be made fully explicit. The important thing about
proofs and calculations is that they must be understandable
and readable to their intended audiences, and that they are
persuasive to them. To serve their purposes as epistemological warrants, they have to be open and democratically
accessible. Hence my claim that mathematics embodies
these values.
Abs.: I agree that mathematics needs to be open and
accessible to mathematicians to provide epistemological
warrants. But I say proofs are primarily epistemological,
and these properties are necessary only incidentally, not as
values of mathematics.
8
The distinction between the contexts of discovery and justification was introduced by Hans Reichenbach (1951) and taken up by Karl Popper (1959).
By a priori knowledge, Kant (1781/1961) means that which we can know and justify by reasoning alone without drawing on any evidence from, or experience of, the
world. In contrast, a posteriori knowledge draws on experience of the world for its justification. Willard V. O. Quine (1953, 1960) and Hilary Putnam (1975) both reject a
clear-cut a priori/a posteriori distinction. Although not overtly excluding the distinction between the contexts of discovery and justification, this makes it more difficult to
sustain in mathematics, where justification is traditionally viewed as a priori and the context of discovery is seen as drawing on the experience of mathematical practice.
10
Lakatos (1976, 1978).
11
Paul Feyerabend (1975) argues against any presupposition that there can be a fixed method of discovery in science.
12
The proof is on page 379 of Whitehead and Russell (1910). Of course part of the work that precedes it is devoted to setting up and defining the logical system
employed.
13
Polanyi (1958).
9
2016 Springer Science+Business Media New York
Con.: But you concede that openness and democratic
accessibility are needed, and they are ethical values, so to
this extent you have conceded my point.
Second Argument
Con.: My second argument for the ethical nature of pure
mathematics is as follows. We agree that pure mathematics
is that field of knowledge in which mathematical concepts,
methods, proofs, problem solutions, and theories are
refined, developed, and extended, often without any
thought of applications outside of mathematics.
Abs.: Yes, I agree, pure mathematics is pure and is thus
unrelated to the world, to applications, human purposes, or
their everyday or philosophical concerns, like ethics.
Con.: Not so fast, please, I agree with your premise but
not all of your conclusions. Newton’s developments in the
calculus are regarded as a triumph of pure mathematics
even though they were at least partly motivated by the
need to solve problems for Newton’s gravitational theory.
Abs.: Are you trying to argue that physical problems and
applications drive the development of pure mathematics
and they bring an ethical dimension with them?
Con.: No, for I acknowledge that much of pure mathematics is developed with no inkling of any real-world
applications in mind, not even on the horizon. Instead I
want to point out that it represents virtuosity both in the
working mathematician and in the refinement and generalisation of the discipline.
Abs.: I acknowledge that great mathematicians exhibit
virtuosity in their inventive practices, but aren’t you
changing the subject? We’re talking about mathematical
knowledge, not about mathematical practice.
Con.: It’s not a change of subject. I want to look at the
growth of mathematical knowledge. We don’t say that the
forces that cause plant growth are not the business of
botany, or that the forces fostering growth of science are
not the business of the philosophy of science. Likewise I
want to say that the intrinsic forces that drive the growth of
mathematics are also relevant and central to mathematics
and its philosophy. Mathematical knowledge is not a oncegiven and forever-fixed body of knowledge. Any philosophy must acknowledge its growth, whether we say it grows
by invention or by discovery. Mathematicians find new
theorems and theories and verify them as sound. What
drives this growth process?
Abs.: Aren’t you going back to the context of discovery,
which I excluded from epistemology?
Con.: I certainly am. I argued earlier that it is wrong to
exclude it. I want to argue that there are two levels of
impulse that drive pure mathematics forward. First, there
are the personal impulses of mathematicians to extend
knowledge, to expand their skills for their own sake, and to
improve their virtuosity as mathematicians. Now my argument is that the development of virtuosity for its own sake
is a move toward improvement, betterment. After all, the
term ‘virtuosity’ is based on virtue and the virtuous, and
14
these are facets of the good. Human virtuosity is part of the
good life, of human flourishing, and is thus intrinsically
good and ethical.
Abs.: You surely can’t maintain that all human virtuosity in
the pursuit of knowledge is good. What about Dr Mengele
and the atrocious experiments on living humans? Or the
hurtful and harmful uses of animals in science during earlier
times? Even if great virtuosity were developed and important
advances in knowledge made, which I am not conceding,
could you really call this an unqualified good? Can you call
this an ethical pursuit of knowledge?
Con.: You make a good point. Not all skills developed to
the point of virtuosity are necessarily ethical or good. I have
to accept this constraint, that we are discussing pure theoretical knowledge whose content and development have
no immediate impact on people, animals, or the world. I
believe that theoretical blue-sky research, and the development of virtuosity that goes with it, are good for humans.
Human virtuosity contributes to the flourishing of humanity
as a whole.
Abs.: Are you claiming that any and all virtuosity, no
matter whether it has any impact on humanity or not, is a
force for good and against evil?
Con.: I do concede that I should be claiming only that
human virtuosity under the constraint I put on it is potentially rather than always good for humankind; but I am also
claiming it is never bad or evil.
Abs.: What about a brilliant painter who expresses his
virtuosity in painting a refugee ship sinking with all souls
lost as he stands before it on the shore with his easel,
without helping anybody?
Con.: I would argue that the painter’s past development
of virtuosity is a good thing even if when he applied his
skills during a crisis he did not do the right thing.
Abs.: What if most of the time he was developing his
virtuosity he ignored urgent ethical demands, or if he
persistently behaved unethically to sustain his own development? Can you still say his virtuosity is a force for good?
Con.: Yes I can, because my argument does not depend
on judging the ethics of individual humans, but on seeing
human virtuosity, especially that of mathematicians, as
contributing to positive cultural growth and human
flourishing.
Abs.: I do agree that development of mathematicians’
virtuosity is intrinsically good, along with the development
of mathematics, I don’t agree that this makes mathematics
ethical. As objective knowledge, it stands aloof from ethical
judgements. It just is, irrespective of our opinions or
applications.
Con.: So, only partial agreement on this part of my
claims. The second level of impulse that drives pure
mathematics forward is the force within mathematical
knowledge itself to expand.14 This is of course a figure of
speech, to say that an artefact should ‘cry out’ for the
development and improvement of itself through analogy,
abstraction, extension, unification, simplification, and so
According to Imre Lakatos (1976) ‘‘Mathematics, this product of human activity, ‘alienates itself’ from the human activity which has been producing it. It becomes a
living, growing organism, that acquires a certain autonomy from the activity which has produced it; it develops its own autonomous laws of growth’’ (p. 146).
THE MATHEMATICAL INTELLIGENCER
on. But an artefact is a tool, in the widest sense, it is imbued
with human intention. It is for something. Even in the case
of art objects and classical music, the purest of human
creations, the larger purpose is human understanding,
enjoyment, and flourishing. All artefacts including mathematics have human intentionality inscribed within them.
Thus the discipline of mathematics has development and
progress inscribed within it. It embodies the drive toward
making our understanding better, toward the good.
According to Habermas, the aim of extending pure
knowledge, even for its own sake, can never transcend the
underlying interest of predicting and controlling the
world.15 Thus even the purest of pure mathematics, as an
expansion and improvement of knowledge, represents the
desire to improve human understanding, technology, and
hence the place of humans in the world. But by striving for
the good, it is inescapably ethical.
Abs.: You will not be surprised to hear that I cannot
accept this argument. First, I do not accept that the virtuosity of mathematicians somehow makes mathematics
good. They may strive to make themselves good or even
excellent mathematicians, but such human features are
immaterial to their discoveries. For if a particular individual
did not make a discovery, then another would make it.
Second, I reject the claim that mathematical knowledge is
just another human artefact. It is a domain of objective
knowledge that transcends the human-made world. Third, I
cannot accept that mathematics is imbued with any drives,
impulses, or intentions. These belong to persons, mathematicians and others, and not to the subject. Fourth, the fact
that mathematics proves useful in predicting and controlling the world is an after-the-fact application, and not a
property of mathematics. Mathematics might wish to claim
credit for a valuable real-world application, but it could not
do so legitimately, because it exists in a separate domain,
unconnected to the world of its application except through
the act of application itself.
Con.: We differ fundamentally; your philosophy disallows the premises and assumptions I build on for my
arguments. It is hard to get you to reexamine your
assumptions because your absolutist philosophy of mathematics has two and a half thousand years of tradition
behind it, and is taken for granted by many mathematicians
and philosophers. In contrast, the ‘maverick’ philosophy of
mathematics that I espouse has less than a century of
existence.16 So we ‘maverick’ philosophers are still struggling to expose the implicit assumptions within ‘received’
philosophies of mathematics, as well as clarifying the
epistemology and ontology of how mathematics is and can
be socially constructed. You list four differences between
you and me, but they centre on one: we differ in what we
mean by saying that mathematics constitutes objective
knowledge.
Abs.: Isn’t it clear what that means? Objective knowledge
comprises brute facts verifiable by the senses in the physical world, or in the domain of knowledge, by dint of
logical necessity. Knowledge that is established objectively
holds independently of any knower, and holds universally
in all contexts, at all times and for all knowing beings, both
real and potential.
Con.: I want to reject or at least critique much of this.
First of all, there can never be total agreement on brute
facts verifiable by the senses in the physical world. The
senses may be deceptive, and besides, I believe that the
fact-value dichotomy cannot be totally upheld.17 Indeed,
my main argument that mathematics is ethical is an example of the failure of fact-value dichotomy. I have already
argued that mathematical knowledge is not established
conclusively by logical necessity, but by persuasive proofs
that fall short of absolute logical criteria. Furthermore, I
think it is hubris to claim that objective knowledge can hold
independently of any knower, universally, in all contexts.
What evidence do we have, or could we possibly have, of
such universality? How could it ever be established objectively by the senses or logic?
Abs.: My definition of objective knowledge is purely a
definition, and its consequences follow by logic.
Con.: I am not saying that your definition of objective
knowledge is inconsistent. I am saying that it is empty, that
no knowledge, especially significant mathematical knowledge, falls under it.
Abs.: What about ‘1 + 1 = 2’ or ‘2 + 2 = 4’?
Con.: I don’t regard these facts as significant mathematical knowledge, since the first is a definition of ‘2’ and
the second is a trivial consequence of definitions like this
and of Peano’s axioms without even using the axiom of
induction. Because of this extreme simplicity these facts are
trivial.
Abs.: Then how do you define objective knowledge?
Con.: I wish to contrast two different meanings of
objectivity. First, there is your definition, which I term traditional or absolute objectivity. In contrast, I take the
meaning of objectivity as opposite to that of subjectivity.
Objectivity in this sense means having an existence that
goes beyond any individual knower’s beliefs. I term this
second, broader definition as cultural objectivity. Laws,
bank account balances, and indeed language are objective
in this cultural sense, because their existence is independent of any particular person or small groups of persons,
though not of humankind as a whole. They are part of what
is termed social or cultural reality.18 Absolute and cultural
objectivity evidently have different meanings, because
15
Jurgen Habermas (1972) argues that all knowledge is based on human interests. The technical interest underpins scientific and mathematical knowledge, which
means that it is about prediction, control, and certainty, rather than understanding (Ernest 1994c). This characterises pure mathematical knowledge even before it is
applied.
16
Philip Kitcher and William Aspray (1988) describe philosophies of mathematics that are antifoundationalist and focus on mathematical practice as forming a maverick
tradition outside of the dominant tendency in the philosophy of mathematics.
17
Many philosophers of science, such as Hilary Putnam (2002) and Harold Kincaid and colleagues (2007), reject the fact-value distinction.
18
There is an upsurge of philosophical interest in social reality as evidenced in the work of John Searle (1995). Building on this, Julian Cole’s (2008 & 2013) social
constructivist philosophy of mathematics proposes that that mathematical facts stand on the basis of collective agreement and are part of what he terms institutional
reality.
2016 Springer Science+Business Media New York
mathematical objects might exist in the social and cultural
realm beyond any individual beliefs, thus having cultural
objectivity without having independent physical existence
or existence due to logical necessity, that is without having
absolute objectivity.
Abs.: I don’t accept your example of mathematical
objects here, because I deny that they could exist only in
culture.
Con.: I could stick to nonmathematical examples in
making the point.
Abs.: But doesn’t your definition of objectivity include
mine?
Con.: Yes, I do say that absolutely objective knowledge
is a proper subset of culturally objective knowledge; it’s just
that I say it is an empty subset.
Abs.: But you are saying that all mathematical knowledge and more generally that all objective knowledge is
something constructed and accepted by people, and that it
is human acceptance that warrants it as knowledge!
Con.: Yes, that is precisely what I claim. New mathematical knowledge is that which is accepted as warranted
by mathematicians belonging to the social institution of
mathematics, that is, those who have mastered the wellentrenched tacit and explicit criteria for knowledge
acceptance.19 Any accepted mathematical knowledge has a
warrant, that is, a proof that persuades mathematicians of
its certainty. Objectivity and certainty in their cultural sense
are redefined as social, as I, and others, argue elsewhere.20
This is how social constructivism views mathematical
knowledge and objects. Such a perspective has a strong
bearing on the discussion of values in mathematics,
because it posits that at least some of mathematics is contingent on human history and culture, and thus
mathematics itself can be imbued with the values of the
culture of its human makers.
Abs.: Of course you know that such claims are anathema
to me and to the majority of philosophers of mathematics.
Third Argument
Con.: Yes, I do know this, but nevertheless it is the basis for
my third argument for the ethical nature of mathematics.
My philosophy of mathematics is social constructivism and
I propose conversation as the underlying epistemological
unit of this philosophy.21
Abs.: I cannot understand how this is relevant. Also, in
what way can a mathematician stuck on a desert island for
30 years writing and proving theorems on her own be said
to be in conversation?
Con.: Surely we acquire the language and its extensions
that make up mathematical language conversationally from
19
others, and internalize conversation as our mode of
thinking.22 So even when we are thinking on our own we
are engaging in a form of internal conversation, taking
different conversational roles such as proponent and critic,
which we internalized during our apprenticeship. Furthermore, the desert island theorems do not become part of the
objective corpus of mathematical knowledge until they are
read and accepted by others. Thus their warranting results
from a further conversational act, their reception by listeners/readers.
Abs.: To me this is a bizarre way to talk, and I don’t see
its relevance to mathematics.
Con.: Just bear with me while I explain how mathematics is based on conversation. I say that conversation,
consisting of symbolically mediated exchanges between
persons, underpins mathematics, and that it does so in five
ways. First, the ancient origins as well as various modern
systems of proof use dialectical or dialogical reasoning,
involving the persuasion of others. These are conversational exchanges. Second, mathematics is a symbolic
activity using written inscriptions and language; it inevitably addresses a reader, real or imagined, so mathematical
knowledge representations are conversational. Third, many
mathematical concepts have an internal conversational
structure.23 Fourth, the epistemological foundations of
mathematical knowledge, including the nature and mechanisms of mathematical knowledge genesis and warranting,
utilise the deployment of conversation in an explicitly and
constitutively dialectical way.24 Fifth, following Julian Cole,
I wish to assert that mathematical facts stand on the basis of
collective agreement and are part of institutional reality.
Now these social dimensions are built on interpersonal
communicative interactions, that is, through conversation.
Overall, the very content of mathematical knowledge—its
concepts, methods, proofs, as well as its genesis and justification—are conversational.
Abs.: My previous objections seem again to apply. The
activities that you have described, apart from the last two,
take place in the context of discovery, not justification, and
hence have no bearing on the nature of mathematical
knowledge. The last two reasons draw on a sociological
notion of warrants which I reject in favour of traditional
objective criteria for certifying belief. Any analogy between
the interior structure of some mathematical concepts and
conversation or dialogue is entirely fortuitous, as far as I am
concerned. Any conceivable structure can be found within
mathematics, for it is the preeminent science of structure.25
Conversation is firmly embedded in human activity and
thereby relevant to mathematicians, but that does not make
it relevant to mathematical knowledge.
See, for example, Ernest (1999).
Bloor (1984), Ernest (1998), Fuller (1988), Harding (1986), and others, propose a social theory of objectivity.
21
A version of social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics is developed in Ernest (1991, 1998); its account of the conversational basis of mathematics draws
on the work of Wittgenstein (1953) and Lakatos’s (1976) Logic of Mathematical Discovery. Other authors such as Hersh (1997) and Cole (2008, 2013) offer social
constructivist philosophies of mathematics, without explicitly drawing on conversation as a basic notion.
22
This is the model of the origins of thought and language acquisition of the influential social constructivist psychologist Lev Vygotsky (1986).
23
These include epsilon-delta definitions of limit in analysis, hypothesis testing in statistics, and many other concepts (Ernest 1994a).
24
The conversational genesis and warranting mechanisms are described in Lakatos’s (1976) Logic of Mathematical Discovery and in Ernest’s (1998) Generalised Logic
of Mathematical Discovery.
25
Lynn Arthur Steen (1988), among others, characterises mathematics as the science of patterns and structure.
20
THE MATHEMATICAL INTELLIGENCER
Con.: I am not trying to persuade you, for I know you
have fixed views on this. I am trying to develop my argument from social constructivist premises. And I have not yet
reached my argument concerning ethics.
Abs.: All right, let’s hear the ethical argument.
Con.: My claim is that conversation, in a number of
ways, lies at the heart of mathematics, providing it with a
human foundation. But conversation as an interpersonal
activity is inescapably ethical, it is not just about
exchanging information.26 It entails engaging with a
speaker or listener with mutual respect and trust,
attending to another’s proposals and responding relevantly, and being aware of reactions to one’s own
contributions. Every participant in conversation has an
ethical obligation to the others. In mathematics, putting
one’s proposals in an appropriate and accessible format
following received norms of acceptability is part of one’s
ethical responsibility throughout pure, applied, and educational mathematics.
Abs.: Ah, so from the premise that mathematics is
conversational, you want to infer that the ethical status of
conversation must be shared by mathematics. Since I
reject the premise, I need not worry about the conclusion, and need not test the strength or weakness of your
logic.
Con.: Perhaps we have reached some understanding. If
you start with an absolutist philosophy of mathematics,
then mathematical knowledge exists in some domain
independent of us, which does not admit ethics.
Abs.: Yes, this is my position and to me it is self-evident.
Con.: However, if you start from a humanistic or
social constructivist philosophy of mathematics, then,
knowing that mathematics is humanly made and warranted, you may well admit the relevance of ethics to
mathematics and mathematical knowledge, as I do.27
Indeed, you do concede that ethical obligations are
entered into within all social practices. Since social constructivism sees mathematics as a social practice and
mathematical knowledge as an artefact of social practice,
it follows that it is ethical.
Abs.: But in what sense is it ethical? Does this mean that
mathematical knowledge carries ethical obligations with it?
This sounds like a non sequitur to me. It’s nonsensical.
Con.: When I say that mathematical knowledge is ethical, I mean that it is for something and that its purpose is for
good or ill. As a human artefact, mathematics is the purposive product of human activity. As such it both benefits
its human makers and contributes to overall human wellbeing. Furthermore, like any human knowledge, mathematical knowledge must be open to human understanding,
both in revealing its warrants and in acknowledging its
human audience and participants.
Abs.: To me, mathematics is more than simply a human
artefact. Irrespective of its human origins, mathematical
knowledge, after it has been correctly formulated and
warranted, is absolutely and universally certain. Thus it
stands apart from the material world and from human
beliefs, psychology, and ethics. These have become
irrelevant.
Con.: I believe that your absolutist philosophy is selfconsistent and defensible, even if I cannot fathom where
you think mathematical knowledge and mathematical
objects might exist nor how we can possibly interact with
them. Needless to say I also believe that my social constructivism is both self-consistent and defensible.
Apparently we have incompatible philosophical foundations, neither of them falsifiable. At least my philosophy
is exempt from the need to bridge two seemingly
incompatible ontological domains: on one hand objective
knowledge and ideal objects, and on the other hand the
physical world including all human activity. I believe that
multiplying ontologies to accommodate the mathematical
and the physical worlds separately is a categorical mistake. Just as a religious believer and a secular thinker
may respect each other’s worldviews, I respect absolutism even though I’m unable to understand your
theology.
Abs.: That’s magnanimous of you (although I don’t
know if ‘theology’ is the right word). Unfortunately I
cannot reciprocate. I am convinced that a social constructivist perspective can be refuted, even if I have not
done so in this debate. I think it is you who make a
categorical mistake. Objective knowledge including
mathematics transcends human activity and knowing, and
all other earthly, transitory things. Thus I reject the idea
that mathematics of itself can be ethical. I apply ethical
considerations only to its worldly uses and applications.
Referee: You still might tell us, Absalom, your reaction
to this point from Plato, which Consuela mentioned but
does not rely on: that learning geometry, say from Euclid’s
Elements, teaches us what a sound and valid argument
looks like. It provides us with an important standard against
which to evaluate the cogency of all kinds of arguments,
including the fit between evidence and conclusions. And
that’s certainly an important part of ethics: offering fair and
cogent arguments.
Abs.: No, I reject that claim too. I regard truth, and
logical argument used in warranting truth, as a part of
epistemology. When you say ‘fair reasoning’ I think you
simply mean correct reasoning. My interpretation puts this
outside of ethics.
Con.: Thank you, Referee, for reminding us of this further way that mathematics is intrinsically ethical. However,
it is evident that Absalom remains unconvinced.
Graduate School of Education
University of Exeter
Exeter EX1 2LU
UK
e-mail:
[email protected]
26
Many authors stress the ethical nature of conversation, including Ernest (1994b), Johannesen (1996), Gadamer (1986), and Rorty (1979), for example. Habermas’s
(1981) idea of universal pragmatics is based on humans as communicative beings; and effective communication, as it requires truthfulness and some kind of equality, is
intrinsically ethical.
27
Reuben Hersh (1997) terms his social constructivist philosophy of mathematics humanistic.
2016 Springer Science+Business Media New York
Critical issues in mathematics education, pp. 189–204. Charlotte,
REFERENCES
American Mathematical Society (2005). Ethical Guidelines of the
American Mathematical Society. Retrieved from http://www.ams.
org/about-us/governance/policy-statements/sec-ethics. (Accessed
6 July 2015).
NC: Information Age Publishing.
Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: New Left Books.
Fuller, S. (1988). Social epistemology. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
Atweh, W. (2013). Is the good a desire or an obligation? The possibility
Gadamer, H.-G. (1986). The idea of the good in Platonic-Aristotelian
of ethics for mathematics education. Philosophy of Mathematics
philosophy (translated by P. Christopher Smith). New Haven, CT,
Education Journal, No. 27. Retrieved from http://people.
exeter.ac.uk/PErnest/pome27/index.htm. (Accessed 6 July 2015).
and London: Yale University Press.
Gold, B., and Simons, R. Eds. (2008). Proof and other dilemmas:
Bloor, D. (1984). A sociological theory of objectivity. In: S. C. Brown,
Ed. (1984) Objectivity and cultural divergence (Royal Institute of
mathematics and philosophy. Washington, DC: Mathematical
Association of America.
Philosophy lecture series, vol. 17), pp. 229–245. Cambridge:
Habermas, J. (1972). Knowledge and human interests. London:
Cambridge University Press.
Heinemann.
Boylan, M. (2013). Mathematics education and relational ethics:
Habermas, J. (1981). The theory of communicative action, 2 volumes.
dimensions and sources. Retrieved from http://www.esri.mmu.
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag (translated by T. McCarthy,
ac.uk/mect2/papers_13/boylan.pdf. (Accessed 6 July 2015).
Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987, 1991).
Burnyeat, M. F. (2000). Plato on why mathematics is good for the soul.
Harding, S. (1986). The science question in feminism. Milton Keynes:
Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. 103. Retrieved from
http://www.britac.ac.uk/pubs/proc/files/103p001.pdf. (Accessed
Open University Press.
Hersh, R. (1990). Mathematics and ethics. The Mathematical Intelli-
15 September 2013).
gencer, Vol. 12, No. 3, 1990, pp. 13–15.
Cole, J. (2008). Mathematical domains: social constructs? In: B. Gold
Hersh, R. (1997). What is mathematics, really? London: Jonathon Cape.
and R. Simons, Eds., Proof and other dilemmas: mathematics
Hersh, R. (2007). Ethics for mathematicians. Philosophy of Mathe-
and philosophy, pp. 109–128. Washington, DC: Mathematical
matics Education Journal, No. 22 (Nov. 2007). Retrieved from
Association of America.
http://people.exeter.ac.uk/PErnest/pome22/index.htm. (Accessed 1
Cole, J. (2013). Towards an institutional account of the objectivity,
May 2015).
necessity, and atemporality of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica (III) Vol. 21 (2013), pp. 9–36.
Høyrup, J. (1980). Influences of institutionalized mathematics teaching
on the development and organisation of mathematical thought in
D’Ambrosio, U. (1998). Mathematics and peace: our responsibilities.
the pre-modern period. In: J. Fauvel and J. Gray, Eds., (1987).
Zentralblatt für Didaktik der Mathematik (ZDM), Vol. 30, No. 3
The history of mathematics: a reader, pp. 43–45. London:
(June 1998): pp. 67–73.
Davis, C. (1988). A Hippocratic oath for mathematicians? In: C. Keitel,
Ed., Mathematics, education and society, pp. 44–47. Paris:
UNESCO.
Press.
Johannesen, R. L. (1996). Ethics in human communication. Long
Davis, P. J. (2007). Applied mathematics as social contract. Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal, No. 22 (Nov. 2007).
Retrieved
Macmillan.
Høyrup, J. (1994). In Measure, number, and weight. New York: SUNY
from
http://people.exeter.ac.uk/PErnest/pome22/
index.htm. (Accessed 2 May 2015).
Ernest, P. (1991). The Philosophy of Mathematics Education. London:
Routledge.
Ernest, P. (1994a). The dialogical nature of mathematics. In: P. Ernest,
Ed. Mathematics, education and philosophy: an international
Grove, IL: Waveland Press.
Johnson, T. C. (2012). Ethics and finance: the role of mathematics.
Retrieved from http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_
id=2159196. (Accessed 15 September 2013).
Kant, I. (1781/1961). Critique of pure reason (translated by N. Kemp
Smith). London: Macmillan, 1961.
Kincaid, H., Dupré, J., and Wylie, A. (2007). Value-free science: ideals
and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
perspective. London: The Falmer Press, pp. 33–48.
Ernest, P. (1994b). Conversation as a metaphor for mathematics and
Kitcher, P., and Aspray, W. (1988). An opinionated introduction. In: W.
Aspray and P. Kitcher, Eds., (1988). History and philosophy of
learning. Proceedings of British Society for Research into Learn-
modern mathematics, pp. 3–57. Minneapolis, MN: University of
ing Mathematics Day Conference, Manchester Metropolitan
University, 22 November 1993, Nottingham: BSRLM, pp. 58–63.
Ernest, P. (1994c). An introduction to educational research methodology and paradigms. Exeter: University of Exeter School of
Education.
Ernest, P. (1998). Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.
Ernest, P. (1999). Forms of Knowledge in Mathematics and Mathematics
Education: Philosophical and Rhetorical Perspectives. Educational
Studies in Mathematics, Vol. 38, Nos. 1–3, pp. 67-83.
Ernest, P. (2009). The philosophy of mathematics, values and Keralese
mathematics. In: P. Ernest, B. Greer, and B. Sriraman, Eds.,
THE MATHEMATICAL INTELLIGENCER
Minnesota Press.
Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: the logic of mathematical
discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lakatos, I. (1978). The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes (Philosophical Papers Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Plato (2000). The republic (translated by B. Jowett). New York: Dover
Publications.
Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Popper, K. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London:
Hutchinson.
Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method (Philosophical
Searle, J. R. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. London: Allen
papers Vol. 1). Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Putnam, H. (2002). The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other
Lane, The Penguin Press.
Steen, L. A. (1988). The science of patterns, Science, Vol. 240, No.
essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
4852: pp. 611–616.
Quine, W. V. O. (1953). From a logical point of view. New York: Harper
Torchbooks.
Tymoczko, T., Ed., (1986). New Directions in the Philosophy of
Mathematics. Boston, MA: Birkhauser.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Thought and language, (Translated by A. Kozulin).
Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
Reichenbach, H. (1951). The rise of scientific philosophy. Berkeley,
Whitehead, A. N., and Russell, B. (1910). Principia mathematica, Vol. 1.
CA: University of California Press.
Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ:
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. (Translated by
Princeton University Press.
G.E.M. Anscombe). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Agate. Cape Schmidt area, Ryveem locality, Chukotka, Russia
It seems to me that a misty army has
risen over the sea, that fairy tales are
revived, that legends are materialized,
that this stone is just a previously
unknown painting of "Sonata of the
Sea" created by the ingenious Čiurlionis.
It seems to me that the music sounds.
But the author slips from memory.
Definitely this is not Č iurlionis himself.
Then who? Perhaps the composer
has not been born yet?
Eugene Plotkin
Bar-Ilan University
Ramat-Gan, Israel
Ciurlionis by Eugene Plotkin
2016 Springer Science+Business Media New York