One of the consequences of the Yoneda embedding is that, given a category $C$ and two objects $A, B$ in $C$, we can obtain an isomorphism between $A$ and $B$ by finding a natural isomorphism between the presheaves $\mathrm{Hom}_C(-, A)$ and $\mathrm{Hom}_C(-, B)$. But suppose we define a smaller category $C^-$ that throws away every object in $C$ besides $A$ and $B$, and throws away every morphism that involves anything besides those two objects. The Yoneda embedding again says that $A$ is isomorphic to $B$ in $C^-$ (which implies isomorphism in $C$) if and only if $\mathrm{Hom}_{C^-}(-, A)$ is naturally isomorphic to $\mathrm{Hom}_{C^-}(-, B)$. And a natural isomorphism between the latter two presheaves seems like it should be strictly easier to obtain, since we have fewer components of the natural isomorphism that we have to define.
In other words, it seems like to show $A$ and $B$ are isomorphic in $C$, we only need to look at “probes” into them from those two objects alone. So what is the advantage of working with all the extra “probes” in the larger category with all the other objects?
\mathcal
,\mathscr
,\mathbf
,\mathsf
or\mathbb
for categories (roughly ordered in popularity), or they denote the objects of $C$ by lowercase letters. Worst case, they use letters $X, Y, \dotsc$ that are further away from $C$. $\endgroup$