Segunda Ley de Newton
Segunda Ley de Newton
Segunda Ley de Newton
Introducción
Una larga línea de newtonianos eruditos y comentaristas – de Hopkins, Thomson y Tait y Maxwell a
mediados de 1800, a través de Dijksterhuis, Ellis, Herivel, Dolby, Perl, Hankins, Cohen, Truesdell,
páramos de Poniente y Nicholas en la década de 1960 y 70, hasta Harman, Erlichson, Blay,
Chandrasekhar y Cohen (otra vez) en la última década y media – ha argumentado que la segunda ley de
Newton del movimiento, según se recoge en el Principia, se aplica sólo a una "fuerza impulsiva", es
decir, a la representación matemática de una "instantánea impacto,"y no, al menos no directamente, a
una"fuerza constante". El presente estudio, funcionamiento contrario a esta visión predominante, toma la
posición de que la interpretación sólo impulso es una misinterpretación, hecho que en la interpretación de
Newton la ley sec-ond se aplica y pretende que se aplique directamente a fuerzas impulsivas y
continuadas. Como evidencia para este cargo, en primer lugar demostramos que el caso de que la
interpretación sólo impulso es débil, presentando counterarguments a los argumentos que han sido
ofrecidos en los años en apoyo de la interpretación sólo impulso. Luego hacemos el caso más
directamente contra el impulso sólo para ver, como que llevar a cabo las diferentes pruebas, corolarios,
definiciones, Escolios, ejemplos, revisiones y observaciones en la obra de Newton dynami-cal que
aparecen confunden, incongruente o incorrecta cuando asumimos la segunda ley se aplica sólo a los
impulsos.
Pasar de la crítica a la constructiva y con dos ejemplos concretos para guiarnos, observaciones de Newton
sobre colisiones oblicuas en el "libro basura" y su análisis del movimiento elíptico en el "manuscrito de
Locke", desarrollamos a continuación lo que llamamos la segunda ley de la Com-libra , una interpretación
alternativa de la segunda ley que se aplica directamente a las fuerzas impulsivas y continuadas. Después de una
pausa para hacer varios comentarios sobre la segunda ley compuesta, comenzamos a presentar pruebas de que
esta interpretación es interpretación de Newton de su segunda ley. Para este caso, mostramos cómo el
compuesto segunda ley explica, simplemente y naturalmente, todos los pasajes en la obra de Newton que
apareció tan problemático bajo una interpretación sólo impulso. (De hecho, la segunda ley de la com-libra es
consistente con cada referencia a la segunda ley, o sus antepasados, en el trabajo de Newton en "racional
mecánica" – en el "libro de residuos", en las versiones más últimas de "De motu", Principiay el de Newton
prevista revisiones de los Principia en el 1690s temprano.) El poder explicativo de la interpretación compuesta,
la sencillez y la armonía revela en el Principia y el trabajo de Newton en mecánica general, consideramos que
esta convincente evidencia de que la segunda ley compuesta es en realidad de Newton interpretación. Por
supuesto en los debates sobre la interpretación del texto,
158 B. Pourciau
los argumentos son raramente decisivos, pero nuestro caso termina con los testigos de más autoritario: en
un manuscrito del 1690s temprano, Newton escribe con cuidado el significado exacto de su segunda ley,
y lo que escribe es la segunda ley del compuesto.
Ley 2
En particular, ¿qué significado que dan a "un cambio en el movimiento"? ¿A la "fuerza motriz
impresionado"? ¿A "lleva a cabo a lo largo de la línea recta en la que se impresiona la fuerza"?
Los partidarios de la interpretación sólo impulso generalmente toman el "cambio en mo-ción" para ser el
cambio en la "cantidad de movimiento," donde según la definición de Newton la "cantidad de movimiento es
una medida de la propuesta que surge de la la velocidad y la cantidad de materia conjuntamente. " [32, 404] Por
lo tanto el "cambio en el movimiento" se toma para ser el cambio M V = M V en lo que llamamos impulso
lineal, donde M está parado para "Cantidad del neutonio de materia" y V denota el cambio en la
velocidad. Algunos comentaristas-tators (por ejemplo, vea [12, 472; 8, 154; 9, 164 – 165; 25, 243]) sugieren
que la V tiene una dirección, presumiblemente "a lo largo de la línea en la que [la] fuerza está impresionada" y
para indicar
−→
Esto escriben V o v en lugar de V , pero estos autores no siempre dejar claro lo que habría sido el
significado de tal un "dirigido el cambio en velocidad o velocidad" a Newton. El "motivo impresionado
de la fuerza" se supone que la medida de un "impulso" , una "fuerza actuando en una sola instantánea,"
cambiar bruscamente la velocidad o dirección del movimiento. Estos comentaristas no ofrecen una
definición independiente o forma de medir este impulso; así que la interpretación sólo impulso de la
segunda ley,
∝ oM∝
MV Me V I,
se convierte, como Cohen admite, "básicamente un tipo de definición," [8, 158] en lugar de una ley física.
Ahora, ¿qué argumentos se ofrecen en apoyo de esta interpretación sólo impulso? Tamizar a través de
la literatura – de Hopkins, Kelvin y Tait en la década de 1800 a Blay y Cohen en 2001 – nos encontramos
con un total de nueve argumentos justificativos. Nos contrarrestar estos argumentos que consideramos:
Argumento 1: ancestros de la segunda declaración de la ley en los Principia aparecen en el "libro basura"
(un libro común que contiene los primeros trabajos de Newton en lo que más tarde llamó "mecánica
racional"), y estos antepasados emplean la cantidad de movimiento para definir o medir una fuerza
impulsiva. [8, 192; 21, 5 y 30 – 31; 33, 111 y 115; 44, 429] Esto es cierto. Por ejemplo, en el manuscrito
etiquetado IId por Herivel [21, 141], vemos la siguiente afirmación en una larga lista de lo que Newton llama
"Axiomes y propuestas":
4. SOE mucho la fuerza es necesaria para destruir cualquier cantidad de movimiento en un cuerpo, soe
mucho se requiere generar; y soe tanto como es necesaria para generar el soe es alsoe necesaria para
destruir lo
Por otro lado, este "axiome," quizás más una definición que una ley de la naturaleza, podría ser un
antepasado, no de la Ley 2 en los Principia, pero de la definición de Newton de "cantidad de motivo de fuerza"
en los Principia. (Más sobre el "fuerza motriz" más adelante.) Pero incluso suppos-ing este "axiome" es un
antepasado de la Ley 2, es un antepasado muy temprano , habiendo sido escribió en el libro"residuos" en 1665
o 1666, cuando Newton era todavía un estudiante en Cam-bridge. Dos ancestros más recientes de la segunda
ley do no apoyo el impulso sólo de vista. Casi veinte años después de Newton registró su "axiomes" en el "libro
de residuos"
– Whiteside sugiere la fecha diciembre de 1684 [29, VI, 74]) – Newton inserta en una revisión de "De
motu" este antepasado:
Lex 2. Mutationem estado movendi vel quiescendi proportionalem esse vi impresse et fieri secundum lineam
rectam qua vis illa imprimitur.
Este "Lex 2", escribe Herivel [21, 31], es "empleado allí [en"De motu"] en la demostración del lema 1 y
el teorema 4, donde se asegura que las fuerzas iguales producen desviaciones igual (en tiempos
iguales)." Estas "desviaciones" son desviaciones o desviaciones de la tangente a la trayectoria producido
por un continuo de fuerza, no una fuerza impulsiva. Así este segundo antepasado de ley, en una versión
aumentada de las vías originales "De motu", emplea la desviación de la tangente, no la "cantidad de
movimiento," para medir la fuerza centrípeta y la ley es aplicada directamente (es decir, sin
ningún aproximación por impulsos) a una fuerza continua . Un segundo antepasado de los Principiade ley
2, otra vez más reciente que nada en el "libro de residuos," se puede encontrar en un manuscrito de
Newton enviada en marzo de 1690 a John Locke, quien antes había pedido a Newton si la "verdad de las
dos proposiciones fundamentales es decir, las proposiciones 1 y 11 en el libro uno, no se podría demostrar
de manera sencilla algunos más. " [5, 176] (Este manuscrito"Locke" es creído por algunos eruditos para
ser una copia de un manuscrito original compuesto por principios, tan pronto pos-camélidos como
1679. La datación es incierta.) En la página de apertura del manuscrito de Locke [21, 246] encontramos:
HYP. 2. la alteración del movimiento es siempre proporcional a la fuerza por la que se modifica.
Este antepasado de la segunda ley se aplica por Newton directamente (sin cualquier aproxim-ción por
impulsos) a la fuerza centrípeta continua asociada a un cuerpo en movimiento elíptico sobre un foco [21, 255,
nota d1 ], y se utiliza como "Lex. 2" en"De motu", para asegurarse de que las fuerzas iguales generan
desviaciones igual desde la tangente.
Así, mientras que temprano "libro basura" las entradas reflejan los estudios de Newton de choques y
los impactos y la medida (o definición) de un impulso por la cantidad de movimiento
160 B. Pourciau
(cuando la fuerza está en la dirección del movimiento), hemos visto que más reciente ances-Tor de
los Principiade segunda ley refleja interés más maduro de Newton por problemas de fuerza continua y
estos antepasados más recientes medir esa fuerza continua directamente, no por un cambio en la cantidad
de movimiento, sino por la desviación de la tangente (que se desarrolla en un momento dado). Tomando
una vista sólo por el impulso de la segunda ley en los Principia nos aprieta por lo tanto en una situación
muy incómoda: nos vemos obligados aasume que la segunda ley en los Principia es menos como sus
antepasados más recientes (que se aplica directamente a las fuerzas continuas) y más parecida a sus
ancestros menos recientes (que se aplican sólo a los impactos).
Argumento 2: por el "cambio en el movimiento" en la segunda ley, Newton debe significar el cambio
en la cantidad de movimiento, es decir, M V = M V , donde V está parado para el cambio de velocidad, y
M V puede ser una medida razonable de la fuerza sólo cuando la fuerza es impulsiva. [32, 111 10, 65-66;
2, 226; 14, 275; 19, 46] Aquí están cinco counterarguments a esta afirmación:
(a) "La segunda ley dice que un 'cambio en movimiento' es proporcional a la ' motivo fuerza
impresionada,"' escribe Cohen. [10, 65; véase también 8, 144] "Algunos comentaristas," él continúa,
ha agregado una palabra o frase a la ley de Newton para que lo lea que la tasa de "cambio en el movimiento" (o el cambio
de movimiento por unidad de tiempo) es proporcional a la fuerza. Esta alteración sería segunda ley de Newton leer como el
encontrado en los libros de física de hoy.
Newton, sin embargo, no hizo un error aquí. Escogió sus palabras cuidadosamente. En su formulación de
la segunda ley, Newton fue declarando explícitamente una ley para las fuerzas impulsivas, no para las fuerzas
continuas. Así segunda ley de Newton afirma acertadamente que una fuerza impulsiva, es decir, una fuerza
que actúa instantáneamente . . . produce un cambio en la "cantidad de movimiento" o impulso.
Así Cohen reprende a comentaristas, como bola de Rouse y Max Jammer (véase [10, 83, Nota 17; 13,
109, nota 4]), que sería injustificadamente Inserte "tasa de" redacción de cuidado-ful de Newton de la
segunda ley. Sin embargo en su siguiente frase Cohen inserta "cantidad de" la segunda ley con casi tan
poca justificación. Si Newton era tal un wordsmith cuidado-ful, y fue, tal vez él realmente significa
exactamente lo que dice: "cambio en el movimiento" y no "cambio de cantidad de movimiento".
(b) La segunda ley aparece por primera vez, en algo parecido a la versión en los Principia, en una revisión
de "De motu". 29, VI, 188ff La tercera (1727) edición de la Principia contiene el aspecto final de la segunda
ley. En el medio, la segunda ley aparece varias veces más, en la impresión y entre los papeles de Newton: en
otra refundición de "De motu", 29, VI, 92ff en el manuscrito de Locke [21, 246-256], en la primera (1687) edi-
ción de los Principia, en ocho diferentes rewordings de la segunda ley como parte de planes de Newton en el
1690s temprano para una revisión radical de la primera edición [8, 160, 177] y luego en la segunda edición
(1713). En conjunto, Newton tenía catorce oportunidades (que conocemos) para volver a escribir la segunda
ley, y no una vez eso wordsmith cuidado reemplazar siempre "movimiento" con "cantidad de
movimiento". Esto sugiere fuertemente que Newton realmente significa "cambio de movimiento" en su
segunda ley y no "cambio de cantidad de movimiento."
(c) "Def. 2 [en los Principia para la"cantidad de movimiento"]," dice Cohen [32, 95], "afirma que la
medida del movimiento adoptado por Newton es presentarse uno de masa y velocidad, nuestro
impulso. Aunque Newton no dice específicamente . . . es esta cantidad de movimiento que quiere decir cuando,
como sucede a menudo, escribe simplemente "movimiento." " Pero no es el caso de que por "movimiento"
Newton siempre significa "cantidad de movimiento". De hecho Newton utiliza la palabra "movimiento" en tres
distintos sentidos técnicos. Utilizar en algunos lugares como una abreviatura para "cantidad de movimiento,"
como señala Cohen. Newton tiene un significado muy diferente en mente, sin embargo, en el título de la
sección 6, libro 1: "para encontrar movimientos en dado órbitas." [32, 510] Aquí por el "movimiento" Newton
significa una correspondencia entre tiempos y lugares como un cuerpo atraviesa una curva dada en el
espacio. Él también utiliza "movimiento" en un tercer sentido, en el sentido de un "desplazamiento". Por
ejemplo, en un libro de cuarenta páginas en la mano de Newton catalogada como Universidad biblioteca
Cambridge manuscrito añadir. 4003
– la fecha de composición está en disputa, encontramos esta definición: "El movimiento es cambio de
lugar". [21, 226]. Vea también [21, 208, 220, 227, 232]. En los Principia (como parte de la famosa scholium en
"tiempo, espacio, lugar y movimiento"), Newton define movimiento absoluto y relativo como cambio de
absolutos y relativos de posición [32, 409], respectivamente, y luego, en una oración como la Declaración de la
segunda ley (que aparece sólo cuatro páginas más adelante), escribe de Newton: "el verdadero movimiento
siempre es cambiado por fuerzas en un cuerpo en movimiento". [32, 412] Por el cambio en el "movimiento
real" Newton manifiestamente significa un cambio de posición, es decir, una traducción o desplazamiento. De
hecho, a lo largo de este cual scho claramente "cambio en el movimiento" significa una traducción de un lugar
a otro. ¿Y qué es lo que sigue esta scholium en la página siguiente? Por qué la declaración de Newton de la
segunda ley: "un cambio de movimiento es proporcional a la fuerza motriz impresionada . . .". [32, 416] Esto
parece sugerir que el "cambio en el movimiento" en la segunda ley puede tener menos que ver con un cambio
de velocidad y mucho más que ver con un cambio en la localización.
(d) Sin duda hay ejemplos en el libro"residuos" y en otros manuscritos donde Newton explícitamente
escribe que la cantidad de movimiento (es decir, M V = M V , donde V es un cambio en la velocidad) mide la
fuerza (por ejemplo [21, 141 Axiome 4 y 158 Axiome 115), hay lugares en los Principia donde la segunda ley
se cita expresamente a garantizar que el cambio de velocidad puede usarse para medir la fuerza (por ejemplo,
libro 2, las proposiciones 3 y 8 [32, 635 y 650]), y hay muchos lugares en los Principia (en el libro 2 en
particular) donde, con no segunda citación de la ley, el cambio en velocidad se utiliza para medir una
fuerza. Pero todos estos casos implican una situación muy especial: la fuerza se mide por el cambio en
velocidad es siempre una fuerza paralela a la direc-ción del movimiento. Claramente Newton hace citar la
segunda ley en estas situaciones para garantizar que el incremento en la velocidad es proporcional a la
fuerza. Pero lo hace no sigue de esto que debe leerse la declaración de la segunda ley diciendo que el
incremento en la velocidad es proporcional a la fuerza. Todo lo que podemos deducir es que para el caso
especial de una fuerza paralela a la dirección del movimiento, la segunda ley implica que el incremento en la
velocidad es proporcional a esa fuerza. (Como veremos más adelante, la interpretación de la segunda ley que
propondremos de hecho tiene como corolario que el incremento en la velocidad es proporcional a la fuerza
paralela a la dirección del movimiento).
De hecho un cambio V de velocidad (en contraste con un cambio en algún tipo de dirección "velocity")
puede ser una medida razonable de la fuerza en dos casos: (i) la fuerza que se mide es paralela a la dirección
del movimiento (tal vez porque un fuerza original ha sido resuelto en los componentes antes de la aplicación de
la segunda ley) o (ii) la frase "V el cambio en la velocidad" se usa para significar el "cambio de velocidad en la
dirección del centro de fuerza" en lugar del cambio de velocidad a lo largo de la trayectoria del
movimiento. (En caso de que (ii) la fuerza debe ser centrípeto y el centro de la fuerza debe ser conocido. Ver
[46,
162 B. Pourciau
(e) En una revisión de "De Motu", en el manuscrito de Locke y en la Proposición 6 de la 1687 Principia la
segunda ley es aplicada directamente a una fuerza continua para asegurar que la desviación de la tangente
(generada en un tiempo determinado) proporcional a la fuerza. (Ver [21, 31 y 255; 5, 252; 30, 103].) Quizá esto
indica que el "cambio de movimiento" en la segunda ley de las medidas de la "desviación de la tangente" y no
un cambio en la velocidad de.
(a) Esto es como afirmar que la declaración hecha por un granjero que "la altura del maíz varía con la
temperatura media" no puede implicar un intervalo de tiempo porque hace la declaración no menciona un
intervalo de tiempo. Pero por supuesto la "temperatura media" por su definición depende sobre el cual se
calcula el intervalo de tiempo y por lo que cualquier declaración que la "temperatura media" también
depende de ese intervalo de tiempo. La similitud con la segunda ley es clara: la "fuerza motriz
impresionado," por su propia definición como el "movimiento que [la fuerza] genera en un momento
dado," [32, 407] depende manifiestamente en el intervalo de tiempo dado que se calcula y así
la Declaración de la segunda ley, que contiene el "motivo impresionado de la fuerza", también debe
depender de ese determinado intervalo de tiempo.
(b) Un scholium final sección 1, libro 2, de los Principia cita la segunda ley en una explicación para
las resistencias proporcionales al cuadrado de la velocidad [32, 641]: "en medios totalmente carente de
rigidez," escribe Newton,
las resistencias que encuentran los cuerpos son como el cuadrado de las velocidades. Por la acción de un
cuerpo más rápido, un movimiento que es mayor en proporción a esa velocidad mayor es commu-nicated a
una cantidad dada de la media en un menor tiempo; y así en un tiempo igual, porque una mayor cantidad del
medio se altera, se comunica un movimiento mayor en proporción con el cuadrado de la velocidad (por las
segunda y terceros leyes de movimiento) la resistencia es como el movimiento comunicado.
Algunos eruditos han ofrecido una variación del argumento "sin intervalo de tiempo, por tanto,
impulso":
Argumento 4: por el "cambio en el movimiento" en la segunda ley, Newton significa los tiempos de
"quan-tity de la materia" el cambio de una "velocidad direccional". Además, este cambio se calcula sin
tener en cuenta un intervalo de tiempo, y esto nos dice que la fuerza es impulsiva. [9, 164 – 165; 13, 112;
12, 472; 25, 221]
Decimos algo vagamente, "cambiar en una ' velocidad direccional,"' porque aparte de
[25] estos autores no definen lo que significa este cambio! Lo que aparece en el sentido de este cambio en la
velocidad de"direccional" es lo que vamos a escribir como v ≡ v1 − v0 , es decir, el moderno cambio en
velocidad del vector. (Aquí v 1 es el vector cuya longitud y dirección igual a la velocidad instantánea y
dirección, respectivamente, del cuerpo antes del impulso. El vector v2 registra la misma información, pero
después del impulso.) No hay intervalo de tiempo es necesaria para calcular el vector diferencia v. Por lo tanto,
no hay intervalo de tiempo le
se requiere para calcular el "cambio en el movimiento" siempre y cuando se fuera a interpretar el cambio
en el movimiento como Mv = M vy esto sería consistente con el hecho de Newton no menciona un
intervalo de tiempo en su declaración de la segunda ley. Esta coherencia se ve entonces por estos
comentaristas como evidencia para una interpretación sólo impulso.
Pero suponiendo que el "cambio en el movimiento" implica una "velocidad direccional" de algunos
especie, Newton nunca definir o calcular este cambio en la manera moderna, sub-
−→
contratante los vectores v 0 y v 1 . Más bien él sería calcular la desviación o desviación LQ de uniforme
generado movimiento de línea recta en un intervalo de tiempo dado h. (Aquí L es el cuerpo habría venido a
través del movimiento de línea recta uniforme en tiempo h había el cuerpo sin obstáculos, Q es el lugar donde
el cuerpo realmente viene en el tiempo de h
−→
debido a la fuerza y LQ está parado para el segmento de línea dirigido desde L a Q.)
Así que para Newton un "cambio de velocidad direccional" no sería la moderna v ≡ v 1 −v0,
−→ −→
pero algo la desviación en un tiempo fijo determinado: V ≡ LQ / h. (Nosotros usamos un signo igual con
tres barras en el sentido de "es igual por definición.") Dado un impulso (y cualquier intervalo de tiempo
−→ −→
h para la informática V ), se puede calcular v y V por separado y por supuesto que
−→ −→ −→ −→ −→ −→
V = v: P L = v0h y P Q = v1h, de modo que LQ = Q P − P L = (v1 −v0) h = v· h . Pero estos dos
cambios de "velocidad direccional" se definen y calculan, por tanto, de muy diferentes maneras, el punto
es que para calcular (lo que necesita para ser) de Newton
−→ −→
cambio en la "velocidad de direccional" V uno debe calcular primero la desviación LQy uno
164 B. Pourciau
no se puede calcular esta desviación sin ser dado un intervalo de tiempo específico h. Si de hecho el "cambio de
movimiento" en la segunda ley es la "cantidad de materia" veces un cambio en "velocidad direccional", como
creo que es – más sobre esto más adelante – entonces realmente el
−→ −→
opción razonable sólo para este "cambio de velocidad direccional" es V ≡ LQ / h, la deflexión generada en un
momento dado. Se deduce que las dos afirmaciones de argumento 4 – el "cambio en el movimiento" implica un
cambio en la velocidad de"direccional" que no implica un intervalo de tiempo – son incompatibles. Por otra
parte, una vez estamos de acuerdo en cambio de que Newton en
−→ −→
"velocidad direccional" debe ser V ≡ LQ / h, entonces el argumento de "no hay tiempo por lo tanto mencionado
impulso" para la interpretación sólo impulso de la segunda ley se evapora, para la deformación por unidad de
tiempo puede ser utilizado como una medida de fuerzas impulsivas ycontinua!
5 argumento: comentando la segunda ley, escribe Newton, "si algunos fuerza gen porta cualquier
movimiento, dos veces la fuerza va a generar dos veces el movimiento, y tres veces la fuerza generará
tres veces el movimiento de... ," y este comentario es coherente con una fuerza impulsiva. [Véase, por
ejemplo, 32, 112; 10, 66]
Es cierto este comentario de Newton es constante con una fuerza impulsiva. No es, sin embargo,
necesariamente incompatible con una fuerza continua, dependiendo por supuesto en cómo Newton mide
una continua fuerza. En este trabajo de hecho vamos construir una cierta interpretación de la segunda ley,
que se aplica igualmente bien a impulsivo y contin-superfluo las fuerzas y entonces sostienen que esta
interpretación del"compuesta" es de Newton lo que significa de la segunda ley de la intención. Desde
Newton "dos veces la fuerza de" observación resulta para ser completamente consistentes con esta
interpretación compuesta de la segunda ley, es difícil ver esta observación como evidencia para una
interpretación sólo impulso.
6 argumento: Newton de "dos veces la fuerza" comentario sigue: "... Si la fuerza se impresionó a la
vez o sucesivamente grados." La descripción "de una vez" ("simul & semel) sugiere un impulso
y"sucesivamente por grados"(" gradatim et sucesivos "), porque"gradatim"significa"paso a paso",
indica, no es una fuerza continua, sino más bien una serie de impulsos. [32, 112; 8, 148]
Por otro lado, entre actualizaciones varias de Newton de la segunda ley en escrito en el 1690s
temprano, nos encontramos con dos casos. [8, 168] En el caso 1 que la fuerza es impresionada en una vez
("simul & semel"), mientras que en el caso 2 la fuerza es impresionados continuamente ("por-petuo"). En
este segundo caso, el "modo de acción," escribe Cohen, "debe ser ' gradatim et sucesivas,' que ahora se
describe como ' perpetuo."' Esto sugiere que Newton, como él considera modificaciones en la redacción
de la segunda ley en el 1690s, decidió que la división "en conjunto y a la vez" ("simul & semel'')
versus"continuamente"("perpetuo") mejor refleja su intención de que la división original "en conjunto y a
la vez" versus "suc-cessively por grados" ("gradatim et sucesivas"). Y además esto sugeriría que Newton
1
pensó de la Ley 2 que se aplica directamente al impulsivo y directamente a las fuerzas continuas.
1
Cohen [8, 148] y Cohen Whitman [32] traducen "perpetuo" como "continuamente" en lugar de "continuamente". En mi
opinión esto es una traducción inexacta, para "perpetuo" no permite interrupciones, mientras que "continuamente" en uso
moderno. Cohen [32, 41] defiende su interpretación de "perpetuo", señalando por ejemplo que el manuscrito escrito en
inglés que Newton enviada a John Locke 1690 utiliza "continuamente" en exactamente las situaciones donde Newton utiliza
"perpetuo" en manuscritos en latín. Pero este argumento pierde su fuerza cuando descubrimos que en la de Newton
Interpretación de Newton de la segunda ley de Newton 165
7 argumento: ver que la fuerza en la segunda ley debe ser un impulso, solo necesitamos mirar 1
corolario de las leyes. Este corolario refiere manifiestamente a impulsos sólo. [10, 66; 12, 472; 14, 274]
Sí y no. Sí, corolario 1 se refiere a impulsos sólo. Pero no, esto no es evidencia de una impulso -
sólo interpretación de la segunda ley. Nos dice que Newton pensaba que de la segunda ley que se aplica a
un impulso. Que no nos dicen que Newton pensaba que de la segunda ley que se aplica
a sóloimpulsos. (De hecho otros corolarios de las leyes, como veremos más adelante, parecen implicar
una fuerza continua .)
Argumento 9: en la sección 11 del libro 1 [32, 561], Newton escribe que le es "considera-ción centrípeta
de las fuerzas como atractivos, aunque tal vez, si hablamos en el lenguaje de la física – podrían más
verdaderamente llamar impulsos." Esto ilustra que en los Principia fuerza impulsiva es primario, mientras que
fuerza continua es derivado de la. [32, 113]
Aviso de condición de Newton: "si hablamos en el lenguaje de la física." Y continúa en la siguiente frase
para recordarnos que "aquí estamos interesados en las matemáticas; y por lo tanto, dejando a un lado cualquier
debate sobre física, estamos utilizando lenguaje familiar con el fin de ser más fácilmente entendido por lectores
matemáticos." Newton claramente desea subrayar la diferencia entre física y fenómenos físicos, por un lado y
matemáticas y representaciones matemáticas en la otra. Bien puede creer la fuerza centrípeta de la gravitación
física a ser impulsivo, de hecho él puede ser imposible-sible concebir otra posibilidad, pero una convicción
sobre la naturaleza física de la gravitación ciertamente no impediría De Newton matemáticas
representaciones de fuerza centrípeta de ser representaciones de fuerza continua, como la fuerza que "actúa en
forma ininterrumpida" en la discusión de la Proposición 1 del libro 1. Tampoco evitaría la segunda ley de ser
directamente aplicables a las fuerzas continuas. Las proposiciones del libro 1 son las
proposiciones matemáticas , que involucra las representaciones matemáticas de
tiempo "continuamente" había tenido ningún significado secundario, como lo hace hoy en día, que permitió
interrupciones. (En Un diccionario [11], por ejemplo, publicó en 1684, Elisha Coles define "continua" como "sin
interrupción.") Esto sugeriría que a lo largo de Cohen y de Whitman fina nueva traducción de los Principia cada
"continuallly" derivan "perpetuo" debería sustituirse por "continuamente" o "ininterrumpidamente".
166 B. Pourciau
fuerza centrípeta y seguramente no sorprende, aunque cree que Newton gravitación física a ser impulsivo,
que sus representaciones matemáticas de la atracción son representaciones de fuerza continua. Para un
movimiento generado por una fuerza continua debe ser lo que llamamos más "suave" movimiento –
donde la velocidad y la dirección varían continuamente, mientras que debe ser un movimiento generado
por una fuerza impulsiva "nonsmooth" o "desigual", con cambios bruscos de velocidad o dirección,
y Herramientas matemáticas de Newton – por ejemplo el var-pagarés geométrico limitantes técnicas en la
sección 1, libro 1 – requieren cierta suavidad antes de que se pueden aplicar. En otras palabras, si Newton
no había asumido la continuidad de sus fuerzas (matemático representaciones de), para que los
movimientos generados sea lisos, entonces su capacidad de establecer teoremas significativos habría sido
disminuido grandemente.
2. Una vez más, el plan para el presente estudio es presentar el caso contra una interpretación sólo impulso
de la segunda ley, entonces para desarrollar, desde un estudio de la obra de Newton, una particular
interpretación, la segunda ley compuesto como lo llamamos, que se aplica por igual a fuerzas impulsivas y
continuo y finalmente argumentar que esta interpretación del"compuesta" es en realidad la interpretación de
Newton. En la sección anterior, al comenzar el caso contra una interpretación sólo impulso, tenemos reunidos
los argu-momentos que han sido propuestos sobre los años para apoyar la afirmación de que Newton tiene la
intención de la segunda ley para aplicar a las fuerzas impulsivas sólo y para cada uno tal argumento nos ofrece
nuestras propia counterarguments. Hasta ahora, entonces, nos hemos estado argumentando contra la
evidencia para un impulso sólo de interpretación. Pero ahora comenzaremos
discutiendo directamente contra una interpretación sólo impulso, señalando las aplicaciones de la segunda ley,
com-ments en escolios, definiciones, ejemplos, corolarios, demostraciones y las revisiones, en la Principia y
revisiones previstas de Newton en su segunda edición – que parecen ser demasiado compleja, confusa,
inconsistente, antinatural o incorrecta cuando asumimos una interpretación sólo impulso de la Ley 2.
Empezamos con los ejemplos que Newton utiliza para ilustrar el concepto de fuerza centrípeta. Según la
declaración de la segunda ley, "un cambio de movimiento es adicional proporcional a la fuerza motriz
impresionada. . .". [32, 416] Pero la única "fuerza de motivo" Newton define es el "motivo cantidad
de centrípeta fuerza" [32, 407] en 8 de definición anteriores a las leyes y todos cuatro ejemplos dados fuerza
centrípeta implican fuerzas continua : gravedad, fuerza magnética, la fuerza "por que los planetas están
continuamente [es decir,"cont-uously,"– véase la nota 1 anterior] retirado de movimientos rectilíneos," y la
"fuerza que [a] Honda continuamente [continuamente] dibuja la piedra hacia atrás, hacia la mano". [32,
405] (De hecho en lo Principia de Newton nunca llama a un impulso centrípeto. Las fuerzas centrípetas son
siempre fuerzas continuas. Una serie de impulsos podría llamarse centrípeta, si cada impulso en la serie se
dirige hacia el mismo punto fijo, pero sería tonto llamar a un único impulso centrípeto, puesto que un solo
impulso tiene una sola dirección.) Así debe el "fuerza motriz" que aparece en la segunda ley "Motivo cantidad
de fuerza centrípeta" de Newton porque es la única "fuerza motriz" que él define y los únicos ejemplos de
fuerza centrípeta que él ofrece son ejemplos de fuerza continua.
Bajo estas condiciones parece difícilmente creíble que Newton tiene la intención de la segunda ley para
aplicar a las fuerzas impulsivas sólo.
Hablar de la fuerza centrípeta, nos permite mirar más cuidadosamente 8 definición: "la cantidad de motivo
de fuerza centrípeta es la medida de esta fuerza que es proporcional al movimiento que genera en un momento
dado". [32, 407] Como nos vamos más adelante, Newton tiene en mente la siguiente medida de fuerza: suponga
que la fuerza mueve un cuerpo, inicialmente en reposo, desde el lugar P al lugar G (a lo largo de la línea a
través P y el centro de la fuerza) en un momento dado h . Entonces la "cantidad de motivo de fuerza centrípeta"
P G
(o simplemente la "fuerza motriz") es la cantidad M h , donde M es la cantidad de"materia" del cuerpo. (La
cantidad de
−→
P G
M h se puede pensar en como teniendo la dirección del segmento de línea dirigido P G. Por lo tanto,
−→
P G
vamos a menudo a elegir, anacrónicamente, a escribir la fuerza motriz como M h .) Observar que esta
medida de fuerza centrípeta aplica igualmente bien impulsivo y fuerzas continuas. (Por supuesto en el caso la
P G
medida M h tiende a cero como el tiempo transcurrido h tiende hacia cero. Pero esto no es un problema
para Newton, por gener-aliado compara las medidas por la formación de su relación, y cuando la parte superior
e inferior de una relación de cada enfoque cero, su proporción no es necesario.) Sin duda sería extraño si la
segunda ley se pretende aplicar a fuerzas impulsivas sólo, cuando la medida de fuerza en la segunda ley, es
decir, la "fuerza impresionado, motivo" se aplica igualmente bien a las fuerzas continuas. De hecho en su
discusión siguiendo la definición 8, Newton hace evidente que la "cantidad de fuerza de motivo" puede
utilizarse para medir la magnitud de una fuerza continua, pues observa que la "fuerza motriz [surge] de la
fuerza despertada y la cantidad de materia conjuntamente." [32, 407] Por la "fuerza despertado él significa la"
velocidad [es decir, la "velocidad" – ver Nota 2 abajo] que [la fuerza] genera en un momento dado, "[32,
P G
definición 7, 407] es decir, h en nuestra notación, una medida que se aplica igualmente bien a impulsivas y
continuadas las fuerzas. Pero el término "despertado" es generalmente utilizado por Newton sólo cuando la
velocidad cambia, no bruscamente, pero continuamente con el tiempo. Sigue que la fuerza de Newton"motiva"
debe aplicarse a las fuerzas continuas , y esto a su vez sugiere que la segunda ley, que prevé el "cambio en el
movimiento" de la "fuerza motriz", debe aplicarse también a las fuerzas continuadas.
3. El término "despertado" aparece otra vez en corolario 6 de las leyes [32, 423]:
Corolario 6
Si los cuerpos se están moviendo en forma alguna con respecto a uno con el otro y se insta por igual fuerzas
despertadas a lo largo de líneas paralelas, todas siguen a mover con respecto a otros de la misma manera como lo
harían si no eran actuados sobre por esas fuerzas.
Demostración corta de Newton hace un llamado a la segunda ley: "para esas fuerzas, actuando por igual
(proporcionalmente a las cantidades de los cuerpos a moverse) y a lo largo de líneas paralelas, voluntad
(Ley 2) mover todos los cuerpos igualmente (con respecto a la velocidad) y por lo tanto nunca cambiar
sus posiciones y movimientos con respecto a uno con el otro". Newton nunca habla de un impulso como
generando una aceleración. Solamente continua fuerzas aceleran cuerpos. Sigue que Newton tiene una
fuerza continua presente en corolario 6. Pero puesto que él invoca Ley 2 en la prueba, sólo podemos
concluir que la segunda ley se aplica a las fuerzas continuas. Así, una interpretación sólo impulso de la
segunda ley parece ser incompatible con la demostración de Newton de corolario 6.
168 B. Pourciau
4. En el scholium después corolario 6, encontramos famoso (o infame) Galileo atribución del neutonio
[32, 424]:
Por medio de las dos primeras leyes y los dos primeros corolarios Galileo encontró que el descenso de los
cuerpos pesados está en la relación cuadrada del tiempo y que el movimiento de proyectiles se produce en
una parábola, como experimento confirma, excepción en la medida en que estos movimientos son un
poco retardado por la resistencia del aire.
Eruditos que apoyan una interpretación sólo impulso de la segunda ley toman una mala opinión de esta
atribución. Viendo como el "cambio en el movimiento" en la segunda ley como un instantáneo cambio en
momentum (lineal o direccional), estos estudiosos concluyen reclamación de que Newton – que Galileo
2
utilizó la segunda ley para derivar el t Ley de caída y de la trayectoria parabólica de los proyectiles, es
mejor en serio exagerado y en el peor com-pletamente incorrecta. (En nuestra opinión, por supuesto, es su
interpretación de la segunda ley que es incorrecto.) "Rastros inconfundibles de la génesis del [segundo]
ley," escribe Herivel [21, 40, 41],
se encuentran en [el "libro de residuos"]. Allí Newton define la fuerza como el cambio en el movimiento
producido. Asimismo, el cambio en la Dirección del movimiento producido en un cuerpo está en la direc-
ción de la actuación de la fuerza en él, "un cuerpo debe mover así que es presionado". Pero esta definición de
fuerza, su conexión con el movimiento y su efecto en dirección surgió directamente de su discusión sobre el
problema de las colisiones. La influencia, si fue por lo tanto, de Descartes, no de Galileo. . .. . . . Por último,
no hay ninguna indicación en las primeras investigaciones de cualquier influencia de Galileo . . . en la
génesis de la segunda ley del movimiento. . . . la posibil idad de cualquier influencia efectivamente es
descartado por la forma real de la ley y su origen indudable en el estudio de Newton impulso y colisiones.
En un artículo dedicado a la mención de Galilea de Newton [7, XXXIX], Cohen afirma que
suponer que Galileo sabía que la relación cuantitativa (proporción exacta) entre impulso y cambio en la
cantidad de movimiento . . . o que Galileo había utilizado la segunda ley para encontrar la ley de la caída de
los cuerpos . . . sería malinterpretar tanto la Diálogo y los Discorsi o imaginar lo que Galileo "debe haber
hecho."
Cohen es contundente también en [8, 176], donde llama atribución de Newton una "mala representación
completa del procedimiento de Galileo." Ellis [14, 227] es justo como directo: "Newton simplemente
podría no tienen los conceptos que él utilizó en particular Ellis significa el cambio en el movimiento
producido por un impulso en la interpretación de un sólo impulso de la segunda ley] del trabajo de
Galileo." (Por supuesto los que objeto la atribución de las dos primeras leyes Galileo podrá objetar por
razones distintas a su interpretación de la segunda ley, el hecho de que Galileo no habla de fuerzas
impresionadas ser un.)
Según éstos y otros eruditos, entonces, una interpretación sólo impulso de la legislación sec-ond es
incompatible con la exactitud de la atribución de Galileo de Newton. Creer en una interpretación sólo impulso
es por lo tanto creo que Newton no sabía lo que estaba hablando cuando le atribuye a Galileo. Consideramos
esto algo fuerte evi-anza contra una sólo impulso de segunda ley. Más adelante veremos que cuando la segunda
ley es lo que sostenemos es la interpretación de Newton, una interpretación que llamamos la segunda ley
compuesto, entonces segunda ley de Newton se convierte en una progresión natural de la hipótesis de Galileo
sobre el movimiento y de Newton Galileo atribución luego
se convierte en el más apropiado. De hecho la segunda ley compuesta abarca una reafirmación de la
capitalización Galileo: en palabras de Galileo, "movimiento estable" (es decir, uniforme movimiento de
línea recta sobre un plano horizontal) compuestos de forma independiente con el "movimiento
naturalmente acelerado" de caída cuerpos para producir el movimiento parabólico real. (Véase [17, 268].)
Cuando un cuerpo cae, la gravedad uniforme, actuando igualmente en partículas individuales iguales de
tiempo, impresiona igual fuerzas sobre ese cuerpo y genera velocidades iguales [velocidad]; y en el tiempo
total que impresiona una fuerza total y genera una velocidad total [velocidad] proporcional al tiempo. Y los
espacios descritos en tiempos proporcionales son como los tiempos y las velocidades [velocidad]
conjuntamente, es decir, en la relación de cuadrados de los tiempos. . . . Y cuando un cuerpo es pro-jected a lo
largo de cualquier línea recta, su movimiento derivados de la proyección se agrava con el movimiento de
gravedad. . . . y la línea curva . . . que el cuerpo describirá una parábola. . ..
Newton considera claramente este pasaje "cayendo el cuerpo" como una aplicación sencilla y directa de las
primeras y segunda leyes de movimiento. Sin embargo, mediante una interpretación sólo impulso de la
legislación sec-ond, esta aplicación parece ser ni simple ni directa. De hecho, no un erudito, entre los muchos
que han comentado en este pasaje, ha demostrado cómo la ley de la caída y la trayectoria parabólica se siga de
las leyes de movimiento (por ellos mismos). (Lea, por ejemplo, [12, 476; 7; 8; 13; 14; 44, 521-522].) Esta
circunstancia puede verse sólo como evidencia en contra de una interpretación sólo impulso de la segunda
ley. Por el contrario, debemos demostrar en §30, t -ley cuadrada de la caída y la trayectoria parabólica siga
fácilmente y naturalmente de la segunda ley compuesta (junto con 1 de la ley). Este éxito constituye una sola
pieza, pero una pieza llamativa, de la evidencia de que la segunda ley compuesta es interpretación de Newton
de la segunda ley.
6 . Consideremos ahora la Proposición 6 (libro 1) de la 1687 Principia. Esta proposición, que aparece
como corolario 1 de una nueva proposición 6 en las segunda y terceros ediciones, registra una fórmula
para medir la magnitud de una fuerza centrípeta continua. En nuestra reproducción parcial de la figura de
Newton que ilustran la Proposición 6,
un cuerpo P, giran sobre un centro de S, describe la línea curva APQ, mientras que la línea recta ZPR toca la curva
en cualquier punto P; y QR, paralelo a distancia SP, se dibuja al gent tan desde cualquier otro punto Q de la curva,
y QT es dibujada perpendicular a esa distancia SP.
En estas condiciones, la Proposición 6 concluye que en el límite como Q tiende a P, la
SP 2×QT 2
"fuerza centrípeta es como · · · inversamente. " [32, 454; 5, 252] La demostración en
QR
170 B. Pourciau
la primera edición se abre con una invocación de la segunda ley: "para"la figura indefinidamente
pequeño QRPT el elemento de línea naciente QR, si se da el tiempo, es como la fuerza centrípeta (por la
Ley 2). . .. [32, 454, nota bb; 5, 252] Claramente se trata de una aplicación directa de la segunda ley para
una fuerza continua. Observe también que la segunda ley se utiliza, no para predecir un
cambio instantáneo de velocidad o "velocidad direccional", sino a predecir un cambio en la posición que
se produce en un momento dado. Este cambio de posición puede verse como
la desviación de R (aproximadamente donde el cuerpo habría sido en ausencia de la fuerza centrípeta)
a Q (donde el cuerpo realmente termina en presencia de la fuerza). Sería difícil construir una aplicación
de la segunda ley más desacuerdo con la afirmación de que la segunda ley se aplica solamente a una
fuerza impulsiva produciendo un cambio brusco en la velocidad con el tiempo no transcurrido.
8 . Para las pruebas finales que nos sometemos en nuestro caso contra un sólo impulso inter-interpretación
de la segunda ley, nos movemos hacia fuera de la publicado Principia y en revisiones propuestas de Newton
para la segunda edición, revisiones en escrito en el 1690s temprano. Además de algunas reestructuraciones
bastante grave de los Principiade primeras secciones, estos planes para la segunda edición incluyen algunas
alteraciones menos dramáticos, más estilísticos, en varios axiomas, lemas y propuestas. [29, VI, 538-567] De
particular relevancia para nosotros son rewordings propuesta de Newton de la segunda ley que se encuentran en
las páginas del manuscrito de la colección de Portsmouth de la biblioteca de la universidad Cambridge (U.L.C.
MS Add.
3965). [29, VI, 539-542; 8, 160 – 169] uno de estos rewordings dice lo siguiente:
Derecho II
Todo el nuevo movimiento por el cual se modifica el estado de un cuerpo es proporcional a la fuerza motriz
impresionado y se produce desde el lugar que el cuerpo lo contrario ocuparía el objetivo al que apunta la
fuerza impresionada.
Para ilustrar la ley, Newton dibuja la figura de abajo (en el que hemos sustituido sus cartas A, a, b, B con
nuestra propia P, Q, L, G) –
Interpretación de Newton de la segunda ley de Newton 171
– una figura absolutamente reñidas con cualquier interpretación sólo impulso de la segunda ley: la
"trayectoria es curva y no una línea recta," preocupa a Cohen (un partidario sólo de impulso),
así parece implicar que el nuevo movimiento es acelerado y uniforme no . . . que la 'fuerza' debe ser continua,
produciendo una aceleración constante, como gravedad, en lugar de un impulso. . .. Sin embargo a pesar de la
figura, allí puede no ser duda el texto sí mismo Newton 'impresionó a fuerza' es impulsivo. . .. [8 164-165]
¿Por no qué él tiene duda la fuerza impulsiva? Porque en el texto de Newton afirma que el "movimiento"
es proporcional a la "fuerza" y "sólo por impulsos", dice Cohen, "puede el 'movimiento' (que él interpreta
como 'cantidad de movimiento,' o impulso) ser proporcional a la ' fuerza." " (Por supuesto nos diría que el
problema es no con Newton, pero con la toma de "movimiento" que significa "cantidad de movimiento.'')
Cohen debe de alguna manera explicar la trayectoria curvada que Newton utiliza para ilustrar este
cambio de redacción de la segunda ley, pero no sólo no simple resolución de este conflicto, un conflicto
creado por la postura sólo impulso de Cohen. Su explicación es una construcción compleja y enrevesada:
The parabola-like orbit is thus an infinitesimal orbital segment, produced by a first-order force-impulse which
itself proves to be compounded of an infinite number of second-order infinitesimal force impulses, each of
which we may consider to be acting instantaneously in a time interval which is not the whole interval d t but
rather d t /n as n → ∞, itself infinitesimally small. [8, 181]
e
If “truth is ever found in simplicity, & not in y multiplicity & confusion of things,” as Newton tells us [26, 6;
31], then Cohen’s characterization cannot be the truth. Manifestly Newton himself regards the curved
trajectory as a simple and obvious illustration of the second law. When a commitment to an impulse-only
interpretation of the second law forces commentators into an overly complex explanation for what ought to be
a simple matter, it is time to question that interpretation. As we shall see later, from the point of view we
defend in this study – that Newton’s own interpretation of the second law is what we call the compound second
law, which applies equally well to impulsive and continuous forces – the explanation for the curved trajectory
is simplicity itself: it merely illustrates the meaning of the second law for the case of a continuous force!
9. It is time to be less critical and more constructive. We now begin to develop the compound second
law, an interpretation of Newton’s second law that applies equally well to both impulsive and continuous
forces. Later, after we have made several comments on this compound interpretation in §14–19, we will
argue that the compound second law is in fact Newton’s own understanding of his second law.
Here, once again, is the statement of the second law from the Principia [32, 416]:
Law 2
A change in motion is proportional to the motive force impressed and takes place along
172 B. Pourciau
Deciding what Newton means by the second law amounts to deciding what he means by “a change in
motion,” “the motive force impressed,” and “takes place along the straight line in which that force is
impressed.”
We begin with “a change in motion.” As we have seen, some impulse-only supporters assume that Newton
somehow forgot to insert “quantitas” into “mutationem motus” in his statement of the second law, for they take
“a change in motion” to mean “a change in the quantity of motion,” that is, to mean an instantaneous change in
(linear) momentum
– this despite the fact that Newton, a very careful writer, rewrote the second law at least fourteen times
between 1684 and 1693 and never once inserted the word “quantitas.” Perhaps we should assume Newton
has some other meaning in mind for “a change in motion.”
To see whether we can uncover that meaning, we first turn to Axiom 122 of the “Waste Book,” an
axiom that involves the oblique collision between two (hard) bodies [21, 159]:
Axiom 122
Therefore if the body p come from c and the body r from d soe much as p’s motion is changed towards w, so
much the motion of r will be changed towards v.
For the moment, let us consider this collision from a more modern stance: Suppose the two bodies, with
(modern) masses m and n, move before the collision with constant (modern vector)
velocities v0 and u0 and move after the collision with constant (mod-ern vector) velocities v1 and u1,
respectively. (We strive in our notation, by choosing lower or upper case letters, to preserve the distinction
between modern and Newtonian conceptions of similar notions. If, for example, by m we mean the modern
mass of a body, then by M we would mean Newton’s “quantity of matter” in that body.) By the conservation
of momentum,
But we can write the lefthand side (as well as the right) in terms of the “deflection” that develops in a given
time interval h:
−→
Here LQ stands for the directed line segment from L to Q. We call this directed line segment
the deflection (generated in time h) from the place L (where the first body would have been in time h in the
absence of the collision) to the place Q (where the first body actually ends up in time h after the collision). (We
might note here that although the
−→
notation LQ for a directed line segment is certainly anachronistic, the notion of a line segment with a given
direction, which occurs repeatedly in the Principia, is certainly
−→
LQ
not.) If we were to call the product m h the “change in motion” of the first body and if we were to define the
change in motion for the second body similarly, then the above equation m(v1 − v0) = −n(u1 − u0), written in
terms of deflections, asserts that “soe much as [the first body’s] motion is changed toward w, so much the motion
of [the second body] will be changed toward v,” [21, 159] just as Newton claims in Axiom 122! Replacing m,
standing for the modern mass, by M, standing for Newton’s “bulk” (moles, used in his earlier work, such as the
“Laws of Motion Paper” [21, 208]) or his “quantity of matter” (massa, used in the Principia), it is natural then
to ask whether the expression
−→
LQ
M h could be what Newton means by the “change in motion,” not just in Axiom 122 of the “Waste
Book,” but in the Principia’s second law as well.
10. For more evidence that the intended meaning of the “change in motion” in the second law involves
the deflection (in a given time) from uniform straight line motion, we consider a second example of
Newton’s work, this one a continuous rather than impulsive force example: Newton’s use of the second
law in the so-called “Locke manu-script.” After the English philosopher John Locke in 1689 asked him
whether the “truth of the two fundamental propositions, namely, Propositions 1 and 11 in Book One, could
not be demonstrated in some more simple way,” Newton responded by sending Locke a manuscript written
in English entitled “A Demonstration that the Planets by their gravity towards the sun may move in
Ellipses.” [5, 176; 4; 18, 293–301; 21, 246–254] In this manuscript, found among Locke’s papers, Newton
gives the following statement of his second law [21, 246]:
Hyp. 2 The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the force by which it is altered.
Newton applies this version of the second law to measure the magnitude of the con-tinuous centripetal
force in the case of a “body . . . attracted towards either focus of
174 B. Pourciau
any Ellipsis and by that attraction . . . made to move in the Perimeter of the Ellipsis.” [21, 251] (In the figure
below and in the subsequent lines from his demonstration, we have replaced Newton’s X, Y, and x, y with
the letters L, Q and l, q, respectively, just
−→
to be consistent with the notation LQ that we have already used for the deflection.) We reproduce part of
the figure he draws to illustrate his argument:
“Let P be the place of the body in the Ellipsis at any moment of time,” writes Newton to begin his
demonstration,
and PL the tangent in which the body would move uniformly were it not attracted and L the place in that tangent
at which it would arrive in any given part of time and Q the place in the perimeter of the Ellipsis at which the
body doth arrive in the same time by means of the attraction. [21, 252]
−→
The directed line segment LQ from L to Q is clearly the deflection we encountered ear-lier in Newton’s “Waste
Book” analysis of an oblique collision, namely the deflection from L, where the body would have arrived in the
given time “were it not attracted,” to Q, where the body actually arrives in the same given time “by means of the
attraction.” “And because the attraction in P is made towards F,” the argument continues,
and diverts the body from the tangent PL, . . . translat[ing the body] from L to Q: the line LQ generated by the force
of attraction in P must be proportional to that force and parallel to its direction to PF. . . . And in like manner if pl be
the tangent of the Ellipsis at p and lq [be the line generated in the same given time by the force of attraction in p] . . .
then “LQ [is] to lq therefore as the attraction in P [is] to the attraction in p by Hypoth: 2 and 3.” [21, 252,
and 255 Note d1] (Hypothesis 3 is the parallelogram rule for “com-pounding motions.”)
Thus Newton compares the magnitude of the force at P to the magnitude of the force at p by comparing the
deflection LQ (generated in a given time) at P to the deflection lq (generated in that same given time) at p, and
in support of this proportionality between deflection and force he cites Hypothesis 2, his English wording of the
second law, that the “alteration of motion is ever proportional to the force.” Clearly Newton regards his citation
of the second law (in the form of Hypothesis 2) as a simple and direct application of this law. Of course no
scholar wedded to an impulse-only interpretation of the second law, with the “alteration of motion” taken to be
the change in (linear) momentum due to an impulse, could ever see an application of the second law to a
continuous force as either simple or direct, but because we do not share this impulse-only view, we are free to
accept the simple and obvious explanation for this application of the second law in the Locke manuscript:
Newton’s definition for the “alteration of motion” must make
Newton’s Interpretation of Newton’s Second Law 175
−→
LQ
it manifestly proportional to the deflection h generated in a given time. Our earlier example, the “Waste
Book” analysis of an oblique collision, points to the “quantity of matter” M as the correct proportionality
constant, which leads us to believe that New-ton’s “alteration of motion” in Hypothesis 2 of the Locke
manuscript, and by natural
−→
LQ
extension Newton’s “change in motion” in Law 2 of the Principia, is by definition M h . 11. Newton’s
second law – “A change in motion is proportional to the motive force impressed. . .” – relates two different
quantities: the “change in motion” and the “motive
−→
LQ
force.” We have just been arguing that by a “change in motion” Newton means M h . Now we ask, what does
he mean by the “motive force”? The “motive force” is short for the “motive quantity of centripetal force,” where,
according to Definition 8 of the Principia, “the motive quantity of centripetal force is the measure of this force
that is proportional to the motion which it generates in a given time.” [32, 407] But how are we intended to
understand the “motion which it generates in a given time”? In his comments that follow Definition 8, Newton
says the “motive force [arises] from the accelerative force and the quantity of matter jointly.” And what does
Newton mean by the “accelera-tive force”? The “accelerative force” is short for the “accelerative quantity of
centripetal force,” which by Definition 7 is the “measure of the force that is proportional to the velocity which it
generates in a given time.” [32, 407].
The meaning of the “motive force” in the second law therefore depends finally on the meaning of the
“velocity which [the centripetal force] generates in a given time.” But the meaning of this ‘generated velocity’ is
less clear than it might seem. Why? Because according to Newton the “accelerative force” refers to the “places of
bodies [seeking a center],” [32, 407] and consequently the “accelerative force” cannot depend on the speed or
direction of the body at the time when the force is applied, but only the location of the body. Yet whatever
Newton might mean by the “velocity which [the force] generates in a given time,” without evidence to the
contrary this ‘generated velocity’ might well vary with either the speed or direction of the body – unless of course
we are guaranteed otherwise by some axiom or law. Since no such axiom or law has been stated at this point in
the Principia (the definitions naturally precede the laws), we have to assume that Newton intends the “velocity
which [the force] generates in a given time” to be measured on a body having some ‘standard’ speed and
‘standard’ direction. But the only speed that could reasonably serve as a ‘standard’ speed would be speed zero,
and the only direction that could reasonably serve as a ‘standard’ direction would be along the line which passes
through the center of force. (As Newton has restricted himself in these definitions to a centripetal force, we do
in fact have a center of force.) In other words, the “velocity which [the force] generates in a given time” must be
measured on a body initially at rest and subsequently moved by the force along a ray from the center of force.
Without this assumption, Definition 7 (for the “accelerative force”) and hence Definition 8 (for the “motive
force”) are rendered unusable by the a priori possibility that the “velocity which [the force] generates in a given
time” might vary with the speed or direction which the body has when the force is applied.
We have been arguing abstractly, not historically, but Newton himself confirms this reading of Definition 7.
Just after Definition 7, he writes that the “force that produces gravity . . . is everywhere the same at equal
distances, because it equally accelerates all
P G/ h
h
176 B. Pourciau
falling bodies. . ..” [32, 407] And much later in the Principia, in his discussion of Propo-sition 19 (Book 3) on
the shape of a planet, he measures the motive force of gravity at the latitude of Paris by calculating the distance
a body falls from rest at that latitude in one second: a “body falling in a vacuum will describe a space of 2,174
lines in the time of one second.” [32, 822] Not only Newton, but scientists of the 17th century generally, from
Galileo onward – Mersenne, Riccioli, and Huygens, just to mention the most prominent
– used the distance fallen in the first second as the measure of surface gravity. Of course in Newton’s case it is
not just gravity that he measures by the movement produced on a body at rest, but other forces as well. In
Propositions 35 and 38 of Book 2, for example, on the resistance to a globe moving in a “fluid medium,” he
applies a nondimensional measure of resistance forces which, as he puts it in the first edition, uses “the force
that, uniformly impressed . . . in the time in which the globe by progressing described 2/3 of its own diameter,
could generate the globe’s velocity in that body.” [40, 308 and Note 42 on 293] As George Smith notes, the Latin
in the first edition is open to two inter-pretations: “progressing uniformly at its acquired velocity” or “progressing
from rest to its acquired velocity.” Given our contention that Newton generally measures forces with the
displacement produced on a body at rest, we would naturally vote for the latter interpretation, and indeed, when
Newton rewrote this section for the second edition, his revision removed any doubt that he had the “from rest”
interpretation in mind.
Let us agree then that the “accelerative force,” that is, the “velocity which [the force] generates in a given
time,” is by definition always measured on a body initially at rest. Now suppose, under the influence of a
centripetal force, that a body of “quantity of matter” M in a given time h falls from rest from P to G along the
line through the center of force. How then does Newton intend us to understand the “velocity which [the force]
generates” in this given time h? A reader today, thinking about the modern concept of
acceleration, might be inclined to represent th is ‘generated velocity ’ by , but New-
ton himself would surely represent it by P G/ h (or perhaps by 2P G/ h, in the case of a “uniform” centripetal
force). For instance, in his argument for Proposition 10 (Book 2), we find the following sentence (where we have
made only a notational change, replacing Newton’s N, I, and t with our P, G, and h): “In a body falling and
describing in its fall the space PG, gravity generates a velocity by which twice that space could have been
P G
described in the same time, as Galileo proved, that is, the velocity 2 h . . ..”[32, 657] Thus, following Newton’s
lead we shall take the “velocity which [the force] generates” in the given time h, that is, the “accelerative force,”
P G
to be the quantity h . But then, because the “motive force [arises] from the accelerative force and the quantity
of matter
−→
P G P G
jointly,” we can deduce the meaning of “motive force”: M h , or, even better, M h , if we wish to register
the direction of the force.
12. Moving on to the last piece of the second law, we have only to decide what New-ton means when he
writes that the “change in motion” must “take place along the straight line in which that force is impressed.” But
given our interpretation for the “change in motion” and the “motive force,” this can only mean that the direction
of the “change in
−→ −→
LQ P G
motion” M h is the same as the direction of the “motive force” M h , or, equivalently,
−→
that the directed line segment LQ has the same direction as the directed line segment
−→
P G.
13. Let us put the pieces together now, and write down our (and we believe Newton’s own) interpretation of the
second law. We call it the Compound Second Law. Suppose a body at rest at P, acted on by a given force, moves along
a line from P to G in time h. (This force may be impulsive, uniform, or continuously varying. In the continuously
varying case, we require the force to be centripetal. Later we shall see how the Compound Second Law can be made
to apply to noncentripetal forces, such as resistance forces.) Suppose the same body, this time in uniform straight line
motion before arriving at P, when acted on by the same force at P, moves along a line or a curve from P to Q in the
same time h. If this force had not acted, this body in uniform straight line motion, by the first law, would have continued
its uniform straight line motion, moving from P to L, say, in time
−→
h. We call the directed line segment LQ the moving deflection generated in time h or just the moving
deflection for short, and we think of the force as deflecting the body from L (where it would have come to in the
absence of the force) to Q (where it actually comes
−→
to in the presence of the force). Similarly, we call P G the resting deflection generated in time h or just the resting
deflection. If the body has “quantity of matter” M, we call
−→
LQ
M h the change in motion (generated in time h) and M in time h).
−→
PG
the motive force (generated
h
−→ −→
LQ PG
M =M .
h h
−→ −→
LQ = P G .
This law holds exactly for any h when the force is either impulsive or uniform and exactly in the limit as h
tends toward zero when the force is centripetal and continuously varying.
14. The definition of impulsive, continuous, and centripetal force. Up to this point, we have been using the
terms “impulsive force,” “continuous force,” and “centripetal force” rather loosely, depending on the reader’s
own understanding and intuition to give our references to such forces some meaning. In so doing, because we
have used these
178 B. Pourciau
terms not just informally but now formally (in the statement of the compound second law above), we have
violated a fundamental rule of correct reasoning: agree on the meaning of an assertion before making that
assertion. Definitions of these kinds of force, from the logical point of view, should have appeared in this
paper, as they do in the Principia, before the statement of the second law. But from an explanatory point of
view, it is easier to motivate these definitions if we can refer to the second law.
Better late than never, then, let us ask how one might characterize “impulsive force,” “continuous force,” and
“centripetal force” in definitions that would appear before the statement of the second law. In the Principia,
forces are characterized in terms of the motions generated in bodies. In particular, by the first law of motion it is
a deflection from uniform straight line motion which announces the presence of a force, and it is then the
magnitude and direction of that deflection which is the natural candidate to indicate the character of that force.
Can we use either deflection, the moving deflection
−→ −→
LQ or the resting deflection P G? Well, after we have stated and assumed the compound second law, we can use
either deflection to characterize the force, because the com-pound second law tells us that these two deflections
are equal (or “equal in the limit,” an expression that we will make precise below). But before the compound
second law is stated, the situation is different, because before the compound second law is assumed it is
conceivable a priori that the “effect of a force” on a given body (that is, the deflection) might depend on the
speed or direction of that body at the time the force is applied. This possibility makes it impossible to define the
kind of force in terms of the moving
−→
deflection LQ, for the kind of force (impulsive or continuous, say) cannot have any conceivable dependence on
the speed or direction which a body has when the force acts. We just cannot have a definition that might tell us
that a force is impulsive when it acts on a given moving body, but continuous when that same force acts on that
same body moving with a different speed or direction. Yet it is only through the compound second law that we
know the “effect of a force” is in fact independent of the speed and direction
−→ −→
of the body’s motion: that the moving deflection LQ equals the resting deflection P G. It follows that any
definitions for “impulsive force,” “continuous force,” and “cen-tripetal force” which appear before the
statement of the second law must be given in terms of what the force does to a body at rest, that is, in
terms of the resting deflection
−→
P G. But these definitions must come before the second law, because the statement of
the second law refers to these forces. So there is no choice: we must characterize the
−→
kinds of force in terms of the resting deflection P G.
Let us begin with the concept of an “impulsive force.” Intuitively, a body at rest which instantaneously
achieves a uniform straight line motion would announce the presence of an impulse. We can easily turn this
P G
into a definition: If a body at rest at P begins to move along a line, reaching G in time h, and if h has
the same value for all times h, we say an impulse or an impulsive force acts at P. Newton would say that
an impulse is a kind of force, but not a “finite force,” where Newton’s meaning of “finite force” is revealed
in Lemma 10 (Book 1):
Lemma 10
The spaces which a body describes when urged by any finite force . . . are at the very beginning of the motion
in the squared ratio of the times. [32, 437–438]
We may restate Lemma 10 as a definition: if a body initially at rest moves from P to G in time h and the limit of
2
P G/ h is finite and nonzero, we say that a finite force acts
at P. (Read [36] for more on Lemma 10 and [37] for more on Newton’s surprisingly good understanding
P G
of limits.) In the case of an impulsive force, the ratio h remains a nonzero constant, which implies the
P G
ratio h 2 grows arbitrarily large as the time h tends toward zero. Thus for Newton an impulsive force is
not a finite force. For that reason we might call it an “infinite force.”
The finite forces addressed in the Principia’s Definitions 6, 7, and 8 – the definitions of the absolute quantity,
the accelerative quantity, and the motive quantity of centrip-etal force – are measures of centripetal forces. In
his Definition 5, Newton writes that a “centripetal force is the force by which bodies . . . tend toward some point
as to a center.” [32, 405] Of course a body at rest would be said to “tend toward some point,” if it falls along a
line through that fixed point. Thus we say a centripetal force acts in a given region of space provided for some
fixed point S every body initially at rest in this region falls along a line through S. Given a finite centripetal force
acting in a given
−→
PG
region, we say the force is continuous if the limit (as h tends to zero) of the ratio
h2
varies continuously (in magnitude and direction) as P varies over the given region. If this limiting value is
constant in magnitude and direction as P varies over the region, we say the force is uniform. Thus by a
uniform force we mean a force which has constant magnitude and parallel “lines of force.” We may regard
a uniform force as centripetal provided we imagine the center of force S as being “infinitely remote.” (A
uniform force, as we have just defined it, where the “lines of force” are parallel, should not be confused
with a force having constant magnitude but nonparallel “lines of force” directed toward a fixed point. Such
“uniform centripetal forces” appear only in Section 10 of the Prin-cipia, where Newton studies “the motion
of bodies on given surfaces and the oscillating motion of simple pendulums.”)
We have given definitions for impulsive, centripetal, continuous, and uniform force in terms of the motion
generated on a body at rest, because in any formal development these definitions would have to appear before the
statement of the second law, that is, at a point in the exposition where it is conceivable that definitions in terms
of a body in motion would be invalid. But after the second law has been stated and assumed, the situation
changes, for the compound second law tells us the moving deflection equals (or equals in the limit) the resting
deflection. In the wake of the compound second law,
−→
therefore, the moving deflection LQ may be used to test for the impulsive, centripetal,
−→
continuous, and uniform forces that we defined in terms of the resting deflection P G. To obtain these tests,
we merely replace in our definitions the resting deflection by the moving deflection.
−→ −→
15. The law LQ = P G holds in the limit. In our statement of the compound sec-
−→ −→
ond law, the equality LQ = P G between the moving and resting deflections is said to hold “in the limit
as h tends toward zero” when the (centripetal) force is continuous
−→
and varying. What does this mean? We mean that although the moving deflection LQ
−→
and the resting deflection P G may not be exactly equal when the force is continuous and
−→ −→
varying, still the difference LQ − P G becomes so small so fast, as h tends toward zero,
−→
−→
−→
−→
180 B. Pourciau
that this difference is small even compared with h2, which itself is very small. More pre-
cisely, we mean that the ratio LQ − P G → → as h → 0. (In general, given two quantities
h2 0
which each tend toward zero, we can compare the rates at which they tend toward zero by studying their ratio. If
their ratio tends toward zero, for example, then the quantity in the numerator “tends toward zero faster” than the
2
quantity in the denominator. See [36; 37].) Using the standard mathematical notation o(h ) to represent any
quantity that
2
2 o(h )
tends toward zero faster than h , that is, any quantity satisfying h
2
→ 0 as h → 0,
−→ −→ 2
we could equivalently write our “equality in the limit” as LQ = P G + o(h ), or, if we
−→ −→
prefer, as an actual equality in the limit: lim LQ lim PG .
h→ 0 =h
h2 → 0 h2
16. Alternate formulations of the compound second law. We have phrased the com-pound second law in
terms of the moving and resting deflections, in part because Newton himself phrases his own interpretation of
the second law in just this way – more about
this later – but we could have formulated the compound second law in other equivalent
−→
ways. For example, the compound second law tells us the effect P G of the force on a body at rest is a vector, not
just because it has both magnitude and direction, but also because
−→
it combines according to the parallelogram law of vector addition with the effect P L
−→ −→ −→
of uniform straight line motion to give the actual location of the body: P Q = P L + P G.
−→
(Of course for a varying continuous force this formula for P Q would not be exact, but would hold “exactly
2
in the limit,” and by this we mean it would hold approximately, with an error which is o(h ).) Naturally
Newton does not use the words “vector” or “vector addition,” but he uses both these concepts when he
interprets the second law, as shall see later when we examine a particular manuscript written in the early
1690s.
Though he does not use the words “vector addition,” Newton does write of motions “compounding,” and in
the language of compounding we can reword the compound second law: From the uniform straight line motion
from P to L that would have occurred
−→
in time h in the absence of a force and from the motion P G that would have been gen-erated by the force
acting on the body at rest, there emerges the actual motion along
−→ −→
a path from P to Q, compounded from the two independent motions P L and P G . In
this compounding, the motions P L and P G combine independently, with neither having any effect on the other.
This law is exact for impulsive and uniform forces and exact in the limit for continuous varying forces. The
independent compounding of motions (at least for horizontal “equable motion” and vertically downward
“naturally acceler-ated motion”) appears as a fundamental assumption in Galileo’s Two New Sciences [17, 222],
where he demonstrates that this compounding, in which these two motions “do not alter, disturb, or impede one
another,” yields a parabolic trajectory. Huygens follows and
slightly generalizes Galileo, as we see from reading the second and third hypotheses of motion in Horologium
Oscillatorium: “By the action of gravity . . . bodies are moved by a motion composed both of uniform motion in
one direction or another and of a motion downward due to gravity. These two motions can be considered
separately, with neither being impeded by the other.” [22, 33] In the present study, we see the Principia’s state-
ment of the second law as having everything to do with the compounding of motions, but Newtonian
commentators generally see the second law and compounding as indepen-dent assumptions. (See, as just one
example, [7, XXXVIII].) There have, though, been rare exceptions. The scientist and philosopher William
Whewell, in his 1819 textbook, An Elementary Treatise on Mechanics [45], gives the following interpretation
specifi-cally for continuous forces only: “The Second Law of Motion. When any force acts upon a body in
motion, the motion which the force would produce in the body at rest is compounded with the previous motion
of the body.”
Speaking of Galileo (whose sandal prints are all over our interpretation of the second law, just as Newton
himself claims – see §30–31), we may also formulate the second law in terms of an invariance principle: If an
observer in one reference frame sees a body at
−→
rest begin to fall and measures the resting deflection P G, then an observer in a second frame moving with
uniform straight line motion with respect to the first frame will see
−→
the same body in motion and will measure a moving deflection LQ equal to (or equal in
−→ −→
the limit to) P G . In the particular case of a varying continuous force, for example, LQ
−→ −→−→ 2
is equal in the limit to P G, by which we mean that LQ = P G + o(h ) or, equivalently,
−→ −→
that lim LQ lim PG , and this implies that each observer will measure the same
h → 0 h2 =h → 0 h2
(modern vector) acceleration of the body at P. The frames will be “equivalent as far as dynamical
experiments are concerned – either frame may be assumed stationary and the other frame in motion, with
all the same laws of mechanics providing correct explana-tions for observed trajectories.” [16, 12–10] This
is what physicists today call “Galilean relativity” or “Galilean invariance.” Honoring Galileo in this way
has some historical justification, given his famous and colorful description in the Dialogo of gnats, flies,
fish, and droplets moving in a room below deck of a ship first at rest and then in uniform straight line
motion. Newton probably never read Galileo (see [7]), but in Newton’s lifetime this invariance principle
appeared prominently in two places: as Corollary 5 to the Laws of Motion in the Principia and, in a paper
well known to Newton, “On the Motion of Bodies Resulting From Impact” by Huygens, where the
invariance principle took the following form:
The motion of bodies and their equal and unequal speeds are to be understood respec-tively, in relation to other
bodies which are considered at rest, even though perhaps both the former and the latter are involved in another
common motion. And accordingly, when two bodies collide with one another, even if both together are further
subject to another uniform motion, they will move each other with respect to a body that is carried by the same
common motion no differently than if this motion extraneous to all were absent. [23, 1]
17. Where is f = ma? We have now phrased the compound second law in terms of deflections, vector
addition, compounding, and Galilean invariance. None of these
182 B. Pourciau
formulations has the f = ma form that physicists today call Newton’s second law. Nev-ertheless, let us show that
by passing to the limit as the time interval h shrinks toward zero, we can derive from the compound second law
a Newtonian version of the familiar
modern form of the second law. −→
P G
We may feel uncomfortable with the motive force M h as a measure of the force at P, for this
measure in the continuous case tends to zero as h tends to zero. Yet for Newton this is not a problem,
because he generally compares two forces by forming the ratio of their motive or accelerative forces. The
numerator and denominator of such a ratio each will tend to zero, but the ratio of such “evanescent
quantities” may well tend to a nonzero, finite limit which then serves to quantify the comparison of the two
forces. As just one illustration of such a comparison, consider the demonstration of Proposition 10 (Book
2), where we see Newton compare the resistance of a given medium to gravity [32, 657]:
In a body falling and describing in its fall the space NI, gravity generates a velocity by which twice that space
could have been described in the same time, as Galileo proved,
that is, the velocity 2N I ; . . . And accordingly, . . .the resistance will be to gravity as
t
GH HI 2N I
2M I ×N I to .
T − t + t ×H I t
After some calculations and estimates, Newton then takes the limit of this ratio, finding
2 2
“the resistance will now be to gravity as . . . 3S 1 + Q to 4R .”
As we noted, however, the modern physicist does not proceed this way, but seeks instead a “stand-alone” or
“absolute” measure of the force at a given point P. Newton’s
−→
P G
motive force M h is more a “relative” measure of force: it can be used to relate or compare one force with
another, but since (in the continuous force case) it tends to zero as h tends to zero, we cannot take the limit and
expect to get a useful measure of the
−→
P G
force at P. On the other hand, the quantity M h 2 has no such problem, for by Newton’s
−→
Lemma 10 (Section 1, Book 1) the limit of P G is finite and nonzero: the space PG
h2
“which a body describes when urged by any finite force . . . [is] at the very beginning of the motion [that
is, in the limit as the time tends toward zero] in the squared ratio of
−→ −→
the times.” [32, 437–438] Let us call A 0
lim 2 h2
PG A and
lim 2 h2
LQ
the resting and
≡ h→0 ≡ h→0
F MA
measures of force, the compound second law (which we believe to be Newton’s own interpretation of the second
law) implies a “limiting version” of the compound second law which has the form of the modern second law.
(By the way, Newton appears to be quite aware of this limiting version of his second law. For example, in his
demonstration for Proposition 24, Book 2, he asserts that the “velocity that a given force can generate in a given
time in a given quantity of matter is as the force and the time directly and the matter inversely. . . .This is manifest
from the second law of motion.” [32, 700].
18. A physical law, but does the matter matter? In its impulse-only interpretation, the second law tells us an
impulse produces a “change in motion” proportional to the magnitude of the impulse. But supporters of this
interpretation never supply an inde-pendent way to gauge the magnitude of the impulse (that is, other than by
observing the “change in motion”), and this turns the impulse-only second law into a definition. In
contrast, the compound second law affirms Galilean invariance, a fundamental physical
−→ −→
law: the effect LQ of a force on a moving body is the same as the effect P G of that force on the same body at
rest. Observe, however, that the “quantity of matter” M cancels out
−→ −→
in the compound second law, leaving only the basic equality LQ = P G. It follows that the “quantity of matter”
plays only a ceremonial role in the compound interpretation of
−→
PG −→
the second law. Of course for a given motive , the resting deflection P
force M h G(and
therefore the moving deflection as well) varies inversely as the “quantity of matter” M. (Newton himself puts it
this way: “To achieve the same motion [that is, to achieve the
−→
LQ
same value of M h ], the translation of a greater body by an impressed force is less, and of a lesser one
greater.” [29, VI, 543]) But this fact contains no real information
−→ −→
beyond the equality LQ = P G, for it derives from this equality plus a mere definition,
−→
P G
namely the definition of motive force as M h . The “quantity of matter” M can enter nontrivially only when
an alternate way – besides the definition itself – of computing the motive force is available. For example,
throughout Book 2 the deceleration produced by a given resistance force depends on the mass of the body. The
resistance force then, often proportional to the speed or the speed squared, is a motive (not accelerative) force,
and the Compound Second Law would be applied in its “massful” rather than massless form. Apart from such
cases, however, for instance in Book 1 generally, the actual physical
−→ −→
content of the second law lies in the equality LQ = P G between the moving and resting deflections, and
the “quantity of matter” plays an integral role – a role in the law itself and not just in a definition – only in
the third law of motion.
19. Newtonian velocity. It is a common view among Newtonian scholars that the “change in motion” in
the Principia’s statement of the second law should be understood as the “change in momentum,” where by the
“change in momentum” some of these scholars [10, 65–66; 32, 111; 2, 226; 14, 275; 10, 46] mean M v = M v,
with v being the change in speed, while others [9, 164–165; 13, 112; 12, 472] appear to
mean Mv = M v with v being the change in modern vector velocity. We took note of such views in §1
(Arguments 2 and 4) and presented several counterarguments. Even accepting these counterarguments, however,
we can in fact see the “change in motion” in the second law as what we might call a “Newtonian change in
momentum,” provided we are careful to understand the “change in velocity,” not as the change in speed nor as
the change in modern vector velocity, but rather in a way more consistent with Newton’s preference for using
the deflection to measure the force.
To see this, let us consider for simplicity the case of a uniform force. Given a body
−→
P G
initially at rest, it would of course be appropriate to call 2 h the “velocity generated” (by the force in the
time h), because the body actually traverses the segment PG in time h.
−→
On the other hand, for a body initially in motion, the moving deflection LQ equals the
−→
−→ LQ
resting deflection P G, making it in this case natural also to call 2 h the “velocity
184 B. Pourciau
generated” (by the force in time h) – even though the body does not actually traverse
−→
−→ −→ LQ
the segment LQ. Provided we remember to use V ≡ 2 h , this “Newtonian change in
−→ −→
LQ PG
velocity,” then our interpretation of the second law, M h =M h , tells us the “New-
−→
−→ PG
! (Notice, by
tonian change in momentum” equals the motive force: M V = M h the
−→
way, that this “Newtonian change in momentum” M V is not a “change in Newtonian
−→
momentum,” – indeed it creates only nonsense to move the in M V in front of the M
−→
– nor is the “Newtonian change in velocity” a “change in Newtonian velocity,” for V is not in fact a difference
of “Newtonian velocities,” but rather a “deflection per unit time.”)
We have just formulated the compound second law as “Newtonian change in momen-tum” equals motive
force, but perhaps we should stress again that this “Newtonian change in momentum” is neither the change in
linear momentum nor the change in vector momentum that we may be familiar with today. In particular, let us
stress the difference between how we measure force today, through the change in modern vector
velocity, v ≡ v(t0 + h) − v(t0), and how Newton measures force in the Principia,
−→
−→ LQ −→
through the “Newtonian change in velocity,” V ≡ 2 h . It is true that v and V
yield equivalent directed line segments for impulsive and uniform forces, but even so they are defined and
thus calculated quite differently. Indeed,
while
−→
V
−→
2 LQ 2 (Q L) .
(The grammatically inclined might say that Newton is more at home with the future perfect subjunctive.)
−→
Moreover, v and V are not equal for a varying continuous force. Indeed if the vector function r = r(t
) records the positions of a moving body in space, it turns out that
1
2
v = a(t0)h + 2 r (t0)h + · · ·
while
−→ 1 2
20. We began this study with a review and rebuttal of the main lines of argument that have appeared over the
years in favor of an impulse-only interpretation for the second law. We then presented more direct evidence
against an impulse-only interpretation, pointing out the many passages – demonstrations, propositions,
corollaries, definitions, scholia, revisions, and remarks – that appear overly complex, incongruous, or just plain
hard to explain, when we take an impulse-only view of the second law. Following this, two examples from
Newton’s dynamical studies – one on oblique collisions in the “Waste Book,” the other on elliptical motion in
the Newton-Locke manuscripts – helped us to develop the compound second law, an interpretation of the second
law that applies directly to both impulsive and continuous forces. Here and there along the way we have professed
our belief that this compound second law is in fact Newton’s own interpretation of the second law. It is finally
time to back up this claim.
How should we proceed to make the case for our compound interpretation? More generally, how should
one go about making the case that a particular interpretation of some text is the correct interpretation? Let
us turn for advice to an expert, a careful, even obsessive, Biblical scholar who has given us sixteen
hermeneutic rules to guide the interpretation of scripture. Here, for example, are rules eight and nine:
ch e
8. To choose those constructions w . . . reduce contemporary visions to y greatest har-mony of their parts.
ch
9. To choose those constructions w without straining reduce things to the greatest sim-plicity.
e
is manifest by the precedent Rule. Truth is ever found in simplicity, & not in y multiplicity
e ch
& confusion of things. As y world, w to the naked eye exhibits the greatest variety of objects, appears very simple
in its internall constitution when surveyed by a philosophic understanding, and so much ye simpler by how much the
better it is understood. . ..
This Biblical scholar – no surprise – is Newton himself, and these rules of interpretation appear in his “Treatise
on the Apocalypse” (ca. 1672). [26, 6; 31] Of course Newton’s rules for textual analysis have been quoted here
more for fun than for any belief that
186 B. Pourciau
they support our argument in a serious way. We do not need Newton to tell us that an interpretation of the
second law of motion which spreads both harmony and simplicity across the pages of the Principia would
be a hard interpretation to resist.
Believing with Newton that “truth is ever found in simplicity,” let us return to those places and passages
in the Principia and elsewhere that appeared confused, overly com-plex, incongruous, or mistaken under
an impulse-only interpretation of the second law and ask these questions: Does this complication and
confusion turn into simplicity and harmony under the compound interpretation? Does the unexplainable
become explain-able, even perhaps natural and obvious? The answer, again and again, is yes. Taking all
these individual increments in simplicity and harmony and explanatory power together, the evidence that
the compound second law is in fact Newton’s own interpretation be-comes overwhelming.
We begin in the “Waste Book.” Recall that in one argument for interpreting the “change in motion” as
the “change in quantity of motion” (that is, as M v = M v, where v is a change in speed), some commentators
point to apparent ancestors in the “Waste Book” of the Principia’s statement of the second law, such as
“Axiome 115”:
Soe much force a[s] is required to generate any quantity of motion in a body, so much is required to destroy
it, and e contra. [21, 158]
Clearly in this early version of the second law the force does generate a change in the “quantity of motion.”
Blay [2, 226–227], as we have seen, makes a similar claim, based not on axioms in the “Waste Book”, but
on the way Newton cites the second law in two demonstrations in Book 2 of the Principia:
Two references to Law 2 Newton gives in the context of the proofs worked out in Book
II confirm [the impulse-only] interpretation of the law. Proposition 3 reads thus: “will be as the absolute forces
with which the body is acted upon in the beginning of each of the times, and therefore (by Law II) as the
increments of the velocities;” and Proposition 8 reads: “for the increment PQ of the velocity is (by Law II)
proportional to the generating force KC.” In neither case is time mentioned. Law II appears then to be
associated with an impulse model of action (action by impact). . ..
Does an invocation of the second law (or one of its ancestors), in order to infer that the increment in speed is
proportional to the force, necessarily imply that the “change in motion” in the Principia’s second law stands for
the “change in quantity of motion,” as Blay, Cohen, and others claim? In §1 (see the discussions following
Arguments 1 and 2), we have given counterarguments to this claim, and we have no wish to repeat those
counterarguments here, but this claim does suggest a first test for our interpretation of the second law: Can the
compound second law “explain” those instances where Newton cites the second law to ensure the proportionality
between the increment in speed and the force? Yes. Can the compound interpretation even explain the many
other cases of resisted motion in Book 2, where the second law may not be cited, but where Newton measures
the resistance (or the resistance together with a component of an oblique force) with a change in speed? Yes
again. In fact every instance where Newton measures a force with a change in speed involves a very special
situation: the force being measured is parallel to the direction of motion. And for the particular case of a force
parallel to the direction of motion, the compound second law implies that the increment in speed
(generated in a given time) is in fact proportional to that parallel force (generated in that same given time)!
Let us see why. Suppose a body with “quantity of matter” M moves under the influence of some force.
We first suppose that the net force on this body is at all times parallel to the direction of motion, resulting
in a straight line motion. When the body comes to P, assume it has acquired a speed which, in the absence
of any force at P, would carry that body in uniform straight line motion from P to L, say, in time h. But
in the presence of the force at P, suppose the body actu-ally moves from P to Q in the time h. Assume the
force at P (impulsive or uniform
−→
P G
for now) has an accelerative force equal to h . By definition this means, that had the body been at rest
at P, it would have moved from P to G in the time h under the influence of this force. Then according to
the compound second law, the moving
−→ −→
deflection LQ equals the resting deflection P G, and it follows that the actual
−→ −→ −→ −→ −→ −→
displacement P Q of the body (in time h) is P Q = P L + LQ = P L + P G. But in straight line motion,
this vector addition becomes scalar addition (or scalar subtraction in the case where the force is
opposed to the direction of motion, as with resistance forces, for example), so that (if v0 denotes the
speed of the body at P) P Q = P L + P G = v0h ± P G, and dividing by h we see that
PQ PG
= v0 ± .
h h
P G
Hence the increment in (average) speed is ± h , which is obviously proportional to the motive force
P G
M h . All this is exact when the force is either impulsive or uniform continuous. A varying continuous force
would merely introduce a negligible error term:
PQ PG
= v0 ± + o(h),
h h
where o(h) denotes a quantity which tends toward zero faster than h itself, in the sense
−→
P G
that o(h)/ h → 0 as h → 0. The increment in (average) speed would then be ± h +o(h) which is “proportional
P G
in the limit” to the motive force M h (by which we mean that the ratio tends toward a finite, nonzero constant,
namely M.) Thus, at least in the case where the net force on the body remains parallel to the direction of motion,
we have established that the change in speed is proportional to that parallel force.
Now suppose that the net force on the body is not in the direction of motion. The body then moves
along a curved trajectory rather than a straight line, but we can still apply the above argument using
the tangent line PL to this trajectory and using as our parallel force the component of the net force which is
parallel to the direction of motion at P. The only change in the argument is that Q now lies on the curved
trajectory and not on the tangent line, but this just introduces a second negligible error term into our speed
equation –
PQ PG
= v0 ± + o(h) + o(h)
h h
PG
= v0 ± + o(h) h
188 B. Pourciau
– and once again we conclude that the change in speed is proportional (exactly or in the limit) to the
motive force.
Thus the compound second law has the following simple corollary which explains every instance
where Newton employs an increment in speed to measure a force:
The increment in speed (generated in a given time) is proportional to the motive force (generated in the
same given time) which is parallel to the direction of motion.
The argument we have given for this corollary, at least in the initial case where the net (impulsive or
uniform) force lies in the direction of motion, is hardly different from the argument in Horologium
Oscillatorium that Christiaan Huygens gives for his Prop-osition 1: “In equal times equal amounts of
velocity are added to a falling body. . ..” [22, 35] We should also point out that Newton uses the phrase
“increment in velocity” to mean the increment in (straight-line) displacement in a given time, that is,
what we might call an increment in average speed. In modern usage, however, “increment in speed” would
probably mean the change in instantaneous speed, namely v(t0 + h) − v(t0), where v(t ) ≡ v(t ) is the
2
instantaneous speed at time t.
21. From the “Waste Book,” we move to the Principia and the famous scholium on “time, space, place, and
motion.” [32, 408–415] The scholium begins with four defini-tions, the last a definition of “absolute [or true]
motion”: “Absolute motion is the change in position of a body from one absolute place to another.” A few
paragraphs later, we find an assertion very similar to the second law: “True motion,” he writes, “is neither
generated nor changed except by forces impressed upon the moving body itself. . ..” Here by a generated “true
motion” Newton manifestly means, not the change in “quantity of motion,” (which would be the change in the
product of the quantity of matter and the speed), but rather the change in position. The scholium ends with
the Principia’s reason for being: “In what follows, a fuller explanation will be given of how to determine the
motions from their causes, effects, and apparent differences, and, conversely, of how to determine from motions,
whether true or apparent, their causes and effects. For this was the purpose for which I composed the following
treatise.” [32, 415] In our interpre-tation of the second law, a change in position is generated by an impressed
force: the
2
Speaking of “speed,” this may be a reasonable place to make a comment about the translation of Newton’s Latin
“velocitas.” According to [1], “velocitas” means “swiftness, fleetness, speed, rapidity, velocity,” and Cohen and Whitman
[32] generally choose the translation “velocity.” But this choice has the potential to cause some confusion, for mathematicians
and physicists today make a clear distinction between what thay call “velocity”, which is the speed together with a direction,
that is, a “vector velocity,” and what they call the “speed,” which is just the speed part
of the vector velocity. Velocity is thus a vector, while speed is a scalar. In the notation used in this paper, velocity is
the vector v(t ), while speed is the scalar ||v(t )|| (the length of the veloc-ity vector). On most of the occasions where
Newton uses the Latin “velocitas,” he has in mind what we would call today the “speed” (although often he means
an average speed, rather than an instantaneous speed). Perhaps then a more accurate translation of “velocitas” would
be speed, rather than “velocity.”
−→
moving deflection LQ, a change in position from L to Q, equals the resting deflection
−→
P G, which measures the force. Nothing could be more in harmony with this scholium. On the other hand,
if the “change in motion” were to mean a change in the “quantity of motion,” as some of the impulse-only
advocates suggest, much of the harmony and consistency between the second law and the scholium which
immediately precedes it is lost.
22. Let us stay on the page with the first two laws of motion. According to the first law, “Every body
perseveres in its state of being at rest or of moving uniformly straight forward, except in so far as it is compelled
to change its state by forces impressed.” [32, 416] Cohen [8, 145–148] asks a natural question: Why does Newton
list the first law as a separate law, since “it may seem to us that the [first law] is simply a special case of the
[second law] when the impressed force is zero.” Answering his own question, Cohen suggests four possible
reasons, three historical and one technical, in a discussion that covers three pages. But under our interpretation
of the second law, a completely compelling reason for a separate first law can be given in one line: in its
compound interpretation, the second law predicts the force by measuring the deflection from L, the place the
body would have been had there been no force, yet only through the first law do we know where to find the place
L, and so without a separate and prior statement of the first law, the second law has no clear meaning! We may
still argue historically, along with Cohen, that in separating the first two laws Newton is following the example
of Huygens in Horologium Oscillatorium, but now we know, courtesy of the compound interpretation, why
Newton could not conceivably have done anything else.
23. If we remain with Huygens for a moment, we can bring out more evidence for the compound
interpretation. Here is what Cohen says about the example Huygens provided for Newton’s laws of motion
[32, 110–111]:
No doubt, another factor in Newton’s decision to have a separate law 1 and law 2 was the model he found in
Huygens’s Horologium Oscillatorium of 1673, a work he knew well. In part 2 of that work, Huygens began the
analysis of gravitational dynamics with three laws which he labeled “hypotheses,” in the same way that Newton
– a decade later in De motu would set forth the laws of motion as “hypotheses.”
Here are Huygens’s first two hypotheses of motion [22, 33]:
Hypothesis 1
If there were no gravity, and if the air did not impede the motion of bodies, then any body will continue its given
motion with uniform velocity in a straight line.
Hypothesis 2
By the action of gravity, whatever its sources, it happens that bodies are moved by a motion composed both of
uniform motion in one direction or another and of a motion downward due to gravity.
Newton’s Law 1 is manifestly a generalization (to any force, not just gravity and air resistance) of Huygens’s
Hypothesis 1. Nothing could be more natural than that Newton
190 B. Pourciau
would make his Law 2 a generalization (to any force, not just gravity) of Huygens’s Hypothesis 2, and
using the compound interpretation, Law 2 is exactly that! Here is the compound second law written
expressly in the language of compounding:
By the action of any force (impulsive or continuous), bodies are moved by a motion compounded from
uniform straight line motion and from the motion generated by that same force on that same body at rest.
The compound interpretation thus puts Newton and Huygens in harmony, a harmony lost under an impulse-
only interpretation.
24. Besides the harmony with Huygens, the compound interpretation produces har-mony with our
expectations as well: indeed the compound second law is what we would naturally expect of a second law, given
the first law. To see this, imagine for a moment that we have seen only the first law, nothing more. Could we
then anticipate the second law? At least its general form? Because each of the examples used to illustrate Law 1
– projectile motion, a “spinning hoop,” and planetary motion – involves a continuous force, we may safely
assume (and indeed all commentators agree) that Newton intends the first law to apply, not only to impulses, but
also to continuous forces, and because the central problem of Book 1, the analysis of orbital motion, involves a
continuous force, we would naturally expect the second law to apply to continuous forces as well. Furthermore,
since the first law tells us that a deviation from uniform straight line motion implies the existence of a force, we
would naturally expect a second law to relate the magnitude and direction of that deviation to the magnitude and
direction of the force. Under the compound interpretation, this is precisely what the second law does! In this
sense, the compound second law is the natural sequel to Newton’s first law. The same
cannot be said for any impulse-only interpretation of the second law.
25. Consider now this claim which follows Newton’s statement of Law 2 in the Principia: “If some force
generates any motion, twice the force will generate twice the motion, and three times the force will generate three
times the motion. . ..” [32, 416] According to Cohen, this assertion holds for impulsive forces, but “has no
meaning for continuous forces since the latter produces a net change of motion that depends on both the
magnitude of the force and the time during which the force acts.” [10, 66] It follows,
he argues, that Newton must intend the second law to apply to impulsive forces only. But
−→ −→
LQ P G
in fact with our interpretation of the second law, we have M h = M h , whether the force is impulsive or
continuous, and clearly (given a fixed time interval h) three times
−→ −→
P G LQ
the force, 3M h , generates three times the change in motion, 3M h , just as Newton claims. (Of course
these equalities are equalities in the limit if the force is continuously varying.)
26. We move now from the “three times the force” sentence immediately following the statement of the
second law to the facing page in the Principia in order to take up Corollary 1 of the laws: “A body acted on by
[two] forces acting jointly describes the diagonal of a parallelogram in the same time in which it would describe
the sides if the forces were acting separately.” [32, 417] To illustrate this corollary, Newton draws the following
figure (where we have replaced his A, B, C, D with our P , L, G, Q):
Newton would never have labeled this assertion a corollary if he did not believe it to be a relatively simple
consequence of the laws, in this case clearly of Law 1 and Law 2. Yet here is a startling fact: no Newtonian
commentator (to my knowledge at least) has ever demonstrated how Corollary 1 follows from the first two
laws (alone) in any way at all, much less in any simple way! (Of course from our point of view this difficulty
in seeing Corollary 1 as a simple consequence of the first two laws derives from an incorrect interpretation
of the second law.)
In contrast it would appear that Corollary 1 is indeed a simple and obvious corollary of the first and second
laws, provided we give the second law its compound interpreta-tion. To be more specific, suppose an
impulse I applied to a body resting at P would move that body (in uniform straight line motion) from P to L in a
given time h, and suppose an impulse J applied to the same resting body at P would move that body from
P to G in the same time h. Then Corollary 1 tells us what happens when the two impulses I and J are
applied simultaneously: the claim is that the body moves (in uniform straight line motion) along the
diagonal P Q of the completed parallelogram P LQG, arriving at Q in time h. At first glance, this result
may seem to be just a statement of the impulse case of the compound second law. But this is not quite so.
For the impulse case of the compound second law concerns an impulse applied to a body already in
uniform straight line motion, while Corollary 1 concerns two impulses applied “jointly,” that
is, simultaneously.
Nevertheless, let us show that Corollary 1 is still a simple corollary of the compound second law, even
if it is not a mere restatement of the impulse case of that law. We first must decide what it would mean,
from the mathematical point of view, to say that a body is “acted on by two impulses acting
simultaneously.” We choose the natural and obvious definition: We define the motion of a body acted on
by two impulses simultaneously to be the limit of the motions generated when the impulses act separately
on that body as the separating time tends toward zero. Using this definition, we can now show how
Corollary 1 follows easily from the compound second law (together of course with the first law):
Suppose in a given time h a given body at rest at P , by an impulse I applied alone at P , would be made to
move in uniform straight line motion from P to L, and by an impulse J , applied alone at P , would be made to
move in uniform straight line motion
from P to G. Let the point Q complete the parallelogram P LQG. Suppose the impulse I acts on this resting
body at P , moving the body from P to P in a small time h . In an additional time h, this body if unimpeded
would continue to move in uniform straight line motion from Pto L , say, where P L = P L.
192 B. Pourciau
But let the impulse J act at P , moving the body instead from P to Q , say, in the
−→
additional time h. Let P G be the resting deflection of the impulse J at P . By the
−→
impulse case of the compound second law, this resting deflection P G equals the mov-
−→ −→
ing deflection L Q . But the resting deflection P G of the impulse J at P must equal
−→
the resting deflection P G of the impulse J at P , and (because Q completes the paral-
−→ −→ −→ −→
lelogram P LQG) P G equals LQ. Hence LQ equals L Q . It follows that LL Q Q is a parallelogram. Yet
clearly L tends to L as the small time h tends toward zero. Hence Q tends toward Q as well. Using our
definition concerning impulses applied simulta-neously, we conclude that the body if acted on by the
impulses I and J simultaneously would be made to move in uniform straight line motion along the diagonal
from P to Q in the time h, just as Newton claims in Corollary 1.
27. Corollary 2 of the laws of motion, dealing with the composition and resolution of forces, is not an
agenda item here, but a comment might be in order before we pass on to discuss Corollary 3: The point of
Corollary 2 is to show how the familiar composition and resolution of forces in mechanics, especially static
forces in equilibrium, follow from the laws of motion. Under the compound interpretation, with its
subjunctive mea-surement of motive force (involving the displacement that would have been observed had
the body been unconstrained and at rest), the second law makes Newtonian forces which produce motion
one with forces in statics. Since Newton clearly does intend his motive forces to represent static forces as
well as forces that produce motion – see for example the treatment of constrained motion in Section 10 of
Book 1, where Corollary 2 is cited repeatedly – we have a strong argument for the compound interpretation
of the second law.
Now, as we continue to explore the simplicity and harmony in the Principia gener-ated by the compound
interpretation of the second law, let us move on to Corollary 3: “The quantity of motion, which is determined by
adding the motions made in one direc-tion and subtracting the motions made in the opposite direction, is not
changed by the action of bodies on one another.” [32, 420] We shall analyze this corollary using the compound
second law and Newton’s third law. The simplicity of the argument will add to our case for the compound
interpretation. Newton says the net “quantity of motion” is “determined by adding the motions made in one
direction and subtracting the motions made in the opposite direction.” We can use the directed line segment
notation to keep a simple record of this directional adding and subtracting. Imagine a body M in uniform straight
line motion which would, if unhindered, move from P to L in a given time h and a body m in uniform straight
line motion which would, if unhindered, move from
p to l in the same given time. (By an efficient abuse of notation generally adopted in the Principia, we
use M and m to stand both for the bodies themselves and for their respective “quantities of matter.”)
Suppose these two (hard) bodies collide at the place P = p.
Then the total “quantity of [directional] motion” before the collision would be
−→ −→
mpl
+
PL V +
−→ −→
+ = pl
h
+ PLh
mv V m
0 M 0 M
−→ −→ −→ −→
= m pl + M P L + m lq + M LQ
h h h h
−→ −→
pq PQ
=m h +M h
= + mv1 MV1.
In other words, the total “quantity of [directional] motion” before the collision equals the total “quantity of
[directional] motion” after the collision, as predicted by Corollary 3.
28. Let us turn our attention to Corollary 4 –
The common center of gravity of two or more bodies does not change its state whether of motion or of rest as a
result of the actions of the bodies upon one another; and therefore
194 B. Pourciau
the common center of gravity of all bodies acting upon one another (excluding external actions and impediments)
either is at rest or moves uniformly straight forward. [32, 421]
– and show how it follows easily from the three laws of motion, provided we give the second law its
compound interpretation. For simplicity we concentrate on a two-body collision, using the same notation
(and referring to the same figure) that we used in our discussion above of Corollary 3. When the body m is
at p and the body M is at P , we call the point
C ≡ mp + M P m + M
the center of mass. (We will use the bold italic letters C, L, and Q when we are referring to locations of the
center of mass.) If there were no collision when p = P , then in the given time h, p would move to l, P would
move to L, and so (by algebra) C would move to
L = ml + M L . m + M
When in fact the bodies do collide at p = P , then in the same given time h, p moves to
q and P moves to Q, and so (by algebra) C moves to
Q = mq + M Q . m + M
For the “center of mass system,” where we imagine the total mass concentrated at the center of mass C, the
change in motion would be
−→ −→ −→
LQ lq LQ
(m + M ) h = m h + M h
−→ −→
pg PG
=m h +M h
where we have used the compound second law to get us from the first line to the second line. In words, this tells
us that the change in motion for the center of mass system equals the combined motive forces
of M on m and m on M. It follows that the center of mass
C moves as if all the masses were concentrated at it and all the forces were applied to
−→
−→
it. But by the third law, m pg / h = −M P G / h, so the right hand side of the second line above is zero. Hence
the center of mass C moves as if no force at all were applied to it. From the first law, the center of mass
must therefore remain at rest or in uniform straight line motion, just as Newton claims in Corollary 4.
Newton’s own argument for Corollary 4 does not mention any one of the three laws of motion, but he
uses all three nonetheless. At one point, for example, he assumes there must be “equal changes in opposite
directions in the motions of these bodies,” [32, 422] and this assumption follows only from the compound
second law together with the third law.
If bodies are moving in any way whatsoever with respect to one another and are urged by equal accelerative forces
along parallel lines, they will all continue to move with respect to one another in the same way as they would if they
were not acted on by those forces.
Advocates for an impulse-only interpretation of the second law must surely begin to doubt themselves when they
read this corollary. “Accelerative forces”? Impulses do not accelerate. How could a second law which applies
only to impulses have as a (presum-ably simple) consequence an assertion concerning “accelerative forces”? Yet
Corollary 6 follows with ease from the compound second law: Bodies “urged by equal accelerative forces along
parallel lines” are bodies which, if they were at rest, would all experience
−→
the same (that is, equal in magnitude and direction) resting deflection, say P G, in the same given time h. The
compound second law applies to such a uniform force and guar-antees that these same bodies in motion, no
matter their speed or direction when the
−→ −→
force is applied, will all experience the same moving deflection, namely LQ = P G, in that same given time h.
Consequently, in the “relative motions,” which are the (vector)
−→
difference motions, the common deflection LQ cancels out, leaving the relative motions unchanged, exactly
as Newton claims in Corollary 6.
30. The “falling body passage.” The case for the compound interpretation of the sec-ond law builds as we
continue to see examples, such as Corollary 6, where this interpre-tation restores harmony and simplicity to what
had appeared unnatural or complicated under an impulse-only interpretation. Directly following Corollary 6 we
find another example, and a truly striking one, namely the infamous “falling body passage,” inserted by Newton
into the third edition of the Principia [32, 424]. (In the passage and its accom-panying figure, we have replaced
Newton’s A, B, C, D, E with our P , L, G, Q, R.):
When a body falls, uniform gravity, by acting equally in individual equal particles of time, impresses equal forces
upon that body and generates equal velocities; and in the total time it impresses a total force and generates a total
velocity proportional to the time. And the spaces described in proportional times are as the velocities and the times
jointly, that is, in the squared ratio of the times. . . . And when a body is projected along any straight line, its motion
arising from the projection is compounded with the motion arising from gravity.
For example, let the body P by the motion of projection alone describe the straight line P L in a given time,
and by the motion of falling alone describe the vertical distance P G in the same time;
196 B. Pourciau
then complete the parallelogram PLQG and by the compounded motion the body will be found in the place Q at
the end of the time; and the curved line PRQ which the body will describe will be a parabola which the straight
2
line PL touches at P and whose ordinate LQ is as PL
Why would we call this passage “infamous”? Because both the placement and context of this insertion
indicate that Newton viewed it as a simple illustration of the second law applied to a truly elementary problem
of mechanics – to predict the parabolic trajectory of a projected body under the sole influence of “uniform
gravity” – and yet Newtonian scholars have found it anything but simple to explain this passage using an impulse-
only interpretation of the second law. The passage “beginning ‘corpore cadente’ [‘when a body falls’],” writes
Pierson [35, 654], “has exercised . . .historians of science . . . at considerable, controversial, and inconclusive
length.” Indeed, as far as I am aware, no commentary on this “falling body passage” has explained (in any way
at all, much less a simple way) how the parabolic motion arises from the first two laws of motion alone, with the
second law given an impulse-only interpretation.
Let us now present, however, the entirely simple and direct way in which the par-abolic trajectory arises
from the first two laws alone, with the second law given the compound interpretation:
Suppose a body at P , urged by uniform gravity, falls from rest along a line from P to
G in a given time t . Divide the interval of time t into n very small and equal subintervals of time h. As a
consequence of the Corollary on Force Parallel to the Direction of Motion (§20), in each of these equal
subintervals gravity will generate an increment in (average) speed proportional to the motive force of gravity.
But Newton assumes uniform gravity, so the motive force of gravity (generated in the same given time h) is the
same at each point all along the line of motion. Hence the increments in speed are all equal. This gives us an
approximation for the total speed v(t ) generated in the time t :
t
v(t ) ≈ v1 + · · · + vn = v= v
t.
h h
(This is only an approximation, rather than an equality, because these increments in aver-age speed are not
quite equal to the corresponding increments in instantaneous speed.) In the limit as the small time h tends
toward zero, the ratio v/ h approaches a finite value (that we call g), and the approximation becomes
exact: v(t ) = gt . But we quote Newton (replacing his N I with our P G): “In a body falling [with the velocity
therefore proportional to the time] and describing in its fall the space [P G], gravity generates a [speed] by
which twice that space could have been described in the same time, as Galileo proved, that is, the
2P G
[speed] t .” [32, 657] In other words, 2P G = v(t )t , and Galileo’s “law of fall” is the consequence:
1 1 2
PG= v(t )t = gt .
2 2
We see then how Galileo’s “law of fall” follows from Newton’s assumption of uniform gravity and the
compound second law.
To continue with the “falling body” argument, suppose now that this same body, rather than falling
from P , is projected from P in any direction and with any initial speed v0. By this projection alone, the
body would move with uniform straight line
motion (by the first law) from P to L, say, in the given time t . According to the com-pound second law (expressed
in the language of compounded motions), this “motion arising from the projection,” as Newton puts it, “is
compounded with the motion arising from gravity.” In other words, if the body actually moves from P to Q in
the time t , then
−→ −→
the moving deflection LQ equals the resting deflection P G, and it follows that
−→ −→ −→
P Q = P L + LQ
−→ −→
= PL+PG
−→ 1 →
g
2
= v0 t+ 2 t ,
which clearly describes a parabola! (In the final line above, our notation became more
−→ → −→
−→ g
modern: v0 has the direction of P L but length v0 and has the direction of P G but
length g.) Indeed the “curved line P RQ which the body describes will be a parabola which the straight
2
line P L touches at P and whose ordinate LQ is as P L ,” exactly as Newton asserts.
Thus the infamous “falling body passage,” so hard to explain with an impulse-only interpretation of the
second law, turns out to be a simple application of the first two laws of motion alone, provided we give the second
law its compound interpretation. Of course this is what we should expect, for Newton offers this passage as an
example to illustrate how the first two laws may be used to solve an elementary problem of mechanics. It would
be unexpected and unnatural for this application to be confusing and complicated, as it is when we insist on an
impulse-only interpretation of the second law. This adds quite dramatically to the evidence that the compound
interpretation is actually Newton’s own interpretation of the second law. By the way, notice that the compound
second law is applied twice in the argument, once in the derivation of the law of fall (at the point where we called
on a consequence of the compound second law – the Corollary on Force Parallel to the Direction of Motion) and
then again when we compounded the downward fall with the projection.
31. Newton’s Galilean attribution. Now that we have studied his “falling body pas-sage,” we may be able to
evaluate Newton’s claim that “by means of the first two laws and the first two corollaries Galileo found that the
descent of heavy bodies is in the squared ratio of the time and that the motion of projectiles occurs in a parabola,
as experiment confirms, except insofar as these motions are somewhat retarded by the resistance of the air.” [32,
424] This “Galilean attribution” is as infamous as the “falling body pas-sage.” As we pointed out in §4, Newton
scholars generally regard this attribution as misleading and mistaken. Cohen, for example, calls this claim a
“complete misrepre-sentation of Galileo’s procedure.” [8, 176] Many of these scholars are forced into this
uncomfortable position – of having to believe that Newton did not know what he was talking about here – at least
in part by their commitment to an impulse-only interpreta-tion of the second law. We have regarded their
discomfort as evidence against such an impulse-only interpretation. But now that we have proposed the
compound second law as an alternative interpretation, we can be more constructive. We ask: If we suppose the
compound second law to be Newton’s own interpretation, do we get a different picture
198 B. Pourciau
of the Galilean attribution? The answer, as we shall now show, is yes. In fact, using the compound
interpretation of the second law, Newton’s bow to Galileo appears, while certainly not totally accurate, at
least more reasonable and appropriate and less mistaken or misleading than previously thought. Not having
to believe anymore that Newton was guilty of a “complete misrepresentation” – well, that is rather good
evidence that the compound interpretation is actually Newton’s own interpretation.
Bernard Cohen [7] constructs a persuasive case that Newton never read the Discorsi, that his knowledge
of Galileo’s derivation of the parabolic trajectory must have come from secondary sources, including, for
example, Huygens’s Horologium Oscillatorium. In what follows, we certainly do not argue against Cohen
that Newton had direct knowl-edge of Galileo’s work. Rather we argue as follows: if, under a compound
interpretation of the second law, Galileo’s and Newton’s arguments for the parabolic trajectory become
more similar, then Newton’s Galilean attribution becomes more appropriate, no matter where Newton may
have come across a description of Galileo’s argument. Of course the two arguments differ in significant
ways, perhaps most notably that Newton sees gravitational fall as produced by a “force” whose variable
efficacy may be measured at each point (by what happens to a body at rest), while Galileo invokes no such
agency to explain or derive his “naturally accelerated” motion. Nevertheless, as we shall see, the arguments
become strikingly similar in structure when Newton’s second law is given the compound interpretation.
We proceed by reviewing Galileo’s derivation of the parabolic trajectory in the Dis-corsi, noting as we
go along any differences between and similarities with Newton’s own derivation (as we have interpreted
that derivation above in §30). Galileo’s argument, just like Newton’s, has two parts: first deduce the “t -
squared law of fall” and then from the law of fall deduce the parabolic path.
Galileo’s argument for the “law of fall” begins by assuming (motivated in part by experiments) that the
correct mathematical model for “naturally accelerated motion” (meaning the accelerated motion of a heavy body
falling from a point near the surface of the earth) is “uniformly accelerated motion”: “I say that motion is equably
or uni-formly accelerated which, abandoning rest, adds on to itself equal momenta of swiftness in equal times.”
[17, 154] Here we see an immediate contrast with the start of New-ton’s argument, for Newton does
not assume that bodies fall with what Galileo calls “uniformly accelerated motion”; rather he derives this from a
prior assumption, that of “uniform gravity,” which, we recall, is an assumption about how bodies fall from rest at
every point: If at a point P a body falls from rest to G in a given time h, Newton
−→
P G
says the “accelerative force of gravity” is h , and to assume “uniform gravity” is to assume the “accelerative
force of gravity” (generated in any fixed time h) is the same (in magnitude and direction) at every place in the
region. According to our reading of Newton’s derivation, as we saw in the previous section, the compound second
law (in the guise of its consequence, the Corollary on Force Parallel to the Direction of Motion) is used to infer
“uniformly accelerated motion” from “uniform gravity.” (This difference in how their projectile arguments begin
– that Galileo assumes“naturally accelerated motion” is “uniformly accelerated motion,” while
Newton derives “uniformly accel-erated motion” from an assumed “uniform gravity” – may reflect a difference
in their attitudes toward the “cause” of such motion. Neither finds it profitable to speculate on the
cause or mechanism, but Newton imagines an agency whose effect varies with location, and he measures the
magnitude and direction of that effect at a given point, for example
−→
P G
by calculating the accelerative force h . This suggests a rather modern concept: that of a “force field.”
When Newton’s “program is laid out of trying to account for the phe-nomena of nature as the effect of
forces of attraction and repulsion,” writes Stein, “what emerges is the view that the natural powers . . . may
all take the form of [central] fields of force associated with the particles of matter. . ..” [41, 287])
Back to Galileo’s derivation. After he assumes “uniformly accelerated motion,” Gali-leo then argues,
in his Proposition II (Third Day), that the “law of fall” is a consequence: “If a moveable descends from rest
in uniformly accelerated motion, the spaces run through in any given times whatever are . . . as the squares
of the times.” [17, 166] And what about Newton? After deriving “uniformly accelerated motion” from
“uniform gravity,” he too infers the law of fall [32, 424]:
. . .uniform gravity, by acting equally in individual equal particles of time, impresses equal forces upon that
body and generates equal velocities; and in the total time it impresses a total force and generates a total velocity
proportional to the time. And the spaces described in proportional times are as the velocities and the times
jointly, that is, in the squared ratio of the times.
Galileo now restates (from an earlier discussion) what we shall call his ‘first law of motion’ [17, 217]
–
A “moveable projected on a horizontal plane, all impediments being put aside,” has an “equable motion
on this plane [that] would be perpetual if the plane were of infinite extent.”
– and then compounds this horizontal equable motion with the vertically downward “uniformly accelerated
motion” of free fall: If this horizontal plane were not of infinite extent but
ended, and [situated] on high, the moveable (which I conceive of as being endowed with heaviness), driven to
the end of this plane and going on further, adds on to its previous equable and indelible motion that downward
tendency which it has from its own heaviness. Thus emerges a certain motion, compounded from equable
horizontal and from naturally accelerated downward [motion], which I call “projection.” [17, 268]
Here Galileo has applied an obvious ancestor of the compound second law, a fundamental assumption concerning
the compounding of horizontal projection with “naturally accel-erated downward” motion. We call this
assumption Galileo’s ‘Second Law of Motion.’
A moveable projected horizontally has a “motion compounded from equable horizontal and from naturally
accelerated downward [motion].” These horizontal and downward motions “in mixing together do not alter,
disturb, or impede one another.” [17, 217, 222]
Provided we give Newton’s second law its compound interpretation, Newton’s next step mimics Galileo’s
application of compounding, except that Newton is more general,
200 B. Pourciau
for he allows the body to be “projected along any straight line.” Just like Galileo, Newton applies his own second
law in compounding the two motions: “When a body is projected along any straight line, its motion arising from
the projection is compounded with the motion arising from gravity.” [32, 424] Both Galileo and Newton conclude
that such a compounded motion must trace out a parabola. As Galileo puts it:
Proposition 1 [Fourth Day]
“When a projectile is carried in motion compounded from equable horizontal and from naturally
accelerated downwards [motions], it describes a semiparabolic line in its movement.” [17, 217]
Recall again now Newton’s Galilean attribution: “By means of the first two laws . . .
Galileo found that the descent of heavy bodies is in the squared ratio of the time and that the motion of projectiles
occurs in a parabola. . ..” [32, 424] As we have noted, many scholars, at least in part because of their commitment
to an impulse-only interpretation of the second law, have been forced to the very uncomfortable conclusion that
Newton did not know what he was talking about in this attribution. On the other hand, as we have just witnessed,
when we interpret Newton’s second law as the compound second law, then Newton’s and Galileo’s arguments
for the parabolic trajectory exhibit such similar structure that Newton’s Galilean attribution becomes more
appropriate than mistaken. This is rather potent evidence for the compound interpretation of the second law, no
matter where Newton learned about Galileo’s work.
32. The harmony of natural progression. We know that Newton read and admired Ho-rologium
Oscillatorium, where Huygens’s second and third hypotheses of motion man-date the independent compounding
of “uniform motion in one direction or another and . . .
a motion downward due to gravity.” So we might expect the second law in the Principia to generalize or in some
natural way succeed these hypotheses in Horologium Oscillato-rium. And indeed, this is precisely what we
find, under our compound interpretation of the second law. This we have already pointed out earlier. Cohen
argues persuasively in [7] that Newton never read the Discorsi, where Galileo assumes the independent
compound-ing of “equable horizontal [motion] and . . . naturally accelerated downward [motion].” But Huygens
knew Galileo’s work, so we might expect the compounding assumption of Huygens to generalize the
compounding assumption of Galileo, and in fact it does.
Not because it adds anything new to the arguments we have already made, but for the pure aesthetic joy
it produces, let us gather together Galileo’s ‘second law’ (as we have called it) from the Discorsi, Huygens’s
second and third hypotheses from Horologium Oscillatorium, and Newton’s second law from
the Principia, reveling in the harmony of natural progression that blossoms before us – provided we give
Newton’s second law its compound interpretation:
A moveable projected horizontally has a “motion compounded from equable horizontal and from naturally
accelerated downward [motion].” These horizontal and downward motions “in mixing together do not alter,
disturb, or impede one another.” [17, 217, 222]
“By the action of gravity, whatever its sources, it happens that bodies are moved by a motion composed
both of a uniform motion in one direction or another and of a motion downward due to gravity. These two
motions can be considered separately, with neither being impeded by the other.” [22, 33]
“A change in motion is proportional to the motive force impressed and takes place along the straight line in
which that force is impressed.” In other words, a body in uniform straight line motion, acted on by any force
(whether impulsive or continuous), has a motion compounded from the uniform straight line motion and from
the motion that would have been generated by that force on that same body at rest. [32, 416]
Observe the natural progression: In Galileo’s ‘second law,’ the “equable motion” is (at least locally) “horizontal,”
that is, along a line tangent to the surface of the earth, the second motion is vertically downward and is the
“naturally accelerated motion” of heavy bodies at the surface of the earth. In Huygens’s second hypothesis, the
“uniform motion” may be in any “direction or another.” In Newton’s second law the uniform straight line motion
may be in any direction, and the second motion may be in any direction and may be generated by any impulsive
or continuous force, not just gravity. What could be more harmonious? Using the compound interpretation,
Newton’s second law becomes a natu-ral progression from Huygens’s second hypothesis, just as Huygens’s
second hypothesis is a natural progression from Galileo’s ‘second law.’
Of course there are significant differences, as the word “progression” suggests – most notably that
Newton introduces a “force” whose strength and direction, measured by the effect on a body at rest, can
vary with location – but even so the harmony among these compounding assumptions is striking.
33. The disappearing second law. According to the impulse-only interpretations of the second law, an
impulse generates a “change in motion” proportional to the magni-tude of the impulse. Yet supporters of
this interpretation never provide a way to measure the magnitude of the impulse other than by observing
the magnitude of the “change in motion.” Under these conditions, the second law, as we have noted before,
is not a law at all, certainly not a physical law, but rather a mere definition. “The French philoso-pher
Malebranche began an attack on forces late in the seventeenth century,” comments Hankins [19, 52–53],
and his criticisms were continued by Hume and Berkeley in England and by d’Alembert and Maupertuis in France.
Forces were never directly observed, only the effects which they produced, therefore if the word “force” was to have
any real meaning, it could only be identified with an observed change of motion. As d’Alembert and Maupertuis
pointed out, this criticism reduced Newton’s second law to a tautology or to a definition at best, because the second
law equated force with an observed change of motion.
What d’Alembert and Maupertuis failed to understand was that Newton’s “motive force” does in fact have
“real meaning,” because it is “identified with an observed change of motion” independent of the “change in
motion” for the body in motion – namely the “change in motion” for the same body at rest! But they did not
understand this, and so
202 B. Pourciau
the second law appeared to them as no more than a definition. Seen as a mere defini-tion and as applying to
impulses only, Newton’s second law could well have seemed peripheral, even unnecessary, to those scientists
studying mechanics in the decades fol-lowing Newton’s death. This may explain an otherwise baffling fact:
Newton himself clearly regarded his second law of motion as a fundamental axiom of mechanics, and yet,
although the f = ma “form of Newton’s second law” certainly did appear, at least in its component form, in the
works for example of Euler and Lagrange,
Newton’s laws of motion [as stated in the Principia] seldom appeared in the major mechanical treatises published on
the Continent. . . .the major contributors to the sci-ence of mechanics in the eighteenth century – the Bernoullis,
Clairaut, d’Alembert, Euler, and Lagrange – never stated the laws at all [as they were given in the Principia]. They
certainly owed much to Newtonian mechanics; his influence is apparent in their works, but the three laws of motion
as stated in the Principia are not to be found. [19, 45]
How could this be? Provided we take the compound second law to be Newton’s own interpretation of his Law 2,
a simple explanation becomes available: Newton saw his second law as affirming a fundamental axiom of
mechanics, what we call today Galilean invariance – the effect of a force (impulsive or continuous) on a body in
motion is the same as the effect of that force on the same body at rest – while the scientists who followed him
misread the statement of Law 2 in the Principia and saw the second law as just the definition of an impulse and
thus peripheral to their investigations.
If we are correct in our claim that Newton’s own interpretation of his second law is the compound
interpretation, then although the “major contributors to the science of mechanics in the eighteenth century – the
Bernoullis, Clairaut, d’Alembert, Euler, and Lagrange” may have not stated the second law (as it was given in
the Principia), they surely used it, without realizing it, over and over again. For every time they compounded the
effects of forces using Galilean invariance, they were using Newton’s second law.
34. The curved trajectory. Presumably not quite satisfied with the wording of the second law as it
appears in the 1687 Principia, Newton experimented with various “resty-lings” of this law in the early
1690s. In §8 we considered a figure drawn to illustrate one of these tentative revisions. This figure, because
it is a curved trajectory,
appears to be generated by a continuous force, and it therefore poses a very serious problem indeed for any
supporter of an impulse-only interpretation for the second law. (Our reproduction of Newton’s figure has the
letters P, L, Q, G in place of his A, a, b, B.) Even if we were somehow able to show that such a curved path could
be generated by a limit of a series of impulses, the curved trajectory could never be seen as a simple illustration
of an impulse-only second law. (Consult [39] for a study of the subtleties – subtleties that Newton certainly
ignored, whether he was aware of them or not – involved in expressing a given motion generated by a continuous
centripetal force as a limit of a
series of motions generated by impulses.) Yet Newton clearly intends this figure to be just that: a simple
illustration of his second law. This contradiction is clear and cogent evidence against an impulse-only
interpretation. This much has been pointed out earlier, in §8.
But in that earlier section we had not yet developed the compound interpretation of the second law.
Now we can test the compound second law against an impulse-only interpretation of the second law: Which
interpretation yields the simplest explanation of Newton’s curved trajectory? Recall Cohen’s explanation,
based on an impulse-only view of the second law [8, 181]:
“The parabola-like orbit is thus an infinitesimal orbital segment, produced by a first-order infinitesimal
force-impulse which itself proves to be compounded of an infinite number of second-order infinitesimal
force-impulses, each of which we may consider to be acting instantaneously in a time-interval which is not
the whole interval d t but rather d t /n as n → ∞, itself infinitesimally small.”
Compare this convoluted and complex “explanation” with the simple explanation which becomes available
under the compound interpretation of the second law:
The curved trajectory merely illustrates the continuous force case of the second law.
35. Staring through the lens of an impulse-only view of the second law, many pas-sages in
the Principia which invoke the second law appear opaque, overly complex, incongruous, or just plain
wrong. About this there is no debate. But through the lens of our compound interpretation, the scene alters
dramatically: what had been opaque becomes transparent, what had been complex becomes simple, what
had been incongru-ous becomes harmonious. Recall Newton’s own rules of interpretation [26, 6], where
he instructs us to choose that interpretation which reduces our “contemporary visions” to the greatest
harmony and simplicity:
ch e
8. To choose those constructions w . . . reduce contemporary visions to y greatest har-mony of their parts.
ch
9. To choose those constructions w without straining reduce things to the greatest sim-plicity.
e
Newton believes that “truth is ever found in simplicity, & not in y multiplicity
& confusion of things.” So do we, that is, so do I, and I am convinced by the arguments in the present study that
the compound interpretation is Newton’s intended meaning for the second law of motion. Then again, I am
naturally biased in favor of my own arguments. Others might still disagree and cling to an impulse-only
interpretation.
204 B. Pourciau
It is rare in the interpretation of text for there to be a final arbiter. Absent the author of the text, no
interpretation has the authority to silence all debate, and the author is generally unknown, mute, or dead. In the
case of imaginative text, the author’s own interpretation, when available, might be influential but not necessarily
final, for imagi-native text may have an interpretive life all its own, independent of its creator. In the case of
scientific texts, however, the author’s own interpretation must be seen as definitive.
Has the author of the Principia ever interpreted his own second law with sufficient clarity to end the
debate about its intended meaning? The answer is yes. And to find this authoritative interpretation we return
to our discussion (at the end of the previous section) of the “curved trajectory,” the figure Newton draws to
illustrate the following planned rewording of the 1687 Principia’s second law (one of several from the early
1690s, as we know) [29, VI, 539]:
Law II
“All new motion by which the state of a body is changed is proportional to the motive force impressed and
occurs from the place which the body would otherwise occupy towards the goal at which the impressed force
aims.”
He follows this rewording of the second law with an explanation of the law, where we find the following
words, written down not once but twice: “. . .in the meaning of this Law. . ..” Observe the careful wordsmith
choosing the word “meaning” (“mente”) to announce his intention to give the meaning of his second law –
not to give an application or consequence – but to give the very definition of the law. Here then (replacing
Newton’s A, a, B, b with our P, L, G, Q) is
If the body P should, at its place P where a force is impressed upon it, have a motion by which, when uniformly
continued, it would describe the straight line P L, but shall by the impressed force be deflected from this line
into another one P Q and, when it ought to be located at the place L, be found at the place Q, then, because the
body, free of the impressed force, would have occupied the place L and is thrust out from this place by that
force and transferred therefrom to the place Q, the translation of the body from the place L to the
place Q will, in the meaning of this Law, be proportional to this force and directed to the same goal towards
which this force is impressed.
Whence, if the same body deprived of all motion and impressed by the same force with the same direction, could in
the same time be transported from the place P to the place G, the two straight lines P G and LQ will be parallel and
equal. For the same force, by acting with the same direction and in the same time on the same body whether at rest
or carried on with any motion whatever, will in the meaning of this Law achieve an identical
translation towards the same goal; and in the present case the translation is P G where the body was at rest
before the force was impressed, and LQ where it was there in a state of motion. [29, VI, 540–543]
As he lays out for us with great care the very meaning of his second law, Newton is man-ifestly describing
the fundamental equality between the moving and resting deflection that we have been calling the
Compound Second Law:
−→ −→
M LQ = M P G .
h h
−→ −→
LQ = P G
In the present study, we have been arguing that the compound second law is Newton’s own interpretation
of his second law. With the authority of Newton’s own words in front of us, the debate ends, and we rest
our case.
Acknowledgments. This paper has benefited in many places from the wise and incisive commentary of the editor,
George Smith. All remaining errors are mine.
References
1. E.A. Andrews, A Copious and Critical Latin-English Lexicon, founded on the larger Latin-German lexicon of Dr.
William Freund, with additions and corrections (London: Sampson Low, Son & Co., 1863).
2. Michel Blay, Force, Continuity, and the Mathematization of Motion at the End of the Sev-enteenth Century,
in Isaac Newton’s Natural Philosophy, edited by Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge: The MIT
Press, 2001), 225–248.
3. Michel Blay, Reasoning with the Infinite: From the Closed World to the Mathematical Uni-
4. J. Bruce Brackenridge, The Locke/Newton Manuscript: Conjugates, Curvatures, and Conjec-tures, Archives
Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences 43 (1993), 280–292.
5. J. Bruce Brackenridge, The Key to Newton’s Dynamics: The Kepler Problem and the Prin-cipia, containing an
English translation of Sections 1, 2, and 3 of Book One from the first (1687) edition of Newton’s Mathematical
Principles of Natural Philosophy, with English translations from the Latin by Mary Ann Rossi (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1995).
6. S. Chandrasekhar, Newton’s Principia for the Common Reader (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).
7. I. Bernard Cohen, Newton’s Attribution of the First Two Laws of Motion to Galileo, in Atti del Symposium
Internazionale di Storia, Metodologia, Logica e Filosofia della Scienza ‘Galileo nella Storia e nella Filosofia
della Scienza,’ Collection des Travaux de l’Acad´emie Internatio-nale d’Histoire des Sciences, N. 16, Vinci
(Firenze: Gruppo Italiano di Storia della Scienza, 1967), xxv–xliv.
206 B. Pourciau
8. I. Bernard Cohen, Newton’s Second Law and the Concept of Force in the Principia, in The Annus Mirabilis of Sir
Isaac Newton 1666–1966 (Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1967), 143–185.
9. I. Bernard Cohen, Introduction to Newton’s Principia (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press,
1971).
10. I. Bernard Cohen, Newton’s Concept of Force and Mass, with Notes on the Laws of Motion, in The Cambridge
Companion to Newton, edited by I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2002), 57–84.
11. Elisha Coles, An English Dictionary, explaining the difficult terms that are used in divinity, husbandry, physick,
phylosophy, law, navigation, mathematicks, and other arts and sciences
. . . (London: Printed for Peter Parker, 1684).
12. E.J. Dijksterhuis, The Mechanization of the World Picture, translated by C. Dikshoorn (London: Oxford
University Press, 1961).
13. R.G.A. Dolby, A Note on Dijksterhuis’ Criticism of Newton’s Axiomatization of Mechanics, Isis 57 (1966),
108–115.
14. Brian D. Ellis, Newton’s Concept of Motive Force, Journal of the History of Ideas 23 (1962), 273–278.
15. Herman Erlichson, Motive Force and Centripetal Force in Newton’s Mechanics, American Journal of Physics 59
(1991), 842–849.
16. A.P. French and A.M. Hudson, Physics – A New Introductory Course, Parts I and II (Cam-bridge,
Massachusetts: Science Teaching Center at MIT, 1965).
17. Galileo Galilei, Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity and Force of Percussion, translated, with
introduction and notes, by Stillman Drake (Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974).
18. A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall, Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1962).
19. Thomas Hankins, The Reception of Newton’s Second Law of Motion in the Eighteenth Century, Archives
Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences 20 (1967), 42–65.
20. P.M. Harman, Newton to Maxwell: The Principia and British Physics, Notes and Records of the Royal Society
of London 42 (1988), 75–96.
21. John Herivel, The Background to Newton’s Principia: A Study of Newton’s Dynamical
22. Christiaan Huygens, Christiaan Huygens’ The Pendulum Clock or Geometrical Demonstra-tions Concerning the Motion
of Pendula as Applied to Clocks, translated with notes by Richard Blackwell (Ames, Iowa: Iowa State University Press,
1986) from the original Latin in Oeuvres Compl´etes de Christiaan Huygens, Volume 18 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
1934), 86–368.
23. Christiaan Huygens, De Motu Corporum ex Percussione, in Oeuvres Compl´etes de Christiaan Huygens, Volume
16 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1929), 29–91, translated and privately circulated by M.S. Mahoney.
24. Max Jammer, Concepts of Force: A Study in the Foundations of Dynamics (New York: Harper and Brothers,
1961).
25. Sir William Thomson and Peter Guthrie Tait, Treatise on Natural Philosophy (Oxford: Claredon Press, 1867).
26. Maurizio Mamiani, To Twist the Meaning: Newton’s Regulae Philosophandi Revisited, in Isaac Newton’s Natural
Philosophy, edited by Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2001), 3–14.
27. J. Clerk Maxwell, Matter and Motion, reprinted with notes and appendices by Joseph Larmor (New York: Dover
Publications, Inc., 1952).
28. Michael Nauenberg, Kepler’s Area Law in the Principia: Filling in Some Details in Newton’s Proof of
Proposition 1, Historia Mathematica 30 (2003), 441–456.
29. Isaac Newton, The Mathematical Papers of Isaac Newton, Volumes I–VIII, edited by D.T. Whiteside
(Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1967–1981).
30. Isaac Newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica, Third Edition with Variant Readings, Volume 1,
assembled and edited by Alexandre Koyr´e and I. Bernard Cohen with the assistance of Anne Whitman (Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1972).
31. Isaac Newton, Trattato sull’ Apocalisse, with an Italian translation and commentary by Maurizio Mamiani,
(Torino, Italy: Bollati Boringhieri, 1994).
32. Isaac Newton, The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, translated by I. Bernard Cohen and
Anne Whitman, preceded by A Guide to Newton’s Principia by
33. John M. Nicholas, Newton’s Extremal Second Law, Centaurus 22 (1978), 108–130.
34. Margula Perl, Newton’s Justification of the Laws of Motion, Journal of the History of Ideas 27 (1966), 585–592.
35. Stuart Pierson, ‘Corpore cadente. . .’: Historians Discuss Newton’s Second Law, Perspectives on Science 1
(1993), 627–658.
36. Bruce Pourciau, The Preliminary Mathematical Lemmas of Newton’s Principia, Archive for History of Exact
Sciences 52 (1998), 279–295.
37. Bruce Pourciau, Newton and the Notion of Limit, Historia Mathematica 28 (2001), 18–30.
38. Bruce Pourciau, Newton’s Argument for Proposition 1 of the Principia, Archive for History of Exact Sciences,
57 (2003), 267–311.
39. Bruce Pourciau, The Importance of Being Equivalent: Newton’s Two Models of One-Body Motion, Archive for
History of Exact Sciences, 58 (2004), 283–321.
40. George Smith, The Newtonian Style in Book II of the Principia, in Isaac Newton’s Natural Philosophy, edited by
Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2001), 249–313.
41. Howard Stein, Newton’s Metaphysics, in The Cambridge Companion to Newton, edited by
I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 256–307.
42. C. Truesdell, Essays in the History of Mechanics (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1968).
43. Loup Verlet, ‘F = MA’ and the Newtonian Revolution: An Exit from Religion through Reli-gion, History of
Science xxxiv (1996), 303–346.
44. Richard S. Westfall, Force in Newton’s Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth
45. William Whewell, An Elementary Treatise on Mechanics, Intended for the use of colleges and universities (Cambridge:
Deightons and London: Whittaker & Co, seventh edition, 1847).
46. D.T. Whiteside, The Mathematical Principles Underlying Newton’s Principia Mathematica, Journal for the
History of Astronomy 1 (1970), 116–138.
Department of Mathematics
Lawrence University
Box 599
Appleton, WI 54912
USA