Piper-CriticalHegemonyAesthetic-1985
Piper-CriticalHegemonyAesthetic-1985
Piper-CriticalHegemonyAesthetic-1985
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs
29
balance that generated them. And for individuals who have a very
deep personal investment in that balance, such critiques may seem
to question the legitimacy of these very individuals themselves.
The long-range effect of this tightly defended consensus is that
the art practitioners who share it determine-through their shared
values and practices, and the economic and social factors that deter-
mine them-the criteria of critical evaluation for all art that aspires
to entry into existing art institutions. I shall describe this as a state
of critical hegemony. That is, the socioeconomically determined aesthetic
interests of these individuals define not only what counts as "good"
and "bad" art, but what counts as art, period. Through art educa-
tion, criticism, exhibitions, and other practices and institutions
devoted to preserving and disseminating what I shall refer to as
Euroethnic art, the socioeconomic resources of this community of in-
dividuals enable its art practitioners to promulgate its fascinating
but ethnocentric cultural artifacts as High Culture on a universal
scale. According to these shared criteria, then, those creative pro-
ducts dominated by a concern with political and social injustice,
or economic deprivation, or that use traditional, or "ethnic", or
"folk" media of expression, are often not only not "good" art;
they are not art at all. They are, rather, "craft", "folk art", or
"popular culture"; and individuals for whom these concerns are
dominant are correspondingly excluded from the art context.'
The consequent invisibility of much nonformalist, ethnically
diverse art of high quality may explain the remark, made in good
faith by a well-established critic, that if such work didn't generate
sufficient energy to "bring itself to one's attention," then it prob-
ably did not exist. It would be wrong to attribute this claim to ar-
rogance or disingenuousness. It is not easy to recognize one's com-
plicity in preserving a state of critical hegemony, for that one's
aesthetic interests should be guided by conscious and deliberate reflec-
tion, rather than by one's socioculturally determined biases, is a
great deal to ask. But by refusing to test consciously those biases
against work that challenges rather than reinforces them, a critic
insures that the only art that is ontologically accessible to her is art
that narrows her vision even further. And then it is not difficult
to understand the impulse to ascribe to such work the magical power
to "generate its own energy", introduce itself to one, garner its
own audience and market value, and so on. For nearly all objects
of consideration can be experienced as animately and aggressively
intrusive if one's intellectual range is sufficiently solipsistic.
Suppose one decides to make a career commitment to becom-
ing a professional artist under these conditions. The critical hegemony
of formalistic art, and particularly its pretension to transcend its
the training in verbal and intellectual skills that the artist has not,
and often has thereby purchased the ability to interpret conceptually
the artist's products at the price of the full development of the critic's
own artistic impulses. Thus the phenomenon of the critic as closet
artist: many art critics (as well as dealers and curators) whose views
and pronouncements are highly influential in determining standards
for the evaluation of art products are themselves artists-whose own
artwork, however, is often completely independent of or even in
conflict with the views on which their own critical reputations rest.
To describe their attitudes towards their own artistic products as
self-effacing is an understatement. The process of aesthetic accultura-
tion tends to divest the artist of control over the interpretation and
cultural meaning of the work by relegating that role to the critic.
But in accepting it, the critic assumes responsibility for disseminating
critical standards from which she herself may be alienated.
Then there is the related phenomenon of the conflict of interest.
Many art practitioners who have achieved recognition within the
art community for their critical writings are justifiably reluctant to
promote their own artwork, for both self-interested and ethical
reasons. To utilize their own, highly developed critical and political
resources to promote their artwork would open them to the charge
of opportunism. But many such art practitioners also anticipate that
their artwork would be found unsophisticated or unintelligent by
comparison with their critical output in any case, by an audience
accustomed to expect only a certain kind of output from those in-
dividuals. Indeed, such an art practitioner may be led to adopt a
pseudonym under which to exhibit his work, merely to get an un-
biased hearing for it. But even here the temptation may be great
to utilize his political clout in its support. The phenomena of closet
artist and conflict of interest dovetail in the recognition that as things
now stand, the role of cultural interpreter and evaluator of work
of art is a source of art-political power that is largely incompatible
with the role of creating works of art.
One reason this division of labor is suspect is because-to butcher
Kant's observation-words without artworks are empty, artworks
without words are dumb. To relegate the creation and interpreta-
tion of art objects to different subjects is to bifurcate the experience
of both. Artists are divested of control over the cultural meanings
of their own creative impulses, while critics are denied access to
theirs, in exchange for authority and control over artists'.
This highly specialized division of labor between artists and critics
exacerbates the problem of critical hegemony. That art critics and
not artists determine the cultural interpretation of an art product
of power and control over the work, he can then hardly be expected
to participate in the interpretive, economic, and social processes by
which the art product is assimilated into the art context-nor,
therefore, into the political and cultural life of society at large. The
artist "just makes the stuff", and therefore is not to be held account-
able for its aesthetic, social, or political consequences beyond its
bare production.
The result of this lopsided division of labor, inherent in the pro-
cess of aesthetic acculturation within existing art institutions, is a
pervasive alienation of the artist, both from her own creative pro-
cesses and products, and also from the background sociocultural
environment that engendered them. For by abdicating control over
the meaning, value, price, function, and material fate of the art-
work after it leaves her studio, the artist thereby abdicates her claim
to have a special relation to that product which is significant and
valuable in its own right. The art product is appropriated by the
art institutions which legitimate it, and is thereafter governed by
its cultural and economic laws, rather than the artist's intentions
and wishes. This means that ultimately neither the creative process
nor the final product is determined by the artist's own aesthetic
imperatives.
One manifestation of the alienation that results from this divi-
sion of labor is the phenomenon of overproduction. For example, a
newly discovered artist may contract with a gallery to show new
work, say, every two years. For some artists, the rate of production
necessary to fulfill the contract may correspond perfectly with their
natural rhythm of art production. For others, this rate of produc-
tion may be far too high, producing stereotyped and superficial work
that the artist has been pressured, by the terms of his contract, into
producing. Now one might think the obvious solution would be to
contract to exhibit less frequently, say, once every four or five years
rather than once every two. But this is improbable. For the dealer's
interest in contracting with the artist at a certain time is predicated
primarily on her belief that the work will be financially marketable
at that time, not on her faith in the enduring aesthetic value of the
work; that is a conviction on which few experienced dealers would
do business. And so if an artist desires gallery affiliation, and the
prestige and recognition it brings, he must be prepared to adapt
his rate of art production to the demands of the economic, not the
creative process. Similar conclusions apply to the nonaffiliated artist
whose work is currently in vogue. That the admittedly grueling rate
of production necessary to sustain one's visibility, by participating
in all the invited exhibitions, performances, lectures, residencies,
external world, is a myth. For even her creative activity within that
realm is largely determined by external socioeconomic imperatives
which are, within the scheme of existing art institutions, beyond
the artist's ability to withstand. The notion of the successful profes-
sional artist as the one who has been freed, by her gallery affilia-
tion, and critical and financial successes, to devote all her time to
creation, is, then, an ideological fiction. It is ideological because it ser
the interests of those who prefer to preserve rather than improve
existing art institutions. And it is a fiction because it is false that
this brand of success promotes genuine freedom or creative
expression.
NOTES
This paper is abridged from a much longer discussion, "Power Relations Within Ex-
isting Art Institutions", in Dale Jamieson and Douglas Stalk, Eds., Recent Art. Philosophical
Problems and Artistic Promise (forthcoming).
'Richard Goldstein makes essentially this point in "Art Beat: Race and the State of
the Arts," The Village Voice, August 23, 1983. 31; and in "Art Beat: 'Darky' Chic," The
Village Voice, March 31, 1980. 34. Also see Robert Pear, "Reagan's Arts Chairman Brings
Subtle Changes to the Endowment," The New York Times, April 10, 1983.
2See Michael Brenson, "Artists Grapple With New Realities," The New York Times,
May 15, 1983.
3' 'Performance and the Fetishism of the Art Object," Vanguard 10, 10 (December
1981-January 1982), 16-19; also see, "A Proposal for Pricing Works of Art," The Fox 1,
2 (1975).