Barnard ed._Fashion Theory An Introduction_2014
Barnard ed._Fashion Theory An Introduction_2014
Barnard ed._Fashion Theory An Introduction_2014
Fashion is both big business and big news. From models’ eating disorders
and sweated labour to the glamour of a new season’s trends, statements
and arguments about fashion and the fashion industry can be found in
every newspaper, consumer website and fashion blog. Books that define,
analyse and explain the nature, production and consumption of fashion in
terms of one theory or another abound. But what are the theories that run
through all of these analyses, and how can they help us to understand
fashion and clothing?
Fashion Theory: an introduction explains some of the most influential
and important theories on fashion: it brings to light the presuppositions
involved in the things we think and say about fashion every day and shows
how they depend on those theories. This clear, accessible introduction
contextualizes and critiques the ways in which a wide range of disciplines
have used different theoretical approaches to explain – and sometimes to
explain away – the astonishing variety, complexity and beauty of fashion.
Through engaging examples and case studies, this book explores:
Malcolm Barnard
First published 2014
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2014 Malcolm Barnard
The right of Malcolm Barnard to be identified as author of this work has
been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced
or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means,
now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording,
or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and
explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Barnard, Malcolm,
Fashion theory: an introduction/Malcolm Barnard.
pages cm
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Fashion—Social aspects. 2. Fashion—Economic aspects.
3. Fashion design. I. Title.
GT525.B37 2014
391—dc23
2013039173
1 Introduction 1
2 Fashion and fashion theories 8
3 What fashion is and is not 25
4 What fashion and clothing do 41
5 Fashion and/in history 57
6 Fashion as communication 73
7 Fashion, identity and difference 91
8 Fashion, clothes and the body 109
9 Fashion production and consumption 128
10 Modern and postmodern fashion 145
11 Globalization and colonialism 161
12 Fashion and (the) image 178
13 Fashion, fetish and the erotic 197
14 Conclusion 215
Bibliography 218
Index 228
contents v
Figures
1.1 Screen grab from Jess Cartner-Morley’s presentation
on The Guardian website 12 April 2013 2
3.1 Facebook Community Page, ‘What is Fashion?’ May 2013 26
6.1 Sender/receiver model of communication 75
6.2 Panzani advertisement 84
6.3 Tony Blair and George Bush at June 2004 meeting of
Euro-Atlantic Partnership Council 85
7.1 Still from YouTube video interview with Jessica Alba,
Vogue, 2012 92
7.2 From Comme il Faut catalogue 2004 100
8.1 A woman looks at a giant poster showing Isabelle Caro,
part of a campaign against anorexia by Italian
photographer Oliviero Toscani, in Milan 110
8.2 Yolanda Dominguez 2011 ‘Poses’ 125
9.1 War on Want action card, 2012 129
11.1 Zambian Coat of Arms 170
12.1 Maison Martin Margiela show, Spring/Summer 1999 182
12.2 TK Maxx logo 192
12.3 Brooks Brothers logo 192
13.1 Dreamcatcher bra by Nichole de Carle London 198
13.2 Patrice, 1977 213
vi list of figures
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank the following people for advice, suggestions, corrections
and permissions to use illustrations: Anne Burns, Lena Ahmed Fallata,
Yolanda Dominguez, Kathryn Hinks, Marsha Meskimmon and Shlomit
Ravid and her colleagues at Comme il Faut, in Israel.
Every effort has been made to contact the copyright holders for their
permission to reprint material in this book. The publishers would be grateful
to hear from any copyright holder who is not here acknowledged and will
undertake to rectify any errors or omissions in future editions of this book.
acknowledgements vii
This page intentionally left blank
chapter 1
Introduction
One of the arguments used in the ‘Rationale’ for this book, (which a hopeful
potential author writes in order to explain the irresistible academic demand
for the book and which provides the publisher with sound economic reasons
to invest in it and publish it), was that while all accounts and even all
anecdotes concerning what we wear and why we wear it presuppose at least
one theory of fashion, few of those accounts and none of those anecdotes
take the time to explain or even become aware of those theories. The unique
selling point of this book was to be that it would take those accounts and
anecdotes, show what the theories were and explain them in a rigorous but
accessible manner.
Examples of these theories will, of course, be found in many of the
books that are published on fashion and clothing. That is what academics
do: they take a phenomenon such as fashion or clothing and they define,
analyse and explain it in terms of some theory or other. These academics
and their theories will be found in the chapters that follow, starting with
the very next chapter, which explains the nature, presence and role of theory
in every explanation and every understanding of fashion and clothing.
Theories will also be found in the essays appearing in the ever-increasing
number of journals that cater for fashion, clothing and textiles: Berg
even calls one of its journals Fashion Theory, while Routledge publishes
the International Journal of Fashion Design, Technology and Education and
Intellect offers us Critical Studies in Fashion and Beauty.
Examples of what we might think of as anecdotal, informal, everyday
statements and arguments concerning fashion and clothing may be found
on the websites of every newspaper that has ever run a story about fashion
or clothing. Following the story of another unfortunate model suffering from
an eating disorder, or lamenting the return or the decline of men’s ties,
introduction 1
there will be pages of comments ‘below the line’ in which the readers offer
their opinions and comments. The point the ‘Rationale’ was trying to make
was that even these informal, everyday opinions and commonplace
assertions concerning what people wear all presuppose some theory or
other. The ‘Rationale’ could reasonably have made the point that these
everyday, commonplace opinions and assertions use exactly the same
theories as the academics in their high-powered books and complicated
essays.
One of the newspapers that I spend a lot of time reading online, The
Guardian, is a rich source of this kind of story and of this kind of below-
the-line comment. Like most broadsheet newspapers, it employs three or
four journalists to contribute articles on all possible manifestations of
fashion and clothing, from the highest haute couture to the most ‘street’
styles. Type ‘fashion’ into The Guardian’s ‘Search Engine’, click the ‘User
Contributions’ button and a story about how to use sheer panels in one’s
dress from 12 April 2013 is first in the list (Cartner-Morley 2013). In this
story, which is accompanied by a video presentation, Jess Cartner-Morley,
the paper’s fashion editor, explains what ‘sheer panels’ are and advises
viewers on how to use them to ‘add textural interest in a minimal way’ to
your clothes and to ‘lighten up’ heavy fabrics (see Figure 1.1). In the video
presentation, she explains that sheer panels are essentially bits of a
garment that you can see through and she distinguishes ‘peek-a-boo sheer,
which is all about “look at my naked skin underneath”’ from ‘sedate
sheer, or polite sheer . . . which is using the sheer as a kind of decoration’
Figure 1.1 Screen grab from Jess Cartner-Morley’s presentation on The Guardian
website 12 April 2013. (Cartner-Morley 2013: www.guardian.co.uk/fashion/2013/
apr/12/how-to-dress-sheer-panels)
2 introduction
(Cartner-Morley 2013). In the text that accompanies the video, she says that
‘fashion is rarely sexy’ and that one of the ‘side-effects’ of fashion being
one of the few areas of popular culture that is not dominated by heterosexual
men is that ‘it is not all about shaggable birds’. The Zara vest she is shown
wearing, with its two panels of sheer fabric at the top, is ‘clean and serene’;
it is discreet and an example of the sedate or polite sheer that she has just
explained.
In the first of the comments below the line, MrVholes is quick to point
out that Cartner-Morley does indeed look ‘sexy’ in the top and suggests
that ‘Fashion is rarely sexy’ is a ‘bizarre comment’. In the second of the
comments, Rainbot disagrees with Cartner-Morley’s account of fashion,
saying that High Street fashion is in fact all about ‘birds who want to look
shaggable’. And the third of the comments, from dickybird1, says ‘Why oh
why does the Guardian continue to post the “How to dress” videos??? Does
anyone else find these a ridiculous waste of time, effort and editorial space?’.
These comments are presented here as examples of the informal,
everyday opinions and commonplace assertions that I suggested above
presupposed some theory or other but which did not explain what those
theories might be and may even have been unaware that they were the
products of theory. MrVholes clearly believes that fashion is either often or
always ‘sexy’. While he makes no mention of Bernard Rudovsky, his theory
that fashion is ‘sexy’ can be related to the theoretical account of fashion
and clothing that Rudovsky proposes. As you will see in Chapter 13, Rudovsky
proposes a theory of fashion that operates in terms of natural selection: all
the beautiful and fashionable things that women wear are simply to attract
a male with whom to have sex and reproduce. Like MrVhole’s account,
Rainbot’s account makes no mention of ‘theory’ but is also absolutely
compatible with Rudovsky’s theory in that it relies on two conceptual
frameworks: one concerning desire and one concerning gender. MrVholes’
account speculates or theorizes about the desire of young women to use
what they wear in order to appear attractive to men, or ‘shaggable’ as s/he
has it. However, it also introduces a distinction into the account of fashion.
He presupposes or relies upon a theory of fashion, as well as theories of
gender and desire. Rainbot distinguishes ‘catwalk’ fashion from ‘High Street’
fashion and says that the latter is still dominated by ‘birds’ (young women)
who want to appear sexually attractive. The young women appearing in
catwalk shows must, by implication, be ‘unshaggable’, which will come as
a surprise to many. The garments that appear in these catwalk shows, on
Rainbot’s theory, are not intended to make women attractive to potential
sexual partners. dickybird1 provides an example of a perennial and therefore
strictly unfashionable theory – that fashion is a ‘ridiculous waste of time,
effort and editorial space’. This theory is a kind of ‘classic’ in that it is
guaranteed to appear in every story concerning fashion or clothing in these
introduction 3
kinds of websites. The idea that fashion is a superficial, ridiculous waste of
time and effort that would be better spent on something more serious is
always popular. The serious/frivolous dichotomy is one of the defining
features of Western thought and it often lines up with other dichotomous
pairs, including the masculine/feminine one. For many Western cultures,
therefore, it is very easy to form what almost amount to gender-equations,
(masculine = serious and feminine = frivolous), and to begin the process,
(as in dickybird1’s comment) of implicitly decrying feminine concerns with
fashion as frivolous. Sometimes this theory is countered by another poster
who uses theories of economic production and consumption to point out
that the fashion and clothing industries are worth £X billion to the UK
economy and therefore not a waste of time or effort. Sometimes it is
countered by a poster who uses theories from cultural studies to argue that
fashion and clothing are the very serious ways in which social and cultural
identities are constructed, communicated and either reproduced or
contested, and that they are therefore anything but superficial.
The point is that even these apparently throwaway, everyday comments
and anecdotes, which are found below the line on every newspaper
website or fashion blog, represent theories. They represent theories of what
fashion is and of what its importance is, theories concerning how it might
best be explained and theories of how it works. MrVholes uses Rudovsky’s
theories of sexual selection; Rainbot also uses these theories but also adds
a useful theoretical distinction to the account of fashion; dickybird1 has a
theory of the seriousness or otherwise of fashion. Throughout this book,
I have tried to introduce whatever the topic is by using a story from popular
media – websites and magazines have been favoured because everyone
who is at all interested in fashion and who might therefore be interested
in reading this book will be looking at those media; they are where fashion
gets reported and discussed. Then I have tried to show how those everyday
popular stories may be used to illustrate the complexities of the issues and
how what are often very complicated theories are used, and maybe abused
and confused in the presentation of and argumentation around those
stories.
Consequently, the following chapters will take various approaches to
the identification, analysis and explanation of fashion and clothing, and show
what the main theories are and how they work. The earlier chapters will be
about what fashion is, what theory is and what, if we put the two together,
fashion theory is. The next chapter begins from what I suspect will be many
a fashion and design student’s experience to introduce the nature and
necessity of theory. Many fashion design and textile design students often
do not see the point of having to study fashion theory, or social theory, as
part of the degree or pre-degree work. The argument in this chapter will
follow up and develop the argument just made in this chapter – that even
4 introduction
the everyday and anecdotal things we say about fashion and clothing embody
and represent theories. Whether we like it or not and whether we are aware
of it or not, we are employing and relying on theories about fashion, clothing,
gender, meaning and many other things whenever we say anything about
the things we wear or why we wear them. I can’t help anyone to like this
fact or these theories but I hope to help everyone to be more aware of the
presence and effects of some of those theories.
Chapter 3 surveys and explains the main theories of what fashion is.
These concern whether fashion and fashion design is art or not. Many
people, possibly most people, are happy to think of fashion as a form of
art, but colleges and universities offer degrees in Fashion Design: I know
of none that offers a degree in Fashion Art or Fashion Arts. The notion of
anti-fashion, which does not interact destructively with fashion but which
is definitely not fashion, will also be investigated. And the notion of whether
what we wear is an addition to, or decorations of, our bodies, or whether
our bodies are already additions and decorated, will be introduced here in
the form of the concept of prosthesis.
Chapter 4 concerns the functions of fashion and clothing – it concerns
what fashion and clothing do, from keeping us warm and decent to
communicating our cultural identities. For such a practical-sounding
chapter, there is a lot of theory here. The question of what fashion and
clothing do leads quickly into a discussion of the relation between the
functions of the things we wear and the ways they look. The form/function
debates introduce the question whether discussing fashion and clothing in
terms of function is reductionist: many fashion theorists are accused of
reducing fashion to a single, over-simplified aspect and this chapter will
defend them from that accusation. It will be argued that even the most
‘basic’ ‘anthropological’ or biological functions of keeping a body warm and
dry cannot be immune to style, they must take some form or other. Keeping
us warm and dry will always have to take some culturally located and
therefore culturally variable form. Variation and cultural location are at the
heart of what fashion is and therefore we must say that fashion is always
with us, and that it has always been with us.
The presence of fashion and clothing in history is the topic of Chapter
5. This sounds dreadfully theoretical and very dull. I can assure potential
readers that it is not. Every time the opening or establishing shot of a film
or television story shows a person wearing anything at all, a place in history
is identified. Fashion and clothing are probably the quickest and easiest
ways for a director to indicate temporal location that they have, apart from
the obvious and visually unexciting caption saying something like ‘The North
of England 1915’ or ‘The Future’. The five positions that fashion may take
with regard to history – from simply appearing in front of it to actually
making it possible – will be identified and explained. Finally, it will be
introduction 5
explained that, of course, fashion has no history; while it may have a memory,
it is not the kind of thing that can have a history.
Picking up some of the threads from Chapter 4, on the functions of
fashion and clothing, Chapter 6 will consider fashion and clothing as forms
of communication. I will be trying once more to make my case that, while
fashion and clothing communicate, they do not send messages. Fashion
and clothing are meaningful but meaning is not something that can be sent
or received. The persistence of the idea that fashion is the sending and
receiving of messages will be introduced through the absurd but popular
notion (taken from a website!), that it is possible to send ‘secret messages’.
Presidential ties and hip-hop fashions will be used to explain the weaknesses
of these theories of fashion communication.
And continuing the theme of fashion as communication, Chapter 7 will
consider the notion that what we wear is a representation of identity. The
idea that identity can be represented through what we wear entails a
discussion of theories of difference. And the chapter will consider various
examples of difference – gender, class and religious difference, for example
– before showing how they are all examples of political difference and
explaining fashion’s inevitably political functions. This chapter will argue
that if there is no natural way of being anything, from being male, to being
black, to being old or to being gay, for example, then identity must be cultural
representation. That means that something is acting as a tool to stand for
or represent one’s identity. That something is clothing and fashion; but
clothing and fashion are not the sort of tools that can be picked up and
put down at will: we are always already using them. Indeed, identity and
fashion work in such a way here that we must say that we are them.
Representation is also one of the main themes of Chapter 8, which
investigates the relations between fashion, clothing and the body. These
matters were introduced in Chapter 3 and they resurface here in the form
of the critiques that are often made of the sorts of cultural studies or
semiological theories that I am interested in, which operate with and in
terms of representation. Fashion is often blamed for causing real eating
disorders in real young women, (and less often in young men), and
sometimes leading to their deaths. This chapter must try to explain these
real tragedies in terms of representation, which is often dismissed as ‘merely
discursive’, and the mortal, fleshy body.
The role of fashion and clothing in production and consumption is the
subject of Chapter 9. The trouble that some globally renowned companies,
such as Nike or Adidas, get themselves into through their less than ethical,
fair or sustainable modes of production will be examined here. Where
identity was one of the main themes of Chapter 7, the relation between
identity and consumption is one of the themes of Chapter 9. Tim Dant’s
revision and expansion of the notion of consumption, to include the long-
6 introduction
term use of fashion and clothing will be dealt with here, and related to
issues of sustainability.
Representation is once again the driving issue of Chapter 10, on theories
of modern and postmodern fashion. The chapter begins with the paradoxical
position that designers such as Martin Margiela find themselves in when
they are described as postmodern or deconstructive designers. Their
position is paradoxical because they are usually said to be postmodern on
grounds that turn out to be the mainstays of classical modernist theory.
This paradox is explored and explained through an explanation of
postmodernity as a crisis of representation. Three examples of garments
that have been held up as prime examples of postmodern fashion design
will be shown to be either as much modernist design as postmodern or as
genuinely exemplifying this crisis of representation.
Tommy Hilfiger’s use of the Bollywood star Arjun Rampal to open his
Mumbai store in 2004 is used to introduce the concerns of Chapter 11:
globalization and colonialism. The ways that fashion is used to establish
Western dominance over all the cultures of the globe, and the ways that
fashion is used by local, indigenous cultures to resist and challenge the
dominance of Western cultures are explained in this chapter. Yves Saint
Laurent, Zambia and Micah Silver have all produced and used versions of
the safari jacket, which was ‘originally’ known as the M65 jacket by British
and American troops, to patronize, colonialize, resist and critique various
forms of globalized and localized power. War on Want’s challenge to Adidas
in the 2012 London Olympic Games concerned the latter’s allegedly brutal
exploitation of local economies, while claiming global niceties and
proprieties.
The image of fashion and fashion companies is also the subject
of Chapter 12. In this chapter the notion of fashion as communicating an
image or an identity will be distinguished from the notion of fashion as
an image. The ways in which fashion and clothing are made into images,
as well as the ways that they are used by us to construct ourselves in some
image or other will be explored here. The sense of image as ‘identity’ will
thus echo some of the concerns of Chapter 7.
Finally, Chapter 13 will consider the relation of fashion and clothing to
the fetish and the erotic. This chapter will be concerned with psychoanalytic
theories of the sexual, and the differences between these kinds of theories
and those proposed by Rudovsky, in relation to sexual selection, will be
explained. Given that the word fashion derives from the Portuguese word
fetico, from which the English word ‘fetish’ derives, it will come as no surprise
to learn that there is a rich and entertaining theoretical relation between
fashion, clothing and the fetish. Roland Barthes’ notion of the erotic, as
distinct from the pornographic, will then be related to what we wear and
shown to be no less fun than the notion of the fetish.
introduction 7
chapter 2
Fashion and
fashion theories
Introduction
Most, if not all, fashion design students will encounter fashion theory or
theories of fashion in the course of their studies. Many of them will be
resentful of this fact: some will simply not see the point of theory and others
will be irritated or intimidated by what appears to them to be the wilful
obscurity of impractical, pretentious and overly-complicated nonsense. How,
they may say, will understanding the difference between essentialist and
performative theories of gender help them design better dresses or suit
jackets? They may wonder what the philosophy of aesthetics or the sociology
of class will add to their ability to design successful repeat patterns or
sportswear. The idea that they have to write essays and even dissertations
on these subjects often strikes them as a difficult and unnecessary
distraction from their main subject.
In England, art and design degrees will consist of about 20 per cent
historical and theoretical studies, a figure suggested in the Coldstream
Reports of 1960 and 1970. These Reports argued powerfully that some
element of the history of art and design was to be included in all Diplomas
in Art and Design (Dip.AD). Their insistence later carried over into the
various art and design degrees that the Dip.AD was replaced by. The
Coldstream Reports also suggested that something called Complementary
Studies (which was much less specified than the history of art and design
and which could include anything that helped students to ‘contextualize’
their studio practice) was also to be included.
What is theory?
The fashion design students who are mentioned in the first paragraph above
are probably in much the same position as the majority of non-specialists
when it comes to understanding what theory is. The common, everyday
and uncritical accounts of theory that one hears include the idea that theory
is the use of abstract, complicated and hard to understand conceptual
frameworks to explain things that are actually quite practical, simple and
easy to understand. Playing the Megadeth power chords you’ve seen in a
YouTube tutorial is perfectly possible and terrifically satisfying without either
understanding the theory of musical intervals or knowing what a ‘fifth’ is.
Your flowery pattern for the material to make a sun dress is no less summery
and girly for your not understanding that gender is a cultural construction
and not a reflection of essence. However, as also noted above, all of these
things involve theory and, if you do not want to be forever learning other
bands’ chords from a YouTube video or endlessly drawing flowers for sun
dresses, an understanding of how theories and the things described in them
work will benefit you enormously.
Our word ‘theory’ comes to us from an ancient Greek word theoria,
meaning ‘looking’ or ‘vision’. It may be surprising to learn that the word
for what is perceived as conceptual and abstract derives from an activity
that is perceived to be the very opposite of the conceptual and the abstract.
Theorein and theoros mean ‘to look at’ and ‘ spectator’, respectively. The
relation between the conceptual and theoretical and the supposedly non-
theoretical visual may be explained using the well-known story of the art
student, the soldier and the farmer. All three find themselves standing in
a field and each gives a different account of what they see when asked to
describe the scene. The soldier sees a position that would be impossible
to defend, exposed to attack from both air and ground forces. The art student
sees the structure of a Claudian landscape, with some large dark green
trees on the left balancing the more open and lighter central plain, which
is accentuated and given depth by the river that winds to the horizon. And
the farmer sees an unprofitable unit with limited wheeled access, fit for
What is fashion?
It should be clear by now that, and why, it would be naïve to expect a theory-
free account of what fashion is. If the farmer, soldier and art student
mentioned above saw a ‘single’ field as three entirely different things, one
can only imagine how many things they would see fashion as. Surveying
the literature, one finds a startling variety of opinions, the products of a
range of theoretical positions. Some see fashion as high art, the very best
that has been thought and achieved in Western civilization; others see it
as irrefutable evidence of capitalist culture’s moronic obsession with
superficial trivia. In the nineteenth century, the novelist H. G. Wells’ ‘extinct
uncle’ believed fashion to be ‘the foam on the ocean of vulgarity’ (Wells
everybody has to get dressed in the morning and go about the day’s
business . . . [w]hat everybody wears to do this has taken different forms
in the West for about seven hundred years and that is what fashion is.
(Hollander 1994: 11)
Once the issues and theories behind it have been understood, this
may be the best that can be done with a definition of fashion. Fashion may
now be understood as everything that is worn on the body and that is
done to or with the body: all the dress, clothing, adornment, modification
and so on that happens on and to the body in the West is fashion. This
includes, but is not restricted to or exhausted by, catwalk creations, street
fashions, civil, military and domestic uniforms, tattooing, cicatrization and
hairdressing. Even things that do not sound like fashion, such as clothing
or things that are no longer fashionable, are also still fashion. They are also
still part of what Barthes called the fashion system because, as Baudrillard
notes, there is no outside this system. In the modern West, at least, there
is no outside to the fashion system and everything is fashion.
However, Hollander’s Western and modern notion of fashion inevitably
invites questions as to what counts as Western and what counts as modern.
It also invites questions concerning the possibility of non-Western and
non-modern fashion. These are questions concerning the global nature
of fashion: whether fashion is a global phenomenon, whether there is such
a thing as local fashion, and the relation of both to colonialism are all
questions that are raised here. While they will be dealt with in more detail
in Chapter 11, they may usefully be introduced here. Some theories of fashion
argue that fashion is possible only in complex societies. Georg Simmel and
Some of the issues constituting and surrounding what theory and fashion
are have been introduced and explained. We have an understanding of what
theory is and we have an understanding of what fashion is, so it should be
relatively straightforward to put the two together to enable us to understand
the nature and role of fashion theory. However, fashion theory is not as
simple as that. There is no single body or set of ideas and there is no one
conceptual framework that we can look to in order to identify, analyse and
critically explain the production and consumption of fashion. This means
that there is no single discipline that can be appealed to and used as fashion
theory. What we have and are confronted with are fashion theories; there
are many theories concerning fashion. Various different disciplines are used
to account for and explain the different objects, practices, institutions and
personnel that make up the fashion system. Each of these disciplines has
its own sets of ideas and its own conceptual frameworks with which it sets
about defining, analysing and critically explaining fashion production and
consumption. This section must survey those disciplines and begin to assess
which ones are likely to prove useful and fruitful in the analysis and
understanding of fashion.
One thing that many new disciplines or areas of study explicitly and
deliberately set out to do is to avoid anecdote and chit-chat. Saussurean
structuralists and the Russian Formalists tried to do this at the beginning
of the twentieth century when they wanted to put the study of language and
literature, respectively, on a ‘scientific’ footing. The study of costume, dress
and fashion is no different; it too wants to avoid chit-chat and to be proper
knowledge. As Fernand Braudel notes, the history of costume is ‘less
anecdotal than would appear. It touches on every issue – raw materials,
production processes, manufacturing costs, cultural stability, fashion and
social hierarchy’ (Braudel 1981: 311). Anecdotes are little stories constructed
out of random details and accidental observations, and any body of study
that wants to be taken seriously needs to construct its stories and accounts
out of rigorous, theoretical and idea-driven enquiry. One can see from
Braudel’s list that he is thinking of such theory-based social science
disciplines as economics, sociology and cultural studies.
Other people have reached similar conclusions concerning the most
appropriate approaches to the study of fashion and dress. Like Braudel,
Lisa Tickner also argues that many different disciplines are necessary.
Fashion, she says, is a ‘rich and multi-disciplinary subject, and a point at
which history, economics, anthropology, sociology and psychology could
be said to meet’ (Tickner 1977: 56). Elizabeth Wilson breaks ranks with the
social scientists at this point and, like Gilles Lipovetsky, begins to associate
Conclusion
This chapter has introduced fashion, theory and fashion theory. It has
outlined some definitions of fashion and it has shown the practical and
visual roots of what we know as theory. And it has argued a case concerning
the relation of fashion to theory in fashion theory. The argument has been
that we are always in theory: from the most anecdotal and entertaining story
about fashion to the driest and most academic thesis, we are using theories.
Systems of heuristic concepts and theoretical constructions are producing
what we say. Everything we say is produced and supported by theory. This
argument will be borne out in all of the following chapters, as I try to
introduce the topics by means of some apparently innocent or everyday
account and demonstrate the theory or theories ‘behind’ them. The
following chapter will begin to think about what fashion is.
Further reading
Kawamura, Y. (2005) Fashion-ology, Oxford, Berg; chapters 2 and 3.
Rose, G. (2012) Visual Methodologies, London, Sage.
Svendsen, L. (2006) Fashion: A Philosophy, London, Reaktion Books.
Williams, M. (2000) Science and Social Science, London, Routledge.
What fashion
is and is not
Introduction
At the time of writing in May 2013 the question ‘What is fashion?’ has its
own Facebook community page, which is itself quite fashionable, and it is
liked by 33 people, which suggests it is not yet a mass or a popular fashion.
The page does not provide much of an answer to the question but it provides
a link to the Wikipedia page, which says that fashion is a popular style,
practice or trend and that it is ‘clothing generally’. Closer inspection of the
Wikipedia page tells us that it has ‘multiple issues’ with the notion of fashion
and that it may not contain ‘verifiable information’. A blogger on a website
for teenagers says that ‘fashion is my unique ability to express my emotions’.
Another says confidently that fashion is definitely not self-mutilation. And
yet another says that fashion is brands (blog-trends.com). Elsewhere, an
ex-editor of French Elle says that fashion talks, that it is a state of mind, a
spirit, an ‘extension of one’s self’ and that, whether you prefer hip-hop or
Chanel, fashion translates self-esteem into a personal style. She also says
that it is not to be taken too seriously (www.pbs.org/newshour/infocus/
fashion/whatisfashion.html; last accessed November 2013).
There is clearly not much agreement here and there are indeed ‘multiple
issues’ involved in the definition of fashion. We are confronted by a range
of conventional, contradictory and mistaken references to style, styles,
emotions, culture, the self, the mind, talk, expression, brands, mutilations
and spirit. However, these attempts at definition provide hints toward, and
elements of, a sensible and useful account of what fashion is and is not.
For example, while neither fashion nor individual garments can be said
to literally ‘talk’, there is little doubt that they communicate, or that they
are used to communicate. One of the bloggers reported here says that she
uses fashion to express her emotions: emotion is being communicated
through or by what this young woman wears. Other people use fashion to
communicate other things: cultural membership is indicated, for example,
in the reference to hip-hop and Chanel. Different people will construct and
communicate membership of different cultural groups by wearing different
garments. Baggy jeans worn low will communicate membership of some
hip-hop cultures and the signature suit and heavily logoed handbag will
communicate one’s allegiance to Chanel. Similarly, while it is hard to believe
that a mass-produced garment, worn by thousands of people, contributes
anything towards anyone’s ‘uniqueness’ or sense of self, the impression
and the experience of that unique self persist and must be explained. One’s
sense of identity and uniqueness easily survives wearing the same jeans or
having the same haircut as one’s friends.
And while the idea that fashion translates that sense of self into style,
or that it is an extension of one’s self, might be dismissed as involving too
much calculation or an overly mechanical conception of fashion, we have
to use something with which to communicate and we must use something
with which to construct ourselves as unique and individual members of
cultures. This example is slightly different from, and slightly trickier than,
the other examples, but it is no less a part of what fashion is and is not.
Fashion is not quite so readily or happily understood as a prosthetic as it
is understood as communication, or as expression of some unique self.
And the self is not so readily understood as the product or construction of
There are two problems with this simple argument. First, it is not clear that
the ‘item of clothing’ is the same as a piece of fashion and Rawsthorn is
sliding from one to the other here. The function of fashion is not quite the
same as the function of clothing: the function of an item of clothing may
be to keep our bodies warm and dry, but (while it may be a side-effect) it
is never the purpose of an item of fashion to keep a body warm and dry.
Every modern and Western attempt to keep a body warm and dry will be
subject to fashion, but this merely proves the point concerning the
difference between clothing and fashion. Second, it is not true that art
has no function. Art has many functions: it constructs, communicates
and reproduces the owner’s social, cultural and economic position, for
example. By purchasing, owning and displaying one or other kind of art,
one identifies oneself as a member of a certain socio-economic class and
as a member of a certain culture. The purchase of the art reproduces the
people and the institutions that exist to produce and sell art works (artists
and art markets). These are the social, cultural and economic functions of
art. Art also functions aesthetically; its function may be to draw our attention
to the nature of our own aesthetic and sensory experience. And art functions
communicatively. It is surely a commonplace to say that artists express
themselves through their art and that art is meaningful. Fashion also
performs precisely these functions and, therefore, art and fashion cannot
be differentiated on the basis of art having no function.
Rhodes takes a different view and argues that having a function does
not preclude the possibility of something being art. She believes that fashion
can be an art form, despite its having a practical function. If a painting were
to be made into a fresco, ‘a part of a wall’, she asks, ‘would you say it was
not art because it was practical?’. The implication is that we would want to
call it art, despite its having a practical function. Fashion on her account
is, therefore, an ‘applied art’ and it can be opposed to ‘fine art’. However,
it is not the ‘art’ that is acting as the wall, or that has a practical function:
it is not the ‘art’ that helps to keep the ceiling up and it is not, therefore,
in spite of the function of the art that we want to call the fresco art. The
colours and shapes of a painting may have been incorporated into some
wet plaster but the colours and shapes are not the ‘art’ and it is not the
‘art’ that makes the wall and stops the ceiling and upper floors falling down.
Therefore, it is not in spite of the function that we want to call it art –
because, as part of the wall, it has no function.
There is a hint, in Viktor and Rolf’s numbered and limited-edition bags
and dresses (noted above) of a satisfactory answer to the question whether
Fashion as prosthesis
The idea of fashion as prosthesis may seem odd. However, if we are happy
to think about fashion and clothing as having functions, then we should
not be squeamish about calling fashion and clothing prosthetics. The
sections above on whether fashion is art or design used the notion of
function to show that art could not be distinguished from design on the
basis of one having functions and the other not. We are, therefore, happy
to think about fashion and clothing as having, and performing, a variety of
functions. To think about clothing and fashion as having, and performing,
functions, whether they be to keep our bodies warm and dry or to construct
a social and cultural identity, is to think of them as tools, as things we use
to accomplish some task or other. The task may be communication, identity
creation, looking nice or keeping us dry, but the clothes have functions and
to that extent they are tools. As tools, they are prostheses: something that
is not us but which we add to ourselves and without which we would
consider ourselves incomplete. Strictly, clothing and fashion are no different
in this respect from both our bodies and language. Neither our bodies nor
language are us but we use them to represent ourselves to other people. I
am not my hair, fingernails or limbs, and I am not the English language,
but I use all of them to represent myself to other people. What I think of,
and experience, as myself is not available to anyone, including myself, except
as representation in, and through, tools such as language. My body and
the language I use are prosthetics, therefore, which are not me and which
I need to learn to use but without which I would hardly be (me) at all.
This conception of fashion as prosthesis must be distinguished from
those approaches to prosthesis that conceive it as a progressive or
increasing integration of machines and non-human parts into bodies. This
conception presents prosthesis as an extension or enhancement of the
properties and capabilities of that body (see the essays in Smith and Morra
Conclusion
This chapter has investigated what fashion is and is not. Whether fashion
is art or not and whether fashion is design or not has been discussed and
it has been argued that fashion is not art. Indeed, on the account presented
Further reading
Arnold, R. (2009) Fashion: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Davis, F. (1992) Fashion, Culture and Identity, Chicago, University of Chicago
Press; chapter 8 on anti-fashion.
http://lucian.uchicago.edu/blogs/mediatheory/keywords/prosthesis/; last
accessed November 2013.
Jain, S. (1999) ‘The Prosthetic Imagination: Enabling and Disabling the
Prosthesis Trope’, Science, Technology and Human Values, 24, 1, Winter:
31–54.
Pappas, N. (2010) ‘The Naked Truth of Antifashion Philosophy’, in Scapp,
R. and Seitz, B. (eds) Fashion Statements, New York, Palgrave.
What fashion
and clothing do
Introduction
The previous chapter used the idea of function to distinguish art and design,
and considered the argument that fashion is design because it has a function
or a series of functions. This chapter will begin to identify and explain those
functions; the chapter will analyse what it is that fashion and clothing do.
We will see that many of the discussions around what fashion and clothing
do have their origin in early anthropological accounts of adornment. These
discussions concern the ways in which what we wear protects us from the
elements, keeping us warm and dry, for example. They also refer to cultural
values regarding appropriate levels of modesty and display. And they
introduce the communicative functions of what we wear, the ways in which
fashion and clothing are meaningful.
Thomas Carlyle
Writing at the beginning of the nineteenth century, Thomas Carlyle pro-
poses either a logical or a chronological sequence of functions in clothing.
pervading law of all things organic, and inorganic, of all things physical
and metaphysical, of all things human and all things superhuman, of
all true manifestations of the head, of the heart, of the soul, that the
life is recognizable in its expression.
(Sullivan quoted in Roth 1983: 345)
Conclusion
This chapter has identified and explained various functions performed by
fashion and clothing. Some, those involving protection, modesty and
seduction, for example, have been tentatively identified as ‘anthropological’
and distinguished from the communicative function. Saying that they are
‘anthropological’ is partly a reference to the early anthropologists who were
interested in asking and answering the ‘why’ questions about clothing. It
is also partly a reference to Roland Barthes’ account of meaning in his essay
‘Rhetoric of the Image’. In this essay he refers to a minimal level of meaning,
a level that applies to knowing that the shapes in a picture represent
tomatoes, or a string bag, for example. He calls this the anthropological,
and wants to indicate that this is a very low level of meaning, almost nothing,
as he says, but not nothing (Barthes 1977: 42). It is not nothing because it
is cultural: one still needs to be a member of a culture to understand this
Further reading
Eicher, J. B., Evenson, S. L. and Lutz, H. A. (eds) The Visible Self, New York,
Fairchild.
Roach-Higgins, M. E., Eicher, J. B. and Johnson, K. K. P. (eds) Dress and
Identity, New York, Fairchild.
Fashion and/in
history
Introduction
This chapter will consider the relation between fashion and history. Fashion
is often used as a kind of shorthand for ‘the past’ or for particular periods
of ‘the past’ in films and television dramas. (It is also used as a kind of
shorthand for ‘the future’: certain genres of science fiction film often feature
‘unisex’ and minimalist clothing in the latest metallic or intelligent textiles,
where they stand metonymically for progress and temporal difference.) And
many would claim that history cannot be successfully or fruitfully taught
without referring to fashion, to the ephemeral things that people wore and
used in their everyday lives. This relation to history resolves very quickly
into a relation to time because history is often conceived as the simple
passage of time and because fashion is itself defined as the passing of one
style and its replacement by another. Given that temporality is at the very
centre of any possible theory of fashion and history, it is surprising how
late the study of fashion history came to the academic party. Anthea Jarvis
says that ‘the history of dress and fashion was not studied seriously in
academic circles before the 1960s’ (Jarvis 1998: 299). Lou Taylor agrees
and adds that the ‘old’ universities in the UK judged object-based studies
of dress and textiles history to be improper subjects until as late as the
1990s (Taylor 2002: 64–5). This impropriety was held by some male-
dominated institutions to be potentially damaging to the ‘real history’ that
they taught and they feared that the study of fashion history would ‘trivialize
history itself’ (Taylor 2002: 1–2).
Backdrop
The first of the five possible relations between fashion and history is that
history is a backdrop to fashion. This is the idea that history, in the guise
of events or things that happen, goes on in the background of fashion or
behind fashion’s back. Fashion is the main event but history is a series of
the optimistic social and economic climate of the early 1960s started
to fade as unemployment and inflation rose . . . . People began to
question the human and environmental consequences of technology.
(Laver 1969b: 266)
Hippy fashions are presented and described in the following two pages with
no mention of any questioning of environmental consequences and Punk
is presented and described four pages later with no mention of how it might
relate to unemployment or inflation: history here is a simple backdrop, going
on inertly in the background of the fashions.
He does something similar when he writes about the fashions
immediately before the Second World War. Commenting on French fashions
at Longchamps in 1930, he says that ‘The skirts are on the eve of going
long again and the waist is about to resume its normal place’ (Laver 1969b:
237). There is a tension here between fashion as a simple Baudrillardian
sequence of differences (skirts are long, then short, then long again; see
Baudrillard 1981: 78–9) and fashion as the norm. If there is a norm, then
fashion cannot be a sequence of differences and Laver’s position is
reminiscent of Veblen’s when he fails to believe that the ‘transient . . .
mimicry’ of fashionably shaved faces will not soon be replaced by the normal
practice of men wearing beards (Veblen 1992: 130). History simply occurs
in the background of fashion and neither one is considered to be any part
of the explanation of the other.
Context
The second position is probably the one with which many students in
England will be most familiar, it being the default position of most, if not
all, of the historical and theoretical studies programmes in art and design
that have been instituted in higher education since the Coldstream Reports.
This position holds that history is a context for fashion: it is a setting within
which fashion takes place. History on this kind of account can be something
that fashion reflects or it can be something to which fashion points. In
all cases, however, fashion derives its meaning and significance from its
Transforming
The third position argues that fashion is able to produce and transform
history. This position is significantly different from the positions discussed
so far because where history pre-exists fashion in the first and second
positions, it is made possible by fashion in this third position. This
preposterous sounding claim may be explained by approaching it through
Outdated or classic?
There is a website concerned with the correct use of the English language
that asks the question, what is the difference between the terms ‘old-
fashioned’, ‘out of fashion’, ‘unfashionable’ and ‘outdated’? The answer
given is that, while all of these phrases could be used insultingly, to put
someone down, only one could be used positively (stackexchange.com).
Only one phrase could have ‘good’ put in front of it and still make sense.
That one phrase is, of course, ‘old-fashioned’. We happily talk about good,
old-fashioned fun, and Google’s auto complete search function suggests
good old-fashioned pancakes and good old-fashioned bluegrass. The
relation between fashion and time, or fashion and history, is clearly an
important one. It is the relation that makes the difference between being
appropriately or acceptably dressed and being dressed inappropriately or
unacceptably. What makes something ‘out of fashion’, ‘unfashionable’
or ‘outdated’ is simply time; the passing of time turns the fashionable
into the unfashionable, the outdated, and it turns fashion into the out of
fashion. Time as the passage of time turns the present, the current and the
fashionable, into history, the past and the unfashionable. It may strike us
as odd, therefore, that we may still talk of ‘good old-fashioned clothes’. The
sense here is that the clothes are well made or of good quality, as they
‘used to be’.
This is an ultimately paradoxical reference to a value involving fashion
that is held to be ‘timeless’. It is paradoxical because fashion is very much
‘of the time’ and is, therefore, the opposite of timeless. We talk of fashion
‘seasons’ and the point of seasons is that they pass and are replaced by
another season. The value that is thus held to be both inside and outside
time in the phrase ‘good old-fashioned clothes’ is ‘high quality’ or ‘good
quality’, a persisting or reliable condition of being authentic or otherwise
excellent. Andy Hamilton provides an example of this kind of thinking when
he says that ‘classic’ means ‘excellent of its kind’ (Hamilton 2011: 68). It
is surely these connotations of quality, excellence and authenticity that
lie behind the positive valuations of ‘retro’ clothing. Something must
differentiate the positivity and attractiveness associated with ‘retro’ or
vintage clothing from the negativity and ugliness associated with dowdy,
Conclusion
This chapter has accounted for the main relations that can exist between
fashion, what we wear and history. Five central positions on the matter
have been identified and explained. History as inert backdrop to fashion,
history as the context of fashion and history as the product of fashion were
outlined. Two more positions, that fashion is a politically ineffective
reflection of existing historical and political ‘reality’ and that fashion can
have no relation to history, were also explained. Finally, the entire notion
of the so-called fashion ‘classic’ was analysed as a relation to time and
history and therefore not outside of either. The following chapter will follow
up one of the hints noted above regarding the construction of meaning in
what we wear and consider the subject of fashion as communication.
Further reading
Bentley, M. (1999) Modern Historiography: An Introduction, London,
Routledge; especially chapter 14: The History of the Present.
Breward, C. (1998) ‘Cultures, Identities, Histories: Fashioning a Cultural
Approach to Dress’, Fashion Theory, 2, 4: 301–13.
Jenkins, K. (1995) On ‘What is History?’, London, Routledge.
Taylor, L. (2002) The Study of Dress History, Manchester, Manchester UP.
Fashion as
communication
Introduction
An article entitled ‘Is Ann Romney Sending Secret Messages With Her
Clothing?’ appeared in New York magazine on 13 June 2012 (http://nymag.
com/daily/intel/2012/06/ann-romneys-secret-clothing-agenda.html).
Written by Margaret Hartmann, the article concerned the tops and dresses
worn in public and in her television appearances by Ann Romney over the
course of the 2012 presidential campaign waged by her husband, Mitt
Romney. While it is in itself of no importance here, the top that received
much attention in the article was a $1,000 Reed-Krakoff bird-print blouse
that featured ‘a giant seagull soaring into her armpit’, according to
Hartmann.
What is of no little importance here is the title of the article. It is
important because it introduces all the issues of this chapter, which concerns
fashion and communication. It also introduces most of the mistakes that
people make when they think and write about fashion and communication.
There are three such issues and three such mistakes, and they are all
characteristic of what is known as the sender/receiver model of com-
munication. First, the title refers to ‘messages’. It assumes or presupposes
that messages are what we are talking about when we talk about clothing
and fashion. Second, the title refers to ‘sending’. It assumes or presupposes
that messages are sent by people’s clothing and, inevitably, that they are
received by the people who are looking at that clothing. And third, the title
fashion as communication 73
refers to ‘secret messages’. It assumes or presupposes that the messages
sent may be not shared or private.
Hartmann attempts to identify the ‘message’ that Ann is sending through
her clothing and says that ‘experts are divided’ as to what it might be. The
‘image consultant’ Sandy Dumont says that the striking top may be a
‘counter’ to Mitt’s sober-suited, stiff formality. Another possible message
concerns a lack of sophistication: that, despite having the horse-riding tastes
appropriate to one of the richest women in the country, she can still relate
to ‘ordinary people’. And the ‘political analyst’ Taylor Marsh says that the
message is ‘This is who I am. I like this shirt’. Despite referring to the sending
of messages, Hartmann does not attempt to identify the recipients of those
messages. However, we may spend a moment imagining them. We may
assume that the first message is sent to the voters of America, who are
wondering whether Mitt is the kind of guy they want as President. If his stiff
formality is a problem for these voters, then the relaxed informality of his
wife may solve it. The recipients of the second message are easier to find as
they are implied in the description of the message. They are, of course, the
relatively unsophisticated and the relatively poor people of America, to whom
the blouse says ‘Don’t worry, I look as vulgar as you sometimes’. And the
third message is surely also intended to be received by the voters of America.
The common-sense and no-nonsense electorate is to be addressed and
impressed by the blouse’s ‘This is me and here I stand’.
The third issue is the most curious and self-contradictory, but it is not
uncommon in accounts of meanings and messages. The idea that a message
might be a secret message makes no sense at all, of course. If a ‘message’
remains truly secret, then it is not a message because it is not sent by
anyone and it is not received by anyone. The point of a message on this
kind of account is surely that it is broadcast, sent and received; and that,
clearly, is not anyone’s idea of a secret. Struggling charitably to imagine
what Hartmann might mean here, one wonders whether the message is
intended for personal friends, or a political inner circle, or to those ‘in the
know’, or to fellow Republicans. On such an account, sceptical or distrusting
Republicans might feel reassured and included by having their fears and
worries assuaged by this colourful blouse. Alternatively, personal friends of
the Romneys might feel a smug familiarity, having seen this blouse at an
intimate private dinner perhaps. Democrats and other strangers will not
receive the message and will feel left out and slighted.
However, to even think about these inside groups, these inner circles of
good friends and close colleagues, is already to think about a message that
is not, or is no longer, or never was, a private message. Whatever the message
is, it has been made public and to make it public is the end of its private
existence. It could also be argued that, in order even to think the message
to oneself (and not say it or display it in one’s blouse), that message must
74 fashion as communication
already be in principle shareable and therefore not private. In order to be
even, or only, in principle communicable, the message is already not private:
the code must already exist and the point of a code is that it is understandable
by more than one person. Similarly, the groups are only groups because they
consist of people who communicate with each other and communication is
the sharing or making public of meanings. To that extent the ‘message’ never
was secret and it never had a private existence; there are no private codes
and there can be no private messages or languages.
Via these three elements, this apparently simple headline introduces
the issues with which this chapter will deal. And, as we shall see, it is also
through those elements, which are central features of the sender/receiver
model of communication, that three main mistakes are introduced when
people think about fashion and communication. The rest of this chapter
will examine various models of communication in order to determine which,
if any, are appropriate to the job of describing fashion as communication.
The chapter will look first at the sender/receiver model, then at semiotic
models, which argue that meaning is negotiated, and finally at some
critiques of both in order to explain fashion as communication.
Sender/receiver models
Sender/receiver models of communication are also called ‘process’ models
because communication is conceived as a process in which someone sends
a message to someone else through a channel. In our case, the channel
will be what we wear – fashion and clothing – and is also called the medium.
Accounts of this model traditionally begin with the work of Claude Elwood
Shannon and Warren Weaver (1949), who were working in telecommu-
nications after the Second World War. Their model may be represented in
the form of a diagram, see Figure 6.1.
In this diagram, the information source provides the information that
is to be transmitted and the transmitter (the encoder) puts the information
into a signal appropriate to the channel. This signal is then sent in the
channel or medium to be received and decoded as a message by the receiver.
At any and all points in this process the signal may be distorted or interfered
with – a distorted signal is said to be ‘noise’ or ‘noisy’.
Noise
fashion as communication 75
One may quite easily imagine the telecommunications equipment that
this model describes. The mouthpiece of the telephone might be part of
the transmitter, which turns sound into electrical charge, the wires would
be the channel along which the electrical charge moves and the earpiece of
the handset might be the receiver, which decodes the electric pulses and turns
them into sounds. Imagining how this model may be turned and applied to
what we wear, however, is less easy. Who or what is the sender or transmitter
in this case? Is it the person who designed our shirt? Is it the shirt itself? Or
are we, the wearers, the senders? What of the receiver – is it the wearer or the
spectator of the shirt? Is it both; could there be many receivers? And what
would constitute fashion noise; what could interfere with or distort the fashion
message? These are very simple problems, which concern the metaphorical
turning of the model from one topic to another, but there are no obvious
answers and the model is not looking convincing so far.
It should be fairly clear that clothing and fashion do not send messages of
a very specific nature. By this I mean that they do not send messages con-
cerning the minutiae of one’s everyday life. Roz Chast’s cartoon, in which
the clothes of Rhonda Perlmutter III send messages saying that she likes
tuna and that her mother lives in Sacramento, effectively makes the point
that is also made by Fred Davis (1992: 7), Grant McCracken (1988: 64) and
Colin Campbell (1997: 347) that clothing does not communicate such
specific things as these. So, it will be a problem for the sender/receiver
model to explain how, if clothes and fashion do not send messages like
these, they send messages at all.
There are more complicated problems that concern the operation of
the model, supposing that we could simply apply it to fashion. It would be
a poor designer who did not know the people for whom they were
designing. The designer need not know the people personally, or individually,
of course, but it would be expected that the designer would know the kind,
or the type, of people for whom they were designing. They will know the
age, sex, social class, cultural identity and so on of their ‘target’ market,
and they will tailor what they design according to what they know of the
preferences of that target market. There is a sense here in which the ‘target’
market, who are presumably the ‘receivers’ of the garment/message, are
in fact determining or creating the nature of what is ‘sent’. This slightly
paradoxical phenomenon has not escaped the notice of the fashions careers’
advisors at wetfeet.com, who explain it like this:
76 fashion as communication
They clearly understand that the receiver is effectively generating the
message in ways that the simple sender/receiver model cannot account
for.
The sender/receiver model remains both prevalent and popular despite
these problems. Not unconnected with this model is the idea that fashion
is a language. People commonly think of speech or writing when they think
of communication, and if fashion is to be understood as communication,
then it probably seems reasonable to them to think in terms of fashion as
a language. The most well-known example of this is Alison Lurie’s The
Language of Clothes (1981). In this book, Lurie valiantly seeks out the fashion
equivalents of some of the elements of language. Individual garments are
said to be like words and there are fashion equivalents of archaic, slang
and foreign words, for example. Where an affluent fashion leader may have
several hundred ‘words’ in their ‘wardrobe’, a poor sharecropper may have
only five or ten ‘words’ in their ‘vocabulary’ (Lurie 1981: 5). Blue jeans and
baseball caps are offered as the equivalents of ‘slang’ words, acceptable in
everyday life but not in any formal context (Lurie 1981: 8).
As Grant McCracken points out, this is a metaphorical use of language
and its transference from writing and speaking to what we wear is not
straightforward (McCracken 1988: 64). McCracken’s case is closely argued
and complex but it reduces to the claim that clothing is ‘incapable of creating
new messages’ (McCracken 1988: 68). Language has ‘combinatorial free-
dom’ – it is able to combine words into new sequences that communicate
things that have not been communicated before: clothing lacks this freedom
and can only repeat existing and ‘pre-fabricated’ messages. As a result,
clothing cannot communicate ‘irony, metaphor . . . [or] ambivalence’
(McCracken 1988: 69). When fashion and clothing tries to be novel and
original in the ways that language can be novel and original, by combining
elements in ways that are not familiar, communication fails as people are
confused and can make no sense of what they are seeing. As McCracken
says, ‘For the clothing code, novelty of the sort possessed by language
is not an opportunity for communication, but a barrier to it’ (McCracken
1988: 66–7).
Quite how those messages first come into existence and then become
old messages is not explained and this is a serious weakness in McCracken’s
account. The logic of the account demands that they must have come
into existence once, that they must have been new and original once and
that the ‘barrier’ of confusion and lack of sense must have been overcome.
If the clothing message came into existence and became an old message,
it must have been understood for the first time, it must have been poss-
ible to understand it as a new thing that had not been communicated or
understood before. And if that must have happened, then fashion must
have had the ability to make new combinations and it must have been
fashion as communication 77
possible to understand those new combinations and make them meaningful.
If that could happen then, why can it not happen now?
What is needed here is an account that does not depend on the first
time of a new understanding, because it presupposes a prior time when
there was no code or structure according to which the new item could be
understood. In clothing and language, the structure or code always pre-
exists us and any new combination we make always presupposes that
existence. Consequently, language and clothing both enjoy some
combinatorial freedom and the existence of the code guarantees that any
initial ‘bafflement’ that results from that freedom can always, in principle,
be overcome.
Colin Campbell’s elegant and powerful critique of the sender/receiver
model is aimed squarely at the ideas that meaning in fashion and clothing
is a message that is sent and received, and that communication through
clothing operates in any way like a language (Campbell 1997). Campbell
points out that, in order for anyone to receive a message through clothing,
one must first of all know what ‘language’ is being ‘spoken’ and one must
be fairly certain that the person to whom one is sending any message also
knows the language (Campbell 1997: 342). A 1991 Gallup poll indicating
that 45 per cent of people asked thought that turn-ups on men’s trousers
were ‘fashionable’ and that 43 per cent of people asked thought that
they were ‘unfashionable’ is taken to suggest that getting on for half of all
people do not know actually know the ‘language’ of trousers at all (Campbell
1997: 343). In a series of moves consistent with those described below
in the semiological account of meaning, Campbell correctly concludes
from this that ‘the “meaning” of any one particular item of clothing . . . will
differ depending on who witnesses it’ (Campbell 1997: 343). Another entirely
correct conclusion is that, even if some successful communication with
some people is achieved, it is likely to be at the expense of not
communicating at all with others and of sending yet others a message that
was not intended at all (Campbell 1997: 344).
Semiotic models
The English word ‘semiotic’ means ‘relating to signs’ and it derives from
the ancient Greek words, semeion meaning ‘sign’ and sema meaning ‘signal’.
Semiotic models of communication are also known as ‘structuralist’ models
because they argue that structures make communication possible. These
structures are social structures on the one hand and the structures within
which signs exist on the other. These structures are explicitly acknowledged
in semiology as always pre-existing us and it is the interaction between the
elements making up these two kinds of structure and ourselves that creates
78 fashion as communication
and reproduces meanings. It is also through this interaction that we
construct ourselves as individuals and as members of cultures and societies.
As Fiske says, ‘semiotics . . . defines social interaction as that which
constitutes the individual as a member of a particular culture or society’
(Fiske 1990: 2–3). We become, or are made, members of different societies
and cultures by interacting with other members and learning the meanings
of the different signs used in and by those societies and cultures.
Communication through or by means of fashion and clothing is a social
and cultural interaction that constitutes us as members of those societies
and cultures. Membership is dependent upon us learning and knowing the
meanings of what we wear and wearing them at the appropriate times and
places.
It is worth noting at this point that this account of fashion in terms of
signs, thinking about the things we wear as signs, is consistent with the
idea of fashion as prosthesis, introduced above in Chapter 3. The things
we wear are literally not us and they are not literally us. However, we use
the things we wear to represent, or stand for, what we think of as us, or as
ourselves. Our clothing and fashion stand for, or represent, our cultural,
sexual, national, class and other identities. They are, therefore, tools and
another word for tool is prosthetic. As signs, then, the things we wear are
prosthetic devices or tools that we use to represent ourselves.
On this account of communication, meaning is constructed and
negotiated and, therefore, subject to endless change and revision, as cultures
change and as members of those cultures change. Consequently, meaning
is not something that is sent from one place and received in another in
the ways that messages are said to be in the sender/receiver model of
communication. Meaning on this account is more like Roland Barthes’
conception of connotation in his 1977 essay ‘Rhetoric of the Image’.
Connotation is a shifting set of associations and feelings concerning the
object that are aroused in an individual as a result of their cultural identity
or location. Meaning is the product of the interaction between the
individual’s cultural values and beliefs (which they have as a result of being
a certain age, nationality, gender, class and so on) and the item of clothing
or fashion. Given that different people will be members of different cultural
groups, they will possess different beliefs and values, and the meaning of
items of fashion will differ between them.
For example, a balaclava will mean something different to an elderly
English ex-serviceman from what it will mean to a young Russian female
fan of Pussy Riot. It will do this not because it sends a different message
(it is the same item; how could it?), but because the cultural values held
by the elderly man will be quite different from those held by the young
woman. It is the interaction between the different values and the item that
generate the different connotations, not the item itself. To the elderly male
fashion as communication 79
ex-serviceman, the garment may have connotations of extreme danger, of
the possibility of dying and the memories of friends and colleagues who
did die. It may also connote certain masculine notions of comradeship and
discipline. To the young woman, the garment may connote a violent and
noisy femininity, a failure to conform to many consumer ideals. It may also
make her think of a grainy and shaky video shot in the main cathedral in
Moscow and the political radicalization of a generation of Russian women.
The cultural locations of these two imaginary people are totally different –
one is old, one is young; one is male, one is female and so on. The cultural
beliefs and values they have as a result of those different locations or
identities determine that they make different things of the garment.
According to one set of values and beliefs the garment means one thing,
or one group of closely related things. And according to a different set of
values and beliefs, the garment means another, different thing, or group
of things.
This negotiation or interaction between values and objects is also one
of the ways in which an individual is (or is not) constructed as a member
(or not) of a cultural group. It therefore relates to matters of identity, which
will be explored in detail in Chapter 7. Agreeing on what garments and other
items of fashion are and are not cool, or masculine, or ‘too old’ is a
large part of what makes one a member of a cultural group. It would be
difficult to sustain a serious claim to membership of any Goth culture while
expressing a preference for pastel twinsets, discreet eye shadow and a nice
tan, after all. And if your values and beliefs lead you to understand that
skimpy tops and short skirts are immodest and decadent, then you are
unlikely to be constructed or seen as a member of any contemporary Western
youth cultures. This is because it is the sharing of the cultural values, via
the application of those values to items and practices of fashion and
clothing, that produces the shared meanings of the items. And it is whether
the values and the understanding of those meanings are shared or not that
makes an individual a member of the cultural group or not. Therefore, the
interaction between the individual, the cultural values and the item of
clothing constructs the meaning of the object and the identity of the
individual at the same time.
It should be clear how this semiological model deals with the problem
of ‘secret’ messages that was raised in the introduction to this chapter. The
New York magazine headline asked whether Ann Romney was sending
‘secret’ messages with or through her $1,000 Reed-Krakoff blouse. It was
argued that the idea of a ‘secret’ message made no sense: a message was
either public and shared, or it was not a message. We are now in a position
to see that not only are messages not sent and received through clothing,
but that what we are talking about are meanings that are constructed and
negotiated by members of cultures. Consequently, we can explain how it is
80 fashion as communication
that different groups of people in Hartmann’s story will construct different
meanings for the blouse according to the different beliefs and values that
they hold. The different beliefs and values are playing the role of different
‘codes’, according to which the same item has different meanings for the
different groups holding those beliefs and values. So, the unsophisticated
and less affluent voter in Hartmann’s account will be reassured by the
‘vulgar’ blouse that Ann is just like them – that she shares their trashy and
garish aesthetic values, for example. The wealthy Republican voters men-
tioned above will be reassured by knowing the source and the price of the
blouse – their shared valuation of expensive and exclusive designer goods
will be understood and reproduced.
This semiological account also allows us to explain how and why it is
that Campbell’s statements above are correct (if not necessarily for the
reasons he gives). He said that ‘the “meaning” of any one particular item
of clothing displayed will differ depending on who witnesses it’ and he argues
that:
Campbell argues these points against the sender/receiver model and against
the idea that clothing functions almost exactly like a language; they are for
him faults of the model and illustrate that the idea is mistaken. However,
on the semiological model, they are true, utterly unsurprising and indicate
no faults or mistakes at all. Of course an item will mean something differ-
ent to each ‘witness’ – meaning is generated in the interaction between an
individual’s cultural values and the item and different values will generate
different meanings. Only if we want the same message to arrive as we
assume was sent is there a problem when meanings change and differ
between individuals.
Similarly, if the meaning of the Goth’s leopard print T-shirt (as a
reference or homage to their culture’s punk roots or as an indication of
rockabilly tendencies) is understood as such by other Goths, then
communication can be said to have been successful. But this is not because
of a message having been sent and received – it is because of the shared
Goth values. If you do not possess or know the values, you will not under-
stand this nuance of meaning, although you may have them explained to
you. As a result, you will understand the culture better than you did before.
Strictly, there can be no such thing as a ‘lack’ of communication, and what
Campbell experiences and describes as such a ‘lack’ of communication is
fashion as communication 81
explained by the fact that the individuals do not share the same values. To
the Goth the T-shirt may be reverent and hark back to a punk heritage;
to the non-Goth it is simply tacky and cheap and connotes a vulgar lower-
class form of femininity. There is no lack or failure of communication,
because a meaning is understood, it is just not the one that the Goth
constructs. And again, what is presented as the ‘arrival’ of an ‘unintended’
message and as a problem for the sender/receiver model is explained in
the very same way. The meaning is constructed according to the values of
the person doing the understanding. It makes no sense to talk of unintended,
because meaning is not a product of intention, it is a product of an
interaction between the values of the interpreter and the clothing item.
Meaning
The following paragraphs will explain in more detail the kind of meaning
that is being proposed and used in this chapter and they will consider the
case of the United Kingdom ex-Prime Minister Tony Blair’s frog pattern
silk tie.
In his 1977 essay ‘Rhetoric of the Image’, Roland Barthes identifies
connotation as a level of meaning and it is only the account of connota-
tion that is of interest here. This is because, although Barthes refers to
denotation, a literal or ‘non-coded’ and culture-free meaning, he admits
that it does not exist. When he is discussing what is required to recognize
and understand the contents of the image – the tomato and the string bag,
for example – he says that what is needed is a knowledge ‘bound up in our
perception’, that this knowledge is ‘not nil’ and that it is ‘anthropological’
(Barthes 1977: 36). That is, we need to have some culturally specific
knowledge even to recognize the things as tomatoes and string bags: were
it not for that cultural, and therefore coded, knowledge, we would not
recognize or understand these things. This level of meaning is already
cultural, therefore, and to that extent connotational. Consequently, and
despite Barthes’ inconsistency on the point, a non-coded denotational level
of meaning does not exist.
On the understanding, then, that there is no such thing as denotation,
that any apparently literal or denotational meaning is in fact always
metaphorical and connotational, we may begin to account for meaning as
connotation. What is of interest here is that Barthes explicitly identifies
connotation with culture (Barthes 1977: 46). As a result, he says that the
reading of any image can, and will, vary between individuals, and that this
variation is not random or ‘anarchic’. Rather, these different interpretations
and readings are the products of the different knowledges and kinds of
knowledges that these different individuals will have as a consequence
82 fashion as communication
of their different cultural locations and identities (Barthes 1977: 46). As well
as providing a series of different values and beliefs, these different cultural
locations and identities provide a series of different ‘practices and
techniques’ and a series of ‘attitudes’ (Barthes 1977: 47). Each of these
provides more ideas and beliefs in terms of which the image or object may
be read and made meaningful.
In the essay, Barthes carefully and methodically explains the workings
of the connotative signs that he identifies in the Panzani advert. He says
that there are four connotative signs and he identifies the signifiers and
signifieds of each. He also identifies the ‘generally cultural knowledge’ that
each requires in order to be meaningful to, or in order to be understood
by, anyone. He makes it absolutely clear, then, that these are not messages
that are being sent, they are meanings that are being constructed in the
interaction between culture and image. The different kinds of knowledge,
the beliefs and values, of the culturally located individuals who see the image
in the adverts are used to construct the different meanings of the image
and the advert. If one does not have the knowledge, or does not share the
values, then one will not understand the meaning: this will be most obvious
in the case of the fourth of the connotations.
The first signified that Barthes identifies is that of ‘a return from market’
(Barthes 1977: 34). Its signifier is the half-open bag and the contents spilling
out over the table. Together they make the connotational sign. In order to
construct this connotational meaning and for communication to take place,
one needs to know certain things and one needs to have certain beliefs and
values. Barthes says that we need to be familiar with the idea of ‘shopping
around for oneself’ (Barthes 1977: 34). The values of a certain self-
sufficiency, of a particular way of ensuring that one does not go hungry,
are required in order to construct this meaning. If one lives in a culture
that forages in the undergrowth for berries, or if one has servants to do the
shopping and the cooking, one is likely to construct quite a different meaning
here. The second signified is Barthes’ famous idea of ‘Italianicity’. Its signifier
is the white, green and red of the mushrooms, pepper and tomato in the
bag. In order to construct this meaning one needs to be familiar with ‘certain
tourist stereotypes’ (Barthes 1977: 34). Unless one lives in a culture in which
tourism is popular or at least possible, unless one understands the idea of
Italy and its flag, one will construct a different meaning from the colours.
The third connotation is that of ‘a total culinary service’ and its signifier
is the ‘collection of different objects’. Barthes does not explain the values
or cultural knowledge that is necessary here but hints that it is a familiarity
with brands and brand names. It is, he says, as though Panzani furnish
everything one needs for a ‘carefully balanced dish’ (Barthes 1977: 34–5).
And the fourth signified is that of the nature morte or ‘still life’, signified by
the ‘composition’ of the image. Clearly, unless one has some knowledge
fashion as communication 83
Figure 6.2 Panzani advertisement. (Image courtesy of The Advertising Archives.)
84 fashion as communication
not mention is through gender. The meaning of the shopping bag, slung
onto the kitchen table, constructed by a single man will be entirely different
from that constructed by a married mother, for example.
Case study 1
The nature of connotational meaning, the role of cultural beliefs, values
and ideas in the construction of meanings and the way that different values
construct different meanings should all be clear. Now we need to explain
how these ideas apply to the things we wear. The matter of ex-Prime Minister
Tony Blair’s tie in the photograph will be used to illustrate how these ideas
explain the construction of meaning in fashion and clothing.
The tie features green frogs on a red background and was, apparently,
one of Blair’s favourites.
First, we should note the role that cultural knowledge plays in seeing
and recognizing the garments in the photograph. Even to see and recognize
the garments being worn as suits, shirts and ties requires some cultural
knowledge that is not available to all cultures. Another angle on this would
be to point out that, even what appear to be the most basic elements of
understanding the meaning of the clothes here, are already connotational:
there is no denotational, non-coded or literal understanding possible. As
Figure 6.3 Tony Blair and George Bush at June 2004 meeting of Euro-Atlantic
Partnership Council. (Credit: NATO Photos: www.nato.int/multi/photos/2004/
m040629f.htm)
fashion as communication 85
soon as they are recognized as such, the suits, shirts and ties are culturally
loaded: their meaning is connotational.
Second, we can consider the colour of the ties here. Both ties are
red. The colour is a connotative signifier. But the cultural differences
between the two men mean that the signifieds of these signifiers will be
different and the meaning of the red will be different for each. Blair’s liberal
background and socialist values will produce a meaning that is different
from Bush’s conservative background and decidedly non-socialist values.
Neither man is strictly sending a message with the red. If they were, the
message of socialist solidarity would be the same and that is surely
unthinkable. Rather, the values that each holds are interacting with the colour
to generate different meanings. The same colour connotes different
meanings because of the different cultural and political values that each
man holds.
If the material that the ties are made of is considered, more layers of
connotation and cultural difference are found. It is almost certain that both
men’s ties are made of pure silk. Both men are engaged at this time with
various Muslim groups and both claim to represent various Christian values.
At the time of this photograph, 2004, it is likely that neither man would set
out deliberately to offend either Christians or Muslims by wearing anything
inappropriate. However, according to some Muslim scholars, Surah A’raf
Ayah 26 of the Qur’an indicates that it is haram, or forbidden, for men to
wear garments made of pure silk (www.al-islam.org). Because neither Bush
nor Blair has this knowledge, because they do not hold these cultural values
and beliefs, neither understands the potentially offensive meaning that the
ties will have for some Muslims. Again, the same material connotes different
things, according to the different values possessed by members of different
cultures. According to the sender/receiver model of communication, we
would have to conclude that the men were deliberately sending offensive
messages to their Muslim audience because that was ‘the’ meaning of the
silk. But now we can see that meaning is the result of the interaction between
values and item, and if one does not hold the values or possess the
knowledge then no such meaning, or a different meaning, is constructed.
The frogs on Blair’s tie are potentially unsettling, if not actually
offensive, to some Christians. The frog has long connoted uncleanliness in
Christian and Old Testament belief systems. Chapter 16, verse 13 of The
Revelation of St. John The Divine, for example, refers to frogs as ‘unclean
spirits’. In chapter 8 of the book of Exodus, the second of the plagues
inflicted by Yahweh on the Pharoah of Egypt is the plague of frogs. Blair’s
Christian beliefs are now well known, even if he downplayed them during
his time in office, but either way it is simply not plausible to suggest that
he would have wanted to unsettle or offend fellow believers at this time.
Consequently, one is obliged to conclude that he does not know this element
86 fashion as communication
of Old Testament theology and, therefore, does not understand this
meaning. However, according to the sender/receiver account of communi-
cation, if we thought that Blair did know this reference, then we would have
to conclude that he was deliberately sending an offensive or unsettling
message.
Case study 2
Hip-hop, street or urban clothing may be used to show not only the ways
in which different cultural values construct different meanings of clothes,
but also the ways in which those clothes and those meanings may be used
by subordinate or ‘subaltern’ cultural groups to resist, oppose and challenge
dominant cultural groups. The different meanings that are constructed
will be explored and explained here, and the ways in which they are used
politically to resist and challenge dominant cultures will be dealt with in
the next chapter.
Let us start on a very broad scale, with some very broad-brush
indications of the different meanings of what members of youth subcultures
wear. Those members consider what they wear to be ‘cool’, ‘hot’, ‘trendy’
or any of the other slang terms used by youth cultures over the years to
indicate what is most recent and most ‘in fashion’ at the time. Authority
figures, including parents, teachers, policemen and so on, have described
the meaning of what these youths wear as ‘delinquent’, ‘disrespectful’ and
sometimes ‘criminal’. The worst or most threatening meaning that such
groups give to the clothing is that it is somehow socially pathological; that
it is indicative or a symptom of a social malaise. Social scientists often give
the clothing a slightly different meaning, saying that it is ‘deviant’ from
social norms or resistant to a dominant and constructing social or cultural
order. The different values and perspectives adopted by these different
groups generate the different meanings.
On a smaller scale or a more tightly focused level, we may ask about
the meanings of individual items of hip-hop wear and about the meanings
of ensembles of such clothing. Some theorists have quoted the rapper
Treach who explains the use of gold chains or dookie/Dukie ropes as a
means of showing solidarity with black prisoners and as a reference to slavery
(quoted by Wilbekin, in Light 1999: 280). Membership of the group is
established and the meaning of the ropes is negotiated through the relation
between the knowledge and the values and the object itself. If you possess
the values and have the knowledge, then you will understand the mean-
ing of the gold chains in this particular way and the necessary, if not
the sufficient, conditions for membership of the group are satisfied. The
meaning of the drooping or sagging pants/trousers worn by certain black
fashion as communication 87
cultures is also much debated. Some suggest that it is another way of
showing respect and sympathy for fellow black people in prison whose belts
have been removed in an attempt to prevent suicide by hanging; less
sympathetic commentators suggest that the practice is an unwitting aping
of gay male prostitute style. Baxter and Marina (2008) argue convincingly
that among the black youth cultures of New Orleans, it is the sympathy
with fellow black people in prison that motivates the practice. The meaning
of the low-slung or saggy trousers/pants is generated by the relation to the
knowledge and values of black solidarity in an act of resistance directed at
the dominant white culture.
Baxter and Marina report and explain the meanings of other forms of
sartorial display as resistance or challenge to the various authority figures
in these communities – parents, teachers and the police, for example. It
becomes clear that what is being resisted or challenged by the use of the
particular clothing and hairstyles is ‘conformity’ with the ‘right’ way and the
‘proper’ way. The right and proper way is defined by the various forms of
‘authority’ the young people encounter, in parental, school and local
government dress codes, for example. As John, one of their correspondents
points out, ‘you could wear baggy pants and pull em up and wear em right
. . . I was taught to wear my pants on my waist’; he is aware of the school
dress code but says ‘nobody ain’t gonna tell me nothin’ (Baxter and Marina
2008: 106–7). We can clearly see that the different values and beliefs, as
to what constitutes the right and proper way to wear one’s pants/trousers,
for example, generate the different meanings of the style. The values held
by the parents and school principals regarding saggy pants/trousers
generate the meaning of worrying delinquency. The young people’s values
generate the meaning of independent rebelliousness.
Yet another way in which different values and beliefs may be seen to
generate different meanings of hip-hop and street style clothing may be
seen in the attempts of the authorities at the National Basketball Association
(NBA) to institute a dress code for its players. In 2005, American basketball
had a poor image. In recent years, there had been a brawl at a Pistons–Pacers
game in The Palace in Auburn Hills, Kobe Bryant had been charged with
rape, Allen Iverson had been arrested on drugs and firearms charges
and there was, according to David J. Leonard, a general perception that
American basketball was being ‘overrun’ by criminals and ‘gangstas’
(Leonard 2012). One of the final straws came during the 2004 Olympics,
according to Leonard, when the USA team attended a dinner in a high-class
restaurant wearing ‘oversized jeans . . . large platinum chains and . . .
diamond earrings’ (Leonard 2012). In response to this perceived crisis, David
Stern, the Commissioner of the NBA, attempted to impose a dress code
for all NBA players in 2005. The code expressly forbids sleeveless shirts,
88 fashion as communication
sports apparel, chains, pendants or medallions worn over the player’s
clothes, and sunglasses while indoors (NBA 2012).
To the NBA, hip-hop styles connoted unprofessionalism and were
associated with criminality. According to the NBA’s values and interests,
which would be those in support of a profitable, TV-friendly and wholesome
family sport, the sports clothing (snapback hats, Starter jackets and so on),
dookie chains and diamonds all represented (meant) a threat to those values
and interests. The code was perceived by many as racist, directed against
the kinds of garments and styles that black hip-hop fans wore and was seen
by them as explicitly anti-black and anti-hip-hop. To the players, the style
represented ‘authenticity’ and a chance to express their personalities. Never
far from the action, Allen Iverson said the code ‘makes it kind of fake’ and
resented the fact that the prescriptions prevented people from expressing
‘their own style’. Although he does not mention racism explicitly, he does
say of the NBA and the prohibitions that ‘they’re targeting guys like me
. . . guys who dress hip-hop’ (bbc.co.uk 2012). The values of the players are
clearly different from those of the NBA authorities and one can clearly see
how the meanings of the garments and the styles are constructed quite
differently according to the membership of one or other of the cultural
groups involved.
Conclusion
fashion as communication 89
number of combinations of levels of knowledge, different knowledges and
individuals with which to construct meanings.
The following chapter will build upon this conception of meaning to
show in more detail how the politics of fashion and clothing operate in
terms of resistance.
Further reading
Campbell, C. (1997) ‘When the Meaning is Not a Message: A Critique of
the Consumption as Communication Thesis’, in Nava, M., Blake, A.,
MacRury, I. and Richards, B. (eds) Buy This Book, London, Routledge.
Damhorst, M. L., Miller, K. A. and Michelman, S. O. (eds) (1999) The
Meanings of Dress, New York, Fairchild.
Johnson, L. (2010) ‘Pod Peeps: Why the iPod and Other Gadgets Are
Fashion Staples in the “Hood”’, in Scapp, R. and Seitz, B. (eds) Fashion
Statements, New York, Palgrave.
McCracken, G. (1988) Culture and Consumption, Bloomington and
Indianapolis, Indiana University Press; see chapter 4.
90 fashion as communication
chapter 7
Fashion, identity
and difference
Introduction
In an interview for Vogue with Ryan Smith, the actor Jessica Alba says ‘fashion
represents one’s identity’ (video available at www.youtube.com/watch?
v=vwGDBFjxgUo&feature=related_; last accessed July 2012).
Elaborating a little, she says that fashion ‘is your personality, on the
outside’ and that it represents ‘who you are’. The interview is interesting
for many reasons, but what is most interesting for us here in this chapter
is that Alba expresses a series of very common assumptions concerning
the relation between fashion and identity.
First, she says that the relation between fashion and identity is one of
representation: fashion represents identity. Representation is correctly
placed at the centre, at the heart of fashion and what we wear. As central
and essential to an account of fashion as representation is, it may yet require
some explanation. Simply, representation is one thing standing for another
thing and we are familiar with it in many areas of our lives. In America
and the UK, for example, elected Members of Congress and Members of
Parliament are not us but they stand for us and represent us in The House
of Representatives and The House of Commons, respectively. In our case,
in this chapter, fashion is said to represent, or stand for, one’s identity.
What we wear represents or stands for us, or stands for something about
us. It is as though one’s identity exists somewhere, separate and apart from
what one wears, and that what one wears stands for that identity. As we
shall see, this is indeed part of what clothing and fashion do, and the
ideal, and they are opposed to the meaning of the wall, the grey, destructive
negativity and the reality of the West Bank. Again, these meanings are the
products of the values held by the members of the groups and it is the
interaction that ensures or prevents membership. As Goldfainer said, ‘I think
the way to solve conflict is not to build walls’ (quoted in Vaughan 2004).
If you believe in the possibility and healing power of the cooperative
work, then the shirts and the shoot will mean one thing: if you believe in
rigid separation and apartheid, then the garments and the set will mean
something else. That the Israeli Government gave it a different meaning,
as a result of their different values, is reported by Goldfainer herself when
she points out that members of the Knesset appeared on radio and television
asking people to ‘boycott’ the catalogue (Scarff 2005: 68). Again, we can
see that the different values generate a different meaning, a different identity
and a different political position; in this case a position that is opposed to
that of the Comme il Faut women.
Conclusion
This chapter has established in what sense it is the case that fashion
represents one’s identity and it has used that explanation to begin the
explanation of the politics of fashion. It has shown that representation is
one thing standing for another thing and that it is necessary for the
construction of one’s self-identity and meaning. Jessica Alba’s common-
sense account of fashion as the representation of personality ‘on the outside’
was examined and found to contain some sense but not all the sense of
the way in which personal identity and cultural difference are established
though what we wear. Fashion stands for, or represents, the values and
beliefs that we have as members of different cultural groups. The chapter
has also demonstrated that the construction of self-identity and meaning
is also the construction of a political position, because even self-identity
and meaning require the relation to other people, and because politics is
simply a series of relations to other people.
Reference has been made to the impossibility of the body (or anything
else) meaning nothing and the following chapter will introduce how the
body relates to our notions of clothing and fashion. We will see one more
aspect of the sense behind Virginia Woolf’s suggestion in chapter 4 of
Orlando that ‘it is clothes that wear us and not we them; we may make
them take the mould of arm or breast, but they mould our hearts, our brains,
our tongues to their liking’ (Woolf 1928: 187–8). The notion of clothing will
be expanded to include all aspects of culture and this has interesting
consequences for our understanding of the body.
Further reading
Fashion, clothes
and the body
Introduction
The fashion industry’s preference for, and dependence on, very thin models
is well known and well documented. Karl Lagerfeld, for example, is famous
for having said in an interview that ‘no-one wants to see round women’
and deriding the ‘fat mummies’ who sit on their sofas eating potato crisps
while saying how ugly the thin models are (Halfhead 2009). And it does
not take long to discover that at least six female fashion models have died
of eating-related disorders since 2006, including the Ramos sisters and
Isabelle Caro, who campaigned against anorexia before her death in
November 2010 aged 28.
Oliviero Toscani is best known for his controversial work for Benetton
in the 1980s and 1990s, which dealt with AIDS, interracial sex and the death
penalty. His work in 2007 for the Italian fashion house Nolita is no less
controversial and is completely opposed to the views of those in the industry,
such as Lagerfeld, using the emaciated body of Caro to illustrate the dangers
of the eating disorder. Doctors believe that UK model Bethaney Wallace
died of a weakened heart caused by the disease in 2012. More rarely, male
models also die of such disorders. Jeremy Gillitzer, for example, suffered
from anorexia and bulimia and died in 2010 aged 38 and weighing 66lb.
There is clearly a predominant fashion for models with thinner, smaller
bodies and until now, with the critical work of photographers such as
Toscani, such bodies have generally been held to be more in fashion and
more desirable than larger or even ‘normal’ sized bodies.
However, the thing that fashion does best is change, and it is no surprise
to see larger bodies and larger models coming into fashion and being used
in catwalk shows and advertising. These larger bodies are sometimes called
‘real’ bodies, and they are sometimes said to belong to ‘real women’. The
other thing that fashion does well is to profit from change. In 2012, Ben
Barry, the CEO of the Ben Barry model agency, argued that women are more
likely to buy fashion and other clothing items if the models they see in
adverts are the same sizes and shapes as they are. In June 2011, the Italian
edition of Vogue used ‘curvy’ models, including Candice Huffine, Tara Lynn
and Robyn Lawley, in a feature entitled Sogno di Donna and shot by Steven
Meisel. New York has run a ‘Full-Figured Fashion Week’ since 2011. Every
model agency now offers a range of so-called ‘plus sized’ women and
Hughes Models in London represent exclusively ‘plus size’ models, offering
size 10+ and size 14+ women. Bodies are not only there to hang fashion
and clothing from; they are not simply the neutral and a-fashionable carriers
of fashion. Bodies are also fashion; they are themselves fashionable items
and different sizes and styles of body go in and out of vogue as the seasons
change, just like the clothes that adorn them.
It was argued above that the body and every body part that one has and
experiences ‘naturally’ is already equipment. That is, bodies and their parts
are already ‘dress’, they are already cultural constructions. This was said to
be because there is no non-cultural experience, perception or account of
the natural, including what we think of as our natural bodies. If that is the
case, then those parts, and one’s body, are already prosthetic constructions
and there can be no natural and proper body to be adorned by something
unnatural and improper, because it is already ‘unnatural’ and ‘improper’.
It is claimed that these statements answer Entwistle’s question concerning
the nature of dress’s involvement with the body. Clearly, the senses of
unnatural and improper have shifted slightly but significantly, as have those
of dressed and undressed. However, we are now left with the problem of
how to account for the real women who are really suffering from real body
dysmorphia issues and dying of real eating disorders. This chapter now
has to reconsider the argument concerning the cultural construction of
the body. Surely these women’s illnesses and deaths indicate that there
is a material body beyond representation that is not a mere cultural
construction?
The simple answer is that, no, they do not. They do not indicate the
existence of a ‘real’, where real people really live and really die, a real that
is beyond mere representation and cultural construction. What they do show
is the irresistible power of cultural construction, meaning and ‘dress’. Again,
the real is a decision, rather than a discovery, and there can be no ‘correct’
definition or image of ‘real women’. There can be what is referred to as
‘politically correct’ images and definitions, but this is the sense behind it:
that it is a decision made in the process of negotiation and communication,
rather than a discovery of an essence or identity. Until the power of that
cultural construction and the role of politics in it is acknowledged and
accounted for, the phenomenon will remain misdiagnosed and the cure
misprescribed.
to adopt the poses and make the moves familiar to us from countless
high-fashion supermodel shoots and records them on video. The women
lie ‘artistically’ in parks, to the consternation of the park-keeper. They pose
‘dramatically’ in street markets and fast-food restaurants, to the obvious
concern of shoppers who clearly fear for their mental health.
Dominguez explained her critical strategy in the Poses project by saying
that:
By showing the absurdity of the poses in the ‘real’ contexts, which are
as staged as anything found in any fashion shoot, and acknowledged as
such, Dominguez effectively and powerfully deconstructs the real/image
dichotomy and shows the constitutive role of representation in what is
supposedly ‘real’ life. The ‘impossibility’ of the poses in the ‘real’ of the
locations clearly shocks and upsets some of the passers by and amuses
others. This is evidence that they are fully aware of the absurdity and unreality
Conclusion
This chapter has tried to explain what the body is and how it relates to
fashion and clothing. It started from our everyday common sense and
possibly unnoticed understanding of the body and its relation to the things
we wear, and it tried to show that that everyday understanding was not as
Further reading
Chin, E. (2010) ‘Tech Savvy: Technology as the New Fashion’, in Scapp, R.
and Seitz, B. (eds) Fashion Statements, New York, Palgrave.
Entwistle, J. (2000) The Fashioned Body, London, Polity.
http://lucian.uchicago.edu/blogs/mediatheory/keywords/prosthesis/; last
accessed November 2013.
Jain, S. (1999) ‘The Prosthetic Imagination: Enabling and Disabling the
Prosthesis Trope’, Science, Technology and Human Values, 24, 1, Winter:
31–54.
Rabine, L. W. (1994) ‘Woman’s Two Bodies: Fashion Magazines, Con-
sumerism and Feminism’, in Benstock, S. and Ferris, S. (eds) On Fashion,
New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press.
Vincent, S. J. (2009) The Anatomy of Fashion: Dressing the Body from the
Renaissance to Today, Oxford, Berg.
Wurst, K. (2003) ‘Designing the Self: Fashion and The Body’, in Henn, M.
and Pausch, H. A. (eds) Body Dialectics in the Age of Goethe, Amsterdam
and New York, Rodopi.
Fashion production
and consumption
Introduction
In 2012 the anti-poverty charity, War on Want, campaigned against the
exploitation of the factory workers who were producing Adidas sportswear.
Adidas were the highly prestigious ‘official sportswear partner’ of the London
2012 Olympic Games, and their advertising posters and visual projections
were to be found all over the Olympic park in east London.
While individuals such as Tyson Gay, Johan Blake and Jess Ennis, along
with the rest of the UK team, were to be seen competing patriotically in
Adidas kit, War on Want were attaching tags saying ‘34p’ (about 53 US cents)
to clothing items for sale in Adidas outlets. The 34p was to represent
the hourly wage that the predominantly female workers in Indonesia were
allegedly paid to produce the kit worn by these heavily sponsored sports
stars, as well as ordinary customers. War on Want’s point was that this is
not much of a wage. War on Want also claimed that workers making the
UK team’s kit in Bangladesh faced physical and verbal abuse and were forced
to work illegally long hours for their money. Although other sportswear
companies, such as Puma and Nike, were also targeted by War on Want,
Adidas had good reason for wanting to avoid this kind of negative publicity.
Only a year before, dozens of young people wearing Adidas sportswear had
been photographed while looting shops in the London riots; the familiar
three stripes and trefoils were everywhere to be seen amidst the smoke and
debris. Even a quick glance at the press coverage of the 2011 London riots
will indicate that the young people’s riot gear of choice was largely Adidas:
the press photographs exist to prove it. And only a year after their 2012
campaign, War on Want were drawing attention to the deaths of at
least 1,000 clothing workers when the Rana Plaza factory near Dhaka,
Bangladesh, collapsed in April 2013. The factory produced clothes for
high street labels such as Matalan, Primark and Mango. Two factory owners
and two engineers, who had issued public safety certificates for the factory,
were being held on charges of criminal negligence and War on Want
argued that the workers need not have died had Primark taken seriously
its responsibilities towards its workers (Al-Mahmood 2013).
These brief references to these stories introduce most of the major
issues of this chapter. They raise various problems involved in the
Economic reductionism
The references to the stories above also introduce a debate around fashion
and economics, which this chapter needs to explain and contextualize. The
debate concerns economic reductionism. Economic reductionism is the
argument that a phenomenon, fashion in our case, may be explained
completely in terms of economics – in terms of production and consump-
tion. In the course of an argument against all forms of reductionism,
Elizabeth Wilson says that:
because the origins and rise of fashion were so closely linked with the
development of mercantile capitalism, economic explanations of the
fashion phenomenon have always been popular. It was easy to believe
that the function of fashion stemmed from capitalism’s need for
perpetual expansion, which encouraged consumption.
(Wilson 1985: 49)
Production
Another function performed by production in relation to fashion and clothing
is the ideological one identified by Angela McRobbie in her British Fashion
Design (1998). The ideological function should be conceived as being
performed as part of, not alongside or separate from, the economic function
of production. This is because, as McRobbie says, the economic cannot be
conceived as ‘existing in some pure state, untainted by the cultural and the
symbolic’ (McRobbie 1998: 5). As we saw in Chapter 4, whatever functions
fashion and clothing are said to perform, those functions must always
manifest themselves in some form, at some particular time and place: they
must take some value-based, cultural and, therefore, meaningful form. Value
and, therefore, ideology is already present in economic function. And this
is to establish the ideological function of fashion production as already part
of the economic function.
McRobbie introduces the ideological function of fashion production by
recalling Robin Murray’s characterization of people working in UK design
consultancies in the 1980s as ‘the engineers of designer capitalism’
(McRobbie 1998: 1). She says that she was puzzled by Murray’s equation
between being a designer and ‘designing for capitalism’ and wanted to ask
whether there was not, in the 1990s, a more nuanced relation between
fashion design and capitalism. McRobbie wants to remind us of the
‘beginnings’ of British fashion in the ‘sweaty spaces . . . of raves and night
clubs and in the bedrooms of the groups of girls who designed and made
their own outfits for these events’ (McRobbie 1998: 9). This reminder is
(still) important because these activities were often different from, and at
odds with, the demands and aesthetics of mainstream fashion and because
some of these girls ‘ended up’ selling their products on market stalls or to
Consumption
It is probably true to say that most analyses and explanations of fashion,
from cultural studies and sociological perspectives, have concentrated more
on the consumption of fashion than they have on the production of fashion.
The following section will do nothing to correct this tendency but it will
explain a side of consumption that is often neglected. Where most accounts
of consumption and identity will stress the sharing of values that engender
cultural belonging and common identity, this chapter will investigate Mary
Douglas’s account of consumption as hostility. It will then consider Tim
Dant’s account of those aspects of consumption that happen long after
one has clicked the ‘Buy’ button or gotten one’s clothes home; wearing
them out.
Conclusion
This chapter has outlined some of the main theoretical positions available
on the matter of production and consumption in fashion. It has explained
how the production and the consumption of fashion raise political, cultural
Further reading
Edwards, T. (2010) Fashion in Focus, Routledge; chapter 5 on consumption
and children.
Niessen, S. (2005) ‘The Prism of Fashion: Temptation, Resistance and
Trade’, in Brand, J. and Teunissen, J. (eds) Global Fashion, Local Tradition:
On the Globalisation of Fashion, Arnhem NL, Terra.
Rivoli, P. (2006) The Travels of a T-Shirt in the Global Economy, Chichester,
John Wiley and Sons.
Veblen, T. (1992) The Theory of The Leisure Class, New York, Transction
Books; classic text on conspicuous consumption.
Modern and
postmodern
fashion
Introduction
In her entry on Martin Margiela for fashionencyclopedia.com (Steel no date),
Valerie Steele says that Margiela is ‘very much’ a postmodern designer.
Included in the list of things that make him a postmodern designer are his
use of ‘frayed threads’ and ‘exposed linings’. These elements draw attention
to the construction and the constructed nature of the clothes we wear; they
illustrate how the parts of the things we wear are cut and joined together.
As Steele says, frayed threads and exposed linings ‘testify to the internal
construction of the garments’ and these practices make Margiela a
postmodernist fashion designer. Features such as these are often included
with other practices, such as distressing, bleaching, slashing and recycling,
to make up a strand of postmodern fashion that has become known as
‘fashion destroy’ or ‘deconstruction fashion’. When this has happened,
Margiela’s name is commonly added to a list of fashion designers that
includes Rei Kawakubo and Hussein Chalayan. Chalayan’s burying of
garments so that they begin the process of decay and decomposition is
taken to be postmodern and ‘deconstructionist’. Kawakubo’s work is often
explained as deconstructionist because of her use of pre-distressed materials
and the ironing in of permanent creases at the production stage. These
practices are described by borrowing the Japanese phrase boro boro, which
is usually translated as ‘worn out’.
Modern fashion
I have noted elsewhere that the phrase ‘modern fashion’ is potentially
tautologous (Barnard 2007: 387). If one takes ‘fashion’ to mean the latest
style or look, and if one takes ‘modern’ to mean the most recent events or
period of time, then the phrase ‘modern fashion’ is the simple repetition
of a single idea or meaning; as such it is a tautology. Consequently, if this
chapter is to contribute anything useful, a different sense of ‘modern’ must
be found. That different sense may be found if ‘modern’ and its close relation
‘modernism’ are used to refer to, or indeed represent, a set of ideas.
Eugene Lunn (1985) identifies modernism as a set of five ideas, which
concern aesthetic form and social function. The first concerns aesthetic
self-consciousness or self-reflexiveness and it indicates the ways in which
artists and designers draw attention to the media and materials with which
they work (Lunn 1985: 34). This idea is found in modernist works from Kant’s
Streetstyle
Ted Polhemus’s account of contemporary fashion is a good example of this
second aspect of how postmodernism has been understood. In the 2010
second edition of his Streetstyle, he develops and elaborates the idea of
Conclusion
The attempts to define modernism and postmodernism and then to use
those definitions to explain fashion have been seen to generate many
problems. First, the definition and central ideas of some people’s accounts
of modernism began to look disturbingly like other people’s accounts of
postmodernism when it came to applying them in the explanation of fashion.
Second, when it came to using those definitions to explain postmodern
garments, the examples of supposedly postmodern fashion proved to have
Further reading
Breward, C. and Evans, C. (eds) (2005) Fashion and Modernity, Oxford, Berg.
Cixous, H. (2009) ‘Sonia Rykiel in Translation’, in Benstock, S. and Ferris,
S. (eds) On Fashion, New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press.
Evans, C. (2003) Fashion at the Edge: Spectacle, Modernity and Deathliness,
New Haven, Yale University Press.
Lehmann, U. (2000) Tigersprung: Fashion in Modernity, Cambridge, MA, MIT
Press.
Globalization
and colonialism
Introduction
In 2004, Tommy Hilfiger Apparel was launched in Mumbai, India. The
tommy.com website is happy to describe Hilfiger as a global brand and
says that they produce a range of clothing ‘celebrating’ the ‘essence of
Classical American Cool’ and provide a ‘refreshing twist’ on the ‘preppy
fashion genre’. Mumbai is a city of 12 million people, made up of 70 per
cent Hindu, 20 per cent Muslim and 10 per cent Jewish, Christian and Jain
religious groups, speaking a variety of languages, including Marathai, Hindi,
Gujarati and English. As ‘Tommy’ says in the ‘diversity’ subsection of the
‘social responsibility’ section of the tommy.com website, ‘I create my clothes
for all different types of people, regardless of their race, religious or cultural
background’. Three years later, in November 2007, Hilfiger felt confident
enough to open their first freestanding store in Delhi. In a filmed interview,
the Bollywood film actor and model Arjun Rampal, who is from a Delhi
family, was happy to endorse the brand, posing in front of the store and
saying that he finds Hilfiger’s clothes ‘easy to wear’ and ‘comfortable’. The
store itself is also shown in the interview (on livemint.com), as the camera
pans across the polo shirts and chinos, and takes a tour of Hilfiger’s familiar
blond wood floors, cream walls, stainless steel rails and dark wood fitments.
In 2012, the globaltommy.com website indicates that there are 46 stores
or outlets in 17 Indian cities, from Jaipur in the north to Cochin in the south.
The events described in this brief paragraph introduce many ele-
ments of the difficult and complex debate that surrounds globalization.
What is globalization?
One may characterize globalization very simply as the sense that wherever
one goes in the world one is in the same place. Roland Robertson, for
example, says that globalization is the ‘crystallization of the entire world as
a single place’ (Robertson, quoted in Arnason 1990: 220). This means that,
wherever one is, one sees the same shops selling the same products as
one sees ‘at home’. It also means that one sees the same advertisements
What is colonialism?
Colonialism is related to globalization in that it, too, concerns the
domination of one group of people by another group of people. In the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, powerful European nations, such as
Great Britain, Spain and Holland, scoured the globe seeking out new
products and new markets. Simplifying and generalizing, British traders went
to Africa, Spanish traders went to the Americas and the Dutch went to
Indonesia. Local cultures experienced the power of, and were forced to adapt
to, these Western countries. Colonialism is related to globalization in that
it, too, is thoroughly political; it concerns the economic and cultural ways
in which those colonized cultures resisted and escaped the domination of
The Zambian coat of arms may be the only national coat of arms that
features recognizable fashion garments. Dating from 1964, when the
Republic of Zambia gained independence from the British Empire, the arms
depict a man standing to the viewer’s left of the escutcheon, or shield, and
supporting it. He is wearing a safari jacket and shorts. To the right is a
Zambian woman in what Wikipedia calls ‘traditional garb’. In September
2012, the Zambian Post Online reported that Professor Michelo Hansungule
had argued in a lecture that the coat of arms should be changed because
it was ‘outdated’. Professor Hansungule also objected to what the people
Conclusion
This chapter has introduced the matter of globalization and fashion. It has
provided a simple account of globalization, as homogenization and
uniformity, and described the various ways in which that model or account
is inadequate. The chapter has also provided a more complex account of
globalization, in which the global is always in relation to that which is
different from it – the local. And it has argued that globalization is usefully
approached as communication, in terms of the different values held by
different groups around the world to generate or negotiate different
meanings. Consequently, the objects and commodities in the case studies
could be seen to mean different things to different cultural groups,
according to the different values and beliefs held by those groups. Local
cultures are said to possess different values from globalizing culture(s) and,
consequently, the meanings of the garments and practices are different for
the members of the different cultures.
Further reading
Paulicelli, E. and Clark, H. (eds) The Fabric of Cultures: Fashion, Identity and
Globalization, London, Routledge.
Ramamurthy, A. (2004) ‘Spectacles and Illusions: Photography and
Commodity Culture’, in Wells, L. (ed.) Photography: A Critical Introduction,
Third Edition, London, Routledge; see pp. 220–35 on fashion photography
and colonialism.
van Beek, G. (2005) ‘Culture in Shreds’, in Brand, J. and Teunissen, J. (eds)
Global Fashion, Local Tradition: On the Globalisation of Fashion, Arnhem
NL, Terra.
Fashion and
(the) image
Introduction
In a 2011 interview, the British fashion designer Giles Deacon said that the
fashion industry presented an ‘unrealistic’ image of women (in Finnigan
and Sawer 2011). The headline for the article in which the interview appeared
suggested that the fashion industry ‘forced’ an ‘unrealistic’ image on women
through its obsession with ‘skinny models’. The article went on to report
the deaths of models Luisel and Eliana Ramos and Ana Carolina Reston
from heart failure following a ‘starvation diet’ and anorexia, respectively
(see Chapter 8 in this volume for theories of how these issues relate fashion
to the body). It also went on to imply that the ‘image’ of women that the
fashion industry created and promoted was responsible for the deaths.
The image, and the fashion industry that created and promoted it, are held
responsible for those deaths because the industry promotes the image and
‘forces’ it onto women. This story introduces some of the themes of this
chapter: an image, a representation of femininity, is generated in and by
the fashion industry and it is deemed so powerful that some women will
die in their attempt to attain it.
This story uses one sense of ‘image’, the sense intended by ‘fashion
and image’ in the chapter title. The sense of image here is that of a model
or ideal of femininity. It is the sense of image as an ideal or desired look,
shape, size or kind of body. It also refers to the self-image that women in
this case have of themselves and to the power that that image has in
controlling or influencing what they eat, how they exercise and how they
it. The actual garment is nowhere to be seen and the use of a photograph
of the garment on the sandwich board suggests that Feuerbach is correct
and we have indeed developed a preference for the representation over the
real thing.
These thoughts may be developed a little if we take another look at
Sontag’s account of photography. She suggests that Plato’s account of
knowledge is made with the intention or in the interest of an ‘image-free’
knowledge and an image-free way of understanding the real. Plato’s point
is that all the humans in his story are compelled to look at shadows and
images: one could argue that anyone outside the cave, anyone who was
able to comprehend the forms in their eternal and essential truth would
very bad. When there are details on a black dress they melt away because
the ink isn’t controlled in the printing. I like the blending effect but
editors sometimes worry about seeing detail on clothes.
(Lennard in di Grappa 1981: 93)
The light is tungsten, a Mole Richardson 1000 scoop on the front and
four lamps on the back . . . everything was shot on Tri-X rated ASA 800
for a grainy effect . . . . Later I went through an FP-4 phase.
(Bailey in di Grappa 1981: 7)
Figure 12.3 Brooks Brothers logo. (Copyright © Brooks Brothers Group Ltd:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Brooks_Brothers_Logo.png)
Conclusion
This chapter has introduced various ways in which fashion and clothing
relate to (the) image. The allegedly deceptive and deceitful aspects of fashion
and clothing were traced back to Plato’s epistemological story of the cave:
this story was explained as an early account of how images are not true
knowledge but untrustworthy and the source, according to Lipovetsky, of
our mistrust of fashion and its images. Fashion’s use of imagery, in
photography, for example, was also introduced. Some of the common
structures and patterns of connotational meaning were identified and
analysed by Barthes’ brief but fecund account of fashion photography. And,
moving in the opposite direction from Barthes, it was argued that
connotation, cultural meaning, could be ‘read’ from fashion photographer’s
descriptions of the technology they favoured. Finally, the customary
Further reading
Brookes, R. (1992) ‘Fashion Photography’, in Ash, J. and Wilson, E. (eds)
Chic Thrills, London, Pandora.
Craik, J. (1994) The Face of Fashion, London, Routledge; chapter 5 on fashion
photography.
Jobling, P. (1999) Fashion Spreads: Word and Image in Fashion Photography
Since 1980, Oxford, Berg.
Ramamurthy, A. (2004) ‘Spectacles and Illusions: Photography and
Commodity Culture’, in Wells, L. (ed.) Photography: A Critical Introduction,
Third Edition, London, Routledge; see pp. 220–35 on fashion photography
and colonialism.
Shinkle, E. (ed.) (2008) Fashion as Photograph, London, I.B. Tauris.
Fashion, fetish
and the erotic
Introduction
In December 2010, the Mail Online website reported that ‘bondage’ is ‘this
season’s dominant lingerie trend’ (Mail Online 2010). Not a website to miss
an opportunity to show Rihanna, Lady Gaga and Cheryl Cole cavorting on
stage in their underwear, the article quotes Helen Attwood, Selfridges’ Head
Buyer for Lingerie, as saying ‘This winter S&M has gone couture’ and points
out that ‘This season, Selfridges’ average lingerie spend is up by 20 per
cent on risqué brands including Agent Provocateur and Myla’. Selfridges’
customers looking for Nichole de Carle London lingerie are apparently
‘fighting’ to pay £220 for the ‘Dream Catcher’ stretch silk bra in order to
enjoy the ‘erotic look’ made famous by Rihanna and Lady Gaga. Apparently
unaware of the pun, the article connects what it calls ‘dominant’ fashion
to such fetishized activities as S&M via the medium of fashionable lingerie,
thus neatly and economically introducing all the concerns of this chapter.
What the Mail Online so enthusiastically mixes up in its pursuit of
readers and click-throughs, this chapter must separate and identify in the
pursuit of analysis and explanation. The fetish of S&M and the erotic charge
of the lingerie are said to be the solution to shoppers’ problems concerning
how to ‘add some spice in the bedroom’. The erotic and the fetish are both
presented here as the answer to a question about how best to arouse sexual
desire, and the consumption of expensive fashionable underwear is
presented here as the natural and unquestioned means of achieving this.
The notions of fashion, fetish and the erotic, and the relations between
It is probably worth noting that only in psychoanalysis does the fetish object
have erotic functions and connotations; in economics and anthropology, it
has neither. We must now investigate the erotic. The English word ‘erotic’
means ‘pertaining to sexual love or passion’. It derives from an ancient
Greek word eros, which meant sexual desire: it also derives from ‘Eros’,
which was the name of the Greek god of love and sexual desire. In his
version of psychoanalysis, Freud presents eros as a universal animating force,
which is both creative and productive. It may be contrasted in his later work
with thanatos, which is an equally universal desire for death or oblivion.
Freud himself relates his ‘enlarged’ conception of eros, which concerns a
wider range of activities and interests than merely sexual passion, to that
found in the work of Plato (Freud 1953: 134). Platonic eros may be thought
of as a universal motivational force. It is an aesthetic and erotic energy that
suffuses one’s body, intellect and soul and which, handled correctly, leads
one to the correct understanding of the good, the beautiful and the true.
While most fashion theorists understand René Koenig’s work The
Restless Image (1973) as sociology, as concerned with class and social
structures, for example, he is very interesting as a psychoanalyst and has
written about both scopophilia and exhibitionism, which he links to auto-
eroticism and to the body. In the section entitled ‘To See and To Be Seen’,
he is concerned to explain how the erotic manifests itself in the desires to
see and to be looked at: in psychoanalysis, the desire to see is called
‘scopophilia’ and the desire to be seen is labelled ‘exhibitionism’. Koenig
argues that the desire to see and the desire to be seen ‘grow from the same
erotic root’; that root is the body (Koenig 1973: 81). The subject’s own body
is originally the source of visual pleasure. What is happening is, therefore,
both scopophilic and exhibitionist as the subject is displaying their own
body to themselves and getting pleasure from it. After this initial stage, the
desire to see develops into the desire to see the bodies of other people and
this is more obviously scopophilia. As Koenig says, ‘only afterwards is the
desire to see directed towards another body for comparison’. And after this
stage, the scopophilic activities are themselves abandoned in favour of
purely exhibitionist passivity. As Koenig says, ‘In the end, this object too
[scopophilia] is abandoned and . . . the activity of looking is transformed
into passivity and the establishment of a new goal, that of being seen’
(Koenig 1973: 82).
It is tempting, if ultimately unsatisfying and unconvincing, to suggest
that scopophilia in fashion and clothing is an immature form of obtaining
pleasure from looking and that exhibitionism is the mature form. Koenig’s
account may be accused of being overly complicated. It would seem
Conclusion
This chapter has explained what the fetish and the erotic are, and it has
explained how fashion and clothing may be explained as fetish and erotic
items. The economic, psychoanalytic and anthropological senses of the word
fetish were all defined and explained, and they were all used to make sense
of the ideas of fashion and clothing. The economic and the psychoanalytic
were the most heuristically fruitful; the notion of fashion as a series of
fetishized commodities, and the notion of fashion as a series of eroticized
and pleasurable items, were seen to be highly productive and entertaining.
Further reading
Arnold, R. (2001) Fashion, Desire and Anxiety: Image and Morality in the
Twentieth Century, London, I. B. Tauris; chapter 3: The Eroticised Body.
Bancroft, A. (2012) Fashion and Psychoanalysis: Styling the Self, London,
I. B. Tauris.
Barthes, R. (2006) ‘Fashion: A Strategy of Desire’, in The Language of Fashion,
Translated by Andy Stafford, Oxford, Berg.
Caws, Mary Ann (1994) ‘An Erotics of Representation: Fashioning the
Icon with Man Ray’, in Benstock, S. and Ferris, S. (eds) On Fashion,
New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press.
Conclusion
One of the arguments that was presented in the Introduction and followed
up in Chapter 2 was that it is impossible to escape theory when we are
talking and thinking about fashion. Everyone, from little girls in the play-
ground to venerable professors in the Senior Common Room, presupposes
and makes use of some theoretical element when they express their
preference for a pink pencil case or for a psychoanalytical explanation of
pleasure. Somehow, little girls know that the construction of a culturally
correct gender identity depends upon their consumption of as many pink
commodities as possible and venerable professors know that psychoanalysis
offers a true, entertaining and educationally profitable account of pleasure.
It was argued that theory, and fashion theory, is inevitably both productive
and supportive of every statement made about fashion and clothing, whether
that statement is some anecdotal schoolyard trivia or part of one’s PhD
defence. Each chapter in this book has tried to begin from some innocent-
looking or common-sense account of some fashion event or phenomenon,
and it has attempted to show that, and how, those accounts are in fact
anything but innocent or common sense, but that they are the products of,
and laden with, all kinds of theories.
Another argument that has appeared regularly throughout this book is
that style is inescapable and that fashion is, therefore, also unavoidable
and always present. In Chapter 4 it was argued that even the most apparently
‘basic’ or functional aspects of clothing could not be accomplished without
appearing in some style or other. If even these most functional aspects (of
keeping one warm or dry, for example) could not be performed without
the garment taking on one style as opposed to another different style,
then fashion is present. As soon as there is difference, or the possibility of
difference, then there is culture and meaning, and as soon as there is culture
conclusion 215
and meaning, then we have fashion. Difference and meaning being present
in even the most basic and ‘anthropological’ aspects of what we wear, then
fashion is also present.
In Chapter 8, it was argued that the body could not be experienced or
perceived without using representation – even thinking ‘to oneself’, one is
obliged to use representation in the form of words and concepts. The claim
was that if the body cannot be experienced or perceived without using
representation, then it is already fashionable. The argument is complicated
but it starts from the idea that an experience that cannot be described, even
(or especially) to oneself, is incomprehensible: an experience is either
meaningful or it is not an experience. This is because it is not possible to
undergo an experience that means nothing (if there is no meaning, then
there is no experience and nothing to undergo). It was also argued that
there was no way of moving, posing, holding or otherwise being in one’s
body that was not thoroughly cultural and cultured: this was developed into
the argument that even the musculature or the body was cultural in that
there can be no non-cultural (and, therefore, ‘natural’) account of what an
appropriate musculature would be. Consequently, it was claimed that the
body is always already ‘dressed’; the body is always already clothed and
made meaningful by culture, in the form of representation. The experience,
perception and even the appropriate shape, size and musculature of the
body, were the result of cultural dressing and the body was, therefore, said
to be always either in or out of fashion. To put the argument another way:
if even the perception and experience of the body is made possible by
this cultural dressing of words and concepts, then insofar as those
representations are cultural, they will always be subject to variations in style.
Variation in style is another way of describing the operation of fashion and
the body will, therefore, be either in or out of fashion.
And in Chapter 12, it was argued that we cannot appear without some
‘image’ or other and that, image being another pseudonym or alias for
fashion and style, fashion and style were once again inescapable. This
argument may remind some people of the claim that someone or something
‘has no style’: it is a common insult to say of someone that they have ‘no
style’. Clearly, everyone and everything must appear in some way or another.
This is to say that they must appear in some style or another. To see the
mistake involved in saying that someone or something has no style, contrast
the statement ‘X has no style’ with the statement ‘X has (or appears in) no
way’. The manifest idiocy of the latter is only the hidden idiocy of the former.
If we must appear in some style or by presenting some image or other,
then we must appear in some way that is related to fashion, either by being
in fashion or by being out of fashion. Image here is a way of representing
one’s identity by means of what we wear and, given that there is no way of
appearing without representing some image or other, we are always either
216 conclusion
in or out of fashion. In this sense, image once again determines that fashion
is inescapable.
So, both fashion and theory are inescapable. One is always in theory
and one is always in fashion. One is always in fashion, not in the sense
that one’s clothes are always guaranteed to be in the latest fashion but
in the sense that one is always in what Barthes and Baudrillard call the
system or economy of fashion. And one is always in theory, not in the sense
that one is out of practice, but in the sense that everything one says
and thinks will be produced and supported by some explanatory and analy-
tical construct, some conceptual economy, or other. And what links these
economies is representation; they are both forms of representation. As noted
in Chapter 4, representation is simply one thing standing for another. Our
clothes stand for, or represent, our selves and our written, spoken and
thought words stand for, or represent, our concepts and ideas. Each of the
examples in this conclusion has centred around the notion of representation.
And as I have tried to argue throughout this book, there is no outside of
representation. Fashion as communication is possible only in the form of
representation. The body is unavailable to us except as representation. We
cannot appear without appearing as image, and image is nothing if it is
not one thing standing for another thing. As Derrida says, ‘all experience
is the experience of meaning’ and all meaning is the differed and deferred
product of representation (Derrida 1981: 30). We can conclude that theory
is representation and fashion is representation and if there is no outside
of representation, then there is no outside of either theory or fashion. There
is no escaping either theory or fashion and neither theory nor fashion would
make any sense were they not both thoroughly representational.
conclusion 217
Bibliography
Abbott Miller, J. (2007) ‘Through Thick and Thin: Fashion and Type’, Eye, 17, 65:
17–23.
Appadurai, Arjun (1990) ‘Disjuncture and Difference in the Global Cultural
Economy’, in Featherstone, Mike (ed.) Global Culture: Nationalism, Globalization
and Modernity, London, Sage.
Arnason, Johann, P. (1990) ‘Nationalism, Globalization and Modernity’, in
Featherstone, Mike (ed.) Global Culture: Nationalism, Globalization and Modernity,
London, Sage.
Arthur, Linda, B. (ed.) (2000) Undressing Religion: Commitment and Conversion from
a Cross-Cultural Perspective, Oxford, Berg.
Ashwell, Lauren and Langton, Rae (2011) ‘Slaves to Fashion?’, in Wolfendale, Jessica
and Kennett, Jeanette (eds) Fashion: Philosophy for Everyone, Chichester,
Wiley–Blackwell.
Back, Kurt (1985) ‘Modernism and Fashion’, in Barnard, M. (ed.) (2007) Fashion
Theory, London, Routledge; and in Solomon, M. R. (ed.) The Psychology of Fashion,
Lexington, MA, Lexington Books.
Back, Les (1998) ‘Local/Global’, in Jenks, Chris (ed.) Core Sociological Dichotomies,
London, Sage.
Bailey, David (1981) ‘David Bailey’, in di Grappa, Carol (ed.) Fashion: Theory,
New York, Lustrum Press.
Bancroft, Alison (2012) Fashion and Psychoanalysis: Styling the Self, London, I. B.
Tauris.
Barnard, Malcolm (ed.) (2007) Fashion Theory, Abingdon, Routledge.
—— (ed.) (2012) Fashion, Volume IV, Abingdon, Routledge.
Barthes, Roland (1972) Mythologies, London, Granada.
—— (1975) The Pleasure of the Text, New York, Hill and Wang.
—— (1977) ‘Rhetoric of the Image’, in Image–Music–Text, London, Fontana.
—— (1984) Camera Lucida, London, Fontana.
—— (1990) The Fashion System, Berkeley, University of California Press.
218 bibliography
Baudrillard, Jean (1981) For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign, St. Louis,
MO, Telos Press.
—— (1998) The Consumer Society, London, Sage.
Baxter, Vern Kenneth and Marina, Peter (2008) ‘Cultural Meaning and Hip-Hop
Fashion in the African-American Youth Subculture of New Orleans’, Journal of
Youth Studies, 11, 2: 93–113.
Bell, Quentin (1947) On Human Finery, London, Allison and Busby.
Benjamin, Walter (1992) Illuminations, London, Fontana.
Bhabha, Homi (1994) The Location of Culture, London, Routledge.
Boyne, R. and Rattansi, A. (1990) Postmodernism and Society, London, Macmillan.
Braham, Peter (1997) ‘Fashion: Unpacking a Cultural Production’, in Du Gay, Paul
(ed.) Production of Culture/Cultures of Production, London/Milton Keynes, Sage/
Open University.
Braudel, Fernand (1981) The Structures of Everyday Life: Civilization and Capitalism
15th–18th Century, Vol. 1, London, Collins.
Breward, Christopher and Evans, Caroline (2005) Fashion and Modernity, Oxford,
Berg.
Burchill, Julie (2005) ‘Yeah But, No But: Why I’m Proud To Be A Chav’, The Times,
18 February.
Campbell, Colin (1997) ‘When the Meaning is Not a Message’, in Nava, M., Blake,
A., MacRury, I. and Richards, B. (eds) Buy This Book: Studies in Advertising and
Consumption, London, Routledge.
Candlin, Fiona (2001) ‘A Dual Inheritance: the Politics of Educational Reform and
PhDs in Art and Design’, International Journal of Art and Design Education, 20,
3: 302–10.
Carlyle, Thomas (1987) Sartor Resartus, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Cavallaro, Dani and Warwick, Alexandra (1998) Fashioning the Frame, Oxford, Berg.
Craik, Jennifer (1994) The Face of Fashion: Cultural Studies in Fashion, London,
Routledge.
Dant, Tim (1999) Material Culture in the Social World, Buckingham, Open University
Press.
Davies, Lizzy (2009) ‘From Juicers to Jackets – Just Don’t Call it Design’, The
Guardian, 17 June.
Davis, Fred (1992) Fashion, Culture and Identity, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
de Perthuis, Karen (2008) ‘Beyond Perfection: The Fashion Model in the Age of
Digital Manipulation’, in Shinkle, Eugénie (ed.) Fashion as Photograph: Viewing
and Reviewing Images of Fashion, London, I. B. Tauris.
Derrida, Jacques (1973) Speech and Phenomena, Evanston, Northwestern University Press.
—— (1978) Writing and Difference, Chicago, Chicago University Press.
—— (1981) Positions, London, Athlone Press.
Design Museum (2009) Fifty Dresses that Changed the World, London, Octopus.
di Grappa, Carol (ed.) (1981) Fashion: Theory, New York, Lustrum Press.
Doe, Tamasin (1999) ‘Art on Your Sleeve’, The Guardian, 21 May, pp. 4–5.
Douglas, Mary (1996) Thought Styles: Critical Essays in Good Taste, London, Sage.
Douglas, Mary and Isherwood, Baron (1979) The World of Goods: Towards an
Anthropology of Consumption, London, Allen Lane.
bibliography 219
Eco, Umberto (1998) Faith in Fakes: Travels in Hyperreality, London, Vintage.
Entwistle, Joanne (2000) The Fashioned Body, London, Polity.
Entwistle, Joanne and Wilson, Elizabeth (2001) Body Dressing, Oxford, Berg.
Evans, Caroline (2008) ‘A Shop of Images and Signs’, in Shinkle, Eugénie (ed.)
Fashion as Photograph, London, I. B. Tauris.
Ferleger Brades (1998) Addressing the Century: 100 Years of Art and Fashion,
Exhibition Catalogue, Hayward Gallery, London.
Fiske, John (1990) An Introduction to Communication Studies, and Second Edition,
London, Routledge.
Flügel, John (1950) The Psychology of Clothes, London, Hogarth Press.
Foucault, Michel (1970) The Order of Things, London, Tavistock.
—— (1983) This is Not a Pipe, Berkeley, University of California Press.
Freud, Sigmund (1953) ‘Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality’, in The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume 7, London,
Vintage/Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psychoanalysis.
—— (1964) ‘Fetishism’, in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works
of Sigmund Freud, Volume 21, London, Vintage/Hogarth Press and the Institute
of Psychoanalysis.
Gadamer, Hans Georg (1975) Truth and Method, London, Sheed and Ward.
Gamman, Lorraine and Makinen, Merja (1994) Female Fetishism: A New Look,
London, Lawrence and Wishart.
Giddens, Anthony (1979) Central Problems in Social Theory, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
—— (1990) The Consequences of Modernity, London, Polity.
—— (1991) Modernity and Self-Identity, London, Polity.
Greenberg, Clement (1965) ‘Modernist Painting’, in Art and Literature, No 4, Spring,
pp. 193–201; and in Frascina, Francis and Harrison, Charles (eds) (1982) Modern
Art and Modernism, London, OU and Paul Chapman Publishing.
Hamilton, Andy (2011) ‘The Aesthetics of Design’, in Wolfendale, Jessica and Kennett,
Jeanette (eds) Fashion: Philosophy for Everyone, Chichester, Wiley-Blackwell.
Hamilton, Edith and Cairns, Huntington (eds) (1961) The Collected Dialogues of
Plato, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Hartley, Leslie Poles (2004) The Go-Between, London, Penguin.
Hauser, Kitty (2005) ‘The Fingerprint of the Second Skin’, in Breward, C. and Evans,
C. (eds) Fashion and Modernity, Oxford, Berg.
Hayward Gallery (1998) Addressing the Century: 100 Years of Art and Fashion,
Exhibition and Catalogue, London, Hayward Gallery Publishing.
Hill, A. (2005) ‘People Dress So Badly Nowadays: Fashion and Late Modernity’, in
Breward, C. and Evans, C. (eds) Fashion and Modernity, Oxford, Berg.
Hobsbawm, Eric (1994) The Age of Extremes: 1914–1991, London, Abacus.
Hollander, Anne (1994) Sex and Suits, New York, Kodansha International.
Hollingworth, Sumi and Williams, Katya (2009) ‘Constructions of the Working-Class
“Other” Among Urban, White, Middle-Class Youth: “Chavs”, Subculture and the
Valuing of Education’, Journal of Youth Studies, 12, 5: 467–82.
Hurlock, Elizabeth (1965) ‘Sumptuary Law’, in Roach, Mary Ellen and Eicher, Joanne
Bubolz (eds) Dress, Adornment and the Social Order, New York, John Wiley and
Sons.
220 bibliography
Jameson, Frederic (1991) Postmodernism or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,
London, Verso.
Jarvis, Anthea (1998) ‘Letter From the Editor’, Fashion Theory, 2, 4: 299–300.
Jones, Ann Rosalind and Stallybrass, Peter (2000) Renaissance Clothing and the
Materials of Memory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Jones, O. (2012a) Chavs: The Demonization of the Working Class, London, Verso.
Kaiser, Amanda (2012) ‘Mainland Marc’, Women’s Wear Daily, 20 July, 204, 14: 6.
Khan, Nathalie (2000) ‘Catwalk Politics’, in Bruzzi, Stella and Church-Gibson,
Pamela (eds) Fashion Cultures: Theories, Explanations and Analysis, London,
Routledge.
Klein, Naomi (2000) No Logo, London, Flamingo.
Koenig, R. (1973) The Restless Image, London, Allen and Unwin.
Kunzle, David (2004) Fashion and Fetishism: Corsets, Tight-Lacing and other Forms
of Body Sculpture, Stroud, Sutton Publishing.
Laver, James (1969a) Modesty in Dress: An Inquiry into the Fundamentals of Fashion,
Boston, Houghton Mifflin.
—— (1969b) Costume and Fashion: A Concise History, London, Thames and
Hudson.
Leiss, W., Kline, S., Jhally, S. and Botterill, J. (2005) Social Communication in
Advertising, Third Edition, Abingdon, Routledge.
Lennard, Erica (1981) ‘Erica Lennard’, in di Grappa, Carol (ed.) Fashion: Theory,
New York, Lustrum Press.
Light, Alan (ed.) (1999) The Vibe History of Hip-Hop, London, Plexus Publishing.
Lipovetsky, Gilles (1994) The Empire of Fashion: Dressing Modern Democracy,
Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Lunn, Eugene (1985) Marxism and Modernism, Berkeley, University of California
Press.
Lurie, A. (1981/1992) The Language of Clothes, London, Bloomsbury.
McCracken, G. (1988) Culture and Consumption, Bloomington and Indianapolis,
Indiana University Press.
McCulloch, Ken, Stewart, Alexis and Lovegreen, Nick (2006) ‘“We Just Hang Out
Together”: Youth Cultures and Social Class’, Journal of Youth Studies, 9, 5: 539–56.
McRobbie, Angela (1989) Zoot Suits and Second Hand Dresses, Basingstoke,
Macmillan.
—— (1998) British Fashion Design: Rag Trade or Image Industry?, London, Routledge.
Martin, Richard (1999) ‘A Note: Art and Fashion, Viktor and Rolf’, Fashion Theory,
3, 1: 109–20.
Marx, Karl (1968) Selected Works in One Volume, Moscow, Progress Press and
London, Lawrence and Wishart.
—— (1973) Grundrisse, Harmondsworth, Penguin.
—— (1976) Capital, Volume One, London, Penguin/New Left Review.
Marx, K. and Engels, F. (1985) The Communist Manifesto, London, Penguin.
Maynard, Margaret (2004) Dress and Globalisation, Manchester, Manchester
University Press.
Moore, Mandy and Prain, Leanne (2009) Yarn Bombing: The Art of Crochet and Knit
Graffiti, Vancouver, BC, Arsenal Pulp Press.
bibliography 221
Palmer, Alexandra and Clark, Hazel (2004) Old Clothes, New Looks; Second Hand
Fashion, Oxford, Berg.
Partington, A. (1992) ‘Popular Fashion and Working Class Affluence’, in Ash, J. and
Wilson, E. (eds) Chic Thrills, London, Pandora.
Polhemus, Ted (1994) Streetstyle: From Sidewalk to Catwalk, London, Thames and
Hudson.
—— (2010) Streetstyle, Second Edition, London, PYMCA.
—— (2011) Fashion & Anti-Fashion: Exploring Adornment and Dress from an
Anthropological Perspective, lulu.com.
Polhemus, Ted and Procter, Lynn (1978) Fashion & Anti-Fashion: An Anthropology
of Clothing and Adornment, London, Thames and Hudson.
Poll, S (1965) ‘The Hasidic Community’ in Roach, Mary Ellen and Eicher, Joanne
B. (eds) Dress, Adornment and the Social Order, London and New York, John
Wiley and Sons.
Rawsthorn, Alice (2003) ‘Is Fashion A True Art Form?’, Observer, 13 July.
Rhodes, Zandra (2003) ‘Is Fashion A True Art Form?’, Observer, 13 July.
Roach, Mary Ellen and Eicher, Joanne B. (eds) (1965) Dress, Adornment and the
Social Order, London and New York, John Wiley and Sons.
Roach-Higgins, Mary Ellen, Eicher, Joanne B. and Johnson, Kim K. P. (eds) (1995)
Dress and Identity, New York, Fairchild.
Roth, Leland, M. (1983) America Builds: Source Documents in American Architecture
and Planning, New York, Harper & Row.
Rouse, Elizabeth (1989) Understanding Fashion, Oxford, Blackwell.
Said, Edward (1993) Culture and Imperialism, London, Chatto and Windus.
Sapir, Edward (1931) ‘Fashion’, Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, 6: 139–44, New
York, Macmillan.
Saussure, Ferdinand de (1974) Course in General Linguistics, Glasgow, Collins.
Scarff, Liz (2005) ‘Fashion in the Firing Line’, Glamour, February, 64–8.
Sennett, Richard (1986) The Fall of Public Man, London, Faber and Faber.
Shannon, Claude and Weaver, Warren (1949) The Mathematical Theory of
Communication, Champaign, University of Illinois Press.
Shinkle, Eugénie (ed.) (2008) Fashion as Photograph, London, I. B. Tauris.
Shirazi, Faegheh (2000) ‘Islamic Religion and Women’s Dress Code: The Islamic
Republic of Iran’, in Arthur, Linda, B. (ed.) Undressing Religion: Commitment and
Conversion from a Cross-Cultural Perspective, Oxford, Berg.
Simmel, Georg (1971) ‘Fashion’, in On Individuality and Social Form, Chicago,
University of Chicago Press.
Smith, Marquand and Morra, Joanne (eds) (2006) The Prosthetic Impulse: From a
Posthuman Present to a Biocultural Future, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Sontag, Susan (1971) On Photography, London, Penguin.
—— (1978) ‘The Avedon Eye’, Vogue (UK Edition), December, pp. 104–7.
Soper, Kate (2001) ‘Dress Needs: Reflections of the Clothed Body, Selfhood and
Consumption’, in Entwistle, J. and Wilson, E. (eds) Body Dressing, Oxford, Berg.
Steele, Valerie (1998) ‘A Museum of Fashion is More Than A Clothes Bag’, Fashion
Theory, 2, 4: 327–36.
—— (2001) ‘Fashion, Fetish, Fantasy’, in Tseëlon, E. (ed.) Masquerade and
Identities: Essays on Gender, Sex and Marginality, London, Routledge.
222 bibliography
—— (2003) The Corset: A Cultural History, New Haven, Yale University Press.
Styles, John (1998) ‘Dress in History: Reflections on a Contested Terrain’, Fashion
Theory, 2, 4: 383–90.
Sullivan, Louis (1896) ‘The Tall Office Building Artistically Considered’, in Lippincott’s
Magazine, No 57, pp. 403–9, March, New York.
Sung Bok Kim (1998) ‘Is Fashion Art?’, Fashion Theory, 2, 1, March: 51–72.
Taylor, Lou (2002) The Study of Dress History, Manchester, Manchester University
Press.
Tickner, Lisa (1977) Women and Trousers, Design Council Publications.
Tomlinson, John (2003) ‘Globalization and Cultural Identity’, in Held, David and
McGrew, Anthony (eds) The Global Transformations Reader, London, Polity/Blackwell.
Tseëlon, Efrat (ed.) (2001) Masquerade and Identities: Essays on Gender, Sex and
Marginality, London, Routledge.
Tyler, Imogen (2008) ‘Chav Mum, Chav Scum: Class Disgust in Contemporary
Britain’, Feminist Media Studies, 8, 1: 17–34.
Veblen, Thorstein (1992) The Theory of the Leisure Class, New Brunswick, Transaction
Publishers.
Wells, H. G. (1895) Select Conversations With an Uncle Now Extinct, New York/
London, Merriam/Kessinger Publishing.
Wilbekin, Emil (1999) ‘Great Aspirations: Hip-Hop and Fashion Dress for Excess
and Success’, in Light, A. (ed.) The Vibe History of Hip-Hop, London, Plexus
Publishing.
Williams, Malcolm (2000) Science and Social Science: An Introduction, London, Routledge.
Williams, Raymond (1980) ‘The Magic System’, in Problems in Materialism and
Culture, London, Verso.
Wills, G. and Christopher, M. (1973) ‘What Do We Know About Fashion Dynamics?’,
in Wills, G. and Midgley, D. (eds) Fashion Marketing, London, George Allen and
Unwin.
Wilson, Elizabeth (1985) Adorned in Dreams, London, Virago.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953) Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, Blackwell.
Wolfendale, Jessica and Kennett, Jeanette (eds) (2011) Fashion: Philosophy for
Everyone, Chichester, Wiley-Blackwell.
Woolf, V. (1928) Orlando: A Biography, New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Internet sources
Alderson, Rob (2011) Yolanda Dominguez.
www.itsnicethat.com/articles/yolanda-dominguez (last accessed November 2013).
Al-Mahmood, Syed Zain (2013) ‘Bangladesh Factory Collapse: Police Detain Owners,
Aa Death Toll Exceeds 350’.
www.guardian.co.uk/world/2013/apr/27/bangladesh-collapsed-factory-owners-
detained?INTCMP=SRCH (last accessed April 2013).
bibliography 223
BBC (2011).
www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-14008167 (last accessed November 2013).
bbc.co.uk (2012).
news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/other_sports/basketball/4392182.stm (last accessed November
2013).
bbc.co.uk (2013).
www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-asia-22462405 (last accessed November 2013).
Cartner-Morley (2013).
www.guardian.co.uk/fashion/2013/apr/12/how-to-dress-sheer-panels (last accessed
April 2013).
Dominguez, Y. (2011).
www.yolande.dominguez.com/en/poses/index.html (last accessed November 2013).
Dove.us (2012).
www.dove.us/Social-Mission/campaign-for-real-beauty.aspx (last accessed November
2013).
224 bibliography
Green, Penelope (1998).
articles.nytimes.com/1998/11/22/style/view-big-pockets-no-pants.html?page
wanted=3 (last accessed February 2013).
Haaretz newspaper.
www.haaretz.com/culture/arts-leisure/crossing-the-seam-line-1.124191 (last accessed
November 2013).
Han, Christina (2013) ‘Vera Wang: Don’t Disguise Yourselves, Brides’, in The Cut
online magazine.
nymag.com/thecut/2013/05/vera-wang-dont-disguise-yourself-brides.html?
mid=twitter_thecutblog (last accessed May 2013).
www.islamreligion.com (2012).
www.islamreligion.com/articles/525/
Hartmann, M. (2012) ‘Is Ann Romney Sending Secret Messages with her
Clothing?’
nymag.com/daily/intel/2012/06/ann-romneys-secret-clothing-agenda.html (last accessed
November 2013).
ivillage.com (2010).
www.ivillage.com/celeb-trend-alert-are-legs-new-boobs/1-a-213723 (last accessed
November 2013).
Kaiser, Amanda (2012) ‘Mainland Marc’, Women’s Wear Daily, 20 July, 204, 14: 6.
www.wwd.com/fashion-news/fashion-features/mainland-marc-6099641 (last accessed
November 2013).
bibliography 225
Knight, Renee (2006) ‘Fashion Industry Accused on Anorexia’.
www.independent.co.uk/life-style/health-and-families/health-news/fashion-industry-
accused-on-anorexia-420159.html (last accessed November 2013).
Li Kejing and Zhao Qi (2011) ‘Green Fashion Under the Concept of DIY’, Proceedings
of the 7th International Conference on Innovation and Management, from Google
Docs (last accessed October 2012).
NBA (2012).
www.nba.com/news/player_dress_code_051017 (last accessed June 2013).
Prasad, Raekha (2011) ‘Rioter Profile: “If I Had a Job, I Wouldn’t Have Stolen”’.
www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2011/dec/05/riots-rioter-profile-job-stolen (last accessed
November 2013).
Smith, S. E. (2012) ‘Yes, People With Physical Disabilities Can Like Fashion Too’.
www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2012/sep/03/physical-disabilities-fashion-
models (last accessed September 2012).
226 bibliography
Sozzana, Franca (2012) Harvard Lecture.
www.vogue.it/en/magazine/editor-s-blog/2012/04/april-3rd (last accessed November
2013).
Sullivan (1896).
www.gwu.edu/~art/Temporary_SL/177/pdfs/Sullivan_Tall.pdf (last accessed November
2013).
usedmagazine.co.uk (2012).
usedmagazine.co.uk/?p=1542 (last accessed February 2013).
Vaughan, Jenifer (2004) ‘Walking a Fine Line’, Palestine Report, 10, 35.
www.palestinereport.ps/article.php?article=289 (last accessed February 2013).
whyiwearhijab.org (2013).
whyiwearhijab.org (last accessed November 2013).
bibliography 227
Index
Page numbers in italics indicate figures.
228 index
Breward, Christopher 148 colonialism 17–18, 161–2, 164–5, 169–72
bricolage 149 Comme il Faut (company) 98–100, 100
British Fashion Design (McRobbie) 135–6, communication: and cultural values
138 51–3, 82–90; and globalization
Brooks Brothers 192, 192 168–9, 172–4, 177; and representation
Burchill, Julie 102 6, 26–7, 53–6, 217; semiotic models
Bush, George 85, 86 78–82; sender/receiver models
73–8
Cambodia 174–5, 176 complementary studies 8–9
Camera Lucida (Barthes) 212 complex societies 17–18, 34–6, 121–2
Campbell, Colin 78, 81 connotation: and image 184, 186–9; and
Capital, Volume One (Marx) 200–1, 208 meaning 79–80, 82–6, 95, 179–80;
capitalism: and class 18, 121–2; and typeface 192–4
commodity fetishism 200–1, 208; and Consequences of Modernity, The (Giddens)
consumption 130–3; and globalization 166
163, 165, 175–6, 183; and production constraint 118–19
135–6 consumption: conspicuous 32, 50;
Carlyle, Thomas 42–4 cultural hostility 98, 139–41; and
Caro, Isabelle 109, 110 feminism 61–2; and globalization 167;
Cartner-Morley, Jess 2–3, 2 and identity 101–2; and morality 131–3;
case studies: chav style 100–3; Comme il post-purchase 142–3; and production
Faut 98–100, 100; hijab 103–5; hip-hop 128–30, 133–5, 138, 143–4
fashion 87–9; qipau 172–4; safari context 22, 59–65, 190
jackets 169–72, 170; Tony Blair’s tie Costume and Fashion (Laver) 59, 60
85–7 Criminal Justice and Public Order Act
‘Catwalk Politics’ (Khan) 63–4, 157 (1994) 156
Cavallaro, Dani 114 crinolines 60
Chalayan, Hussein 145–6, 157–9, 160, 181, Critical Studies in Fashion and Beauty 1
183, 195 ‘Cultural Meaning and Hip-Hop Fashion
Chanel 61, 72, 193–4 in the African-American Youth
change see difference; society Subculture of New Orleans’ (Baxter
Charles, Prince of Wales 37–8 and Marina) 88
‘Chav Mum, Chav Scum: Class Disgust in cultural values: and the body 39, 113–15,
Contemporary Britain’ (Tyler) 102 119–21, 123–6, 216; and
chavs 100–3 communication 21–2, 42, 51–6, 169;
Chavs: The Demonization of the Working and connotation 82–7; globalization
Class (Jones) 102 and colonialism 162–8, 171–4; and the
China 106, 119, 138, 165, 172–4 meaning of fashion 64–5, 68–9,
class: and classic fashion 32, 71–2; and 79–82, 93, 95, 176–7; modesty and
consumption 134, 139–40; and gender protection 43, 44–5, 51–2, 104, 116;
61–2; hostility 100–3; mobility 37, and politics 98–107; resistance 140–1;
121–2, 165; theory 10, 18, 34 subcultures 32, 87–9, 97–8
classic fashion 32, 70–2, 184 Culture and Consumption (McCracken)
clothing: boundary with the body 114–15; 77
and communication 73–82; and
constraint 118–19; and fashion 29, 33, Dant, Tim 142, 168
41–2; functions 38, 42–5, 50–5, 215–16; ‘David Bailey’ (Bailey) 188–9
sustainability 137–9, 140; written de Perthuis, Karen 114–15
184–5 see also case studies; fetish Deacon, Giles 178
Coldstream Reports 8, 59 deception 180–3, 189, 195
Cole, Cheryl 197, 199, 203 Derrida, Jacques 55, 115, 217
index 229
design: art and design 8–11; and Entwistle, Joanne 16–17, 18, 50, 54,
capitalism 135–6; and fashion 31–3, 111–12, 113
39–40; form and function 45–9 ephemerality 32, 63–4, 122
Design Museum 47, 61 ‘Erica Lennard’ (Lennard) 187–9
designers: anonymity 32–3; as artists erogenous zones 204, 205–8
27–8; modern and postmodern 145–6, eroticism 197–9, 198, 211–14, 213 see also
149, 153; target market 76 see also fetish
brands; named designers Evans, Caroline 148, 181–2, 195
desire 3, 197–8, 201–2, 205–8, 211–14 see exhibitionism 211–12
also seduction
Dianna, Limor 98 Facebook 25, 26
difference: and commodity fetishism Fall of Public Man, The (Sennett) 167
208–9; and fashion 36–7, 59; and fashion: and art 27–31; and capitalism
globalization 167–9; and identity 165; and communication 51–6, 73–82;
96–7, 105–6, 107, 140–1; and meaning cultural function 32, 43–5; definition
66–8, 93, 215–16; and opposition 13–17, 25–7, 39–40; derivation of word
97–105 7, 199; and design 31–3; icons 37–8;
Dior, Christian 36, 37 image of 190–1; inescapability 217;
disability 119–21 and social complexity 17–18, 34–7 see
‘Disjuncture and Difference in the Global also clothing; postmodernism; style;
Cultural Economy’ (Appadurai) 164 theories of fashion
display 52–3, 116–17 see also modesty Fashion & Anti-Fashion: An Anthropology
DIY fashion 136–7, 138 of Clothing and Adornment (Polhemus
Dominguez, Yolanda 124–6, 125, 137 and Procter) 16, 34
Douglas, Mary 98, 140–1 Fashion & Anti-Fashion: Exploring Adornment
Dove (company) 124 and Dress from an Anthropological
dreamcatcher bra 197, 198, 201 Perspective (Polhemus) 36–7
Dress and Globalisation (Maynard) 166–8 Fashion and Modernity (Breward and
‘Dress in History: Reflections on a Evans) 148
Contested Terrain’ (Styles) 61–2 Fashion as Photograph (Shinkle) 183
‘Dress Needs: Reflections on the Clothed ‘Fashion’ (Sapir) 60
Body, Selfhood and Consumption’ ‘Fashion’ (Simmel) 34–5
(Soper) 112, 116 Fashion System, The (Barthes) 179, 184–7
Duchess of Cambridge 37–8 Fashion Theory 1, 27, 28
Dyson, James 47 ‘Fashion: Unpacking a Cultural
Production’ (Braham) 134
eating disorders 109, 110, 123–7, 178–9 Fashioned Body, The (Entwistle) 16, 50, 54,
Eco, Umberto 118–19 111, 112, 113
economics: commodity fetishism 200–1, Female Fetishism: A New Look (Gamman
208–9; economic reductionism 130–3, and Makinen) 210
144; exchange and distribution 134; femininity 9–10, 22, 62, 104, 119, 193
and globalization 162–4; significance feminism 61–2, 98–9
of fashion 4, 32 see also consumption; Ferleger Brades, Susan 14, 28
production fetish: definition 199–200; and
Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, economics 200–1, 208; and fashion 7,
The (Marx) 97 203–8, 213–14; and gender 209–10;
Elizabeth II (queen) 36–7 psychoanalysis 201–3
Ellis, Henry Havelock 204, 205–6 ‘Fetishism’ (Freud) 202
embodiment 54–5, 113–14, 126 Feuerbach, Ludwig 181
empiricism 20–1 Fifty Dresses that Changed the World
‘End of Safari’ (Silver) 171 (Design Museum) 61
230 index
‘Fingerprint of the Second Skin, The’ Harper’s Bazaar 193
(Hauser) 142–3 Hartmann, Margaret 73–4, 80–1
Fiske, John 79 hats 204–5
fixed and modish costume 35–6, 165–6 Hauser, Kitty 142–3
flapper dress 61 Hazlitt, William 14
Fleming, E. McClung 20–1 Hemingway, Wayne 120
Flügel, John 17–18, 35–6, 44, 165–6, 204, hijab 44, 51–2, 103–5, 116
205–7 Hill, Andrew 152
foot-binding 119 hip-hop fashion 87–9, 95, 98
For a Critique of the Political Economy of history: as a backdrop to fashion 58–9; as
the Sign (Baudrillard) 66–8, 208–9 a context for fashion 59–61;
form: and content 15–16; and function temporality and fashion 57–8, 70–2;
45–9 transformed by fashion 60–2;
Foucault, Michel 113, 148 unaffected by fashion 63–5; and
Frere-Jones, Tobias 193 understanding fashion 68–70;
Freud, Sigmund 201–5, 209–10, 211, 213 unrelated to fashion 65–8
frivolity of fashion 4, 15, 47–9 Hobsbawm, Eric 58
function: of art 47; of clothing 38, 42–5, Hollander, Anne 17, 18
50–5, 215–16; differentiates art and Huffington Post 124, 191
design 28–32, 33, 40; of fashion 36, Hunter, Joe 155
41–2, 45–7, 131, 133, 135; and form
45–9 see also prostheses identity: communicated by fashion 26–7,
32, 80; and consumption 6–7, 139–41;
Gadamer, Hans-Georg 69 and difference 96–105; gender 62, 65;
Gamman, Lorrain 210 and image 178–80, 189–90, 192–4;
gender: cultural constructions 54, 60, national 158–9, 170–4; as performance
61–2, 126; and fetishism 209–10; and 95–6, 97; representation 53–5, 91–4,
globalization 138; theories 3, 9–11 see 92, 107, 216–17 see also politics of
also femininity; feminism fashion
Giddens, Anthony 148, 166 illustration 191–4 see also photography
Gillitzer, Jeremy 109 image: of fashion 190–1; and identity 7,
globalization: and colonialism 7, 161–2, 92, 178–80, 189–90, 192–4, 216–17;
164–5, 169–72; and cultural identity illustration and photography 83–5,
172–4; definition 162–4; and fashion 179, 183–7, 191–4; and prosthesis
17–18, 35–6, 128–30, 165–9; and 194–6; reality and deception 123–6,
history 69–70; and production 136–8, 180–3, 195
144, 174–7 India 161–2
‘Globalization and Cultural Identity’ Indonesia 128, 174–5
(Tomlinson) 172–3 International Journal of Fashion Design,
Goldfainer, Sybil 98, 100 Technology and Education 1
goths 80, 81–2, 96, 97 Introduction to Communication Studies, An
graphic design 191–4, 192 (Fiske) 79
‘Green Fashion Under the Concept of Iran 103
DIY’ (Li Kejing and Zhao Qi) 138 ‘Is Ann Romney Sending Secret
Green, Penelope 156 Messages With Her Clothing?’
Grundrisse (Marx) 133–5 (Hartmann) 73–4, 80–1
Guardian 2–3, 2, 37 ‘Is Fashion A True Art Form?’
(Rawsthorn) 28–9, 41–2, 45–7
Hamilton, Andy 47–8, 49, 70 ‘Is Fashion A True Art Form?’ (Rhodes)
Hamnett, Katherine 63–4 29
Hansungule, Michelo 169–70, 171, 172 Isherwood, Baron 141
index 231
‘Islamic Religion and Women’s Dress make-do-and-mend.org 137
Code: The Islamic Republic of Iran’ Makinen, Merja 210
(Shirazi) 103 Mapplethorpe, Robert 212, 213
islamreligion.com 104 Margiela, Martin 145, 149, 181–2, 182, 195
Israel 98–100 Marina, Peter 88
Iverson, Allen 88, 89 Martin, Richard 28
ivillage.com 206 Marx, Karl 97, 133–5, 165, 200–1, 208
Marxism and Modernism (Lunn) 147–8
J. Walter Thompson (company) 136–7 Masheke, Malimba 170, 172
Jacobs, Marc 106 Material Culture in the Social World (Dant)
Jameson, Frederic 154, 156–7 142
Jarvis, Anthea 57 Maynard, Margaret 166–8
jeans 118–19, 142–3, 168 meaning: connotational 79–80, 82–6,
Jones, Ann Rosalind 68–9 179–80, 184, 186–9, 192–4; cultural
Jones, Owen 102–3 55–6, 81–2, 87–9, 93, 95, 189–90; and
difference 66–8, 97–105, 215–16; and
Kaunda, Kenneth 170–2 ephemerality 64; and metaphor 158–9,
Kawakubo, Rei 145, 149 160; negotiation of 80, 89–90; and
Khan, Nathalie 63–4, 157 politics 105–7, 176–7; and semiotics
Khomeini, Ayatollah Ruhollah 103 78–9 see also representation
Klein, Naomi 140, 166 Meisel, Steven 110, 124
König, René 211 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 113
Kouyaté, Lamine Badian 149 messages 73–8, 80–2
metaphor 23, 158–9, 160, 180–1
Lady Gaga 197, 199, 203, 206 Miller, J. Abbott 193–4
Lagerfeld, Karl 27, 109 ‘Mind in Matter: An Introduction to
Langton, Rae 118 Material Culture Theory and Method’
language 16–17, 21–2, 66, 77–8, 80–1 (Prown) 20
Language of Clothes, The (Lurie) 77 Miyake, Issey 149
Lanvin 124 models 63, 109–10, 124–6, 178
Lask, Bryan 124 modernism 146–51, 154–7, 159–60
Laver, James 14, 50, 59, 60, 203–6, 207–8 ‘Modernism and Fashion’ (Back) 146,
Leiss, William 150–1 148
Lennard, Erica 184, 187–9 modesty 43, 44, 51–2, 104, 116
Leonard, David J. 88 Modesty in Dress (Laver) 203–6, 207–8
Li Kejing 138 montage 148, 149
lingerie 197–8, 198, 201 morality 131–3, 153, 162
Lipovetsky, Gilles 19–20, 180 Morris, William 33
local cultures 35–6, 162–9, 177 see also Murray, Robin 135
globalization musculature 39, 112, 216
‘Local/Global’ (Back) 163–4 ‘Museum of Fashion is More Than A
Location of Culture, The (Bhabha) 164 Clothes Bag, A’ (Steele) 20–1
Louis Vuitton (LV) 106
Lunn, Eugene 147–9 nakedness 18, 111, 112–13
Lurie, Alison 77 National Basketball Association (NBA)
88–9, 95
McCracken, Grant 77 nature: and culture 33, 113; and history
McQueen, Alexander 120 71–2
McRobbie, Angela 135–6, 138, 139 New Look 37, 62
Magritte, René 116 New York Times 156
Mail Online 175–6, 197–9, 200, 202–3 Nichole de Carle London 197, 198, 201
232 index
Nolita 109, 110 Postmodernism or The Cultural Logic of
nostalgia 154–5, 160 Late Capitalism (Jameson) 154, 156–7
Procter, Lynn 16, 34
Obama, Barack 106 production: and consumption 133–5,
Olympic Games: Athens (2004) 88; 143–4; and exploitation 128–30, 138,
London (2012) 7, 128, 138, 174–7 174–7, 191; ideological function 135–6;
On Photography (Sontag) 181, 182 localized and DIY-based 136–7, 138;
Orlando (Woolf) 107 sustainable 137–9, 140
ornament 43 see also adornment prostheses: Carlyle on 43; description 27,
33, 38–9; and disability 120; and
Palestine 96, 98–100 identity 79, 194–6; and the natural
‘Panoramic’ (Chalayan) 181, 195 body 117–18
Panzani advertisement 83–5, 84 protection 43–5, 55, 104, 116
parody and pastiche 156–7 Prown, Jules 20
Partington, Angela 62 Psychology of Clothes, The (Flügel) 35–6,
‘Patrice’ (Mapplethorpe) 212, 213 165–6
‘People Dress so Badly Nowadays:
Fashion and Late Modernity’ (Hill) 152 qipau 172–4
personality 91–4 see also identity
PETA (People for the Ethical Treatment of Ramos, Eliana and Luisel 109, 178
Animals) 63 Rampal, Arjun 161, 162
Philosophy in the Boudoir (Magritte) 116 Rana Plaza factory 129, 175, 191
photography 179, 181–9, 212 Rankin 114–15
‘Piece of Cloth, A’ (Miyake) 149 Rattansi, Ali 152
piercings 121–3 Rawsthorn, Alice 28–9, 41–2, 45–7
Plato 180–1, 182–3, 211 ‘real’ women 110, 123–6, 125
Pleasure of the Text, The (Barthes) 212 reductionism 50–1, 53, 55, 130–3, 144
Polhemus, Ted 16, 34, 36–7, 121–2, 153–5, Reed-Krakoff blouse 73–4, 80–1, 95
156 refugees 157–9
politics of fashion: Chalayan’s religion 44–5, 51–2, 86–7, 103–5
‘Afterwords’ 157–9; chav style 100–3; Renaissance Clothing and the Materials of
Comme il Faut case study 98–100, Memory (Jones and Stallybrass) 68–9
100; consumption 139–41, 143–4; representation: and the body 106, 113–14,
disability 120–1; effectiveness 63–4, 117, 125–6, 216; and communication 6,
72; hijab 103–5; identity and difference 53–6; crisis of 150, 152–9; of identity
32, 93–4, 96–8; ubiquity 105–7; Vexed 38, 91–4, 92, 107, 216–17; image and
Generation Parka 156–7 see also reality 181–3, 195; inescapability 217;
globalization; society modernism and postmodernism 7,
Poll, Solomon 44–5 146–7
‘Popular Fashion and Working Class reproducibility 30–1
Affluence’ (Partington) 62 Republic (Plato) 180–1, 182–3
pornography 212–13 resistance 88, 140–1, 169, 172
Poses (Dominguez) 124–6, 125 Restless Image, The (König) 211
Positions (Derrida) 217 Reston, Ana Carolina 178
positivism 21 retro fashion 70–1
postmodernism: crisis of representation ‘Rhetoric of the Image’ (Barthes) 55, 79,
152–3, 157–9; deconstructionist 145, 82–5, 185
155; eclecticism 153–5; and modernism Rhodes, Zandra 28, 29
146–51, 155–7, 159–60 Rihanna 197, 199, 203
Postmodernism and Society (Boyne and riots, London (summer 2011) 102–3,
Rattansi) 152 128–9
index 233
Roach-Higgins, Mary Ellen 44–5 Spry, Constance 47, 48
Robertson, Roland 162 Stallybrass, Peter 68–9
Romney, Ann 73–4, 80–1, 95 Starck, Philippe 32
Rosen, Andrea 64 Steele, Valerie 20–1, 27, 145, 146, 180
Rudovsky, Bernard 3, 4, 204, 207 stereotypes 61, 62
Streetstyle: From Sidewalk to Catwalk
safari jackets 7, 165, 169–72, 170 (Polhemus) 121, 156
Said, Edward 164 Streetstyle (Polhemus) 153–5
Saint Laurent, Yves 171 see also Yves Saint structuralism 16, 19, 78–9 see also
Laurent (company) semiotics
Sapir, Edward 60 Structures of Everyday Life, The: Civilization
Sartor Resartus (Carlyle) 42–4 and Capitalism 15th–18th Century
Saussure, Ferdinand de 16, 66 (Braudel) 19
science fiction 57, 58 Study of Dress History, The (Taylor) 57–8
sciences, natural and social 12–13, 19–21, style: definition 17; and design 47–9; and
22–4 fashion 57, 121–3, 165, 215–16; and
scopophilia 211–12 form 15–16; and postmodernism
seduction 52–3, 60, 206–8 see also desire 153–5
Selfridges 197, 201 Styles, John 61–2
semiotics 78–82, 147 see also signs subcultures 87–9, 95, 96–8, 100–3, 135–6
Sennett, Richard 167 suits 65, 167–8
Sex and Suits (Hollander) 17 Sullivan, Louis 46, 49
sexuality 201–5, 207–8, 209–10 sumptuary laws 139–40
Shannon, Claude Elwood 75 Sunday Telegraph 102
Shinkle, Eugénie 183 Sung Bok Kim 28
Shirazi, Faegheh 103 sustainability 137–9, 140
‘Shop of Images and Signs, A’ (Evans) symbolism 36, 67–8, 151, 204–5 see also
181–2, 195 fetish
Shorter Oxford English Dictionary 14–15
signs: differentiation 66–8; semiotic Takolia, Nadiyah 104
models 78–82; sign objects 208–9; tattoos 121–3
signifier and signified 83–4, 86, 147, Taylor, Lou 20, 57–8, 61
151, 152–3, 159 technology, photographic 187–9, 195
Silver, Micah 7, 171 Telegraph 37–8, 102, 175
Simmel, Georg 17–18, 34–5, 50, 71, 116 Thatcher, Margaret 63
skirt length 59, 66–7, 118, 209 theories of fashion: academic studies
slavery 87, 95, 164 8–9; and cultural values 21–2; multi-
‘Slaves to Fashion?’ (Ashwell and disciplinary 19–21, 22–4; nature and
Langton) 118 role of 1–5, 215, 217; Rudovsky 3, 4,
Smith, S.E. 119–20 207
Social Communication in Advertising (Leiss theory: and cultural values 21–2;
et al.) 150–1 definition 10–13; form and content
society: change and fashion 61–5, 150, 15–16; inescapability 24, 217;
156–7; functions of clothing 32, 43–5, ladenness 12, 20
201; simple and complex 17–18, 34–6; Theory of the Leisure Class, The (Veblen)
social mobility 37, 71–2, 121–2, 165 see 59, 118
also cultural values Thorpe, Adam 155, 156
‘Sogno di Donna’ (Meisel) 110 Thought Styles: Critical Essays on Good
Sontag, Susan 181, 182, 183–4 Taste (Douglas) 140–1
Soper, Kate 112, 116 Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality
Sozzani, Franca 124 (Freud) 201–3
234 index
‘Through Thick and Thin: Fashion and ivillage.com 206; Mail Online 175–6,
Type’ (Miller) 193–4 197–9, 200, 202–3; make-do-and-
Tibet 106 mend.org 137; stackexchange.com 70;
Tickner, Lisa 19, 58 Weibo 106; wetfeet.com 76;
ties 85–7, 205 whyiwearhijab.org 103–4
time: and anti-fashion 35–7; fashion and Welch, Raquel 117–18
history 57–8, 70–2; and social Wells, H. G. 13–14
complexity 34–5 Western and non-Western fashion 17–18,
Times 102 116, 121–2, 131–2, 167–8, 173 see also
TK Maxx 192, 192 cultural values
Tomlinson, John 172–3 Westwood, Vivienne 50–1
Tommy Hilfiger Apparel 161–2 wetfeet.com 76
tools see prostheses ‘When the Meaning is Not a Message’
Topshop 137 (Campbell) 78, 81
Toscani, Oliviero 109, 110 ‘Why “Chavs” Were the Riots’
‘tulip-line’ dress 36, 37 Scapegoats’ (Jones) 102–3
Tyler, Imogen 102 whyiwearhijab.org 103–4
typefaces 192–4, 192 Wilson, Elizabeth 19–20, 23, 111, 116, 130,
tzniut 44, 51 133, 165
women see femininity; feminism; gender;
Utility styles 62 ‘real’ women
Women and Trousers (Tickner) 19
values see cultural values Women’s Wear Daily 106
Veblen, Thorstein 32, 47, 50, 59, 118 Woolf, Virginia 107, 114
Vexed Generation Parka 150, 155–7, 160 ‘Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical
Viktor and Rolf 28, 29 Reproduction, The’ (Benjamin) 30
Vogue 91–2, 92, 110, 115, 193 World of Goods, The: Towards an
Vreeland, Diana 28 Anthropology of Consumption (Douglas
and Isherwood) 141
Wallace, Bethaney 109
Wang, Vera 191 Xuly Bet 149
War on Want 7, 128–9, 129, 138, 144,
174–7 ‘Yes, People With Physical Disabilities
Warwick, Alexandra 114 Can Like Fashion Too’ (Smith) 119–20
Weardrobe 137 Yves Saint Laurent (company) 7 see also
Weaver, Warren 75 Saint Laurent, Yves
websites: ‘below the line’ comment 1–4,
104; Facebook 25, 26; Guardian 2–3, Zambia 165, 169–72, 170
2, 119–20; islamreligion.com 104; Zhao Qi 138
index 235