Ehrlich DeterrentEffectCriminal 1972
Ehrlich DeterrentEffectCriminal 1972
Ehrlich DeterrentEffectCriminal 1972
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The University of Chicago Law School and The University of Chicago Press are collaborating
with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Legal Studies
ISAAC EHRLICH*
I. INTRODUCTION
THE specter of crime has been haunting the U.S. and other western coun
throughout the last decade. The President's Commission on Law Enforcement
and Administration of Justice estimated the economic costs of reported crim
in the U.S. in 1965 at $21 billion (about four per cent of the reported nation
income),' which exceeded the economic costs of unemployment in that year.
A survey sponsored by the Commission revealed that crime is seen by t
public as the second most important domestic issue after race.2 Crime, broad
defined as all violations of law, has probably been on the rise throughout th
century if only because legislation has expanded beyond providing protection
for personal safety and property rights to cover virtually every aspect of bus
ness life.3 Crime control is far from costless. In 1965 public expenditure
police, criminal courts, defense counsel and "corrections" at the federal, stat
and local levels amounted to $4.6 billions. But while considerable resourc
are spent on enforcement of existing laws, and while new laws are being con
templated, very little is known in fact about the deterrent effect of the vario
measures of combatting crime or about the extent to which crimes of variou
kinds can be deterred.5
The idea that law enforcement-the apprehension and punishment of la
breakers-serves partly as a means of deterring future crimes by those a
4 U.S. President's Comm'n on Law Enforcement & Admin. of Justice, supra note 1, at 55.
5 U.S. President's Comm'n on Law Enforcement & Admin. of Justice, supra note 2, at
96, 141.
259
6For an overview of the literature, see Donald R. Taft & Ralph W. England, Jr.,
Criminology (4th ed. 1964).
7 Following their experimental investigation of the effect of punishment on rats, Skinner
and Estes concluded that punishment is ineffective in eliminating undesired behavior, and
Skinner suggested that it be eliminated as a social instrument. B. Skinner, The Behavior
of Organisms (1938); Estes, An Experimental Study of Punishment, 57 Psychological
Monographs 263 (1944), cited in Barry F. Singer, Psychological Studies of Punishment,
58 Calif. L. Rev. 405, 413 (1970). This conclusion stood unchallenged for 20 years and
undoubtedly influenced the thinking of criminologists. However, recent studies in ex-
perimental psychology have firmly rejected Skinner and Estes' earlier conclusions. Barry
F. Singer, supra, at 413-414.
8 A well-known study concluded on the basis of a simple correlation of homicide rates
in contiguous retentionist and abolitionist states that "the presence of death penalty-in
law or in practice-does not influence homicide death rates." Thorsten Sellin, Homicides
in Retentionist and Abolitionist States, in Capital Punishment 138 (Thorsten Sellin ed.
1967). The findings presented in this paper constitute an indirect challenge to Sellin's
conclusion, although I do not discuss the specific effect of punishment by execution.
9 This approach is largely due to recent efforts by Belton M. Fleisher, The Economics
of Delinquency (1966); A. Smigel-Leibowitz, Does Crime Pay? An Economic Analys
1965 (unpublished M.A. Thesis, Columbia Univ.); Gary S. Becker, Crime and Punishment:
An Economic Approach, 76 J. Pol. Econ. 169 (1968); Isaac Ehrlich, The Supply of Il-
legitimate Activities, 1967 (unpublished paper, Columbia Univ.); Isaac Ehrlich, Particip
tion in Illegitimate Activities: An Economic Analysis, 1970 (unpublished Ph.D. disserta
tion, Columbia Univ.) [hereinafter cited as An Economic Analysis]; Isaac Ehrlich
Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation, Feb
1972 (unpublished paper at Center for Math. Studies in Bus. & Econ., Univ. of Chicag
[hereinafter cited as A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation].
to Note that under this approach crime always "pays" if the variety of monetary and
psychic costs and returns offenders derive from crime are taken into account, for if the
offender is free to choose, and always acts to maximize his utility given his opportunities,
the fact of his engaging in crime indicates that utility is thereby maximized. This positive
approach may constitute the main difference between our analysis and some traditional
theories in criminology.
11 Other things being equal, the subjective probability Pi of an "average individual" is.
assumed throughout our empirical analysis to be a positive monotonic function of the
actual extent of law-enforcement activity by police and courts, and linearly related to the
fraction of offenders actually apprehended and punished for crime.
12 In practice, the criminal's prospects include more contingencies than the two just
mentioned, depending upon the form and extent of the punishment imposed or the re-
ward obtained. The analysis can easily be generalized to cover any finite number of
states.
14 The variance of income accruing from an offense is V = P(1 - P)F2, and the differ-
ence between the effect on V of a one per cent increase in F relative to P is PF2[2(1 - P)
--(1 - 2P)], which is necessarily greater than zero.
15 The reason for this somewhat surprising result is that an increase in the potential
punishment facing those actually engaged in criminal activity does not isolate a pure
substitution effect in favor of alternative activities, but generates a wealth effect as well.
If an offender is a risk preferrer, the reduction in his prospective wealth in the event of
punishment can be shown to enhance his willingness to venture additional criminal activity,
which may partly or fully offset the opposite substitution effect.
16 Mathematical proofs of these statements are given in An Economic Analysis, app. II.
In = ai + bi In Pi + b2i In T
-- ci In X ? c_2 In W + el In NW + [i21
where
(Qi) - rate
N per ofpopulation
state the ith crime category;
in year t. the number of offenses known
20 The samples from 1960 include 47 state observations and those from 1950 include
46. The 1940 sample sizes vary between 36 and 43. Data are unavailable for auto theft
and rape in 1940 and 1950, and are incomplete in the case of murder and nonnegligent
manslaughter in 1940.
21 To obtain efficient estimates of the regression coefficients all the regressions under-
lying the results reported in Table 1 have been weighted by the square root of the popula-
tion sizes in each state, since a residual analysis of the corresponding unweighted
regressions showed a negative correlation between the absolute values of estimated residuals
and the population size.
22 The desired denominator of this ratio is the total number of offenders, rather than
the number of offenses known, in the same state and year-for which there is no informa-
tion available. However, the number of offenders and the number of offenses may be
linearly related across states.
23 A more efficient estimator of the offenders' expectation in year t of their prospective
length of imprisonment if apprehended and convicted of crime might be some weighted
average of the average time spent in prison by offenders released in year t as well as in
previous years (for which no information is available, in general). However, some scattered
evidence suggests that there has been very little variation over time in specific Ti's in
each state.
(-
N iand Pi. With a fixed level of resources devoted to
activity, the rate of crime and the probability of apprehension
ment for crime might be negatively related but the causalit
posite direction from the one predicted by our theoretical
crime rate might cause the probability of apprehension and
decline. (For example, in a riot, the probability of apprehen
vidual rioters, as well as for offenders committing other crim
considerably below their levels in normal times.) To cope wi
(as well as, indirectly, with the problem caused by errors of m
the reported crime rates) we used a two-stage least-squares
tion technique. Since in the second stage of the estimation proc
rates were regressed on combinations of variables that did
current estimates of crime rates or expenditures on law enforc
mates of bli and b2i derived via this method may be relatively
simultaneous-equation biases (i.e., those associated with the
problem referred to above) and the spurious negative corre
Q C
(
N )i
Q and Pi ( )i.27
The 2SLS estimates are
least-squares procedures.
ever, in the sense that
the rate of burglary ma
Variable Pi Ti Pi Ti Pi Ti
VI. CONCLUSION
The approach one takes in analyzing the deterrent effect of law enforcement
on crime is inseparable from the approach one takes in analyzing the determi-
nants of criminal behavior itself. The basic thesis underlying this article is that
offenders, as a group, respond to opportunities (costs and gains) available to
them in legitimate and criminal activities in much the same way that those
engaged in strictly legitimate activities do as a group. This does not necessarily
imply that offenders are similar to "other people" in all other respects or that
counted cost of imprisonment (Fi) and therefore our estimates of b2i necessarily under-
state the true elasticities of the various crimes with respect to the appropriately measured
severity of punishment (Fi), especially in the case of crimes punished by long imprison-
ment such as robbery and murder. Thus, given the validity of our 2SLS and SUR estimates
of bli and b2i, we may conclude unambiguously that burglars and thieves are risk avoiders.
Whether other offenders are risk preferrers cannot be determined unambiguously, how-
ever, without specific knowledge of offenders' discount rates: the higher the latter, the
larger would be the absolute values of our revised estimates of the elasticities of specific
crimes with respect to Fi.