Harris Raviv 1993
Harris Raviv 1993
Harris Raviv 1993
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Oxford University Press, The Society for Financial Studies are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Financial Studies
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion Make
a Horse Race
Milton Harris
University of Chicago
Artur Raviv
Northwestern University
"It were not best that we should all think alike; it is difference of opinion
that makes horse races" (Mark Twain in Pudd'nhead Wilson, 1894). Milton
Harris is the Chicago Board of Trade Professor of Finance and Business
Economics at the University of Chicago. Artur Raviv is the Alan E. Peterson
Professor of Finance, Northwestern University. The authors gratefully
acknowledge the financial support of the Bradley Foundation. Professor
Harris wishes to acknowledge partial financial support from Dimensional
Fund Advisors. The authors also thank Yakov Amihud, Stephen Blough, Peter
DeMarzo, Michael Fishman, Larry Harris, Ronen Israel, Charles Kahn, Robert
Korajczyk, Josef Lakonishok, Mark Mitchell, Katherine Schipper, Bill Schwert,
Chester Spatt (the executive editor), Lars Stole; and Paul Pleiderer, the
referee, for valuable comments, as well as seminar participants at the Federal
Reserve Board, The Economics of Financial Markets Conference at Johns
Hopkins University (April 1991), American Finance Association Meetings
(January 1992), Michigan, Berkeley, Stanford, MIT, Dartmouth, USC, and
Rochester. Address correspondence to Milton Harris, Graduate School of
Business, University of Chicago, 1101 East 58th Street, Chicago IL 60637.
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
474
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
available, each trader updates his beliefs about returns using his own
model (likelihood function) of the relationship between the news
and the asset's returns. We assume that there are two types of risk-
neutral, speculative traders. The two types agree on whether a given
piece of information is favorable or unfavorable, but they disagree
on the extent to which the information is important. Speculators in
the "responsive" group increase (decrease) their probability of high
returns more upon receipt of favorable (unfavorable) information
than those in the "unresponsive" group. Therefore, when the cumu-
lative impact of the past information is favorable, the responsive spec-
ulators value the asset more highly and will own all of it. On the
other hand, when the cumulative impact of the past information is
unfavorable, the unresponsive speculators value the asset more highly
and will own all of it. Thus, trading occurs when, and only when,
cumulative information switches from favorable to unfavorable, or
vice versa.
Our main results are as follows:
2 Another line of research focuses on volume caused by tax-driven trading strategies. This research
shows, for example, that volume will be higher after a decline in the price of the asset. See, for
example, Lakonishok and Smidt (1986).
475
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
and Shalen (1993)].3 There are two major differences between the
approach in this literature and our approach. First, in rational expec-
tations models, trade is not generated by public information signals.4
Second, in rational expectations models, disagreement is the result
of private information. Consequently, speculators try to infer the infor-
mation of others from their behavior and from market prices; that is,
agents are influenced by the beliefs of others.5 As a result, the ability
of traders to learn from prices and the behavior of other traders must
be obscured by noise.6 Our differences-of-opinion approach allows
us to ignore learning from market prices and to dispense with noise
traders.
Volume results derived from rational expectations models are dif-
ficult to compare with those from our model, because volume in these
models includes portfolio rebalancing, liquidity, and speculative
trades. Our results concern only speculative trades. Moreover, much
of the volume of trade in rational expectations models is driven by
exogenous shocks, for example, to liquidity traders' demands or to
endowments, or by exogenous assumptions about the volume of trade
amongliquidity traders. Nevertheless, some comparisons can be made.
Similar to our result, Pfleiderer (1984) shows that successive price
changes are negatively correlated, although he attributes this result
in his model to the assumed nature of liquidity trading (see p. 17).
Pfleiderer (1984), Blume et al. (1991), and Wang (1992) show a
positive contemporaneous covariance between volume and absolute
price changes. Shalen (1993) shows that dispersion of beliefs con-
tributes to this covariance. In Pfleiderer's model, however, this result
is due entirely to nonspeculative trading, because the correlation
between speculative trading volume and absolute price changes is
zero (see p. 18). Foster and Viswanathan (1993a) and Wang (1992)
also show that trading volume has positive serial correlation. Admati
3 Diamond and Verrecchia (1981) do not include liquidity traders. Instead, they postulate random
shocks to the endowments of privately informed traders. In this model, volume consists of portfolio
rebalancing and speculative trades. Also, Blume et al. (1991) do not include liquidity traders. In
their model, traders have private information about the risky asset and about the precision of this
information.
Kim and Verrecchia (1991a, 1991b) and Grundy and McNichols (1989) are exceptions. In these
models trade is generated by public information, because traders disagree on its interpretation due
to prior private information. Kim and Verrecchia (1991a, 1991b) show that trading volume is
proportional both to absolute price change and the extent to which the precision of prior, private
information differs across traders. Grundy and McNichols (1989) obtain an expression relating the
volume of trade to the strength of the correlation between the errors in the public and private
signals and the precisions of the signals.
Thus, noisy rational expectations models with private signals cannot be interpreted as models with
common signals and differences of opinion, contrary to the claim in Pfleiderer (1984) and Holthau-
sen and Verrecchia (1990).
6 Milgrom and Stokey (1982) show that speculative trades based purely on differences in private
information cannot occur among risk-averse traders in the absence of noise traders. See Varian
(1989) for a short review of this and similar "no-trade" results.
476
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
and Pfleiderer (1988) and Foster and Viswanathan (1990) show that
volume will tend to be high in some periods and low in adjacent
periods. If we interpret periods in our model as being the same as
in these two models, then this implication is at variance with our
result that volume is positively autocorrelated. On the other hand, if
our periods are shorter or longer than their periods, there is no con-
tradiction. Also, Foster and Viswanathan (1990) show that volume
can be expected to be lower on Mondays, just the opposite of our
result.7
The second branch of the literature in which trading is induced by
differences of opinion is exemplified by the work of Harrison and
Kreps (1978), Varian (1985, 1989), Blough (1988), Hindy (1989), De
Long et al. (1990), and Kandel and Pearson (1992). Harrison and
Kreps (1978) analyze a model very similar to ours to show that prices
can contain a speculative component in addition to reflecting fun-
damental value. Varian (1985, 1989) focuses on differences in prior
beliefs as opposed to differences in models. He shows "the relation-
ship between the equilibrium price and volume of trade and the
equilibriumprobabilitybeliefs about those assets" (1989, p. 5). Blough
(1988) examines the effect on the informativeness of asset prices
when traders have both private information and differences of opin-
ion. The model of Hindy (1989) includes traders who have different
models and who also receive both public and private information.
He shows, using examples, that this model is capable of producing
expected volumes and price changes that are "positively related,
negatively related for all time periods, or have a relation that changes
from positive to negative, or vice versa, over time" (p. 8). De Long
et al. (1990) include two types of traders, one who correctly antici-
pates future price movements and one whose estimate of future prices
is distorted by an additive, random noise term.8 They show that their
model can account for such apparent anomalies as closed-end fund
discounts and premia and the equity premium and excess volatility
puzzles. The approach in Kandel and Pearson (1992) is very similar
to ours, although the specific models are somewhat different. In both
models, traders receive only public information. The major differ-
ences are that traders in Kandel and Pearson (1992) have both dif-
ferent prior beliefs and different likelihood functions and are risk
averse. We consider only different models. Moreover, Kandel and
Pearson analyze only a two-period model and make different distri-
butional assumptions. Their main results are that volume and absolute
7 Their result follows from the assumptions that private information accrues over weekends, but
public information does not, and that liquidity traders can postpone their trades by at most one
day.
8 See also Shleifer and Summers (1990) for a less technical description.
477
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
price changes are positively related and that volume can be positive
even when price does not change. This last result is in contrast to
our model in which volume occurs only when price changes.9
To summarize, the theoretical literature has only recently begun
to produce results concerning volume. Several articles obtain a result
similar to ours on the relation between volume and absolute price
changes. Pfleiderer (1984) also obtains our result that consecutive
price changes are negatively correlated. Admati and Pfleiderer (1988)
and Foster and Viswanathan (1990) show that trading will tend to
bunch. Foster and Viswanathan (1993a) and Wang (1992) show that
volume is positively autocorrelated. Finally, Foster and Viswanathan
(1990) predict lower volume on Mondays. Our results that do not
appear in the previous literature are that absolute changes in the
mean forecast of the final payoff and volume are positively related,
and volume is larger than usual on average at the opening of the
market after any period in which it is closed. Moreover, our model
produces all these results from a single framework.
Empirical results on volume are fairly abundant. To a large extent,
these are consistent with our implications. A number of studies have
documented empirically the positive correlation between volume and
absolute price changes or price variance over time [see, e.g., Karpoff
(1987), Jain and Joh (1988), Schwert (1989), Gallant et al. (1992),
and Lang et al. (1992)]. Patell and Wolfson (1984) find, consistent
with our result and that of Pfleiderer (1984), that successive trans-
action price changes are negatively autocorrelated. Evidence that
volume tends to be higher in the beginning and end of trading days
is provided by Jain and Joh (1988). Amihud and Mendelson (1987,
1991) find evidence of higher volume at the opening of the market.
Foster and Viswanathan (1993b) also observe a U-shaped intradayvol-
ume pattern and find that trading volume is lower on Mondays.10
Lakonishok and Maberly (1990), however, point out that volume for
individuals is larger on Mondays, and volume for institutions is smaller.
Our prediction of higher volume following a period of market closure
is consistent with the evidence of high volume at market opening
and greater individual trading on Mondays (we discuss this point
further later). Also consistent with our implication, Ziebart (1990)
documents a positive relation between volume and the absolute
change in the mean forecast of analysts. Our prediction of positive
autocorrelation in volume is supported by evidence in Harris (1987).
9 An additional recent model involving differences of opinion is presented in Detemple and Murthy
(1992).
0 Both Foster and Viswanathan (1993b) and Brock and Kleidon (1992), using intraday data, find that
volume and trading costs are positively correlated. This is inconsistent with the prediction of Admati
and Pfleiderer (1988).
478
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
1. Model
Fkoas fo r s ?-0,
C(s) = Uo2(-S) 0
Hkob-s for s < 0, (1)
where ao and bo are parameters strictly between 0 and 1, and ko is a
constant required to make or (s) and or (s) density functions.12 Using
Bayes' rule and Equation (1), after observing a history of signals st -
(sl,... St), we find the true posterior probability that R = H is
Later, we assume that traders realize that the true prior probabilities are equal. This assumption
makes the analysis much more tractable. We conjecture that all our results go through if traders
share the same probabilities even if they are not one-half.
2 Additivity requires that the likelihood functions be symmetric, that is, that the probability of a
particular signal when the final payoff is high is the same as the probability of minus that signal
when the final payoff is low.
479
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
13One could assume that speculators are unsure of the true model and revise their beliefs about it
as well as about the final payoff. We neglect this added complication on grounds that the true
model is likely to change sufficiently rapidly that such updating is of negligible importance. Thus,
the period length and the number of periods, T, in our model should be interpreted as fairly small.
Note that absolute belief in a model is not irrational in the Bayesian sense, especially since, in our
formulation, there are no possible realizations of the signal that are inconsistent with either group's
model (i.e., occur with zero probability according to the model).
1 Thus, while we maintain the assumption of rational agents, we drop the assumption that rationality
is common knowledge.
480
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
conditional on the final payoff, but they do not know the true density
functions ao?(s). Instead, group j (j = 1, 2) believes that the condi-
tional density of a signal s given final payoff R is ai(s), where a3i is
the same as ao with parameters kj, a1, and bj replacing ko, ao, and bo.
As before, aj and bj are between 0 and 1, and we assume Oj0 baj/
< 1 forj E {1, 2}. The posterior probabilities, irJ1(m), derived from
the prior and group j's model of the signal-generating process are
given by the same formula as the true posteriors [i.e., Equation (2)],
with j replacing 0.
Obviously, given the foregoing assumptions, if the groups are to
have models resulting in different posterior beliefs, they must have
different values of 0j. As a convention, we assume that 01 < 02. Con-
sequently, given the previous interpretation of 0, group 1 believes
the signal is of higher quality than group 2 and therefore responds
to a given signal history to a greater extent.15 It follows that group 1
is more optimistic when the cumulative signal is positive and is more
pessimistic when m is negative. When m = 0, both groups revert to
their prior beliefs, namely that the payoff is high with probability 2.
Figure 1 depicts rir(m) for j = 1, 2. We refer to group 1 as the
"responsive" group and to group 2 as the "unresponsive" group.
Two important properties of 1r-(m) that follow from (2) are that
xi, is monotone increasing in m and is concave for m > 0 and convex
for m < 0 (see Figure 1). These properties reflect the facts that larger
cumulative signals indicate greater likelihood of high final payoff and
that the posterior is more sensitive to changes in cumulative signal
when beliefs are more diffuse (i.e., when m is near zero).
We turn now to the speculators' preferences and trading. Recall
that all traders are risk neutral. Risk neutrality is appropriate since
we are interested primarily in volume generated by speculation as
opposed to hedging or life-cycle considerations. Thus, in our model,
there is no trading except for speculative purposes. Risk neutrality
also implies, however, that demand functions are infinitely elastic.
Thus, any trader will seek to buy (sell) an infinite number of shares
at any price below (above) his reservation price. Consequently, to
make the equilibrium well defined, we must assume that there is a
fixed number of shares available. This implies that short sales are not
allowed and that, whenever trading occurs, all available shares will
be purchased by the more optimistic group. Furthermore, as long as
one group remains more optimistic, there will be no further trade.
Trade will occur only when the two groups "switch sides." This fact
is a direct consequence of our risk-neutrality assumption. In a model
15 Note that the two groups have access to exactly the same information; that is, neither group has
more precise information than the other. One group simply believes the signal is more informative
than the other group does.
481
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
0)
0 ~~~~~Posterior
~~~4% ~~~Behief s
.... .Group 2
Posterior
Behef s
Figure ~ ~ ~ ~ ~ ~ . Gru1
Cumulative Signal, m
Figure 1
The probability of a high final outcome is shown as a function of the cumulative signal, m, for hoth
groups of speculators. Group 1 is assumed to be more responsive to the signal than group 2. For
a positive cumulative signal, group 1 values the asset more highly; the reverse is true for m < 0.
"I Notice that we are assuming that the market price equals the price taker's reservation price even
in periods in which there are no gains to trade. This is innocuous, since, in such periods, any price
between the two reservation prices results in no trade.
19 If one assumes that the equilibrium price is competively set in each period, then the price in any
period in which there is trade will equal the reservation price of the buyer. This occurs because
the buyer has infinitely elastic demand, but the supply is bounded. Which group is the buyer
482
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
where 7rH is given by (2). Note that, since the beliefs depend on the
signal history only through the cumulative signal, so does the price.
Moreover, as is clear from (3), price changes are proportional to
changes in the posterior of the price-taking group.
changes from period to period. Consequently, each group's reservation price in any period will
involve that group's expectation of the other group's reservation price in the next period. Therefore,
the equilibrium price in any period will involve each group's expectation of the other group's
expectation of the first group's expectation, and so forth. This quickly becomes intractable. We are
grateful to Charles Kahn for clarifying our thinking on this point.
20 As mentioned, one's reservation price today is his expectation of tomorrow's equilibrium price.
For the price-taking group, tomorrow's equilibrium price is the price taker's expectation in that
period of the following period's equilibrium price. The result follows by successive iteration forward
to period Tand applying the "law of iterated expectations." See Lemma 2 for a formal proof.
Covariances and expectations in all theorems are calculated with the true distribution of the signal.
These correspond to the estimates of the covariances and expectations that would be obtained
from a time series generated by the model.
483
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
a,
0.
Figure 2
The probability of a high final outcome is shown as a function of the cumulative signal, m. If the
current cumulative signal is M, signals s < -M result in positive volume. Signals s 2 -M result
in zero volume. Three ranges of such signals are shown. For signals between -Mand M, the change
in probability of high outcome is smaller in absolute value than the change for s = -M. For s >
M, the change in probability is smaller in absolute value than that corresponding to -s.
22 Some of the empirical work [e.g., Schwert (1989)] establishes the positive covariance between
volume and price or return volatility, as opposed to absolute price change. We can show numerically,
but not analytically, that such a relationship holds for our model.
484
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
signals not resulting in volume. To see this, we first argue that for
any current cumulative signal and any current signal that results in
no volume there is a corresponding current signal that results in
positive volume and a larger absolute price change. Suppose that M
> 0. For volume to be positive, the signal must be below -M (see
Figure 2). Consider a signal s for which volume is zero (i.e., s >
-M). First suppose that s is between -M and M. From Figure 2, it is
clear that the price change for any such signal is smaller than the
price change for s = -M. Thus, the price change for s E [-M, M] is
smaller than the smallest price change associated with positive vol-
ume. Second, suppose that s > M. The price change associated with
this zero-volume signal is smaller than that associated with the cor-
responding positive-volume signal -s.
To summarize, we have shown that for any current value of m > 0
and any signal corresponding to zero volume, there is a signal that
induces positive volume and results in a larger absolute price change.
A similar argument holds for m < 0. The result does not quite follow
from this argument, however, for two reasons. First, the distribution
of signals may be such that, for zero-volume signals, large values of
the signal are much more likely than small values, whereas the oppo-
site is true for positive-volume signals. In fact, there is sufficient
symmetry in the distributions assumed here to prevent this. Second,
the intuition given above is for positive correlation given any current
price or cumulative signal. The formal proof shows that the result
can be extended to the unconditional covariance.23
In addition to the positive correlation between volume and absolute
price changes, a positive correlation has also been observed between
volume and absolute changes in mean earnings forecasts. More spe-
cifically, Ziebart (1990) documents a positive correlation between
volume and the absolute percentage change, as a result of earnings
announcements during the year, in the mean of analysts' earnings
forecasts for the coming year. We view these annual forecasts as pre-
dictions of (more or less) long-run performance of the firm. In terms
of our model, earnings announcements correspond to our signal,
st, and analysts' forecasts correspond to the speculators' forecasts of
final returns. A speculator's forecast is measured by his conditional
expectation of final payoff, R. From equation (3), group j's forecast
at date t of the final payoff given cumulative signal m is -x1(m) (H -
L) + L. The mean forecast at date t is therefore
23 We are grateful to the referee for suggesting a method of proving this extension.
485
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
H- L
= 7rH m + s) XH( m)
The intuition for these results is quite simple. Part (a) follows from
the fact that transactions occur only when the cumulative signal crosses
486
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
487
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
3. Risk-Averse Investors
One problem with the model analyzed in the previous two sections
is that, due to risk neutrality of investors, short-sale restrictions are
required and trading is always all-or-nothing. In this section, we exam-
ine a model in which investors are risk averse and short sales are
freely allowed. Our purpose is to see to what extent our previous
results are robust to this modification.
Introducing risk aversion adds considerable complexity to the prob-
lem. To restore a measure of tractability, we make three simplifying
assumptions. First, we assume that investors have identical exponen-
tial (constant absolute risk aversion) utility functions. Second, we
488
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
assume that investors are myopic in the sense that, in each period,
they chose portfolios as if there will be no further trading. Obviously,
this is a very strong assumption and is counter to the analysis of the
previous sections. These two assumptions allow us to derive demand
functions that are simple, independent of the investor's wealth at
each date, and depend on time only through the cumulative signal.
Third, we assume the asset is in zero net supply; that is, we consider
only prices and volume of pure bets.
With the above assumptions, an investor in group j with current
wealth W and cumulative signal m, who takes the current price of
the risky asset, p, as given, chooses quantities q of the risky asset and
b of the riskless asset to solve the following problem:
subject to pq + b= W
Qj(P) 1 [nlr-'ii(m)H-pl
= r(H-L) rir( m) pH- L
Equating total demand with zero net supply of the risky asset results
in an equilibrium price given by (3), except that the price-taking
group's 0 in (2) is replaced by 0= (0102) 1/2 Thus, group l's equilibrium
holding of the risky asset in any period in which the cumulative signal
is m is
24 In the risk-averse model, trade occurs even when the relative optimism of the two groups of traders
does not reverse; that is, trade will occur even as the optimistic group becomes more optimistic.
Thus, there is no simple relation between the sequence of transactions and price changes.
489
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
4. Conclusions
490
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
For example, both groups may agree that future interest rates can be
either high or low, and they agree on the probabilities but disagree
about the impact of high (or low) interest rates on the final payoff.
Formally, suppose that all speculators agree on the prior distribution
g(co) of the state of nature c and on the conditional distribution of
the signal given the state (the likelihood function) but disagree about
the mapping R = fj(w) relating the state to the final payoff. Thus,
speculators disagree about the prior distribution of the final payoff,
but j's prior beliefs are of the form gj(R) = g(f-l (R)) for all j. In
this case speculators will not trade except at the last date. To see this,
consider the last date. The traders will have different reservation
prices based on different fj functions. These reservation prices will
result in an equilibrium price that is a function only of the past signals.
At the second-to-last date, all speculators agree about the distribution
of the next signal since they agree on the state probabilities and the
likelihood function. Therefore speculators agree about the distribu-
tion of the next price since it depends only on current information
and the distribution of the next signal. Since the only reason for
trading at the second-to-last date is to speculate on the equilibrium
price at the last date, speculators' agreement about the distribution
of the price at the last date implies that they have no reason to trade
at the seocnd-to-last date. This argument can be extended to any
previous date by backward induction. Thus, to obtain sequential trad-
ing over time, one must assume that speculators disagree either about
likelihoods or about the fundamental states of nature.
Appendix
We start by stating several important formulas that are used later. First,
it follows immediately from the definition of 1rj(m) that
It follows that
491
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
Xn(m) = I (m n- = X)Xn-l(X) dx
_00
= f r(m + x -x)Xn_1(-x) dx
_00
= | rf(-m -x x)Xnl(x) dx
400
492
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
where p'(mt) = Hir-(mt) + L-r{ (mt). Also, for every t, m, andj, the
reservation price for the risky asset of group j at date t after cumu-
lative signal m is given by r/(m) = Ej[pt+1(m + s) I m ], where E'
denotes the expectation with respect to group j's posterior beliefs.
Thus, r' (m) = p' (m) and r2 (m) = E2[p'l(m + s) I m ]. Obviously,
if group 2 is the price-taking group, the lemma goes through with all
group indices reversed.
493
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
Now, let
Proof. This will be shown only for m > 0. The proof for m < 0 is
symmetric. Since
E0[7rH(m, s) I m]
= ,) iHr(m + s)r(s I m) ds
k m [ 0 (M + )ds + i ? (m+s) ds
494
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
lrH(m + s) (s + m)
7ro,Km + s)
+ 7r m s) -ls)(-s)lr%(m)
+ lrH(m l(m - s) < 7rH(m), (A13)
495
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
Lemma 6. Suppose g(m, s) and h(m, s) are two functions with the
following properties: g(m) E?[g(m, s) I m] and h(m) = E?[h(m,
s) I m] are symmetric about m = 0, both strictly monotone in the
same direction for m > 0, and Cov[g(m, s), h(m, s) I m] ' Ofor all
m with strict inequality for m =# 0. Then Cov[g(fi, s), h(m, s)] > 0.
Lemma 7. q1(m) ' qo(m) for all m with strict inequality for m 7# 0.
r(s I m) ds
1 - T(-m I m)
> m Alffm sr(s I m) ds
> 00 A-,(m, s) T(- m I i) (A15)
It is easy to check that
and
496
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
Therefore,
fm A( s (s I m) ds
_00 T(-m I m)
- rH(m - - r(s I m) ds
s00 T(-m I m)
T(-m I m) - T(m I m)
+l H XH(Om + s) - 7rH(Tm) I m)
J-m -T(-m T(-s I mm)m) d
1( Im
F (x) = T( 1m- T(-
T(-m II m)
m) for x >- - m. (A17)
The cdf on the right-hand side, G(x), has a mass point of
x(sInm) ds rm r (s I m) ds
G(x)=Go0+ f 4 I = Go +JT(mI)
J^m T(- m I m) Jx T(- m I m)
_T(- m I mn) - T(-x I mn)
T( m)-in T(-x n) m) for x > -im. (A19)
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
This is true, however, since a, and b0 are less than 1 and m < 0.
Q.E.D.
Proof.
Proof. It easy to check from (A6) that v(m) = v(-im) and that v' is
strictly decreasing in m for m ' 0. Similarly, that q(m) = q(- m)
follows from (A23). To apply Lemma 6, we must show that, for m' >
m > 0, the following expression is positive:
0,
where the inequality follows from (A3) and (A10), and the final
equality follows from (A3).
498
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
where the equality follows from a change of variable and the inequal-
ity uses (A3) and (AlO). Therefore, it suffices to show that d(m, s)
- d(m, -s) is decreasing in m for s and m > 0. This is equivalent
to showing that lrH(m + s) - rH(m - s) is decreasing in m for s and
m > 0, or, since
Proof. Using (4) and the fact that 7r1 (m + s) - 7r (m) < 0 if and
only if r2 (m + s) - 7r2(m) < 0,
499
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies / v 6 n 3 1993
Lemma 10. Cov[Ai t(m, s), Air(m, s) I m, = m] ' Ofor all m with strict
inequality for m # 0.
E0[APt I -im]
_00
= (H - L) [7rH(-m - t) - rH(-m)]r(t m i) dt
J-
=-EO[AptI m] (A23)
Now,
500
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
Xt(m I St1 >0) > X(-m I st1 >0) foreverym> Oand t> 0.
Consequently, it also suffices to show that
Xt(m I st-1) > Xt(-m I st-,) for every m > 0, st1 > 0, and t > 0.
But, this inequality is equivalent to
using Lemma 1. This inequality follows easily from the facts that
ofH(s) > of- (s) for s > 0 and ri (m) > 2 > ir2 (m) for m > 0. Q.E.D.
= n,=i,i1=n)r(m - n In) dm
Jw EO(vt+l I mt = m, mt-, = n) Ttn|n
00 ~~~~~~T(- n In)
o r(m - n n) dm
= I ro (m)a-m
0- TT(-n n)
N (n)
T(-n I n) (a + )
(A25)
(a + O
501
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
The third equality follows from (A6), the fourth equality from (A2),
the fifth from the definition of o-?, and the last from (Al) and (A4).
A similar calculation shows that this formula is also valid for n < 0.
Since the expression does not depend on n, EO(vt1 I vt > 0) =ko
(a + O).
Similarly, for n > 0,
EO(v,+l I vt 0, mt-I = n)
= EO(vt+1 mt > 0, mt1 = n)
00 r()m(m -n n) dm
= 4K)bg iT(-n n)
l0 (n) (0o
l-T(-n
1 T(-n n Jbmo-%(m
I n) 0 b d -n) dm
IH bbn--dm + bman+n d
_l-T(-
___________F
n I n) [ 1a1 f3J
= ~ ~~~ +,
1 - T(- n I n) a +
or
We next calculate the density and cdf of the sum of two signals.
502
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
? ~~ ?(a +: (A29)
For t < 0,
+ f a-b-s dsl
For R = L, one simply reverses the roles of a0 and b0, since o-?L is o%H
with a0 and bo interchanged. The formulas can be stated compactly as
w(t | R) = H (A31)
( 2 ort 0 and R = H
?(+a+f + t) fort-0
w(tI | H = (A32)
0 : ( a +: ) for t < 0,
503
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
7+rL(m)bmkm(1 2 m)
- rH(m)a-mko( k +
The first equality uses the fact that vt+2 > 0 if and only if st + st+1 >
-m and (A32) to average 1 - W(-m I R) over R = H,L, using
7rH(m) and 7r2(m). The second equality uses (Al) and (A5). Now
EO(vt+l I mt= m) = 1 - T(-m I m) = ir%(m)(ao)m.
The result for m < 0 follows since 1 - mko > 1. The proof for m >
0 is symmetric. Q.E.D.
References
Admati, A., and P. Pfleiderer, 1988, "A Theory of Intraday Patterns: Volume and Price Variability,"
Review of Financial Studies, 1, 3-40.
Amihud, Y., and H. Mendelson, 1987, "Trading Mechanisms and Stock Retturns: An Empirical
Investigation," Journal of Finance, 42, 533-553.
Amihud, Y., and H. Mendelson, 1991, "Volatility, Efficiency, and Trading: Evidence from the Jap-
anese Stock Market," Journal of Finance, 46, 1765-1789.
Bamber, L. S., 1987, "Unexpected Earnings, Firm Size, and Trading Volume Around Quarterly
Earnings Announcements," Accounting Review, 62, 510-532.
Beaver, W., 1968, "The Information Content of Annual Earnings Announcements," Empirical Research
in Accounting, Journal of Accounting Research (Suppl. to vol. 6), 67-92.
Blough, S., 1988, "Differences of Opinion and the Information Value of Prices," working paper,
The Johns Hopkins University.
Blume, L., D. Easley, and M. O'Hara, 1991, "Market Statistics and Technical Analysis: The Role of
Volume," working paper, Cornell University.
Brock, W. A., and A. W. Kleidon, 1992, "Periodic Market Closure and Trading Volume: A Model of
Intraday Bids and Asks," Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 16, 451-489.
De Long,J. B., A. Shleifer, L. H. Summers, and R. J. Waldmann, 1990, "Noise Trader Risk in Financial
Markets," Journal of Political Economy, 98, 703-738.
Detemple, J., and S. Murthy, 1992, "Intertemporal Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Information
and Beliefs," working paper, Columbia University.
Diamond, D. W., and R. E. Verrecchia, 1981, "Information Aggregation in a Noisy Rational Expec-
tations Economy," Journal of Financial Economics, 9, 221-235.
Foster, F. D., and S. Viswanathan, 1990, "A Theory of the Interday Variations in Volume, Variance,
and Trading Costs in Securities Markets," Review of Financial Studies, 3, 593-624.
504
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Differences of Opinion
Foster, F. D., and S. Viswanathan, 1993a, "The Effect of Public Information and Competition on
Trading Volume and Price Volatility," Review of Financial Studies, 6, 23-56.
Foster, F. D., and S. Viswanathan, 1993b, "Variations in Trading Volumes, Return Volatility and
Trading Costs: Evidence on Recent Price Formation Models," Journal of Finance, 48, 187-211.
Gallant, A. R., P. E. Rossi, and G. Tauchen, 1992, "Stock Prices and Volume," Review of Financial
Stuidies, 5, 199-242.
Grossman, S. J., and J. E. Stiglitz, 1976, "Information and Competitive Price Systems," American
Economic Review, 66, 246-253.
Grossman, S. J., and J. E. Stiglitz, 1980, "On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets,"
American Economic Review, 70, 393-408.
Grundy, B. D., and M. McNichols, 1989, "Trade and Revelation of Information through Prices and
Direct Disclosure," Review of Financial Studies, 2, 495-526.
Harris, L., 1987, "Transaction Data Tests of the Mixture of Distributions Hypothesis," Journal of
Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 22, 127-14 1.
Harrison, J. M., and D. M. Kreps, 1978, "Speculative Investor Behavior in a Stock Market with
Heterogeneous Expectations," QuarterlyJournal of Economics, 93, 323-336.
Hellwig, M., 1980, "On the Aggregation of Information in Competitive Markets," Journal of Eco-
nomic Theory, 22, 477-498.
Hindy, A., 1989, "An Equilibrium Model of Futures Markets Dynamics," working paper, MIT.
Holthausen, R. W., and R. E. Verrecchia, 1990, "The Effect of Informedness and Consensus on
Price and Volume Behavior," Accounting Review, 65, 191-208.
Jain, P. C., and G-H. Joh, 1988, "The Dependence between Hourly Prices and Trading Volume,"
Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 23, 269-283.
Jones, C. M., G. Kaul, and M. L. Lipson, 1991, "Transactions, Volume and Volatility," working paper,
University of Michigan.
Kandel, E., and N. D. Pearson, 1992, "Differential Interpretation of Public Signals and Trade in
Speculative Markets," working paper, University of Rochester.
Karpoff, J. M., 1987, "The Relation between Price Changes and Trading Volume: A Survey," Journal
of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 22, 109-126.
Kim, O., and R. E. Verrecchia, 1991a, "Trading Volume and Price Reactions to Public Announce-
ments," Journal ofAccounting Research, 29, 302-32 1.
Kim, O., and R. E. Verrecchia, 1991b, "Market Reactions to Anticipated Announcements," Journal
of Financial Economics, 30, 273-309.
Kyle, A., 1985, "Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading," Econometrica, 53, 1315-1335.
Lakonishok, J., and E. Maberly, 1990, "The Weekend Effect: Trading Patterns of Individual and
Institutional Investors," Journal of Finance, 45, 231-243.
Lakonishok, J., and S. Smidt, 1986, "Capital Gains Taxation and Volume of Trading," Journal of
Finance, 41, 951-974.
Lang, L. H. P., R. H. Litzenberger, and V. Madrigal, 1992, "Testing Financial Market Equilibrium
under Asymmetric Information," Journal of Political Economy, 100, 317-348.
Milgrom, P., and N. Stokey, 1982, "Information, Trade and Common Knowledge," Journal of
Economic Theory, 26, 17-27.
Osborne, M. F. M., 1962, "Periodic Structure in the Brownian Motion of the Stock Market," Oper-
ations Research, 10, 345-379.
505
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Review of Financial Studies/ v 6 n 3 1993
Patell, J. M., and M. A. Wolfson, 1984, "The Intraday Speed of Adjustment of Stock Prices to Earnings
and Dividend Announcements," Journal of Financial Economics, 13, 223-252.
Pfleiderer, P., 1984, "The Volume of Trade and the Variability of Prices: A Framework for Analysis
in Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibria," working paper, Stanford University.
Schwert, G. W., 1989, "Why Does Stock Market Volatility Change over Time?," Journal of Finance,
44, 1115-1153.
Shalen, C. T., 1993, "Volume, Volatility and the Dispersion of Beliefs," Review of Financial Studies,
6, 405-434.
Shleifer, A., and L. H. Summers, 1990, "The Noise TraderApproach to Finance,"Journal of Economic
Perspectives, 4, 19-33.
Varian, H. R., 1985, "Divergence of Opinion in Complete Markets," Journal of Finance, 40, 309-
317.
Varian, H. R., 1989, "Differences of Opinion in Financial Markets," in Courtenay C. Stone (ed.),
Financial Risk: Theory, Evidence and Implications, Proceedings of the EleventhAnnual Economic
Policy Conference of the Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis, Kluwer, Boston, 3-37.
Wang, J., 1992, "A Model of Competitive Stock Trading Volume," working paper, MIT.
Ziebart, D. A., 1990, "The Association Between Consensus of Beliefs and Trading Activity Sur-
rounding Earnings Announcements," Accounting Review, 65, 477-488.
506
This content downloaded from 141.218.1.105 on Thu, 04 Aug 2016 10:49:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms