States of Emergency (30 10 2008)
States of Emergency (30 10 2008)
States of Emergency (30 10 2008)
Asanga Welikala
1
All rights reserved.
Centre for Policy Alternatives (CPA) and the author.
Material from this publication may be used with due acknowledgement to the author and
CPA.
ISBN 978‐955‐1655‐50‐1
The Friedrich Naumann Stiftung für die Freiheit (FNF) is the only German political
foundation, committed to liberal principles. The Foundation is a non proLit organization
working in 60 countries of the world, promoting liberal concepts, with the objective of
contributing towards political, economic and social development. The Foundation
celebrated its golden anniversary in May 2008 and introduced “Freedom” as the new
motto of FNF’s future work. The foundation worldwide has developed and canvassed
liberal ideas and liberal approaches through its numerous activities and events. The
Foundation’s main task is to continually underline the relevance of freedom for
developing an open, free and tolerant society.
Address : 24/2, 28th Lane, off Flower Road, Colombo 7, Sri Lanka
Telephone : +94 (11) 2565304/5/6
Fax : +94 (11) 4714460
Web : http://www.cpalanka.org
2
This book is dedicated to J.S. Tissainayagam
3
Table of Contents
Foreword – Dr. Paikiasothy Saravanamuttu ........................................ 08
Preface .................................................................................................................... 10
1. Introduction .................................................................................................. 16
4
3. The Neo‐Roman Constitutional Model of
Accommodation: Comparative Experience ....................................... 64
6
6. Fundamental Rights ...................................................................................... 208
6.1. Chapter II: Sri Lanka’s Constitutional Bill of Rights .................. 209
Annexures
7
Foreword
The recourse to emergency rule has taken its toll on the political
culture, institutions and processes of governance without securing
the objectives of security and law and order for which they were,
ostensibly, resorted to. Under the guise of national security, regime
8
security has been prioritised and the state has traversed the full
spectrum from protector and provider to predator. Consequently,
Sri Lanka’s claim to be a functioning democracy has been called
into question to the extent that the question of ‘state failure’ has
also been posed in relation to our government and governance.
Special thanks are due to Asanga. His passion for and commitment
to liberal democratic ideas and values, as well as his considerable
intellectual curiosity are amply reLlected in this work. I hope and
trust that this volume will be received as a singular contribution to
debate and advocacy for democratic governance in Sri Lanka, I
believe it is.
9
Preface
In May and June 1958, in Ceylon, occurred what were up till then
the most serious communal riots in Sri Lanka’s troubled history of
ethnic relations. In retrospect, the events of 1958 were mere
portents of the horrors that were to come. A contemporaneous
journalistic account of what happened was written by Tarzie
Vittachi, editor of Asia’s oldest newspaper, the Ceylon Observer,
satirical columnist, and intrepid political commentator. In the
context of the blanket censorship imposed under Sri Lanka’s Lirst
post‐independence experience of emergency rule, the manuscript
was published in London under the title Emergency ’58 by Andre
Deutsch, in what has now become a classic of Sri Lankan political
literature. The book was banned in Ceylon, and Tarzie Vittachi
subsequently left the country, under the cloud of death threats.
11
State, especially during the second rebellion in the period between
1987 and 1991.
12
nationalist political ideology (mirroring the monolithic political
and militaristic standpoint of the LTTE) that has, outside the
theatres of battle, institutionalised a worldview that has little
patience for the assumptions regarding human rights, the rule of
law and constitutional government during states of emergency at
the heart of this book. A corresponding and massive arrogation of
an extraordinary array of emergency powers by the State has been
the formal and legal result. The more informal, in the sense of
‘political’, consequence has been the entrenchment of an
epistemological discourse of ‘patriot or traitor’ that has
legitimised a culture of impunity and immunity against even the
most egregious human rights violations and violators. Civil society
in general, and journalists in particular, have borne the full brunt
of this dreadful political ideology.
13
Head of the Legal & Constitutional Unit, CPA) responded to the
presentation. Thanks are due to the panel for their comments, the
quality and rigour of which truly reLlected the panellists’
distinction, length and diversity of experience in the defence of
civil liberties and the rule of law at the Bar, in academe and as
members of Sri Lanka’s civil society. Thanks are also due to the
interventions and lively debate generated by participants at the
seminar.
The Centre for Policy Alternatives (CPA) and the author would like
to acknowledge with appreciation the Linancial support for this
project given by the Friedrich Naumann Stiftung für die Freiheit
(FNF). The author wishes in particular to thank the FNF Resident
Representative in Sri Lanka, Mrs. Sagarica Delgoda, and her
colleagues at the FNF Colombo ofLice for the great Llexibility,
understanding and patience they have shown in bringing this
book to publication, delays and extensions notwithstanding.
14
Needless to say, responsibility for errors that doubtless remain
lies with the author.
Asanga Welikala
Colombo
th
27 August 2008
15
Chapter 1
INTRODUCTION
Sri Lanka has been governed under emergency powers for the
best part of the last three decades. The crisis conditions
necessitating recourse by the State to emergency powers are the
result of deep‐rooted political anomalies of the Sri Lankan State
and its constitutional order. These have given rise to two instances
of attempted overthrow of the State driven by socio‐economic and
ideological considerations in the South, as well as the continuing
ethno‐political conLlict and armed secessionism in the North and
East of the country.
17
The choices imposed by this tension are of course a dilemma faced
by democracies and democrats, because authoritarian regimes do
not face a choice between liberty and order. To the latter, the only
considerations are those such as efLiciency, the allocation of
resources, and the political and physical survival of the regime. In
democracies, the recognition of the need for emergency powers
requires an acceptance of an expansion of the role of the executive,
by deLinition at the expense of some facets of democracy.
Primarily, this involves the derogation or limitation of some
fundamental rights and the suspension of some institutional
checks and balances. For the reason that emergency powers are
seen as exceptional measures to deal with a crisis, democratic
practice and international law seeks to impose temporal,
procedural, and substantive limits to emergency powers. Thus the
theory and practice relating to states of emergency in
constitutional democracies concern certain overarching themes
such as the fundamental distinction between emergency and
normalcy already mentioned (and accordingly the separation of
treatment between exceptional measures and ordinary law and
processes). Flowing directly from this is the concern to limit the
operation of emergency powers in time; to establish requirements
of justiLication prior to invocation of these powers; the
mechanisms for approval, oversight and accountability; and to
regulate the substantive reach of emergency powers, especially
where fundamental rights are implicated.
18
the exception discussed below. Nonetheless, a theoretically and
normatively coherent, critical understanding of the Sri Lankan
situation in the light of comparative experience cannot be
undertaken without making this assumption.
19
indeed, ambiguous social subscription to liberal democratic
values.
It has also been the case that even the institutional safeguards
envisaged by the constitution have been rendered nugatory by the
failure of parliamentary review over executive action, both
procedurally and in terms of substantive rule‐making. Likewise,
both the independence and the capacity of the law enforcement
apparatus of the State, including the police, the Attorney General’s
Department and the judiciary, are once again becoming a matter of
international concern. The Supreme Court as the constitutional
guarantor of fundamental rights has had a mixed record. It has
been a relatively robust defender of fundamental rights in the
past, although the tenor of its jurisprudence has not always
corresponded with international trends and standards. More
recently, however, the Supreme Court has been responsible, inter
alia, for a shocking retreat from Sri Lanka’s international
obligations under the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights and its enforcement framework under the First Optional
Protocol. Other mechanisms such as the national Human Rights
Commission have become wholly ineffectual in dealing with
challenges on the ground. There is very little conLidence that the
institutions of the State are possessed of the necessary will,
20
independence or capacity to ensure the protection of the human
rights of its citizens against abuse of emergency powers in the
context of escalating conLlict.
21
ethnic discrimination, detentions without charge, internal
displacement, and the arbitrary expulsion of civilians from the
metropolis, is one in which there is no public conLidence in human
rights protection and the rule of law, which in turns erodes
conLidence in and legitimacy of the constitutional order itself.
22
reinterpretation of its constitutional sphere as well as go beyond
to the politics of self‐legitimation.
23
Having set out the theoretical framework of analysis in this way,
the discussion explores the Roman model of constitutional
accommodation further, as the model that is the prototype for
emergency institutions in the large majority of modern
democracies as well as for the standards set by international law
and practice, and which also ostensibly informs the text and
constitutional assumptions of the Sri Lankan legal framework on
emergency rule. The second model, also known as the ‘business as
usual’ model, is of limited application to the Sri Lankan
experience, and is only included here for the sake of completeness.
24
issues from comparative experience that must inform a discussion
of Sri Lankan states of emergency. Likewise, there is a regulatory
framework for states of emergency and derogations from
international obligations as set out in the International Covenant
on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), to which Sri Lanka is a
signatory; and the First Optional Protocol to the ICCPR which
mandates individual communications to the Human Rights
Committee, in relation to which the status of Sri Lanka is in doubt
following the Supreme Court decision in the Singarasa Case in
2006. In addition to these are the norms of general international
human rights law. The ICCPR and other provisions of human rights
and humanitarian law are peremptory norms of international law
by which the Sri Lankan State is bound as a member of the
international community of States.
25
second edition of Fundamental Rights in Sri Lanka (2006) have
been useful.
26
27
PART I
28
29
CHAPTER II
30
In their recent comprehensive study of the theory and practice of
states of emergency, Gross and Ní Aoláin1 have advanced three
broad conceptual models that facilitate a more systematic
understanding of states of emergency and the competing issues
they involve. The typology used by Gross and Ní Aoláin is the
analytical framework adopted in this chapter. These are (a) the
models of accommodation; (b) the ‘business as usual’ model; and
(c) the extra‐legal measures model.
32
in the process, destroy democracy. As Gross and Ní Aoláin suggest,
“This compromise…enables continued adherence to the principle
of the rule of law and faithfulness to fundamental democratic
values, while providing the state with adequate measures to
withstand the storm wrought by the crisis.” 2
With the fall of the monarchy in 509 BC, the new Roman republic
established a form of executive government that was designed to
avoid the perils of centralisation of power. The result was an
executive branch that was headed by two consuls, who were
vested with a vast array of power including that of command over
the army.9 However, the logic of the system was sustained by two
key underlying principles: (a) the principle of collegiality and
equal power, and (b) the principle of limited and non‐renewable
tenure. The Lirst principle meant that each consul enjoyed equal
authority and had the same range of powers and responsibilities.
It also meant that each had an unlimited veto over the decisions
and actions of the other. The second principle established that
each consul was elected for a period of one year only without the
possibility of consecutive re‐election. 10
However, the Romans recognised that this system may not work
well in times of grave peril, when the need for swift and decisive
10See Max Cary & Howard H. Scullard (1975) A History of Rome down to
the Reign of Constantine (3rd Ed.) (New York: St. Martin’s Press): p.56,
62‐63
35
action may not be served by a collegial executive which ran the
real risk of deadlock. For these occasions, therefore, the Romans
devised the institution of the dictatorship, which would
concentrate the powers of the State necessary to tide over the
threat in a single appointed ofLicial.11 It was an innovative attempt
to constitutionally revive the essence of the monarchy, albeit for
strictly limited purposes and duration. Given what Hamilton
described as its ‘formidable title’ and the connotations of the term
in common parlance, it is important to bear in mind that the Latin
origin of the term dictator is dictus, meaning named, or
appointed.12 In the Roman republic, this title was given to the
person exercising powers under the emergency regime for the
reason that he was the only magistrate that was appointed. All
others including the consuls were elected ofLicials. The
dictatorship we are concerned with is that exempliLied by
Cincinnatus,13 not the constitutionally destructive tyrannies of
Sulla or Caesar. As Gross and Ní Aoláin observe, “The main thrust
of this emergency institution was its constitutional nature.
Operating within the republican constitutional framework the
dictator was vested with extraordinary yet constitutional powers.
Emergency was met with special powers of an authoritarian
character, but the employment of such powers and the authority
to use them were regulated by law.” 14
The dictator was appointed by either one of the consuls, but the
consuls were neither replaced nor their powers taken away by the
A Linal check as Machiavelli saw it, and one which has particular
resonance for any discussion on states of emergency in Sri Lanka,
27Rossiter (1948), op cit., p.16; see also Joseph B. Kelly & George A.
Pelletier, Jr. (1966) ‘Theories of Emergency Government’ 11 South Dakota
Law Review 42 at p.46
29Max Radin (1942) ‘Martial Law and the State of Siege’ 30 California Law
Review 634 at p.637
While the source, scope and content of martial law has been the
subject of much debate, Gross and Ní Aoláin broadly discern two
strands of opinion as to the source of martial law, on which the
determination of its scope depends. In the Lirst strand, martial law
is seen as a matter of the English common law right to repel force
by force, which is the same principle as the criminal law doctrine
of self‐defence. The second school of thought sees martial law as
an aspect of the panoply of powers available to the Crown under
the royal prerogative.32
31 See Charles Fairman (1943) The Law of Martial Rule (2nd Ed.)
(Chicago: Callaghan): pp.9‐19; F.K.M.A. Munim (1989) Legal Aspects of
Martial Law (Dhaka: Bangladesh Institute of Law and International
Affairs): p.12; George M. Dennison (1974) ‘Martial Law: The Development
of a Theory of Emergency Powers, 1776 – 1861’ 18 American Journal of
Legal History 52; Matthew Hale (1987) The History of the Common Law
of England (1713) (Colorado: F.B.Rothman): p.34; Robert Blackstone
(1979) Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765) (Chicago: Chicago
UP): p.400
The other view of martial law is that it Llows from the royal
prerogative.37 According to Gross and Ní Aoláin, the origin of this
theory goes back to the Court of the Constable and Marshal which
operated under the prerogative. They see evidence of this
approach in certain legislative measures against riots and
disturbances in Ireland which stipulated explicitly that “nothing in
this act contained shall be construed to take away, abridge or
37Fairman (1943), op cit., pp.1‐6; Munim (1989) op cit., pp.7‐9; J.V. Capua
(1977) ‘Early History of Martial Law in England from the 14th Century to
the Petition of Right’ 36 Cambridge Law Journal 152
44
diminish, the acknowledged prerogative of his Majesty, for the
public safety, to resort to the exercise of martial law against open
enemies or traitors.”38 The philosophical basis of this approach, as
we see below, is principally Locke’s theory of the royal prerogative
used according to his conception of the ‘public good’ in times of
emergency and when measures available under the ordinary law
are inadequate or the procedures of the ordinary legal system are
too slow.
38Gross and Ní Aoláin: p.34 and statutory references; Colm Campbell (1994)
Emergency Law in Ireland, 1918 – 1925 (Oxford: Clarendon Press): pp.
125‐148
Constitutional Accommodation
Interpretive Accommodation
49
discussed above, in that in the latter, emergency‐sensitive judicial
interpretation of ordinary laws are contemplated, whereas in this
model, there is no difference in interpretive outcomes of ordinary
law between times of emergency and normalcy.
The majority in ex parte Milligan has both its adherents and its
harsh critics for a variety of reasons, including for the latter, the
naivety and even hypocrisy of holding an idealistic line against the
odds of reality. Part of the reasoning of the majority was the
product of the peculiarity of the US constitution which, unlike
modern constitutions, does not provide explicitly for emergency
powers, except to make reference to the congressional power to
call out the militia, and the permissibility of the suspension of the
privilege of habeas corpus under certain conditions. For this and
45See for e.g. Jack Donnelly (2000) Realism and International Relations
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP); Carl J. Friedrich (1957) Constitutional
Reason of State: The Survival of the Constitutional Order (Providence:
Brown UP): p.14
51
from Jewish law,46 Locke’s theory of the executive prerogative,47
Dicey’s ‘spirit of law,’48 and the Weberian ideal‐type,49 inherent
conceptual requirements of institutional morality and legitimation
bring the argument for extra‐legal emergency measures rather
closer to liberal democratic imperatives than some models of
accommodation, in particular the theory of constitutional
necessity. The doctrine of constitutional necessity for validating
emergency measures is borne out of vague, inadequate or absent
constitutional provision for emergency powers, with the result
that necessity has to be recast as an independent source of
constitutional law in general and emergency powers in
particular.50
47Ibid, pp.119‐130; see also Mark Goldie (Ed.) (1994) John Locke, Two
Treatises of Government (London: Tuttle Publishing): ‘Introduction to
Two Treatises of Government’ by Mark Goldie
48 Gross and Ní Aoláin: pp.130‐132; see also Dicey (1982), op cit., p.273
49Gross and Ní Aoláin: pp.132‐134; see also Max Weber (1946) ‘Politics as
Vocation’ in H.H. Gerth & C. Wright Mills (Eds. & Trans.) (1946) From Max
Weber: Essays in Sociology (New York: Oxford UP): p.77
52 Ibid
54
Carl Schmitt: Sovereign Dictatorship, the Concept of the
Political and the State of Permanent Exception
55
yield real analytical insights about extra‐legality and the exercise
of power. These insights are most evident in respect of the more
salient aspects of his thesis such as the (lack of) traction of liberal
democratic values in the political culture of ofLicial and popular
subscription, the falsity of the assumption of separation between
normalcy and emergency, and his argument about the
permanency of crisis as the natural condition of politics. In this
way, chillingly it must be admitted, the differences between the
Nazi regime and the Sri Lankan State become a matter of moral
and political degree, i.e., a more‐or‐less question of egregiousness.
Thus while it would be factually wrong and analytically misleading
to equate the human rights abuses of the Sri Lankan State to the
fundamentally genocidal character of Nazi Germany, for the
purposes of an unromantic, sceptical and searching analytical
understanding of the behaviour of the Sri Lankan State in times of
emergency, it can be treated as a permutation within the
Schmittian ontology of political power and statehood. In short,
therefore, Schmitt’s contribution to political and legal theory
should read in abstract and applied to the Sri Lankan conditions
and experience, without succumbing to the distraction of his
personal association with the Nazi regime.
58 Ibid, p.6
60 Ibid
63 Ibid, pp.37, 38
58
The centrepiece of Schmitt’s model of emergency powers is the
sovereign dictatorship, the principal characteristic of which is the
suspension of the entire existing legal order.64 SigniLicantly, the
sovereign dictator acting under emergency powers can “…actively…
change the existing legal order and transform it, in whole or in
part, into something else.” 65 As Gross and Ní Aoláin observe, “The
norm becomes subservient to the exception, thereby reversing the
relationship between the two. In fact, Schmitt eliminates
altogether the notion of the normal and replaces it with the
exception.” 66 By replacing the existing legal order with the
exception, Schmitt renders the exception the only valid general
rule. The exception as general rule thus is not only norm‐less
(having replaced the ordinary legal system), it also becomes
exception‐less: that is, because Schmitt’s exception as general rule
admits of no separation between normality and emergency (i.e.,
the state of exception), there can be no exception from the
exception.67 The consequence is a permanent state of exception
(i.e., emergency under the sovereign dictatorship).
66 Ibid
From Dyzenhaus’s critical look at how liberal legal systems (in this
case Commonwealth jurisdictions and the United States) with
avowed commitment to the rule of law have responded to Carl
Schmitt’s challenge – that in times of emergency it is in the nature
70 Ibid, p.166
64
As we noted before, the institution of the dictatorship in the
Roman republic has served as the model for modern democracies
in devising their constitutional and legal arrangements with
respect to emergency powers. The features of the Roman model
germane to modern constitution‐makers are, in Gross and Ní
Aoláin’s summary: “temporary character, recognition of the
exceptional nature of emergencies, appointment of a dictator
according to speciLic constitutional forms that separated, among
other things, those who declared an emergency and those who
exercised dictatorial power on such occasions, the appointment of
dictators for well‐deLined and limited purposes, and the ultimate
goal of upholding the constitutional order rather than changing or
replacing it.” 74
82Section 37 (1) (a) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act
108 of 1996 (the ‘Final Constitution’). Cf. Articles 180‐182 of the
Constitution of Ecuador and Article 29 of the Constitution of Mexico
84Articles 38, 39, Basic Law: The Government, 1780 SH (2001); see also
Baruch Bracha (2003) ‘Checks and Balances in a Protracted State of
Emergency – The Case of Israel’ 33 Israel Yearbook on Human Rights 123
86See Venelin I. Ganev (1997) ‘Emergency Powers and the New East
European Constitutions’ 45 American Journal of Comparative Law 585
69
emergency’.87 The former remains undeLined, whereas the latter
must be deLined by statute. The constitution of Portugal
distinguishes between a ‘state of emergency’ and a ‘state of siege.’
Thus, a state of siege or a state of emergency may be declared ‘in
cases of actual or imminent aggression by foreign forces, serious
threat to or disturbance of the democratic constitutional order or
public calamity’, whereas a ‘state of emergency is declared where
the circumstances mentioned in the preceding paragraph are less
serious’.88
90Gross and Ní Aoláin: p.42; see also Brian Loveman (1993) The
Constitution of Tyranny: Regimes of Exception in Spanish America
(Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh UP)
91Articles 91, 87a(4), 12a(5)‐(6), 80a, 115a‐l of the German Basic Law
(Grundgesetz); John E. Finn (1991) Constitutions in Crisis: Political
Violence and the Rule of Law (New York: Oxford UP): pp.196‐200; Note
(1969) ‘Recent Emergency Legislation in West Germany’ 82 Harvard Law
Review 1704
94Emergencies Act 1988, S.C. 1988, Ch.29, S.80. See also Peter Rosenthal
(1991) ‘The New Emergencies Act: Four Times the War Measures Act’ 20
Manitoba Law Journal 563 at p.565‐573; Eliot Tenofsky (1989) ‘The War
Measures and Emergencies Acts’ 19 American Review of Canadian
Studies 293
96 Article 86
72
alarm concerns natural disasters, scarcity of basic commodities or
essential services; a state of emergency is declared where ‘the free
exercise of the citizen’s rights and liberties or the normal
functions of democratic institutions, public services essential for
the community or any other aspect of public order are altered to
the extent that the ordinary powers prove insufLicient to re‐
establish or maintain them’; and a state of siege is proclaimed ‘in
the event of an insurrection or threat of insurrection or an act of
force against the sovereignty or independence, territorial integrity
and constitutional order of Spain which cannot otherwise be
resolved.’97
99 Ibid
102
Clinton Rossiter (1948) Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis
Government in Modern Democracies (Princeton: Princeton UP): pp.
297‐306
74
In comparative experience, this principle Linds near universal
recognition, although the particular institutional architecture to
give effect to it varies widely depending on contextual political
factors, the general system and speciLic structures of government,
and constitutional traditions of each jurisdiction. It is important to
bear in mind that the distribution of power under the
constitutional dispensation as a whole inLluences the design of
arrangements regarding states of emergency. This applies both to
the ‘horizontal’ arrangements at the centre in terms of the
separation of power between the executive and the legislature,
and in federal‐type systems, where more complex ‘vertical’
arrangements may be in place for mediating between multiple
orders of government. Broadly, however, the constitutional
provisions for declaration of states on emergency fall into three
groups: viz., those that vest the power of declaration in the
legislature (usually parliamentary systems), those empowering
executive initiative (generally presidential systems), and others
that are hybrid.
103 For e.g. Article 38 (c) of the Israeli Basic Law: The Government
107 See also Article 48 (1) of the Greek Constitution; Articles 78, 87 of the
Italian Constitution; Ganev (1997), op cit., pp.587‐589 for Eastern
European constitutions
75
to undertake, these jurisdictions may allow a limited power of
declaration and even rule‐making to the executive, subject to
ratiLication by the legislature.
110 Ibid
112See esp. H.M. Seervai (1996) Constitutional Law of India (4th Ed.)
(Bombay: Tripathi): Ch. XXIX; S.R. Bommai v. Union (1994) 3 SCC 1
115Articles 80a and 115a of the German Basic Law; Article 352 (6) of the
Indian Constitution
77
whereby each successive extension of a state of emergency
requires ever increasing legislative majorities until a small
minority becomes capable of halting further extension.116 A like
approach is adopted in the South African constitution where the
initial declaration requires only a simple majority, but extensions
require the support of a special majority of 60% of legislators.117
117 Section 37 (2) (b) of the South African Constitution; see for the position in
Sri Lanka prior to the Tenth Amendment to the Constitution, Chapter 5, infra
118For e.g. Article 38b of the Israeli Basic Law: The Government; Section 37 of
the South African Constitution; Article 352 (5) of the Indian Constitution
120 See also Cheadle, Davis & Haysom (2002) op cit., Ch.31
79
may override ordinary statutes. As Gross and Ní Aoláin note, “…in
order to prevent repetition of the mistakes that led to the
destruction of the Weimar constitutional experiment…modern
constitutional provisions often proscribe any change or
modiLication of the constitution itself during an emergency, or at
least any change to, or modiLication of, the nature of the regime
and its core constitutional norms.”121
121For e.g. Article 89 (4) of the French Constitution; Articles 187, 196 of
the Belgian Constitution; see Gross and Ní Aoláin: p.60‐61. Under Article
155 of the Sri Lankan constitution, the President is empowered to make
emergency regulations which can override the provisions of any ordinary
law, but not the provisions of the constitution. This is salutary. But in
practice, rule by emergency powers have become so endemic, and
executive accountability so weak, that emergency rule‐making often
strays into the sphere of the unconstitutional: see Chapter 5, infra
80
provision of a blanket legal overriding power, to both legislative
and executive action during a time of emergency. The only legal
limitation on its invocation is its purposes (i.e., grave
emergencies), which if bridged allows the government to virtually
re‐write the constitution through emergency measures. It would
seem that the most salient counter against abuse of such
provisions is the extra‐legal one of deeply rooted liberal
democratic cultures in these countries (for example, the Swiss
provisions have only been invoked twice: during the two world
wars), preventing the unhappy political experiences under such
provisions as Article 96 (1) of the Algerian constitution which
provides that ‘during a period of state of war, the Constitution is
suspended [and] the President of the Republic assumes all the
powers.’
81
natural disasters, and a negative list in respect of security‐related
or man‐made crises.122
122 For examples of all three approaches, see Gross and Ní Aoláin: p.8
132
See N. Manoharan (2006) Counterterrorism Legislation in Sri Lanka:
Evaluating EfZicacy, Policy Studies 28 (Washington DC: East‐West
Center)
134 Ibid
136
Edward S. Corwin (1947) Total War and the Constitution (New York:
Knopf): pp.35‐37
85
demonstrate this.137 Other federations such as Germany, India and
Russia provide explicitly for the suspension of fundamental
federal constitutional principles during times of emergency.138
While it would seem that the unitary State of Sri Lanka would not
encounter these considerations, it is important to remember that
one of the central debates about the schema of devolution under
the Thirteenth Amendment to the Constitution (1987), has been in
respect of the emergency powers framework. Proponents of
meaningful devolution have argued that the retention by the
centre of wide emergency related powers are a signiLicant fetter
137 Herbert Marx (1970) ‘The Emergency Power and Civil Liberties in
Canada’ 16 MacGill Law Journal 39 at pp.57‐61; Christopher D. Gilbert
(1980) “There will be Wars and Rumours of Wars’: A Comparison of the
Treatment of Defence and Emergency Powers in the Federal Constitutions of
Australia and Canada’ 18 Osgoode Hall Law Journal 307; Donald G.
Creighton (1944) Dominion of the North: A History of Canada (Boston:
Houghton MifLlin): p.439; Patricia Peppin (1993) ‘Emergency Legislation
and Rights in Canada: The War Measures Act and Civil Liberties’ 18
Queen’s Law Journal 129 at p.131; Rosenthal (1991), op cit., p.576‐580;
Peter W. Hogg, ‘Canada: From Privy Council to Supreme Court’ and Jeffrey
Goldsworthy ‘Australia: Devotion to Legalism’ in Goldsworthy (2006), op
cit., pp.64‐66, 85, 102 and p.138
138 Article 53 (a) (2) of the German Basic Law; David P. Currie (1994) The
Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany (Chicago: Chicago UP):
pp. 134, 138‐139; Donald P. Kommers, ‘Germany: Balancing Rights and
Duties’ in Goldsworthy (2006) op cit., pp.163, 167, 169, 185; Articles 353,
356, 360 of the Indian Constitution; Durga Das Basu (1982) Introduction
to the Constitution of India (9th Ed.) (New Delhi: Prentice‐Hall): pp.
302‐316; S.P. Sathe, ‘India: From Positivism to Structuralism’ in
Goldsworthy (2006), op cit., pp.222, 245, 246, 247‐251, 259, 264, 339,
344; Article 88 of the Russian Constitution
86
on devolution,139 whereas opponents of extensive devolution have
strenuously held that such retention is essential to safeguard the
territorial integrity of the country against attempts at secession by
the North and East region. 140 By provisions introduced by the
Thirteenth Amendment, presidential emergency powers extend to
the issuing of orders and instructions to provincial Governors in
respect of actual or imminent public security threats141 and
emergency regulations made by the President override provincial
statutes.142 We shall revisit this issue later.143
140 H.L. de Silva P.C., Professor G.H. Peiris, Gomin Dayasiri & Manohara de
Silva P.C. (2006) Interim Report of Sub‐Committee B of the Experts Panel
of the All Party Representative Committee, 11th December 2006
141 Article 154J (1) of the constitution. See also Articles 154K (failure of
provincial Governors to comply with presidential directions) and 154L
(failure of the administrative machinery of a Province)
144
Section 37 (3) of the South African Constitution; Cheadle, Davis &
Haysom (2002), op cit., Ch.31
145 Article 150 (8) of the Malaysian Constitution; Article 28.3.3° of the
Irish Constitution
147Article 15J (2) of the Constitution and section 3 of the PSO. Section 8 of
the PSO also provides that no emergency regulation, order, rule or
direction shall be called in question in any court, although this does not
oust the jurisdiction of the Supreme Court to review such acts for
constitutionality and consistency with fundamental rights.
149 Gross and Ní Aoláin: p.63; In Korematsu v. United States (1944) 323
US 214 at p.224, Frankfurter J. stated: “…therefore the validity of
action under the war power must be judged wholly in the context of
war. That action is not to be stigmatized as lawless because like action
in times of peace would be lawless.” However, Jackson J., dissenting,
compared such legal modiLications to a “…loaded weapon ready for
the hand of any authority that can bring forward a plausible claim of
an urgent need.” (at p.246). See also Hirabayashi v. United States
(1943) 320 US 81. In the United Kingdom, much the same judicial
thinking applied in the majority decision in Liversidge v. Anderson
(1942) AC 206, where the issuing of an administrative detention order
by a Minister was held to be a matter solely for executive discretion,
barring positive evidence of mala Kides or mistaken identity: per Lord
Wright at p.261. The dicta of Goddard L.J., in Greene v. Secretary of
State (1942) AC 284 in the Court of Appeal was cited with approval:
“…where on the return an order or warrant which is valid on its face is
produced, it is for the prisoner to prove the facts necessary to
controvert it.”
89
may be curbed by the judiciary.” 150 It has not been the Sri Lankan
experience, however, that governments, even from a perception of
self‐interest, have quite adopted this attitude to judicial review.
152Articles 155 (4), (5), (6), (7), (8) of the constitution; section 5 (3) of
the PSO
153Coomaraswamy & de los Reyes (2004), op cit, pp.273, 277; see also
Charles L. Black, Jr., (1960) The People and the Court: Judicial Review in
a Democracy (New York: Macmillan): pp.56‐86; Ronen Shamir (1990)
“Landmark Cases’ and the Reproduction of Legitimacy: The Case of Israel’s
High Court of Justice’ 24 Law and Society Review 781
90
themselves, which do not provide a sufLiciently robust legal
framework for legislative oversight. Other factors relate to
political and democratic cultures, including undue deference to
leadership and tolerance of authoritarianism. There is also what
Gross and Ní Aoláin call the ‘consensus generating effect of
emergencies’ and Russett the ‘rally round the Llag effect’154
whereby in times of grave peril, the dynamics of electoral politics
impel even parliamentary oppositions to support the government:
“…it is likely that the emotional effects of emergencies (such as
fear or rage) and the desire to appear patriotic to voters will lead
legislators to support vesting in the government broad and
expansive authorisations and powers and to do so without
delay.”155 The resonance of this observation in the Sri Lankan
context needs no emphasis. The dangers of this psychological and
political effect undermining the expectations of the separation of
powers was seen by Madison early on when he observed that “…an
enthusiastic conLidence of the people in their patriotic leaders,
which stiLled the ordinary diversity of opinions”,156 and argued
that the logic of the US constitution’s system of checks and
balances must be so devised as to give “…those who administer
154
Bruce Russett (1990) Controlling the Sword: The Democratic
Governance of National Security (Cambridge: Harvard UP): pp.34‐38
157
Federalist No. 51 (James Madison) in Rossiter (Ed.) (1961), op cit., p.
319; Tushnet (2005), op cit., p.2674
159 In Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer (1952) 343 US 579 at 653,
Jackson J. observed, “Party loyalties and interests, sometimes more
binding than law, extend [the president’s] effective control into branches
of government other than his own, and he may win, as a political leader,
what he cannot command under the Constitution.”
92
historical considerations, and they in turn shape governance and
political cultures in the exercise of emergency powers. In this
section, we turn to some of the political consequences of
emergencies which in spite of, and in some cases, because of
constitutional frameworks continue to pose serious challenges to
liberal constitutionalist assumptions about the separation
between emergency and normalcy, and commitment to the
protection of human rights and the rule of law during times of
crisis.160
160
Jackson J. also observed that, “…emergency powers tend to kindle
emergencies.”, ibid, at p.650
162
See Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule (2003) ‘Accommodating
Emergencies’ 56 Stanford Law Review 605, at p.607
166
Between 1919 and 1932, Article 48 was invoked more than 250 times:
Rossiter (1948), op cit., pp.37‐60
98
situations, it is not merely the legal transgressions of
constitutional rights that result: it also debases the moral
judgement of society, and devalues notions of justice and fair play
that would otherwise prevail.
All of this is all too familiar in the Sri Lankan experience, where in
the context of ethno‐political conLlict going to the heart of the
State’s legitimacy, the use of emergency powers by the
government has become almost completely ethnicised. Generally,
even if the Sri Lankan State has failed to address the substantive
anomalies at the root of the conLlict and minority grievances, it has
claimed to represent all Sri Lankans regardless of ethnicity in its
counter‐insurgency measures against the LTTE. The broader
political and constitutional dimensions of the matter are beyond
this discussion, but even as the military prosecution of the war has
led to widespread patterns of routine violations, there has also
been the occasional executive act of ethnic discrimination that has
170See
h t t p : / / c p a l a n k a . o r g / r e s e a r c h _ p a p e r s /
Press_Release_on_the_interim_order.pdf; http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/
south_asia/6729555.stm; http://www.alertnet.org/thenews/newsdesk/
IRIN/7f915ea1a45ece47a1199f9a7f30884d.htm; http://www.hrw.org/
reports/2007/srilanka0807/6.htm; http://www.un.org/apps/news/
story.asp?NewsID=22851&Cr=sri&Cr1=lanka; http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/
south_asia/6732961.stm
100
3.2.3 The Concept of Militant Democracy and the Sixth
Amendment
171 Preamble
173 Council for Liberal Democracy (1986) ‘Statement calling for the Repeal
of the Sixth Amendment to the Constitution’ in Chanaka Amaratunga (Ed.)
(1990) Liberalism in Sri Lanka 1981 – 1991: A Documentary Record
(Colombo: Council for Liberal Democracy and Friedrich Naumann
Stiftung): p.132
178The Socialist Reich Party Case (1952) 2 BVerGE 1; The Communist Party
Case (1956) 5 BVerGE 85
179
Refah Partisi v. Turkey (2003) 37 EHHR 1; Paul Harvey (2004) ‘Militant
Democracy and the European Convention on Human Rights’ 29 European
Law Review 407
104
with wide and deep ramiLications in a deeply divided and conLlict‐
affected society. Admittedly, the then government enjoyed an
unusual 5/6th majority in Parliament which allowed it to impose
its will, at will, but in the context of a crisis, this merely eased the
way for an ill thought out and reactionary measure.
105
to the thoughts, feelings, and energies of the people. The
despotism of Augustus prepared the Romans for Tiberius. If the
whole tone of their character had not been prostrated by nearly
two generations of that mild slavery, they would probably have
had spirit enough left to rebel against the more odious one.” 180
More recently, we considered the experience of the Weimar
republic in which the constitutional authority for emergency
powers in Article 48 was used so frequently and extensively that
both ofLicials and public came to regard it as normal, before of
course, that very provision was used by the Nazis to destroy the
constitutional order.
180
John Stuart Mill (1971) Three Essays – On Liberty, Representative
Government, the Subjection of Women (1861) (Oxford: Oxford UP): p.
185
106
used medication in order to experience the same level of relief, so
too with respect to emergency powers…” 181
This ‘getting used to’ effect, for obvious reasons, starts with
government and ofLicialdom. Gross and Ní Aoláin note the
following characteristics of this dynamic: Lirst, “…it [is] easier to
pass new legislation than to examine why it is that the existing
legislation, and the powers granted under it to government and its
agencies, was not sufLicient. The result is a piling up of legislative
measures into a complex state of emergency…”; second,
government and its agents grow accustomed to the convenience of
emergency powers. Once they have experienced the ability to
operate with fewer restraints and limitations they are unlikely to
be willing to give up such freedom.”; third, is “…the use of
emergency and counter‐terrorism legislation for purposes other
than those for which it was originally promulgated.”182
183 Centre
for the Study of Human Rights & the Nadesan Centre (1993)
Review of Emergency Regulations 3 (Colombo: University of Colombo)
108
infringements of critical civil liberties such as the freedom of
expression, many of the Supreme Court’s most important
pronouncements have been concerned with resolving emergency
regulations, or executive action thereunder, inconsistent with
fundamental rights. Without belittling the Supreme Court or its
many important determinations, the point remains that an
important source of law in a common law system, in this respect
the case law of the highest court in the land deciding the reach of
the constitutional bill of rights, has not evolved under normalcy,
but rather, under a normalisation of the exception.
109
CHAPTER IV
STANDARDS GOVERNING STATES OF
EMERGENCY AT INTERNATIONAL LAW AND
PRACTICE
110
4.3. International Human Rights Standards in States of
Emergency under the ICCPR: The Legal Regime of
Derogations
111
The past Live decades – the post World War II, United Nations era –
has seen the development of international human rights law and
practice, both in terms of wide codiLication in binding multilateral
treaties and in the promotion of behavioural standards. These set
out the nature and scope of positive rights and their permitted
restrictions. In this chapter, we examine how international human
rights norms apply within the domestic jurisdiction, especially in
terms of their enforcement mechanisms, and how they seek to
regulate derogations from international obligations to protect
those rights during states of emergency. We do not intend to give
an account of the range of rights available under international
human rights law. Our concern is to see how international human
rights law accommodates states of emergency by allowing, within
set limits, derogations from human rights during crises.
112
Moreover, human rights norms during states of emergency have
also been the subject of several standard setting exercises, notably
the Paris Minimum Standards of Human Rights Norms in a State of
Emergency (Paris Minimum Standards)184 and the Siracusa
Principles on the Limitation and Derogation Provisions in the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (Siracusa
Principles). 185 While these are informal and strictly speaking
legally non‐binding, they enjoy wide acceptance as setting the
international standards on human rights during emergencies and
as interpretive guides to States.
184
Richard B. Lillich (1985) ‘Paris Minimum Standards of Human Rights
Norms in a State of Emergency’, Vol.79, No.4 (October, 1985): pp.
1072‐1081
188
Patrick Birkinshaw (2003) European Public Law (London:
Butterworths): Ch.9
114
such as the Human Rights Committee, the European Court of
Human Rights, and the Inter‐American Commission and Court.
115
interpreting these provisions. Subsequently, we will take up the
body of general principles that govern states of emergency under
international human rights law with the main focus on the ICCPR
and the jurisprudence of the Human Rights Committee, as well as
a description of the ICCPR’s enforcement mechanisms. It should,
however, be remembered that it is not only international human
rights instruments (such as the ICCPR), to which this discussion is
restricted, that establish governing principles in relation to human
rights in crisis contexts. In what is a growing area of human rights
protection, general international and humanitarian law and the
laws of war also establish such principles, extending the
regulatory reach of human rights protection within the laws of
external and internal armed conLlict, and binding States as well as
non‐State actors.
116
of that case in Part II, we discuss the ICCPR framework of
enforcement in some detail later in this chapter.
4.1.2 Derogations
198 Article 4 (2) ICCPR; Article15 (2) ECHR; Article 27 (2) ACHR
199UN Human Rights Committee (2001) General Comment No. 29: States
of Emergency (Article 4), CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.11 (31st August 2001):
para.11; hereinafter General Comment No.29
202The issue has come to a head in the debate about the renewal of the
‘GSP Plus’ tariff beneLits scheme of the European Union for Sri Lanka,
which requires ‘ratiLication and full implementation’ by the beneLiciary
country of 27 international treaties including the ICCPR: see Centre for
Policy Alternatives (2007) ‘Press Release on the Draft Bill Purporting to
enact the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR)’, 3rd
October 2007; Rohan Edrisinha & Asanga Welikala (2008) ‘GSP Plus’
BeneKits: The Need for Constitutional Amendment’ available at http://
www.cpalanka.org/Newspaper_Articles/Article_on_ICCPR.pdf; Rohan
Edrisinha & Asanga Welikala (2008) ‘GSP Plus and Constitutional Reform:
What We Did and Did Not Say’, The Sunday Island, 26th June 2008;
discussion in Chapter 6, infra
123
that it would “…take a State party’s other international obligations
into account when it considers whether the Covenant allows the
State party to derogate from speciLic provisions of the
Covenant.”203
203 General Comment No. 29, para.10; see for section 4.3, infra
124
a member State; (e) that derogation case law of all systems are
substantially concerned with due process rights; and (f) that all
systems are limited in their range of effective and genuinely
responsive remedies.204
Further below, we will deal with the derogations regime under the
ICCPR in some detail.205 However, some preliminary observations
may be made here by way of explication of the general functional
framework of the Committee under the ICCPR and what it can and
cannot do in respect of derogations and states of emergency
within the scope of Article 4 of the ICCPR. It is to be noted that the
Committee’s position under the ICCPR as a supervisory and
enforcement mechanism is relatively weak in comparison to the
European Court of Human Rights and the Inter‐American Court.
We discuss the strengths and weaknesses of the enforcement
framework of the ICCPR in the next section.206 In relation to the
Human Rights Committee, its role is encumbered with several
problems.
207See further discussion on this case and the Supreme Court’s Advisory
Opinion (2008) on the compliance of Sri Lankan law with rights
recognised by the ICCPR in Chapter 6.
126
Within these institutional constraints, therefore, the Committee
has been (a) generally reluctant to gainsay the initial political act
of declaration of an emergency, although it has been far more
robust in reviewing the proportionality of substantive
measures.208 This goes to the heart of the question whether the
right of derogation is the exclusive right of States guaranteed
under international law (b) the Committee has also generally been
unable to address the question of perpetuated emergencies, again
arising out of the weaknesses of the State reporting procedure;
and (c) notwithstanding (a) and (b), the Committee has
demonstrated a willingness to challenge States and review
excessive substantive emergency measures against the ICCPR
standards as interpreted by it.209
On the other hand, the Human Rights Committee has built a solid
reputation for independence, expertise, fairness and impartiality
as a rules‐based and adjudicative decision‐making body, in
contradistinction to most other international bodies which
operate under the dictates and dynamics of international politics
and diplomacy. Ironically, it appears that it is this very positive
feature that makes it unable to exert the kind of political pressure
or harness the media spotlight in the furtherance of human rights
protection within States.
130
of the Secretary General of the United Nations and of States
Parties, are set out in Part IV (Articles 28 – 30) of the ICCPR.212
The several competences of the Committee are to be found in
Articles 40 (State Parties’ reporting obligations and basic
procedure), Articles 41 and 42 (Inter‐State communications and
the role of the Committee including conciliation) and in the First
Optional Protocol (individual communications).213
Under Article 40 (1) and (2), a State Party’s initial report must be
submitted within one year of accession to the Covenant,
describing the measures it has adopted to give effect to the rights
established in the Covenant, and must also include reference to
any constraints in giving effect to same. The Committee has
decided in terms of Article 40 (1) (b) that periodic reports are to
be submitted every Live years by States. In exceptional cases, it
may also call for special reports, and in others, supplemental
reports in order clarify or seek fuller information. The Committee
212
See Javaid Rehman (2002) International Human Rights Law: A
Practical Approach (London: Longman): Ch.4, pp. 83‐84.
213 See Steiner in Alston & Crawford (2000), op cit; Dominic McGoldrick
(1991) The Human Rights Committee (Clarendon; Oxford): Chs.2‐3;
Rosalyn Higgins (1991) ‘United Nations Human Rights Committee’ in
Robert Blackburn & John Taylor (1991) Human Rights for the 1990s
(London: Mansell) p.67; Ineke BoereLijn (1995) ‘Towards a Strong System
of Supervision’ 17 Human Rights Quarterly 766
131
has also issued guidelines regarding the form, content, and
procedure for the submission of these reports.214 In terms of
Article 40 (4), the Committee is required to study the State report
and transmit its reports along with general comments to the State
Party and to ECOSOC. The Committee provides the State Party an
opportunity to introduce its report and answer questions
(including questions relating to follow up measures from previous
reporting cycles) prior to drafting and adopting its views on the
State report.215
It has been pointed out that this approach of the Committee to the
reporting procedure has engendered a more constructive
relationship with State Parties. It seems to have encouraged States
to not only meet their obligations in respect of timely submission,
but has also enhanced the quality and completeness of their
reports, as well as the importance they place in responding to the
Committee’s invitations to present and clarify such reports.
218
Rehman (2002), op cit, pp.88‐89; see also P.R. Ghandhi (1998) The
Human Rights Committee and the Right of Individual Access: Law and
Practice (Aldershot: Ashgate)
134
particularly one that is as convoluted and non‐imperative as this.
It is nonetheless remarkable for being contemplated in the bi‐
polar international context of the 1960s.219 It is hardly surprising
that the mechanism has never been used. Perhaps with the
growing importance of human rights as a principle of
international law and practice, there may be a future role for this
mechanism, but admittedly, even now this is a remote possibility.
220
See esp. Davidson in Conte, Davidson & Burchill (2004), op cit, Ch.1;
Rehman (2002), op cit, pp.92‐101
135
The relevant State Party has an opportunity to respond to the
allegations on both admissibility and merits. It may also inform
the Committee regarding any remedial measures that have been
taken subsequent to the communication. The Committee takes
into account the information given by both the complainant and
the State Party in arriving at its views.
4.2.5 Conclusions
138
treaty‐based international human rights regime applicable to Sri
Lanka. Where necessary, reference will be made to the other
instruments.
223 See for the South African approach: Halton Cheadle & Dennis Davis,
‘Structure of the Bill of Rights’, Dennis Davis, ‘Rights’, Halton Cheadle,
‘Limitation of Rights’ and Nicholas Haysom, ‘States of Emergency’ in Halton
Cheadle, Dennis Davis & Nicholas Haysom (2002) South African
Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights (Durban: Butterworths): Chs.
1,30,31
139
these rights. Derogation involves possible suspension of all
the rights recognised by the treaty, except obviously the non‐
derogable rights, during a state of emergency, subject to the
restraints set out in the derogation clause.
225 Ibid
140
“Article 4
1. In time of public emergency which threatens the life
of the nation and the existence of which is ofLicially
proclaimed, the States Parties to the present
Covenant may take measures derogating from their
obligations under the present Covenant to the extent
strictly required by the exigencies of the situation,
provided that such measures are not inconsistent
with their other obligations under international law
and do not discrimination solely on the ground of
race, colour, sex, language, religion or social origin.
2. No derogation from articles 6, 7, 8 (paragraphs 1 and
2), 11, 15, 16 and 18 may be made under this
provision.
3. Any State Party to the present Covenant availing itself
of the right of derogation shall immediately inform
the other States Parties to the present Covenant,
through the intermediary of the Secretary‐General of
the United Nations, of the provisions from which it
has derogated and of the reasons by which it was
actuated. A further communication shall be made,
through the same intermediary, on the date on which
it terminates such derogation.”
141
rights under any circumstances, and include those of
proportionality, non‐discrimination, and consistency with other
international obligations. The principle of exceptional threat is a
mixture of procedural and substantive requirements. We may now
discuss each of these in turn.
227
Lawless v. Ireland (1960‐1961) 1 Eur.Ct.HR (ser. B) 56 (Commission
Report)
230 para.2
144
and legitimate in the circumstances. On a number of occasions
the Committee has expressed its concern over States parties
that appear to have derogated from rights protected by the
Covenant, or whose domestic law appears to allow such
derogation in situations not covered by article 4.” 231
231 para.3
Article 4 (3) of the ICCPR (as well as the ECHR and the ACHR),
requires States Parties availing themselves of the right of
derogation to inform other States Parties ‘immediately’ through
the UN Secretary General, of (a) rights from which they have
derogated, (b) reasons therefor, and (c) communicate the date on
which the act of derogation is terminated. This gives an indication
of both the timeframe in which the requirement of notiLication
must be met, and also the content of such notiLication.
149
proportionate, in addition to conformity with domestic legal and
constitutional stipulations.
There has been some debate about the legal effect of a failure by a
derogating State to fulLil the requirement of notiLication, in regard
to which there are two different aspects: (a) total failure to submit
a notiLication, and (b) the partial failure to do so (i.e., where the
notice of derogation is incomplete, contains insufLicient
information, or has not been sent within a reasonable time
period.)
240
UN Human Rights Committee (1983), Report of Sri Lanka, CCPR/C/SR.
473 (1983)
241
Sri Lanka (report reviewed on 3rd November 1983; notiLication, 21st
May 1984; see also A/39/40, p.25, para.123
As Oraá explains, “In the drafting of the [ICCPR, the ECHR and the
IACHR] there was unanimity on the necessity of including that
principle in the derogation clause…Even though there was total
agreement on this principle, the problem of establishing which
rights should be made non‐derogable was far from an easy task for
the drafters [of the three treaties]. One of the striking features of
the derogation clause of these treaties is that they contain a
different list of non‐derogable rights…The difLiculty of agreeing on
a concrete list non‐derogable rights is well illustrated in the
travaux préparatoires of the treaties.”244
the ICCPR selection, it also appears that they have not been
applied very consistently or coherently. Thus certain rights which
are fundamental and requiring special protection have been
excluded, whereas others which are not so fundamental and may
not in any case be especially endangered during a state of
emergency, have been included.
247Oraá: p.96 et seq; Questiaux (1982), op cit., p.19; General Comment No.
29, para.11
250 para.11
157
Statute of the International Criminal Court in its
interpretation of ICCPR Article 4)
158
Finally, it is clear from both the textual formulation of Article 4 (1)
as well as General Comment No. 29 that there are three
substantive conditions which must be adhered to by States
seeking to derogate from rights during a state of emergency. These
are the requirements that the derogating measures must only be
‘to the extent strictly required by the exigencies of the
situation’ (i.e., the principle of proportionality), that such
measures must ‘not involve discrimination solely on the ground of
race, colour, sex, language, religion or social origin’ (i.e., the
principle of non‐discrimination), and that the measures are ‘not
inconsistent with…other obligations [of the State] under
international law (i.e., the principle of consistency). Each of these
substantive requirements, being conditions precedent to the
invocation of the derogations clause, must be examined in turn.
159
derogability. Even in times of most serious public
emergencies, States that interfere with the freedom to
manifest one’s religion or belief must justify their actions by
referring to the requirements speciKied in article 18,
paragraph 3. On several occasions the Committee has
expressed its concern about rights that are non‐derogable
according to article 4, paragraph 2, being either derogated
from or under a risk of derogation owing to inadequacies
in the legal regime of the State party.”252
257 Ibid
163
The Human Rights Committee has repeatedly, and without
challenge, afLirmed its competence to review a State Party’s
compliance with the principle of proportionality. In this regard, it
has held that the legitimacy and legality of resorting to derogating
measures is justiLied only in cases where ordinary legislation and
normal executive powers for maintaining law and order are
insufLicient for dealing with the emergency. Moreover, in
consonance with the principle of exceptional threat discussed
before, and the fundamental assumption throughout, that
emergencies are exceptions to normalcy, derogating measures are
justiLied only so long as the emergency lasts. Derogations must
have a direct bearing and relation to the emergency. Thus, for
example, the restriction of political rights in dealing with a natural
disaster will not be regarded as valid. The Human Rights
Committee has striven to assess speciLic measures of derogation
for proportionality and necessity, although the insufLiciency of
detailed information has made this difLicult. It has also attempted
to examine not only the extent of derogating measures (in the
context of the constitutional and legal frameworks of States
Parties), but also how such measures operate in practice.
Therefore, mere reference to abstract legal frameworks would not
be sufLicient; States Parties must also demonstrate the practical
effect of how restrictions of rights under derogation actually
operate. In this regard, the Committee would also examine the
procedural and other safeguards in place to prevent abuses of
human rights, even where a State has (validly) invoked the right of
derogation.
164
limited to the extent strictly required by the exigencies of the
situation. This requirement relates to the duration, geographical
coverage and material scope of the state of emergency and any
measures of derogation resorted to because of the emergency.”258
260 para.5
166
language, religion or social origin), and not on the other grounds
encapsulated in the general prohibition on discrimination found in
Articles 2 (1) and 26. The excluded grounds in the attenuated list
in Article 4 (1) are political or other opinion, national origin,
property, and birth or other status. Secondly, even in relation to
the included grounds, what Article 4 (1) prohibits is
discriminatory derogating measures based solely on those
grounds. Therefore, the derogation clause allows derogating
measures to discriminate even on grounds of race, colour, sex,
language, religion or social origin, provided that the measures are
connected to some other reasonably justiLiable grounds, such as
grave military exigencies which are demonstrably necessary to
overcome the threat posed by the crisis.
263 Ibid
167
The only occasion in which the Human Rights Committee dealt
with an allegation of discrimination through emergency measures
in contravention of the provisions of Article 4 (1) was in
Weinberger v. Uruguay (1978),264 in which the communication
alleged discrimination solely on grounds of political opinion.
However, since the State Party was unable to substantiate an
actual state of emergency in fact or law, and thereby the
circumstances for a valid derogation, the Committee found in
favour of the author of the communication on other grounds
(Article 25) on the basis of normal standards used in peacetime.265
265However, see the position under the ECHR in Ireland v. UK, 2 EHRR 25,
and under the ACHR in the Nicaragua – Miskitos Case, IACHR, p.120
168
Covenant.”266
268 para.9
170
this respect, States parties should duly take into account the
developments within international law as to human rights
standards applicable in emergency situations.”269
269 para.10
171
PART II
172
173
CHAPTER V
174
The framers of the Second Republican Constitution of 1978 clearly
perceived the declaration and the conduct of government in a
state of emergency to be purely political and administrative
matters; primarily the prerogative or right of the executive and to
the extent oversight was contemplated, they vested Parliament
with that responsibility. Whether this was driven purely on
considerations of executive convenience or whether it was
symptomatic of an underlying tendency to authoritarianism is a
moot point.270 More palpable is the fact that those involved in the
making of this particular constitutional scheme shared a political
and legal philosophy that drew copiously from Dicey and Austin:
in other words, imperial‐era British legal doctrines about omni‐
competence, plenary power, strong government, and command‐
theory positivism. This is why perhaps a recent commentator –
with distinct overtones of the Diceyan conception of martial law
and the common law doctrine of necessity – felt able to make the
extraordinary assertion that:
270 See Parliamentary Series No.14 of the Second National State Assembly
(1978) Report of the Select Committee of the National State Assembly
appointed to consider the revision of the Constitution, 22nd June 1978: p.
141; Dissenting Report of the Members of the Sri Lanka Freedom Party: p.
149; Draft Article 149 on Public Security: p.602. See also A.J. Wilson
(1980) The Gaullist System in Asia: The Constitution of Sri Lanka
(1978) (London: Macmillan): pp.54‐56; The ‘architect’ of the 1978
Constitution, President J.R. Jayewardene, Lirst articulated his case for a
presidential executive in December 1966, in a speech to the Ceylon
Association for the Advancement of Science, cited in Wilson (1980), op
cit., p.1.
175
emergency without having to look over its shoulders to
check whether there could arise a need, in the future, to
answer in a court of law for declaring it. But thereafter the
executive power remains answerable to the Supreme
Court for the contents and for the application of the
Regulations it might promulgate under such an
Emergency. Such an arrangement clearly satisLies the
interests of the principal parties. The state and the
citizen.” 271
271
Lakshman Marasinghe (2007) The Evolution of Constitutional
Governance in Sri Lanka (Colombo: Vijitha Yapa): p.273
176
statutory framework is founded on the assumption that
emergencies are the temporary exception to the norm of
constitutional government, in practice what we have seen is that
the fact of protracted and intractable conLlict has made the
exception the norm. Thus, apart from brief periods, emergency
government has become institutionalised and normalised, with
many of the empirical and structural consequences we discussed
in detail in Chapter 3. Moreover, the special regime of anti‐
terrorism powers under the Prevention of Terrorism (Temporary
Provisions) Act is not merely a nomenclatural misnomer; it has
served to negate the fundamental analytical assumption of the
legal accommodation model about the norm and the exception. 272
276
Article 155 (3A) introduced by the Thirteenth Amendment to the
Constitution (1987)
281Joseph Perera v. Attorney General (1992) 1 SLR 199 (decided in March 1987,
eight months before the enactment of the Thirteenth Amendment in November
1987)
282
Radhika Coomaraswamy & Charmaine de los Reyes (2004) ‘Rule by
Emergency: Sri Lanka’s Postcolonial Constitutional Experience’ I.CON, Vol.2, No.2,
272 at p.287
179
Chapter XVIII was predicated on the existing statutory framework
governing public security set out in the PSO as amended from time
to time. The Proclamation bringing Part II of the PSO into
operation (i.e., the declaration of a state of emergency) is at the
discretion of the President under Section 2. Under this provision,
the President may issue such a Proclamation where, in view of the
existence or imminence of a state of public emergency, he is of the
opinion that it is expedient to do so, in the interests of public
security and the preservation of public order or for the
maintenance of supplies and services essential to the life of the
community.283
283 For a discussion of the meaning of the phrases ‘in the interests of’ and
‘public order’, see J.A.L. Cooray (1995) Constitutional and Administrative Law
of Sri Lanka (Colombo: Sumathi): p.752, hereinafter Cooray (1995)
180
empowers Parliament to add to, alter, or revoke any emergency
regulation by resolution.
184
It is a cardinal principle of Sri Lankan criminal law290 and
international human rights law 291 that laws creating criminal
liability must be framed in clear and precise language. The
principle of legality in criminal liability would be infringed if
people cannot easily understand the nature of the offence, and if
they cannot with sufLicient certainty anticipate what conduct
would lead to liability. Under international law, this requirement
must be respected even in emergency law‐making in a crisis
context of armed conLlict.292 Vague, ambiguous and unclear legal
deLinitions clearly contravene international law.293 Vague,
ambiguous or overbroad language may also fall foul of the
constitutional requirements upheld by the Supreme Court, where
emergency regulations operate to restrict or abridge fundamental
rights.294
290
G.L. Peiris (1999) General Principles of Criminal Liability in Sri
Lanka (Colombo: Stamford Lake): Ch.13
291
See e.g. ICCPR Article 4 (2); ECHR Article 15; ACHR Article 27. See also
UN
Human Rights Committee, General Comment No. 29, para.7
292 Ibid
185
mens rea requirement for any act of commission or omission,
central to any conception of serious criminal liability. The Lirst
proviso to Regulation 8, however, provides for exemptions to
engage in approved transactions in certain circumstances such as
the furtherance of peace and the termination of terrorism with the
written permission of the Competent Authority appointed by the
President. This will give the Competent Authority, sweeping
discretionary power over the activities, inter alia, of civil society
organisations including those committed to human rights, national
reconciliation and also the media. Such powers will give the
government excessive control over civil society organisations
which is incompatible with the freedom of expression and
association and other freedoms which are necessary for the
independence and autonomy of such organisations.
The dangers of these regulations are made worse by the fact that
an appeal from the decision of one presidential appointee, the
Competent Authority is to be made to an Appeals Tribunal
consisting entirely of other presidential appointees, the
Secretaries to the Ministries of Defence, Finance, Nation‐Building
and Justice. There are two principled objections to this
arrangement. The Lirst is that it is in breach of international law,
which requires a right of appeal from an administrative decision to
an independent judicial body. Secondly, conferring what amounts
to at least quasi‐judicial powers to persons in the executive branch
of government is a violation of the principle of separation of
powers and is an unconstitutional encroachment into the judicial
sphere. Furthermore, it is fanciful to believe that a tribunal
consisting of Secretaries to Ministries can function as an
independent appeals body.
186
servants and other authorised persons, who act in good faith in
the discharge of their ofLicial duties. This sadly reLlects a wholly
obsolete attitude to the accountability of administrative action,295
especially where fundamental rights are implicated, and could be
used, as so often in the past, to protect members of the police,
armed forces and other persons who may infringe fundamental
rights in the discharge of their duties or under colour of ofLice.
Given the wide ranging powers provided to the State and its
ofLicers under these regulations, the absence of independent
review, the history of abuse of similar draconian legislation,
including the Prevention of Terrorism Act, to stiLle legitimate
democratic activity and political dissent, and the culture of
impunity that has developed in Sri Lanka in recent years in
particular, such a clause could easily become one that promotes
impunity rather than providing for immunity for bona Kide actions.
296See Chapter 3, section 3.1 and Chapter 4, sections 4.3.2 and 4.3.3,
supra
304
See N. Manoharan (2006) Counterterrorism Legislation in Sri Lanka:
Evaluating EfZicacy, Policy Studies 28 (Washington DC: East‐West
Center)
191
question whether executive law‐making under Section 5 of the
PSO was an unconstitutional alienation of the legislative power of
Parliament. Based on the doctrine of delegation, however, this
issue was settled that the PSO and regulations made under it were
valid and that there was nothing in the PSO to suggest that
Parliament had abdicated its legislative power. In Weerasinghe v.
Samarasinghe (1966), Sansoni C.J., held that, “One thing is
essential for the validity of a delegation of [Parliament’s] law‐
making power, and that is that it should not abandon its legal
authority to which it has delegated the power. It must not
transform the executive into a parallel legislature and abdicate its
function.” 305 The two republican constitutions have expressly
provided for emergency rule‐making by the executive, and
therefore, the more common question to be determined by the
courts in respect of impugned regulations or executive and
administrative action nowadays is the question of vires. 306
306Articles 16 (1), 155 (1) and 168 (1) of the 1978 Constitution;
Wickremabandu v. Herath (1990) 2 SLR 348. On the reasoning of the
Supreme Court in Yasapala v. Wickremasinghe (1983) 1 FRD 143, Cooray
has noted that the President’s power of making emergency regulations
under the 1978 constitution is ‘co‐extensive’ with that of Parliament,
except for the limitation as to the period during which emergency
regulations are in force. The ‘limitation’ is that found in Article 155 (3) to
the effect that emergency regulations override law made by Parliament.
Cooray (1995), op cit, p.750, fn.3
192
the detainee) to establish a prima facie case against the good faith
of the Secretary, and that the petitioner must prove the facts
necessary to controvert the matter stated in the order, namely that
the Secretary was of the opinion that it was necessary to make the
detention order for the purpose speciLied in the order itself.307
Hirdaramani v. Ratnavale (1971) and similar cases followed the
(now discredited) reasoning of the majority in Liversidge v.
Anderson (1942)308 where it was held that the court could not
enquire into the grounds for the belief that led to the making of
the order under emergency powers. It was a matter for
administrative discretion, although the court may examine
positive evidence of mala Kide or mistaken identity. As Cooray
observes, the essence of the decision was that, “In regard to a
‘political and non‐triable issue an objective test of reasonableness
could not be applied but only a subjective test.”309 The majority in
Liversidge relied on the dictum of Goddard L.J. in Greene v.
Secretary of State (1942) that, “…where on the return an order or
warrant which is valid on its face is produced, it is for the prisoner
to prove the facts necessary to controvert it.” 310
314
Cooray (1995), op cit, p.758; In re Bracegirdle (1937) 39 NLR 193 at
212
194
Supreme Court was initially restrained in the engagement of its
fundamental rights jurisdiction under Article 126 of the 1978
Constitution, which contemplated a more robust role for the court
in the enforcement of justiciable positive rights against executive
and administrative action.
316Carltona Ltd .v. Commissioners of Works (1943) 2 All ER 560 at 564; see also
Bhagat Singh v. King Emperor (1931) AIR 111 (PC); H.W.R. Wade & C.F. Forsyth
(1994) Administrative Law (7th Ed.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press): p.442 et seq.
195
struck down a detention order after an investigation into the
circumstances of the impugned detention and in Nanayakkara v.
Perera held that reasons for arrest and detention must be given to
the detenu.
322
See Asanga Welikala (2000) ‘The Censorship Case: An Immanent Critique’,
Moot Point, Vol.4 (Colombo: Centre for Policy Alternatives): p.8
198
in force, gives rise to several issues when viewed against the
conceptual requirements of the models of accommodation and
international standards set out in Part I of this book. The general
observations in this section are grouped under the main elements
of a framework of emergency powers in the discussion in Part I:
(a) the deLinition of emergency; (b) the legal framework for the
declaration, extension and termination of an emergency; (c) the
legal effects of a declaration of emergency; and (d) the framework
of institutional checks and balances. These elements, or
conceptual features, of the model of legal accommodation of
emergencies as we saw, inform both the design of constitutional
frameworks for states of democracy in liberal democracies as well
as the derogation framework under the ICCPR. The following
discussion should thus be treated as an exercise in recapitulative
assessment of the Sri Lankan framework in the light of these
conceptual, comparative, international considerations.
199
its underlying policy and motivations.323 However, on the face of
the text, the PSO is a fairly typical piece of legislation of its genre,
which draws on similar, if quondam, British and Commonwealth
legal formulations and structures of the era.
323See Coomaraswamy & de los Reyes (2004), op cit, p.274; A.J. Wilson
(1979) Politics of Sri Lanka, 1947 – 1979 (London: Macmillan): p.119;
Robert N. Kearney (1971) Trade Unions and Politics in Ceylon (USA:
California UP): p.138‐140
200
higher threshold of justiLication as to the existence or imminence
of the actual emergency situation than is required by the Sri
Lankan law.
202
is the principal oversight mechanism in the emergency
framework, having in addition the power under Section 5 (3) of
the PSO to add, alter or revoke any emergency regulation, it may
be expected that the monthly emergency debate would be an
important one, involving opposition and backbench scrutiny of the
government and rigorous ofLicial justiLication of emergency
measures. In practice, however, this is not the case, due perhaps in
equal measure to legislative apathy and, in the context of
communal alienation and conLlict, the fear of antagonising public
opinion. There is also no report of Parliament exercising the
power to amend or revoke emergency regulations, which is a
testament to both the weakness of Parliament’s committee system
and the quality of parliamentarians.
203
extension requires a special majority of 60 per cent, following a
public debate in the legislature.
325 This is dealt with in detail in Chapter 6 and will not be discussed here
204
to the executive.326 These have the effect of overriding the
provisions of ordinary law made by Parliament, but they cannot be
inconsistent with the constitution (except to the extent the
constitution itself permits restrictions to be imposed on
fundamental rights under Article 15). The courts are the
guarantors of ensuring that executive law‐making is kept within
these bounds. Under no circumstances can the constitution be
suspended using emergency powers (or indeed any other means
than the procedure established by the constitution itself), and Sri
Lanka has been fortunate, unlike several regional neighbours, of a
never having experienced a suspension the constitution through
extra‐constitutional means.
207
CHAPTER VI
FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS
6. Fundamental Rights
208
Certain civil and political rights, as are guaranteed by the Sri
Lankan constitution are set out in Chapter III. Sri Lanka’s Lirst
post‐independence constitution did not contain a bill of rights,
apart from a general anti‐discrimination clause in Section 29.
While the First Republican Constitution of 1972 did indeed
contain a bill of fundamental rights, it has generally been accepted
that it was a much weaker framework than that envisaged by the
1978 Constitution. Certain socio‐economic principles are
enunciated in Chapter IV as ‘directive principles of State policy’,
which neither create rights nor are justiciable. Sri Lanka acceded
to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights in 1980
(including the Inter‐State Complaints Procedure), and its First
Optional Protocol (Individual Complaints Procedure) in 1997. In
November 2007, Parliament enacted the International Covenant
on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) Act No.56 of 2007. Despite its
title, however, this law is not aimed at the domestic recognition of
the ICCPR as a whole.
209
Permissible restrictions on these rights are set out in Article 15 for
various purposes including national security, public order,
protection of public health and morality, the protection of the
rights and freedoms of others, the interests of racial and religious
harmony or the national economy, or of meeting the just
requirements of the general welfare of a democratic society. Not
all rights are subject to the same restrictions and Article 15
enumerates the restrictions as may be imposed on discrete rights.
All restrictions must be prescribed by law, and in respect of
restrictions made in the interests of national security and public
order, ‘law’ includes emergency regulations.
210
violations is provided for by way of petition to the Supreme Court
in the exercise of its jurisdiction under Article 126. This is an
exclusive jurisdiction of the Supreme Court and is in the nature of
a discretionary public law remedy.
211
6.2.1 Structure and Content
It is not clear from the text the basis on which the rights selected
for inclusion were chosen, the order in which they appear was
determined, or why certain textual formulations were adopted
when more liberal options were available. The three instruments
of the International Bill of Rights, viz., the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (1948), the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966) had been well‐
established in international law by the time the constitution was
drafted in 1977 – 78, as had other regional instruments such the
European Convention on the Protection of Human Rights and
Fundamental Freedoms (1950). These could have provided useful
guidance in designing the bill of rights, but apart from some
textual evidence that the drafters drew from the UDHR and ICCPR,
it seems as if the design and drafting was informed by political
212
considerations other than a principled pursuit of human rights
protection and promotion. The result is that the bill of rights
resembles a randomly cherry‐picked cluster of inchoate rights that
cannot at the conceptual level amount to a proper bill of rights
compatible with modern expectations. 328
328See for a discussion of the South African Bill of Rights, Halton Cheadle
& Dennis Davis, ‘Structure of the Bill of Rights’ in Halton Cheadle, Dennis
Davis & Nicholas Haysom (2002) South African Constitutional Law: The
Bill of Rights (Durban: Butterworths): Ch.31
213
reLlection of the high importance accorded to fundamental rights
by the constitutional order introduced in 1978.329 However, case
law from the early years of the constitution evinces a general
attitude of difLidence in developing its fundamental rights
jurisdiction, and showed extreme deference to the executive in
circumstances of public emergency. This changed later when the
Supreme Court demonstrated a more aggressive approach to
holding the executive to account and in developing its
fundamental rights jurisprudence.
331 Siriwardene and Others v. Liyanage and Others (1983)2 SLR 164
336 See for e.g., Vivienne Gunawardene v. Perera (1983) 1 SLR 305; Sudath
Silva v. Kodituwakku (1987) 2 SLR 119; Edirisuriya v. Navaratnam (1985)
1 SLR 100; Nanayakkara v. Perera (1985) 2 SLR 375
339See for e.g., Amaratunga v. Sirimal and Others (1993) 1 SLR 264;
Shantha Wijeratne v. Vijitha Perera (2002) 3 SLR 319; Karunatilleke v.
Dissanayake No.1 (1999) 1 SLR 157
341 Lilanthi de Silva v. The Attorney General and Others (2000) 3 SLR 155
218
and exercise, and that in exceptional circumstances, such as states
of emergency, some rights may be require to be temporarily
suspended. From the recognition of these necessities and the
consequent distinction between limitations and derogations Llow
a set of detailed rules that govern the substantive and procedural
dimensions of limitations and derogations, including the
constitutional enumeration of absolutely non‐derogable rights.
Similar to the ICCPR, however, the Sri Lankan bill of rights adopts
the older approach which involves attaching restrictions based on
different justiLications to speciLic rights. Article 15 employs the
term ‘restrictions’ and in its enumeration of permissible
restrictions encompasses both limitations (e.g. for the protection
of the rights of others) and derogations (i.e., restrictions based on
national security). However, the Sri Lankan bill of rights does not
follow the ICCPR in expressly setting out a list of non‐derogable
rights. These are identiLied by implication as described above.
220
The Siracusa Principles set out general interpretative guidelines
on limitation clauses. These include requirements such as that the
scope of a limitation cannot be so wide as to jeopardise the
essence of the right itself and all limitation clauses are to be
interpreted strictly and in favour of the rights at issue (Principles
2 and 3); that every limitation is subject to legal challenge and
remedy against abusive application (Principle 8); that whenever a
limitation is required as ‘necessary,’ the limitation must be (a)
based on one of the grounds justifying the limitations recognised
by the rights conferring instrument itself, (b) responds to a
pressing public or social need, (c) pursues a legitimate aim, and
(d) is proportionate to that aim. Any assessment as to necessity is
to be made on objective considerations (Principle 10); and that in
applying limitations, a State is bound to use no more restrictive
means than are required for the achievement of the purpose of the
limitation, and the burden of justifying limitations lie with the
State (Principles 11 and 12).
221
suppressing opposition aimed at such violation or at perpetuating
repressive practices against its population.”
Sri Lanka acceded to the ICCPR on 11th June 1980 (entry into force
11th September 1980). At the time of accession, it made a
declaration recognising the competence of the treaty body, the
Human Rights Committee, under Article 41 (i.e., the Inter‐State
Complaints Procedure). Sri Lanka made a second declaration and
acceded to the First Optional Protocol (i.e., the Individual
Complaints Procedure) recognising the competence of the
Committee to entertain complaints by individuals subject to its
jurisdiction on 3rd October 1997 (entry into force 3rd January
1998). No other reservations or objections have been entered by
Sri Lanka. The ICCPR is thus part of the international obligations
of Sri Lanka, while controversy prevails as to where it stands in
respect of the First Optional Protocol following the judgment of
the Supreme Court in the case of Singarasa v. Attorney General
(2006).343
Article 4 (1) sets out the objective conditions that must be met,
where in exceptional circumstances a State may derogate from its
obligations under the Covenant. There must be a public
emergency, ofLicially proclaimed, that threatens the life of the
nation. Derogations must only be pursued to the extent strictly
required by the exigencies of the situation, must not be
inconsistent with the State’s other obligations under international
law and cannot undertake prohibited forms of discrimination.
Article 4 (2) lists the non‐derogable rights. Article 4 (3)
establishes the signiLicant obligation, that where a State avails
itself of the right of derogation, it must through the UN Secretary
General inform other States Parties to the Covenant, of the treaty
provisions from which it has derogated and the reasons by which
it was actuated. A similar communication must be made at the
termination of the period of derogation. It will be seen below that
the emergency regulations currently in force (as well as the PTA)
223
considerably diverge from, and in some cases vitiate, the rights
and standards of restrictions established by the ICCPR. Despite
this, however, Sri Lanka has made no communication of
derogation as required by the procedure set out in Article 4 (3).
This is a prima facie violation of a treaty obligation aimed at
international monitoring of human rights within States, and
thereby diminishes an important device of human rights
protection in Sri Lanka.
224
1.4.1 The Singarasa Case and Sri Lanka’s International
Obligations
In the course of the judgment, Silva C.J., speaking for the court,
went on to make some remarkable pronouncements that are of
major signiLicance not only for human rights protection in Sri
Lanka, but which also throws into question the fulLilment of
fundamental international obligations by the Sri Lankan State.
225
The court’s reasoning with regard to the constitutionality of, and
rights available under the ICCPR and the First Optional Protocol
rest on two principal arguments, which are both founded on the
court’s interpretation of sovereignty and the separation of powers
as laid down in Articles 3 and 4 of the constitution. These require
separate analysis.
First, with regard to the ICCPR itself, the Court found that the
executive power of the people as exercised by the President under
Article 33 (f) read with Articles 3 and 4 (b) of the Constitution
empowered the President to represent Sri Lanka abroad and
under customary international law to enter into treaties, the
contents of which must be consistent with the Constitution and
the laws of Sri Lanka. The court found that the accession to the
ICCPR was a valid exercise of executive power and found its
contents consistent with the Constitution of Sri Lanka. Citing the
dualist tradition of Sri Lanka with regard to international law,
however, the court took the position that no enforceable rights as
a matter of domestic law could automatically Llow from the
accession in the absence of enabling legislation enacted by
Parliament to give effect to the ICCPR. The court deemed it
presumable that speciLic legislation to give effect to the ICCPR in
domestic law was not enacted because the government considered
the fundamental rights declared and recognised in the
Constitution as adequate fulLilment of Sri Lanka’s treaty
obligations.
226
further, conferred a right on individuals to address
communications to the Human Rights Committee alleging
violation of Covenant rights. In the view of the court, this was a
purported legislative act by the President in excess of powers,
because the creation of rights could only be done through
legislation passed by Parliament. Under Article 76 read with
Articles 3 and 4 (b) of the Constitution, Parliament cannot alienate
its legislative power, except to make provision for the President to
promulgate emergency regulations. Secondly, the court was of the
view that the declaration of accession to the First Optional
Protocol recognising the competence of the Human Rights
Committee to receive and consider communications from
individuals was a conferment a judicial power (and therefore
unconstitutional alienation of sovereignty) on the Human Rights
Committee, in contravention of Article 3 read Articles 4 (c) and
105 (1) of the Constitution.
227
embrace judicial activism, in not only the enforcement and
protection, but also the active promotion of international human
rights norms capable of bringing the Constitution into modernity
through adjudication and interpretation is unfortunate. This puts
the Supreme Court of Sri Lanka at variance with the progressive
traditions of judicial behaviour that increasingly characterise
superior courts elsewhere in the world, including in Asia and
Africa. More to the point, the Singarasa judgment is directly at
odds with the Human Rights Committee’s views as the
authoritative interpreter of the meaning of the ICCPR.
228
consequent incompatibility. This understanding Llows
directly from the principle contained in Article 27 of the
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, according to
which a State Party ‘may not invoke the provisions of its
internal law as justiLication for its failure to perform a
treaty.’ Although Article 2, paragraph 2, allows States
Parties to give effect to Covenant rights in accordance with
domestic constitutional processes, the same principle
operates so as to prevent States parties from invoking
provisions of the constitutional law or other aspects of
domestic law to justify a failure to perform or give effect to
obligations under the treaty.”
345
Javaid Rehman (2003) International Human Rights Law: A Practical
Approach (London: Longman): Ch.4
230
power to it, whether constitutionally or otherwise, and the
foundation of the Court’s argument in this respect collapses.
231
own judgment in Singarasa reLlects on the commitment of the Sri
Lankan State to human rights and its obligations at international
law in respect of a multilateral treaty, that is a foundation stone of
the international legal system today.
232
a comprehensive schedule annexed hereto was prepared with two
columns. The column on the left gives the particular Article of the
Covenant and the column on the right gives the legislative
compliance within Sri Lanka and the relevant pronouncements
made by the Supreme Court and the other Courts to further
strengthen the guarantee of rights recognised in the Covenant.”
This has not been publicly available, and it is therefore difLicult to
verify its claims in respect of the compliance of Sri Lankan law
with the ICCPR. The Supreme Court dismissed all of the
submissions on seven speciLic matters made by counsel for the
intervenient petitioners, mainly on the ground that many of these
of submission were based on hypotheses. The court came to the
conclusion that “…the legislative measures referred to in the
communication of…the President dated 4.3.2008 and the
provisions of the Constitution and of other law, including the
decisions of the Superior Courts of Sri Lanka give adequate
recognition to the Civil and Political Rights contained in the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and adhere to
the general premise of the Covenant that individuals within the
territory of Sri Lanka derive the beneLit and guarantee of rights
contained in the Covenant” and “that the aforesaid rights
recognised in the Covenant are justiLiable through the medium of
the legal and constitutional process prevailing in Sri Lanka.”
233
legal assistance, interpreter and safeguard against self‐
incrimination; certain rights of the child; and right of access to
State beneLits, respectively), and that these provisions are
formulated in terms substantially and signiLicantly different from
the corresponding provisions of the ICCPR.
234
235
CHAPTER VI
CONCLUSION
236
as respect for human dignity regardless of socially constructed
identities.
237
certain commitments, and then acting on them. The commitments
are with regard to positing human rights and the rule of law as
non‐negotiable values, and the constitutional reform debate in
respect of states of emergency needs to be conducted from this
standpoint.
238
239
TABLE OF CASES
A Publication and a Printing Company v. Trinidad and Tobago,
Communication No. 361.1989
240
Habeas Corpus in Emergency Situations, Advisory Opinion, (1987)
8 Inter‐Am.Ct.HR (ser. A) 33, OEA/ser.L/V/111.17.doc.13 (1987)
Ireland v. UK 2 EHRR 25
Janatha Finance and Investments v. Liyanage (1982) 2 FRD 373
242
The Socialist Reich Party Case (1952) 2 BVerGE 1 (German
Constitutional Court)
243
PROCLAMATIONS
AND EMERGENCY
REGULATIONS
244
Proclamations by the President, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1552/1 of 2 June 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1548/28
of 8 May 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1548/14
of 6 May 2008
Proclamations by the President, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1547/22 of 2 May 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1544/27
of 11 April 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1543/40
of 6 April 2008
Proclamations by the President, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1543/23 of 2 April 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1540/3
of 10 March 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1539/31
of 6 March 2008
Proclamations & c., by the President, Gazette Extraordinary
No. 1538/37 of 2 March 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1535/18
of 8 February 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1535/5
of 6 February 2008
Proclamations by the President Gazette Extraordinary No.
1534/24 of 2 February 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1531/25
of 11 January 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1530/37
of 6 January 2008
Parliament High Security Zone Regulations, No. 8 of 2007,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1529/11 of 26 December 2007
245
Yala National Park Regulation 7 of 2007, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1529/12 of 26 December 2007
Prohibition on Publication and Transmission of Sensitive
Military Information Regulations, No. 6 of 2007, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1521/25 of 1 November 2007
Prohibition on Publication and Transmission of Sensitive
Military Information Regulations, No. 6 of 2007, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1521/3 of 29 October 2007
Prevention and Prohibition of Terrorism and speciLied
Terrorist Activities (Amendment) Regulations, No. 7 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1518/8 of 8 October 2007
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1511/9
of 21 August 2007
Prevention and Prohibition of Terrorism and speciLied
Terrorist Activities (Amendment) Regulations, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1511/9 of 21 August 2007
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1508/08
of 30 July 2008
Restriction on the Procurement of certain items Regulations,
No. 5 of 2007, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1508/8 of 30 July
2007
Katunayake Airport High Security Zone Regulations, No. 4 of
2007, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1504/11 of 4 July 2007
Fuel Storage High Security Zones Regulations 1 of 2007,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1499/24 of 30 May 2007
Appointment of Competent Authority under Regulation 3 of
Fuel Storage High Security Zones Regulations 1 of 2007,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1499/24 of 30 May 2007
Muttur (East)/Sampoor High Security Zone Regulations No. 2
of 2007, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1499/25 of 30 May 2007
Appointment of Competent Authority under Muttur (East)/
Sampoor High Security Zone Regulations No. 2 of 2007,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1499/25 of 30 May 2007
246
Restricted Use of Outboard Motors Regulations No. 8 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1477/24 of 29 December 2006
Appointment of Competent Authority under regulation 15 of
Prevention and Prohibition of Terrorism and SpeciLied
Terrorist Activities (Amendment) Regulations, No. 7 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1475/13 of 13 December 2006
A Proclamation by His Excellency the President of the
Democratic Socialist Republic of Sri Lanka, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1474/5 of 6 December 2006
Prevention and Prohibition of Terrorism and SpeciLied
Terrorist Activities (Amendment) Regulations, No. 7 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1474/5 of 6 December 2006
Restricted Zone Regulations, No. 6 of 2006, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1472/27 of 25 November 2006
Appointment of Competent Authority under Restricted Zone
Regulations, No. 6 of 2006, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1472/27 of 25 November 2006
Port of Colombo Regulations, No. 5 of 2006, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1468/7 of 25 October 2006
Appointment of Competent Authority Port of Colombo
Regulations, No. 5 of 2006, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1468/7
of 25 October 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation,
No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1464/26 of 29
September 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation,
No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1462/8 of 12
September 2006
Appointments by the President of the Commissioner General
of Rehabilitation under Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers
Regulation, No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1462/9
of 12 September 2006
247
Establishment of a new Department of Civil Security, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1462/20 of 13 September 2006 2008
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1458/5
of 15 August 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1458/5 of 15 August 2006
Appointment of Commissioner‐General of Essential Services,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1458/5 of 15 August 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1456/27 of 3 August 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1456/4 of 31 July 2006
Government NotiLications, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1456/4
of 31 July 2008
Fuel Storage High Security Zones Regulations, No. 4 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1455/37 of 28 July 2006
Colombo High Security Zone Regulations, No. 3 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1452/28 of 8 July 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1450/18 of 21 June 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1448/21 of 8 June 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1442/16 of 27 April 2006
Revoking of Temporary Suspension of Regulation No. 2 of
2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1442/13 of 25 April 2006
248
Administration of Local Authorities Regulation, No. 1 of 2006
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1441/8 of 19 April 2006
Establishment of Prohibited Zone Regulations No. 1 of 2006,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1438/8 of 27 March 2006
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
(Amendment), No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No.
1414/22 of 13 October 2005
Temporary Suspension of Regulation No. 2 of 2005, Gazette
Extraordinary No. 1411/14 of 21 September 2005
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1405/14 of 13
August 2005
Proclamation by the President declaring a State of Emergency
throughout Sri Lanka, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1405/13 of
13 August 2005
The Prevention of Terrorism (Temporary Provisions) Act,
Gazette Extraordinary No. 1400/17 of 8 July 2005
High Security Zone (President’s House and its Environs)
Regulations No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1400/17
of 8 July 2005
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1378/23 of 3
February 2005
Emergency Miscellaneous Provisions and Powers Regulation
No. 1 of 2005, Gazette Extraordinary No. 1374/15 of 6
January 2005
249
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Philip Alston & James Crawford (Eds.) (2000) The Future of UN Human
Rights Treaty Monitoring (Cambridge: Cambridge UP)
Charles L. Black, Jr., (1960) The People and the Court: Judicial Review
in a Democracy (New York: Macmillan)
250
Baruch Bracha (2003) ‘Checks and Balances in a Protracted State of
Emergency – The Case of Israel’ 33 Israel Yearbook on Human Rights
123
Capua (1977) ‘Early History of Martial Law in England from the 14th
Century to the Petition of Right’ 36 Cambridge Law Journal 152
Max Cary & Howard H. Scullard (1975) A History of Rome down to the
Reign of Constantine (3rd Ed.) (New York: St. Martin’s Press)
Centre for Policy Alternatives (2007) ‘Press Release on the Draft Bill
Purporting to enact the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights (ICCPR)’, 3rd October 2007
Centre for the Study of Human Rights & Nadesan Centre (1993) Review
of Emergency Regulations 3 (Colombo: University of Colombo)
Halton Cheadle & Dennis Davis, ‘Structure of the Bill of Rights in Halton
Cheadle, Dennis Davis & Nicholas Haysom (2002) South African
Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights (Durban: Butterworths)
Alex Conte, Scott Davidson & Richard Burchill (2004) DeZining Civil
and Political Rights: The Jurisprudence of the United Nations Human
Rights Committee (Aldershot: Ashgate)
251
J.A.L. Cooray (1995) Constitutional and Administrative Law of Sri
Lanka (Colombo: Sumathi Publishers)
Edward S. Corwin (1947) Total War and the Constitution (New York:
Knopf)
Council for Liberal Democracy (1986) ‘Statement calling for the Repeal
of the Sixth Amendment to the Constitution’ in Chanaka Amaratunga
(Ed.) (1990) Liberalism in Sri Lanka 1981 – 1991: A Documentary
Record (Colombo: Council for Liberal Democracy and Friedrich
Naumann Stiftung)
252
George M. Dennison (1974) ‘Martial Law: The Development of a Theory
of Emergency Powers, 1776 – 1861’ 18 American Journal of Legal
History 52
De Silva H.L, P.C., Professor G.H. Peiris, Gomin Dayasiri & Manohara de
Silva P.C. (2006) Interim Report of Sub‐Committee B of the Experts
Panel of the All Party Representative Committee, 11th December 2006
Albert Venn Dicey (1982) Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution (8th Ed.) (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics)
Rohan Edrisinha & Asanga Welikala (2008) ‘GSP Plus’ BeneKits: The
Need for Constitutional Amendment’ available at http://
www.cpalanka.org/Newspaper_Articles/Article_on_ICCPR.pdf
Rohan Edrisinha & Asanga Welikala (2008) ‘GSP Plus and Constitutional
Reform: What We Did and Did Not Say’, The Sunday Island, 26th June
2008
253
European Commission for Democracy through Law (1995) Emergency
Powers (Strasbourg: Council of Europe)
Charles Fairman (1943) The Law of Martial Rule (2nd Ed.) (Chicago:
Callaghan)
John Ferejohn & Pasquale Pasquino (2004) ‘The Law of the Exception: A
Typology of Emergency Powers’ 2 International Journal of
Constitutional Law 210
Gregory H. Fox & Georg Nolte (1996) ‘Fox & Nolte Response’ 37 Harvard
International Law Journal 238
254
Carlo Galli (2000) ‘Carl Schmitt’s Antiliberalism: Its Theoretical and
Historical Sources and its Philosophical and Political Meaning’ 21
Cardozo Law Review 1597
Venelin I. Ganev (1997) ‘Emergency Powers and the New East European
Constitutions’ 45 American Journal of Comparative Law 585
P.R. Ghandhi (1998) The Human Rights Committee and the Right of
Individual Access: Law and Practice (Aldershot: Ashgate)
255
Oren Gross and Fionnuala Ní Aoláin (2006) Law in Times of Crisis:
Emergency Powers in Theory and Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge
UP)
256
W.S. Holdsworth (1902) ‘Martial Law Historically Considered’ 70 Law
Quarterly Review 117
257
K
258
Karl Loewenstein (1937) ‘Militant Democracy and Fundamental Rights’
31 American Political Science Review 417
Karl Popper (1971) The Open Society and its Enemies (5th Ed.)
(Princeton: Princeton UP)
259
Herbert Marx (1970) ‘The Emergency Power and Civil Liberties in
Canada’ 16 MacGill Law Journal 39
260
P
Max Radin (1942) ‘Martial Law and the State of Siege’ 30 California
Law Review 634
Peter Rosenthal (1991) ‘The New Emergencies Act: Four Times the War
Measures Act’ 20 Manitoba Law Journal 563
261
Eugene V. Rostow (1945) ‘The Japanese American Cases – A Disaster’ 54
Yale Law Journal 489
Clinton Rossiter (Ed.) (1961) The Federalist Papers (New York: The
New American Library)
262
Henry J. Steiner, ‘Individual Claims in a World of Massive Violations:
What Role for the Human Rights Committee?’ in Philip Alston & James
Crawford (Eds.) (2000) The Future of UN Human Rights Treaty
Monitoring (Cambridge: Cambridge UP)
263
UN Special Rapporteur on the Independence of Judges and Lawyers
(1998) UN Doc. E/CN.4/1998/39/Add.1
H.W.R. Wade & C.F. Forsyth (1994) Administrative Law (7th Ed.)
(Oxford: Clarendon Press)
Max Weber (1946) ‘Politics as Vocation’ in H.H. Gerth & C. Wright Mills
(Eds. & Trans.) (1946) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (New
York: Oxford UP)
A.J. Wilson (1980) The Gaullist System in Asia: The Constitution of Sri
Lanka (1978) (London: Macmillan)
264
Z
265