SPROJ - Research #1
SPROJ - Research #1
SPROJ - Research #1
SPROJ - Research #1
Haniel Barazarte
Books:
- Conservatism
2
1. Methodology
I find it essential to begin this piece by making certain clarifications regarding Panagiotis
Kondylis' method. First, because it's a method I personally share and will be using in my thesis,
and second, because it explains the Greek’s approach when discussing 'legal universalism.' This
way, I can avoid over-explaining why Kondylis says x or y, saving myself from having to write
even more.
a) Polemology
In Power and Decision, Kondylis refers to his philosophy (which subsumes his methodology) as
prescriptive decisionism (Nietzsche). It's worth discussing the difference between these two
forms of decisionism: the descriptive merely asserts that behind any decision lies a "claim to
power," which, in one way or another, hides beneath "norms"; the prescriptive, on the other hand,
implies a "positive nihilism" in Ernst Jünger’s terms, meaning the often voluntaristic call to
destroy existing norms. Descriptive decisionism, then, seeks to adopt what Weber called
"value-freedom."
decisionism here. However, I will focus on one of its primary aspects that directly relates to my
For Kondylis, life—and therefore ideas—are of an agonistic nature: to think, for our author, is to
think against someone or something and in favor of someone or something. In this way,
friend and enemy to an essential methodological distinction. Kondylis also gives it a Marxist
Therefore, the content and forms of ideas are ultimately determined by the polemical nature of
b) Formalism
I would like to begin the discussion of Kondylis' methodological formalism directly with the
following quote:
Revelation and Authority was not translated inside of the Enlightenment into a positive
Philosophy, 15)
The quote in question is timely, primarily because it highlights the issues involved in reducing a
idea that one or several Enlightenment authors had of Reason. A concrete example would be the
reduction of Enlightened Reason to instrumental reason, which in some measure defined the
Thus, the concept of Enlightened Reason requires "a multi-dimensional apprehension" (23), due
to the variety of its content. For this reason, it is necessary to seek a form—an "ideal type"—that
So, how does this sort of formal unity of Enlightened Reason emerge? The formal unity, as it
could only be, is a polemical formal unity, one that stands in opposition to the "formal unity" of
The idea of Enlightened Reason is thus forged within "Enlightenment’s rehabilitation of the
senses and the sensorial" (18), against the intellectualist asceticism of the Aristotelian-Thomistic
view that elevates the vita speculativa over the vita activa.
The methodological lesson we derive is this: the content of the authors will not be the organizing
principle of our study but rather one more object of knowledge. This material variety must be
consolidated formally through the creation of an ideal type, a type forged in polemic with others.
Kondylis is to Conceptual History what Thomas Kuhn is to the History of Science. For Kondylis,
there is no conceptual continuity between one period and another. The idea of citizenship in
Montesquieu is not the same as the idea of citizenship (in the sense of legal universalism) held
by the French Revolutionaries, and even less so the idea of citizenship upheld by the legal
and Analytic-Combinatory. And each period has its own “social bearers”: aristocracy,
Before discussing Kondylis' conception of legal universalism, it is first necessary to define what
we mean by the term. Although Kondylis never used this term explicitly, it is still possible to
offer a general and minimal definition, based on a reading of his work, of what we commonly
A legal doctrine that emerges in opposition to an estate-based society and assumes the
This minimal definition arises from two key aspects of the concept of legal universalism as it
functions in Kondylis' work: its polemical nature in opposition to the Ancien Régime and,
consequently, its historical character. In a disjunctive sense, it also encompasses both the formal
defense of liberalism and its radical, material (economic) version in 19th-century socialism
(social-democracy). However, for the purposes of this text, we will focus on its
"liberal-bourgeois" version.
The polemical-historical nature of this definition is already present in nuce in Kondylis' book
Montesquieu and the Spirit of the Laws. Here, Kondylis seeks to position the Frenchman as an
intermediary figure between what he calls societas civilis (the Ancien Régime) and bourgeois
liberalism.
Naturally, Kondylis must discuss legal universalism here, and he introduces it precisely to
highlight the discontinuity between what Montesquieu defended and what the French
We understand that the liberal principle of equality under the law presupposes a connection
between two values: political freedom and equality. This unity is realized through "legislation [as
the embodiment of national sovereignty], which was intended to apply to all citizens regardless
In bourgeois liberalism, political freedom also constitutes a "function of the social composition
of a land" (96), standing in opposition to Montesquieu's idea, which situates political freedom
Kondylis does not provide a concrete definition of what political freedom entails, whether in its
liberal sense or its earlier form. Rather than posing a problem, this omission opens the door to a
new line of inquiry. What is clear, however, is that Kondylis associates legal universalism with
the legal principle of legislative sovereignty, a concept we will explore further later on.
b) Historical Context
framework: legal universalism, in this sense, is an expression of the extension of the state
Here, Kondylis adopts the thesis of continuity between absolutism and liberalism: both, in one
way or another, shared the same enemy, namely the "feudal anarchy" with its notion of plural
(Conservatism, 75), in contrast to the new (modern) sovereignty, i.e., a "unified competence that
encompasses and justifies all other individual rights of the sovereign" (Conservatism, 76).
The social bearer of "conservatism" was, then, the aristocrats, who were always in tension with
absolutism, that is, with the expansion of the state apparatus over the estate-based society, which
Kondylis dedicates the early chapters of his book Conservatism to explaining this tension.
Suffice it to say that the aristocracy, despite maintaining their social privileges within absolutism,
always feared the administrative expansion of the state. Undoubtedly, this thesis is worth
exploring further, and I would add that its clearest expression was not so much in the European
theater but rather in the extra-European context, with the reaction (resentment) of Spaniards and
Englishmen in the New World toward the respective modernizing reforms promulgated by their
metropolises.
The social nature behind social universalism must be explored because it determines its genesis,
absolutism; it is enough to read Hobbes's atomic view of society in the political body to confirm
Kondylis sees, as could not be otherwise, the conflict between legal universalism and legal
particularism within the framework of class struggle: legal universalism is tied to the bourgeoisie
(and later to the proletariat in its socialist form), while the defense of legal prerogatives and
privileges is tied to the aristocracy. Undoubtedly, Kondylis recognizes the simplifying nature of
this interpretive framework, and similarly seeks to identify certain fissures in the continuity
8
between ideology and social class. Nevertheless, class struggle remains central in his work when
Here we fully enter the theoretical plane without any direct reference to the social. It’s important
to affirm, though this may sound trivial, that legal universalism did not emerge ex nihilo but is
part of a series of theoretical developments that had been germinating since the 17th century.
In fact, our author establishes a strong connection between legal universalism and the changes
occurring in the field of science during the 17th century. Here, we are referring, among other
understanding of Nature. There are several points to consider: first, the autonomy of Nature in
relation to God and the search for self-regulating laws. Second, how this autonomy is linked
All of these arguments are scattered throughout Kondylis's work: the task here is to synthesize
This is a point that Kondylis repeatedly emphasizes when interpreting "bourgeois thought,"
perhaps because the autonomy of Nature implied a significant shift at the level of the "ontic": the
sciences" in their search for laws within Nature that determine its internal functioning
9
independently of God. It's worth noting that independence does not equate to atheism: rather,
Kondylis then mentions Newton and the importance the Englishman had, particularly regarding
the question of Nature's regulatory laws. However, Kondylis's explanation of Newton is not
exhaustive, but far from being a problem, this presents an opportunity for my own project to
What is important for our purposes is that this autonomy of Nature (in relation to God) led to a
generalized turn toward the immanent. As Kondylis states: "man from now on chooses this world
This shift toward immanence, Kondylis argues, corresponds with the transition in the ethical
sphere toward the vita activa, in contrast with the transcendentalism underlying the ascetic
morality of Christian origin. This turn toward the immanent involved a certain primacy of the
anthropic: man is now also seen from the perspective of his own immanence, in light of
“Main is increasingly looked at as a natural being whose spirit takes root in the
Enlightenment, 18).
The autonomy of nature thus elevated the view of man as a sensory being, opposing the elevation
of the intellective element (over the volitional) in Christian morality. Kondylis associates this
10
shift toward will with the action-centered philosophies characteristic of "Modernity," referencing
figures as varied in content as Nietzsche, Marx, and pragmatism. I won't delve here into the
actual tension between legalistic determinism and voluntarism; it’s enough to state that
voluntarism gained significant momentum following the collapse of the theological mindset
That said, it’s important to note that Kondylis does not adopt a one-dimensional interpretation of
the Enlightenment: Will does not stand in opposition to a cold, instrumental Enlightened Reason.
On the contrary, the elevation of the volitional—of emotions and passions—is a direct result of
the developments born within the heart of the Enlightenment, in opposition to the supremacy of
Kondylis’ book The Decline of the Bourgeois Thought-Form and Life-Form serves as one of the
main theoretical bases for my project, particularly because it addresses “holotic theory”—that is,
the philosophy concerning the relationship between parts and the whole. This focus aligns with
the distinct totalization of society introduced by the French Revolution, which brought about a
Although discussing the mass democratic thought form could be useful for a final chapter, my
primary emphasis here is this: that the synthetic-harmonizing thought form serves as the
“The part exists inside of the whole, and it finds its determination by contributing to the
harmonic completeness and perfectness of the whole, but not by denial of, but by the
development and unfolding of its own individuality”
There are a few key points to emphasize here. First, the individual parts—though they may exist
in a state of difference, or more precisely, discontinuity (and perhaps even contradiction)—must
be harmonized into a whole. In Hegelian terms, this harmonizing could be described as a
speculative moment. Secondly, the parts are perceived in their individuality, which relates to the
question of voluntarism, as individuals will overcome the constraints of tradition. This view is,
of course, opposed to how parts were conceived under the Ancien Régime: parts were not
“atomical” but “anatomical”—guilds, nobles, peasants, etc. Lastly, Kondylis asserts that “things
are thought about and contemplated on the basis of their function.” He does not explore this
claim further, which opens a new line of inquiry for us: how does the idea of function—and, by
extension, substance—relate to revolutionary legal universalism?