The Subject of Knowledge in Collaborative Science
The Subject of Knowledge in Collaborative Science
The Subject of Knowledge in Collaborative Science
Abstract
The epistemic subject of collective scientific knowledge has been a matter of dispute in
recent philosophy of science and epistemology. Following the distributed cognition
framework, both collective-subject accounts (most notably by Knorr-Cetina, in Epistemic
Cultures, Harvard University Press, 1999) as well as no-subject accounts of collective
scientific knowledge (most notably by Giere, Social Epistemology 21:313–320, 2007; in
Carruthers, Stich, Siegal (eds), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University
Press, 2002a) have been offered. Both strategies of accounting for collective knowledge are
problematic from the perspective of mainstream epistemology. Postulating genuinely
collective epistemic subjects is a high-commitment strategy with little clear benefits. On
the other hand, eliminating the epistemic subject radically severs the link between
knowledge and knowers. Most importantly, both strategies lead to the undesirable
outcome that in some cases of scientific knowledge there might be no individual knower
that we can identify. I argue that distributed cognition offers us a fertile framework for
analyzing complex socio-technical processes of contemporary scientific knowledge
production, but scientific knowledge should nonetheless be located in individual knowers.
I distinguish between the production and possession of knowledge, and argue that
collective knowledge is collectively produced knowledge, not collectively possessed
knowledge. I propose an account of non-testimonial, expert scientific knowledge which
allows for collectively produced knowledge to be known by individuals.
Introduction
I will argue that epistemology should be extended in a way that can accommodate
collectively produced knowledge, but that we will have a serious problem if this involves
denying scientific knowledge to individuals. If the members of a large research
collaboration cannot be said to know the collectively produced epistemic outcomes, we
would have to accept the absurd conclusion that either no one or only a supra-individual
entity learns from the most successful research collaborations we have. I will both advance
skepticism against the collective subject view and counter the skepticism towards
individual knowledge in the context of distributed cognition. To this aim, I will argue for
conceiving research collaborations in terms of a cognitive system that produces (not
possesses) knowledge, which can eventually be possessed (though not produced) by
constituent individuals when certain conditions are met. Firstly, the distributed research
process should be reliable in producing scientific evidence and secondly, there should be a
reliable distributed process of criticism for scrutinizing the reliability of the scientific
evidence that is collectively produced. I will analyze both conditions in terms of
distributed first-order and second-order justification, where I put forward a virtue
reliabilist account of justification that is compatible with epistemic dependence. I will
3
conclude that the notion of justified epistemic dependence enables us to attribute
knowledge to individuals when knowledge production is irreducibly social.
The structure of the paper is as follows. In Sect 1 I briefly outline how the
distributed cognition framework has been applied to collaborative research and the
radically divergent accounts of collective knowledge it inspired; namely, the collective
subject account and the no-subject account. In Sect 2 I elaborate on the problems both the
collective-subject account and the no-subject account face. In 2.1 I examine several
examples of the strongly anti-individualist perspective on collective scientific knowledge
which treats groups as genuine epistemic subjects. In 2.2 I examine the eliminativist
strategy which opts for impersonal or subjectless knowledge. In Sect 3 I present my
original account of collectively produced, individually possessed scientific knowledge. In
3.1 I characterize research collaborations as distributed cognitive systems for producing
objective knowledge (i.e., a system of scientific propositions). In 3.2 I present my account
of knowledge that allows for attributing non-testimonial, expert scientific knowledge of
collectively produced epistemic outcomes to individual scientists. In Sect 4 I conclude the
paper with some thoughts on potential further directions that can be taken by a social
epistemology of science that does not investigate collective epistemic subjects.
In thinking about this facility, one might be tempted to ask, who is gathering the
data? From the standpoint of distributed cognition, that is a poorly framed
question. A better description of the situation is to say that the data is being
gathered by a complex cognitive system consisting of the accelerator, detectors,
computers and all the people actively working on the experiment. Understanding
such a complex cognitive system requires more than just enumerating the
components. It requires also understanding the organization of the components.
And […] this includes the social organization.
Giere (2002b) also provides a more general description of distributed cognition (which he
does not intend as a definition): We speak of distributed cognition where two or more
individuals reach a cognitive outcome by combining un-shared individual knowledge and
by interacting with epistemic artifacts. Karin Knorr-Cetina (1999) similarly depicts the
High Energy Physics experiments she observed during her field research stay at CERN in
terms of distributed cognition:
For Knorr-Cetina, the epistemic subject in the case of HEP experiments is the
experiment itself. The whole collaboration, together with the instruments it employs and
all the communicative and practical activities and interactions that weave the people and
the instruments into a unitary entity, presents a novel epistemic subject:
The HEP experiments studied, in continually integrating over themselves (to put it
in mathematical terms), continually assemble the collaboration into a community
reflexively bound together through self-knowledge. The medium that brings this
assemblage about is the conversation a collaboration holds with itself. This
conversation, I maintain, replaces the individual epistemic subject, which is so
prominent in other fields. It construes, and accounts for, a new kind of epistemic
subject, a procurer of knowledge that is collective and dispersed. No individual
knows it all, but within the experiment's conversation with itself, knowledge is
produced (Op. Cit., p. 178).
For Knorr-Cetina the subjectivity of the individual subject is erased, and through
distributed cognition the experiment not only becomes a supra-individual entity (e.g., a
system) but an epistemic subject tout court, as it acquires “a stream of (collective) self-
knowledge” (p. 171-173), “a sort of consciousness” (p. 178).1
1In her portrayal even the instruments become organismic entities by virtue of the way in which researchers
interact with them and are integrated into an organismic whole that is the experiment – which she models
along the lines of Durkheimian collective consciousness. The above quoted paragraph continues: “For those
6
Giere (2002b, 2007), on the other hand, finds such an ascription of collective
subjectivity to research collaborations too much of an ontological commitment. 2 He argues
that we can view certain research collaborations as distributed “cognitive systems”
because they realize a cognitive task,3 not because they exhibit as a whole cognitive
properties that imply agency. Thus, we do not need to postulate distributed cognitive
agents in order to speak about distributed cognitive systems. In particular we do not need
to endow such systems with mental states such as knowledge or (its prerequisite) belief.
Giere maintains, instead, that we should characterize them in a depersonalized or
impersonal way, “so that we would say things like ‘This experiment has shown that. . . .’
or ‘This experiment leads to the conclusion that. . . .’” He envisions that the developing
science of cognition could allow us to redefine cognition as a technical scientific concept
(which does not correlate with mindedness or agency) rather than a folk-psychological
one, and to leave behind the assumption that “if knowledge is being produced, there must
be an epistemic subject, the thing that knows what comes to be known” (2007, p. 316).
2. Why both no-subject and the collective-subject accounts of scientific knowledge are
problematic
who still remember Durkheim (1933: chap. 3), the conversation produces a version of his much-rebuffed
‘conscience collective’.”
2Kitcher (1994) and Thagard (1997) similarly argue against the view that knowledge can possessed by a
collective subject.
3 For taking the “task” as the individuating factor for distributed cognitive systems, see also Magnus, 2007.
4 Knorr-Cetina’s supra-individual subject, the experiment, comprises not only the human members of a
research team but also the technical instruments the research team relies on in producing knowledge.
7
research collaborations such an implication would be mistaken—which again disqualifies
the individual along with any other candidate entity.5
As both Knorr-Cetina and Giere admit, it is clear that some modern forms of
scientific inquiry substantially challenge some of our core epistemic intuitions, starting
with our traditional individualism about knowledge. Distributed cognition provides us
with a framework in which we can reconsider this core individualistic assumption of
epistemology and talk about collective epistemic states and achievements, as it is
increasingly being done in social epistemology (E.g., Gilbert, 1987; 2004; Goldman, 2014;
List and Petit, 2011; Tuomela, 1992; 2004). I maintain, however, that this extension or
revision of traditional epistemology (cf. Palermos and Pritchard, 2013) should not go as far
as postulating collective epistemic subjects or endorsing an exclusively impersonal view of
knowledge. Both these strategies are problematic, as they entail the possibility that no one,
strictly speaking, learns from the most successful research collaborations we have.
However, as I will argue in the third section, collective production of scientific knowledge
does not present us with a forced choice between these two. What we need to
acknowledge is only that some epistemic processes whereby individuals come to acquire
knowledge can require for their realization complex cognitive systems that comprise other
agents and possibly epistemic artifacts.
5 It may be argued neither account necessarily denies individual knowledge but only argues for the
possibility of knowledge without an individual knower. Such a weaker reading would not make a
significant difference for the present argument.
8
how distributed cognition implies distributed mental states. Such an account must go
beyond joint epistemic actions and argue for irreducibly collective mental properties.6
6There are other accounts of collective epistemic states which do not make the ontological commitment in the
second step, such as the joint commitment or acceptance accounts of group belief by Raimo Tuomela (1992,
1995, 2004) and Margaret Gilbert (1987, 2004, 2014).
7 For a similar invocation of Durkheim in regard to group knowledge, see Wray, 2007.
8Actually, this thought example can testify to the no-subject or impersonal knowledge account much better
than it does to the collective-subject account, as there is hardly any reason to presume a collective belief that
q.
9
defined tasks. He extends it to wider science on the basis of the epistemic interdependence
of the scientific community, calling it a single entity.
A core concern here is obviously that Bird’s account is not able to differentiate
between unified cognitive systems and loosely organized epistemic communities (see also
Wray, 2007). For this reason, the framework of distributed cognition loses its conceptual
role in accounting for collective knowledge. Epistemic interdependence in the broad sense
can be said to characterize all human epistemic endeavors and we can clearly not speak of
an epistemic subject who is absolutely autonomous in producing knowledge. In this
regard, he is not in a position even to delineate an actively interacting epistemic
community from its long past contributors, since findings, theories and inventions live
much longer than their originators. This directly leads to the worry that the subject of
scientific knowledge is inflated to the point of meaninglessness.9
For Palermos, collective knowledge that arises in such a distributed cognitive system is a
special kind of group knowledge, one that is not summative. Palermos’ argument contains
the premise that the emergent system is an irreducible group agent, which can also be seen
as a group mind. The reason is that emergent distributed cognitive systems exhibit, for
Palermos, socio-cognitive properties that do not belong to any individual member
(2016b).10 Palermos’ account (2020) is clearly free from the kind of inflation of the
9A similar objection directed at the extended (or distributed) cognition thesis is known as the “cognitive
bloat” (see e.g., Rupert, 2004). I am not concerned with this argument in this paper, since I assume that
distributed cognitive systems can be meaningfully individuated although I argue against attributing them
subjective or agentive states.
10Against the possible objection that the attribution of a mind implies attribution of consciousness, which
groups lack, Palermos (2016b) states that consciousness may not be necessary for mindedness. In particular,
he considers it plausible that groups manifest specific cognitive processes such as memory, decision-making
and knowing. See n.1.
10
epistemic subject, since his criterion of inclusion is continuous and reciprocal interaction.
This criterion, for Palermos, applies to distributed cognitive systems in the same way it
does to individual (biological) cognitive systems. Individual cognitive systems are
characterized by cooperative interactions between the (functionally parsed) constituent
parts and sub-parts of the system (e.g., memory, motor control). Distributed cognitive
systems are organized through the coupling of multiple cognitive systems through
continuous and reciprocal interactions and by virtue of functional equivalence they also
deserve the status of cognitive systems. Further, in case distributed systems can
accomplish the same cognitive functions as biological systems, such as decision-making or
belief-formation, the resulting cognitive/epistemic states are those of the entire system in a
non-summative, irreducible sense. Thus, they can be manifest at the system level even if
no constituent member manifests them.
I think one can convincingly argue that distributed cognitive systems have weakly
emergent collective properties, which do not compel us to invoke collective subjective
states. In the case of research collaborations, the “reliability” or the “efficiency” of the
distributed research process in yielding credible empirical evidence are such weakly
emergent properties which cannot be obtained by simply adding up the corresponding
11 This positive epistemic standing of group beliefs consists, according to Palermos, in their being reliable
and epistemically responsible.
12 Using Carter’s (2020) formulation, this group of virtue epistemological accounts of collective knowledge
endorse a symmetrical conception of aptness, which they apply equally to individual and group apt belief.
11
properties of constituent sub-processes with disregard to the organizational structure of
the system. Similarly, the required complex “expertise” or “competence” for
implementing the collectively agreed research design, data collection and analysis
strategy, and for the manipulation and coordination of the heterogeneous set of scientific
instruments is a property of the research collaboration as a whole. It is perfectly possible
and oftentimes true that no member of a research collaboration individually manifests
this complex competence manifested at the system level. Moreover, the system-level
competence can comprise certain “skills” that no member of the research collaboration
exercises; namely, those that are due the scientific instruments which function as epistemic
artifacts in extending (or replacing) human cognitive capabilities (see e.g., Palermos, 2011).
However, the collective epistemic competence of a research collaboration is not an
irreducible property. There is nothing in this complex competence that cannot be analyzed
in terms of constituent skills and the way in which they are organized and coordinated (cf.
Carter, 2020;13 Pino, 202114). As Kallestrup similarly maintains, “a group’s innermost
competence is reducible to a summation of innermost competences of its individual
members and their manner of arrangement within the group,” hence, “novel competences
of groups do not spring into existence or mysteriously emerge when conjoining existing
individual ones” (2016, p. 10).15 No single member of a research collaboration manifests
13 Carter maintains that not only the aptness of group beliefs but also group competences are genuinely or
irreducibly collective. His argument is based on the case of so-called Mandevillian intelligence; i.e., “some
dispositions that are unreliable and thereby are not individual-level competences can […] lead to knowledge
conducive dispositions at the collective level” (2020, p.24). There is one minor and one major problem with
this argument. The minor one is that the case for Mandevillian intelligence (see Smart, 2018) lacks convincing
real-world examples of collaborative research and rests largely on computer simulations. For this reason, its
external validity remains to be explored. The major one is that the concept, assuming that it has some
external validity, is applicable to loosely organized scientific communities rather than research
collaborations. Research collaborations have clear cognitive goals and research strategies to achieve them,
both of which are often set in advance. Thus, they do not give the individual researchers sufficient elbow
room to engage in “deviant” epistemic behaviors which would be incompatible with the collective aims. We
can see this more clearly if we take some applications of the idea to scientific inquiry, such as Zollman’s
(2010), who argues that individuals who are intellectually dogmatic can possibly bring about epistemic
benefits at the collective level by exploring areas of the “epistemic landscape” that would be left uncharted
by those who are motivated by “truth.” While such independent exploration can take place in a loosely
organized scientific community such as a research field, it is unrealistic to expect it in a research
collaboration.
14 Pino (2021) defends that group epistemic competence should be seen as an irreducible property, as “group
normative status that guides towards knowledge.” However, his argument rests on an anti-intellectual
conception of group know-how. Research collaborations are typically much more fitted for an intellectualist
interpretation, according to which a “group is guided by explicit norms that result from the member’s joint
acceptance.”
15 Kallestrup conjoins this deflationist account of group competence, however, with a non-deflationist
account of group knowledge on the basis of group apt belief, which I reject as I see belief as an unfit category
12
fully the complex competence that we see at the level of the distributed cognitive system,
but the latter consists in a particular organization of various individual competences.
to describe the collective epistemic output of research collaborations. I elaborate on this in the rest of the
paper.
16 Unlike subjecthood, I have no objection to the application of the concept of collective accountability to
research collaborations. Collectives can sensibly be treated as agents for specific purposes, such as
attributing due credit or blame when they make assertions in the form of publications or public
announcements, similar to the category of juridical persons in law. But it is important to note that when we
treat groups as agents who are subject to praise and blame, a strongly social view of knowledge is
particularly problematic. As Lackey (2014) maintains, when a group knows that p without any individual
member knowing that p, then it will be epistemically irrational for the group to act on p. Since a public
assertion (e.g., publication) is an action, even if we grant strongly emergent epistemic states such as belief or
knowledge that p to a research collaboration, it would be epistemically irrational for the collaboration to
assert that p—which would undermine its purpose.
17 I should note that Palermos (2020) does not premise his argument on the metaphysics of collective belief.
His focus is on the justificatory properties of processes of belief-formation rather than beliefs themselves.
Nonetheless, he treats distributed research processes as processes of belief-formation, which I think is not
necessary. See also my next note.
13
sense, which does not imply genuinely collective mental states.18 Beliefs are generally
considered to be automatic or involuntary (Hakli, 2006). However, in these and similar
cases in science the goal (e.g., investigating whether p) is typically determined beforehand
in panels and committees, and the results do not automatically turn into epistemic outputs
as the collaborations still have to decide whether to make the findings public or examine
them further. Moreover, a collaboration may always revise the conclusions drawn on the
basis of the findings or decide to retract a publication upon finding a mistake in the
calculations. Thus, while the epistemic output of a research collaboration, typically a
publication or public announcement, can be regarded as involving a propositional attitude
for certain intends and purposes, such as attributing due credit or blame, such
propositional attitudes are better characterized as acceptances and assertions rather than
beliefs (see also Hakli, 2007; Wray, 2001). Consequently, the distributed cognition
framework is pertinent for conceiving how research collaborations realize the cognitive
task of evidence-generation, but we do not have sufficient reason to regard collective
research processes as processes of belief-formation (cf. Carter, 2020).
18 A research collaboration can be said to summatively believe that p when most or all collaboration
members believe that p (see Quinton, 1976). The summative interpretation of group belief may still be
difficult to apply to most research collaborations, because it is perfectly possible that a collaboration refrains
from publicly affirming that p (for instance due to high epistemic or other kinds of risks involved) while all
collaboration members believe that p. A notion of group acceptance can thus be more suitable in most cases.
For accounts of group acceptance, see Hakli (2007), Wray (2001).
19 Similarly to how cognition has largely been de-psychologized in turning into a cognitive scientific concept.
There are also widely acclaimed proposals for de-psychologizing the concept of mind. See “extended mind,”
Clark & Chalmers, 1998.
14
level epistemic properties as being qualitatively distinct from individual ones, because
there are properties that can be exhibited by social organizations and not by individuals
(no matter with or without subjective states) and vice versa. I will come back to this point
in the last section of the paper.
20 Palermos’ motivation for postulating epistemic group agents, as he explicitly states, is to avoid an
impersonal construal of collective knowledge as proposed by Giere (2020, pp. 117). As I argue in the next
section, I agree with him that such a position “significantly departs from mainstream epistemology, which has
always assumed that knowledge is knowledge of a subject S.” However, his proposal (or any other similarly
anti-individualist proposal) equally departs from mainstream epistemology for its rejection of its individualist
framework) and is not necessary to avoid the impersonal knowledge view. Moreover, I believe that
“knowledge without an individual subject” does not fare much better in terms of desirability than
“knowledge without a subject.”
21 For further epistemological problems with this conclusion, see Lackey, 2014.
22 I have to note that Hutchins himself is more sympathetic to the idea of a distributed mind than I am.
15
scientific propositions, and I doubt that it is an appealing conclusion to say that some
scientific propositions are not known by anyone but a supra-individual entity.
To turn to the no-subject account, we can admit that conceiving scientific knowledge as
impersonal knowledge, or knowledge without a subject has some conceptual advantages
and a certain appeal. Scientific knowledge, arguably unlike mundane knowledge-that and
knowledge-how, is at a fundamental level a system of statements that are interwoven via
logical operations and methodological rules. In this respect, scientific knowledge can be
regarded as “objective knowledge” in Popper’s sense (1968) in contradistinction to
“subjective knowledge” which is a mental phenomenon—specifically, a form of belief:23
Although Giere does not specify what he means by impersonal knowledge beyond
suggesting that we reformulate knowledge attribution statements in passive form, his
account can lend itself to be interpreted in a way quite similar to Popper’s notion of
objective knowledge (see esp. Giere, 2007). However, the concept of objective knowledge
lacks any reference to acts of thinking and practices of inquiry. For this reason, it does not
tell us by itself anything about the processes of scientific knowledge production, which
establish the empirical justification for the targeted system of statements, or where this
kind of knowledge resides—in individual minds, groups of minds, or in books, articles,
databases? It merely refers to the outcome of an epistemic process, which in turn can be
regarded as mental content as well as a material system of external signs. Thus, the
concept of objective knowledge does not imply any commitment to any epistemic subject
either in its production or its possession. Consequently, we still have to ask the question of
what exactly is collective in collective scientific knowledge, to which we can in principle
give two answers: We can say that it is collectively produced knowledge or that it is
23For a similar point, see Faulkner, 2018. Faulkner further remarks that Popper’s distinction between
objective and subjective knowledge can be likened to the distinction between the justification of a
proposition and the justification of a belief, which does not have the ontological commitment to a third
world of intelligibles as does Popper’s.
16
collectively possessed knowledge (or both). The way Giere analyzes research collaborations
through the concept of distributed cognition leads us to the first option: Research
collaborations produce objective knowledge (e.g., a scientific finding) by realizing
collectively the complex cognitive processes that are required for its establishment, where
these processes involve combining various kinds of background knowledge (i.e.,
expertise), interacting with various scientific instruments (i.e., epistemic artifacts), and
organizing various cognitive activities into a coherent procedure (e.g., analyzing data,
drawing inferences, comparing calculations).
While scientific knowledge is in one respect clearly objective knowledge, which can
“reside” in systems of material, external signs (e.g., printed in books), it would be a far-
fetched conclusion to say that it can reside solely in this manner. Can we say that it will still
be known that the universe is expanding even if the world enters another dark age, and
nobody is left who understands physical cosmology? It is reasonable to say, with Popper
(1968), that the following two scenarios would not be the same: There is no living person
who has sufficient knowledge in physical cosmology, but (i) all scientific publications are
preserved in libraries, or (ii) all scientific publications are also destroyed. In the first case it
is highly probable that one day some people who will have trained themselves in physical
cosmology using the materials in the libraries will read the relevant publications and be
able to learn that the universe is expanding. Nevertheless, we can say without much
hesitation that until that happens it would not be known that the universe is expanding.
Thus, it is difficult to say that objective knowledge can exist without furnishing the content
of subjective knowledge.
17
The no-subject account of collectively produced knowledge leads us, just like the
collective subject account, to the absurd possibility that nobody comes to know what is
established in some of the most successful cases of scientific research, such as the empirical
confirmation of the Higgs boson. I think a much more commonsensical position is to say
that objective knowledge implies subjective knowledge. Tuomela (2004) also hints at such
an implication by saying that “such knowledge is not an abstract entity floating around in
some kind of Platonic ‘third world’. Rather it is knowledge that some actual agent or
agents actually have or have had as contents of their appropriate mental states.” Thus, we
should be able to say that research collaborations produce knowledge in a distributed
manner, but it is the individual scientists that come to know the outcomes of the
distributed cognitive process. Giere actually has a suggestion in a similar direction, though
he does not specify it in a way that would satisfy the epistemologist. He remarks that it is
the individual scientists who evaluate the outcomes and draw conclusions on the basis of
the experiments, and indirectly the lay person through (a chain of) testimony. He
maintains that while this kind of knowledge cannot be produced by individuals, the final
result can be known by individuals in the ordinary sense of the term (2002b, p. 643).
Although Giere’s suggestion is completely in line with one of my two main points, namely
that individuals can come to know collectively produced knowledge, he takes lightly the
challenge posed by distributed knowledge production for epistemology. Giere does not
offer any specification for how the scientists can be said to know the final results of
collaborative experiments, and testimonial knowledge (which he ascribes to all others who
learn about the results) is already not part of the challenge. The individual scientist does
not come to know collectively produced knowledge in any “ordinary” sense of the term.
Let me first explicate the challenge in more detail, and then provide a suggestion for how
to meet it.
24See also Palermos, 2016a. Palermos formulates epistemic autonomy in terms of autonomous possession of
justification.
19
3. A third way: Collectively produced, individually known
The most parsimonious and plausible way to save both subjective knowledge of scientific
propositions and the premise that the proper epistemic subject is the individual goes
through reconsidering the requirement for epistemic autonomy and updating our view of
knowledge to accommodate epistemic dependence. We can then be in a position to
formulate an alternative account of collective scientific knowledge by conceiving research
collaborations as distributed cognitive systems that produce (not possess) knowledge
(section 3.1), which can eventually be possessed (though not produced) by constituent
individuals when certain conditions are met (section 3.2).
In research collaborations the “output” is not a collective mental state such as belief but a
system of scientific propositions (i.e., a scientific claim) which stand in inferential relations
to the reported data given the documented methodological procedures.25 We can more
particularly say that the distributed cognitive process is one of evidence-generation in
support of collectively made assertions. Thus, as far as we see the product as
“knowledge,” it is not knowledge in the subjective sense but only in the objective, non-
mental sense.26
25Cf. Vaesen (2011), who argues that if one rejects distributed knowledge, then the only way to apply the
distributed cognition framework to science is endorse a deflationary view and regard the proper “output” of
distributed cognitive systems in science as information or data. However, this alternative ignores that
research collaborations typically put forward a system of scientific statements, not merely the empirical
results of the research. On this basis, they make collective assertions (e.g., scientific publications) for which
they can be held accountable. If, on the other hand, a distributed cognitive system was to merely produce
data, we would have little reason to regard it as anything else than a giant socio-technical data collector.
26According to Palermos (2020), in the case of epistemic collaborations, the collective cognitive property is
the resulting beliefs’ positive epistemic standing. But we do not have to accept that “positive epistemic
standing” implies a collective agent, since it is not even a cognitive property. For instance, a high “degree of
corroboration” of a scientific claim can ground positive epistemic standing, although it is an objective,
formal property.
20
argued, the research process as a whole is not a mental, agentive or subjective activity like
belief formation, but a process of knowledge production in the objective sense or, still
more clearly, one of evidence-generation.
27 I.e., to a degree that meets the evidential standards of the scientific community or the research field.
21
distributed higher-order regulative mechanism, which we can call the distributed process of
criticism. The distributed research process and the distributed process of criticism together
constitute the epistemic performance of the research collaboration. Thus, the epistemic
performance of a research collaboration is distributed, while this distributed performance
has a distinct output; namely, first-order and higher-order evidence in support of a
scientific claim. This output constitutes what we referred as objective knowledge.
Following Sosa’s (2007, 2009, 2010, 2011, 2015) twofold distinction between animal
and reflective knowledge, we can conceive scientific knowledge of the expert as a species
of reflective knowledge; that is, a case of knowledge which not only implies that one
reaches true beliefs through the exercise of reliable cognitive skills or abilities (i.e.,
epistemic competence), but also that one has a positive judgment regarding the reliability
of the skills or abilities in question. In order to attain reflective knowledge, this judgment
should also manifest competence; namely, a meta-competence for evaluating the reliability
of one’s epistemic performance (Sosa, 2010; 2011). In other words, animal knowledge can
enjoy merely first-order justification, while reflective knowledge requires both first-order
and second-order justification. Generally speaking, while epistemic support for the
proposition p constitutes first-order justification, epistemic support for the reliability of the
processes whereby one’s belief that p is formed constitutes second-order justification.
Evidence for the proper functioning of my visual system constitutes second-order
justification for my perceptual belief that p, good calibration of the astronomer’s telescope
constitutes second-order justification for the accuracy of the measurements made with it,
or my reasons for believing that A’s testimony that p is based on A’s knowledge that p
constitute second-order justification for p.
I believe that the force of the collective-subject argument rests on the implicit
intuition that epistemic dependence is not compatible with knowledge.29 Strong anti-
individualist perspectives on collective knowledge, such as those of Bird and Palermos,
28There is no need to dwell on the possibility of there being no candidate for expert scientific knowledge in
the research collaboration, as it would fit only an impersonal, objective knowledge account.
29For a similar interpretation, see Pritchard (2015).
23
arguably still conceive epistemic justification in traditional individualistic terms. They
seem to assume, namely, that attributing a belief the status of knowledge, or any other
valuable epistemic standing requires that the processes of justification that underly or
support the belief should be autonomous. In other words, they should be the primary
target of epistemic credit or blame. Since no individual scientist in a research collaboration
is not primarily creditable with the success of the distributed research process, there
should be a collective subject or agent who is thus creditable. Thus, epistemic dependence
will lead us to postulate collective subjects only if we assume that knowledge requires
sufficient justification on the basis of autonomous cognitive agency.
Sosa already leaves the door open for knowledge-enabling epistemic dependence by
saying that knowledge does not require that the relevant epistemic competence is
exclusively seated in the individual (2007, p. 97; 2011, p. 87-88). Sosa’s account allows for
the case that a subject A comes to know that p through the exercise of a complex social
competence that is partially seated in A. A similar formulation of weak epistemic anti-
individualism can also be found in an earlier work by Palermos (2015), where he argues
24
that in certain cases knowledge can be creditable to social factors as well as to the
individual.
In the following I will go into the knowledge-enabling external factors and the
weak cognitive ability condition with respect to distributed cognitive systems in science,
which in conjunction give us an account of epistemically dependent expert scientific
knowledge.
3.2.1 First-order justification and reliability of distributed research processes
The reliability of a distributed research process implies that the individual pieces of
information (including data, results, other testimony) contributed by the members of the
collaboration are true sufficiently often and manifest suitable kinds of scientific expertise,
and they cohere into a unified body of scientific evidence necessary for asserting the
scientific claim put forward by the collaboration. In order to achieve this, (i) the
organization of the distributed cognitive system should realize an efficient division of
scientific labor and reliable flow of information, and (ii) the research process should
manifest theoretical, methodological and experimental virtues such as valid inferential
connections between theory, hypotheses and data, good research design, and proper
25
choice and application of data analysis tools. The former (i.e., efficient division of scientific
labor and reliable flow of information) pertain to the more general or constitutional
properties of the distributed cognitive system that enable it to investigate certain kinds of
research questions.30 They give us the general epistemic competence of the distributed
cognitive system as a whole to produce epistemically valuable outputs, such as true
empirical propositions, in a certain field. In many research collaborations this general
competence also comprises well-calibrated and suitable scientific-technical infrastructure.
The latter (i.e., theoretical, methodological and experimental virtues) are the kind of
properties one expects to see in the methodology section of a scientific publication and
pertain to the particular research process that sets and implements a specific research plan.
These constitute the manifestation of the general epistemic competence of the distributed
cognitive system in the realization of its particular cognitive goal. The appropriate
manifestation of the epistemic competence of the distributed cognitive system is a
substantial determinant of the evidential quality of the research outputs and the extent of
empirical support they confer to the scientific propositions asserted by the research
collaboration. In the case of epistemic failure, such as false or highly uninformative
empirical findings, both the general epistemic competence of the research collaboration
(e.g., lacking sufficient statistical expertise or employing unreliable scientific instruments)
and its manifestation (e.g., flows in the data collection strategy) can be found responsible
for the failure.
Together with the condition of a basic cognitive access to the research outcomes,
this system-level or distributed epistemic competence and its appropriate manifestation
constitute complete first-order justification for affirming the (set of) scientific
proposition(s) put forward by a research collaboration.
30Itis possible to draw an analogy here to Hardwig’s (1991) analysis of trust in a testifier in terms of trust in
the epistemic and moral character of the testifier. The epistemic character of the testifier can be replaced by
the efficient division of scientific labor in a research collaboration, and the moral character can be replaced
by successful (i.e., sufficiently free from error and noise) internal communication. However, instead of trust I
prefer to speak of justification, in the reliabilist sense, since a research collaboration has to plan, implement
and constantly monitor the performance of its epistemic and social organization.
26
3.2.2 Distributed second-order justification and reliability of criticism
The objective reliability of the research process, namely the epistemic competence of the
distributed cognitive system31 to produce objective knowledge is only a necessary condition
for acquiring subjective scientific knowledge through reliance on the distributed research
process. A further requirement is that one can positively evaluate the epistemic
competence of the distributed cognitive system and its successful exercise, hence the
reliability of the distributed research process. This evaluation gives us second-order
justification for affirming the (set of) scientific proposition(s) put forward by a research
collaboration. In the scientific context, second-order justification concerns all assessments
of reliability regarding the data, methods, instruments, or the track-record of other experts
as informants. The whole body of such assessments, which we called the process of
criticism, constitute second-order justification that the resulting (set of) scientific
proposition(s) are the outcome of a reliable process of scientific justification. In research
collaborations the process of criticism is necessarily distributed, because the total higher
order evidence is a highly heterogeneous set in regard to the expertise required to
establish it.
31WhileI extend Sosa’s notion of epistemic virtue (i.e., competence or reliable skill) to distributed cognitive
systems, I do not extend either of his two levels or grades of knowledge beyond the individual agentive
components of the system (cf. Carter, 2020; Kallestrup, 2016; Palermos, 2020).
27
CMS) as well as vertically organized review processes realized by nested work groups,
panels and committees. Together with the high transparency and ongoing record-keeping
of all aspects of the research process, the distributed process of criticism gives the
collaboration members second-order justification to affirm the findings and conclusions.
Individual members of a collaboration do not have to scrutinize all aspects of the research
process when this task of scientific scrutiny or criticism can be realized as a reliable
distributed process.
The reliability of the distributed research process and the reliability of the
distributed process of criticism together co-determine whether the affirmation of an
individual researcher of the scientific proposition(s) put forward by the collaboration (if
true) counts as knowledge. In Sosa’s (2011) terms, the proper explanation of the epistemic
success of an individual researcher’s judgment that p features the epistemic competence of
the distributed cognitive system for empirically investigating whether p, and its meta-
competence for evaluating the reliability of this empirical investigation, both of which are
partially seated in the individual researcher.
32 In Sosa’s (2015) terms, this would amount to a fully apt epistemic performance.
30
Conceiving collective scientific knowledge as collectively produced objective
knowledge allows us to accommodate truly distributed cognitive processes of scientific
justification, and the concept of socially extended knowledge allows us to retain the
commonsensical intuition that objective knowledge implies subjective knowledge. Thus,
collective scientific knowledge fruitfully prompts us to reconsider processes of scientific
justification without necessarily leading to a dilemma regarding its epistemic subject.
The account I presented may be said to rule out collective knowledge in an irreducible or
strong sense. But such a conclusion does not radically shrink the subject matter of a
collective epistemology of science. While I defended here a rather conservative view of the
epistemic subject in collaborative research, there is a plethora of directly related issues on
which a break with the tradition opens novel, fertile avenues of thought.
I believe that a collective epistemology of science will be the most fruitful when it
investigates how collectives qualitatively differ from individuals rather than how they
resemble individuals. Such an epistemological investigation cannot be done with the
notions crafted originally for individualist epistemology. If we once more take virtue
epistemology as an example, a collective virtue epistemology of science can make a
substantial contribution by investigating how individual, group and scientific community
level epistemic virtues differ, and how an epistemic virtue at one level may complement,
contribute to, or hinder the realization of one at another level. Some examples of
community-level (or epistemic system-level, see Goldman, 2011) epistemic virtues can be
cognitive diversity (Kitcher, 1993), organized skepticism (Merton, 1973), openness
(Vicente-Saez, R., & Martinez-Fuentes, C., 2018) or communalism (Merton, 1973), none of
which are sufficiently meaningful properties at the individual level. On the other hand,
scientific groups and communities cannot manifest epistemic virtues such as intelligence,
open-mindedness, scientific integrity, inquisitiveness or intellectual humility—except
metaphorically. A multi-level approach can also greatly benefit the study of epistemic
vices in the scientific context. To illustrate, scientific misconduct such as data fabrication or
questionable research practices such as data dredging and selective reporting of results or
studies may arise not only due to individual factors such as lack of scientific integrity but
also due to factors that belong to the structure of the scientific community, for instance
through publication bias (Sterling, 1959; Sutton, 2009) or misaligned incentives (Heesen,
2018). Thus, I think that collective epistemology of science would do better if it
complements individual epistemology rather than modelling itself on it, and such a
collective epistemology of science can do without collective epistemic subjects.
32
References
Bird, A. (2014). When Is There a Group that Knows? Distributed Cognition, Scientific
Knowledge, and the Social Epistemic Subject. In J. Lackey (Ed.), Essays in Collective
Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (1996). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. MIT Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Gilbert, M. (2013). Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World. Oxford University
Press.
Raul Hakli. (2007). On the Possibility of Group Knowledge without Belief, Social Epistemol-
ogy, 21:3, 249-266. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691720701685581
33
Hakli, Raul. (2006). Group Beliefs and the Distinction Between Belief and Acceptance.
Cognitive Systems Research, 7 (2-3), 286–97.
Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(12), 693-708.
Heesen, R. (2018). Why the reward structure of science makes reproducibility problems
inevitable. The Journal of Philosophy, 115(12), 661-674.
https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20181151239
Huebner, B., & Bright, L. K. (2020). Collective responsibility and fraud in scientific
communities. The Routledge Handbook of Collective Responsibility, 358.
https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12034
List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate
Palermos, O. (2016a). Spreading the Credit: Virtue Reliabilism and Weak Epistemic Anti-
Individualism. Erkenntnis, 81, 305–334. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9741-2
Palermos, O. (2016b). The Dynamics of Group Cognition. Minds & Machines, 26, 409–440.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-016-9402-5
Palermos, O., & Pritchard, D. (2013). Extended Knowledge and Social Epistemology. Social
Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2(8),105-120.
Pritchard, D. (2010). Cognitive ability and the extended cognition thesis. Synthese, 175, 133-
151. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9738-y
Quinton, A. (1976). Social objects. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 76, 1–27.
Sterling, T. (1959). Publication decisions and their possible effects on inferences drawn
from tests of significance−or vice versa. Journal of the American Statistical Association,
54(285), 30-34.
Sutton, A. J. (2009). Publication bias. The handbook of research synthesis and meta-analysis, 2,
435-452.
Tuomela, R. (1995). The Importance of Us: A Philosophical Study of Basic Social Notions.
Stanford University Press.
Vicente-Saez, R., & Martinez-Fuentes, C. (2018). Open Science now: A systematic literature
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbusres.2017.12.043
Winsberg, E., Huebner, B., & Kukla, R. (2014). Accountability and values in radically
collaborative research, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 46, 16-23.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2013.11.007.
Wray, K. B. (2007). Who has Scientific Knowledge? Social Epistemology, 21(3), 337–347.