Chapter 1 P 2
Chapter 1 P 2
Chapter 1 P 2
Copyright © McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education.
1
Summary
Predicate Logic (First-Order Logic (FOL), Predicate
Calculus)
The Language of Quantifiers
Logical Equivalences
Nested Quantifiers
Translation from Predicate Logic to English
Translation from English to Predicate Logic
2
Section 1.4
3
Section Summary
Predicates
Variables
Quantifiers
Universal Quantifier
Existential Quantifier
Negating Quantifiers
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
Translating English to Logic
Logic Programming (optional)
4
Propositional Logic Not Enough
If we have:
“All men are mortal.”
“Socrates is a man.”
Does it follow that “Socrates is mortal?”
Can’t be represented in propositional logic. Need a
language that talks about objects, their properties, and
their relations.
Later we’ll see how to draw inferences.
5
Introducing Predicate Logic
Predicate logic uses the following new features:
Variables: x, y, z
Predicates: P(x), M(x)
Quantifiers (to be covered in a few slides):
Propositional functions are a generalization of
propositions.
They contain variables and a predicate, e.g., P(x)
Variables can be replaced by elements from their
domain.
6
Propositional Functions
Propositional functions become propositions (and have
truth values) when their variables are each replaced by a
value from the domain (or bound by a quantifier, as we will
see later).
The statement P(x) is said to be the value of the
propositional function P at x.
For example, let P(x) denote “x > 0” and the domain be the
integers. Then:
P(-3) is false.
P(0) is false.
P(3) is true.
Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U is
the integers.
7
Examples of Propositional
Functions
Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all three variables) be
the integers. Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5)
Solution: F
R(3,4,7)
Solution: T
R(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition
Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as the integers.
Find these truth values:
Q(2,-1,3)
Solution: T
Q(3,4,7)
Solution: F
Q(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition
8
Compound Expressions
Connectives from propositional logic carry over to predicate
logic.
If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:
P(3) ∨ P(-1) Solution: T
P(3) ∧ P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → ¬P(-1) Solution: T
Expressions with variables are not propositions and therefore do
not have truth values. For example,
P(3) ∧ P(y)
P(x) → P(y)
When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next), these
expressions (propositional functions) become propositions.
9
Quantifiers Charles Peirce (1839-1914)
11
Existential Quantifier
x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as “There is an
x such that P(x),” or “For at least one x, P(x).”
Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
true. It is also true if U is the positive integers.
2. If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive integers, then
x P(x) is false.
3. If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then x
P(x) is true.
12
Thinking about Quantifiers
When the domain of discourse is finite, we can think of
quantification as looping through the elements of the domain.
To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
If at every step P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true.
If at a step P(x) is false, then x P(x) is false and the loop
terminates.
To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
If at some step, P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then x
P(x) is false.
Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the
quantifiers this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in some
cases.
14
Properties of Quantifiers
The truth value of x P(x) and x P(x) depend on both
the propositional function P(x) and on the domain U.
Examples:
1. If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then x P(x) is true, but x P(x) is false.
2. If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then both x P(x) and x P(x) are true.
3. If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement
“x > 2”, then both x P(x) and x P(x) are true. But if
P(x) is the statement “x < 2”, then both x P(x) and
x P(x) are false.
15
Precedence of Quantifiers
The quantifiers and have higher precedence than
all the logical operators.
For example, x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (x P(x))∨ Q(x)
x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.
Unfortunately, often people write x P(x) ∨ Q(x) when
they mean x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).
16
Returning to the Socrates Example
Introduce the propositional functions Man(x)
denoting “x is a man” and Mortal(x) denoting “x is
mortal.” Specify the domain as all people.
The two premises are:
19
Equivalences in Predicate Logic
Statements involving predicates and quantifiers are
logically equivalent if and only if they have the same
truth value
for every predicate substituted into these statements
and
for every domain of discourse used for the variables in
the expressions.
The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are logically
equivalent.
Example: x ¬¬S(x) ≡ x S(x)
20
Thinking about Quantifiers as
Conjunctions and Disjunctions
If the domain is finite, a universally quantified proposition is
equivalent to a conjunction of propositions without quantifiers
and an existentially quantified proposition is equivalent to a
disjunction of propositions without quantifiers.
If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:
Even if the domains are infinite, you can still think of the
quantifiers in this fashion, but the equivalent expressions
without quantifiers will be infinitely long.
21
Negating Quantified Expressions
Consider x J(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in Java.”
Here J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java” and
the domain is students in your class.
Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case
that every student in your class has taken Java.” This
implies that “There is a student in your class who has
not taken Java.”
Symbolically ¬x J(x) and x ¬J(x) are equivalent
22
Negating Quantified Expressions
(continued)
Now Consider x J(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a course in
Java.”
Where J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java.”
Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case
that there is a student in this class who has taken Java.”
This implies that “Every student in this class has not
taken Java”
Symbolically ¬ x J(x) and x ¬J(x) are equivalent
23
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
The rules for negating quantifiers are:
32
Charles Lutwidge Dodgson
Lewis Carroll Example (AKA Lewis Caroll)
(1832-1898)
The first two are called premises and the third is called the
conclusion.
1. “All lions are fierce.”
2. “Some lions do not drink coffee.”
3. “Some fierce creatures do not drink coffee.”
Here is one way to translate these statements to predicate logic.
Let P(x), Q(x), and R(x) be the propositional functions “x is a
lion,” “x is fierce,” and “x drinks coffee,” respectively.
1. x (P(x)→ Q(x))
2. x (P(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
3. x (Q(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
Later we will see how to prove that the conclusion follows from
the premises.
33
Section 1.4
41
Section Summary
Nested Quantifiers
Order of Quantifiers
Translating from Nested Quantifiers into English
Translating Mathematical Statements into Statements
involving Nested Quantifiers.
Translated English Sentences into Logical Expressions.
Negating Nested Quantifiers.
42
Nested Quantifiers
Nested quantifiers are often necessary to express the
meaning of sentences in English as well as important
concepts in computer science and mathematics.
Example: “Every real number has an inverse” is
x y(x + y = 0)
where the domains of x and y are the real numbers.
We can also think of nested propositional functions:
x y(x + y = 0) can be viewed as x Q(x) where Q(x) is
y P(x, y) where P(x, y) is (x + y = 0)
43
Thinking of Nested Quantification
Nested Loops
To see if xyP (x,y) is true, loop through the values of x :
At each step, loop through the values for y.
If for some pair of x andy, P(x,y) is false, then x yP(x,y) is false and both the
outer and inner loop terminate.
x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through each x.
To see if x yP(x,y) is true, loop through the values of x:
At each step, loop through the values for y.
The inner loop ends when a pair x and y is found such that P(x, y) is true.
If no y is found such that P(x, y) is true the outer loop terminates as x yP(x,y)
has been shown to be false.
x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through each x.
If the domains of the variables are infinite, then this process can not
actually be carried out.
44
Order of Quantifiers
Examples:
1. Let P(x,y) be the statement “x + y = y + x.” Assume
that U is the real numbers. Then x yP(x,y) and
y xP(x,y) have the same truth value.
2. Let Q(x,y) be the statement “x + y = 0.” Assume that
U is the real numbers. Then x yQ(x,y) is true, but
y xQ(x,y) is false.
45
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 1: Let U be the real numbers,
Define P(x,y) : x ∙ y = 0
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)
Answer: True
3. xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
4. x y P(x,y)
Answer: True
46
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 2: Let U be the real numbers,
Define P(x,y) : x / y = 1
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
3. xy P(x,y)
Answer: False
4. x y P(x,y)
Answer: True
47
Quantifications of Two Variables
Statement When True? When False
P(x,y) is true for every There is a pair x, y for
pair x,y. which P(x,y) is false.
48
Translating Nested Quantifiers into
English
Example 1: Translate the statement
x (C(x )∨ y (C(y ) ∧ F(x, y)))
where C(x) is “x has a computer,” and F(x,y) is “x and y are
friends,” and the domain for both x and y consists of all
students in your school.
Solution: Every student in your school has a computer or
has a friend who has a computer.
Example 2: Translate the statement
xy z ((F(x, y)∧ F(x,z) ∧ (y ≠z))→¬F(y,z))
Solution: There is a student none of whose friends are
also friends with each other.
49
Translating Mathematical
Statements into Predicate Logic
Example : Translate “The sum of two positive integers is
always positive” into a logical expression.
Solution:
1. Rewrite the statement to make the implied quantifiers and
domains explicit:
“For every two integers, if these integers are both positive, then the
sum of these integers is positive.”
2. Introduce the variables x and y, and specify the domain, to
obtain:
“For all positive integers x and y, x + y is positive.”
3. The result is:
x y ((x > 0)∧ (y > 0)→ (x + y > 0))
where the domain of both variables consists of all integers
50
Translating English into Logical
Expressions Example
Example: Use quantifiers to express the statement
“There is a woman who has taken a flight on every
airline in the world.”
Solution:
1. Let P(w,f) be “w has taken f ” and Q(f,a) be “f is a
flight on a .”
2. The domain of w is all women, the domain of f is all
flights, and the domain of a is all airlines.
3. Then the statement can be expressed as:
w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
51
Calculus in Logic (optional)
Example: Use quantifiers to express the definition of the limit of a
real-valued function f(x) of a real variable x at a point a in its
domain.
Solution: Recall the definition of the statement
is “For every real number ε > 0, there exists a real number δ > 0
such that |f(x) – L| < ε whenever 0 < |x –a| < δ.”
Using quantifiers:
52
Questions on Translation from
English
Choose the obvious predicates and express in predicate logic.
Example 1: “Brothers are siblings.”
Solution: x y (B(x,y) → S(x,y))
Example 2: “Siblinghood is symmetric.”
Solution: x y (S(x,y) → S(y,x))
Example 3: “Everybody loves somebody.”
Solution: x y L(x,y)
Example 4: “There is someone who is loved by everyone.”
Solution: y x L(x,y)
Example 5: “There is someone who loves someone.”
Solution: x y L(x,y)
Example 6: “Everyone loves himself”
Solution: x L(x,x)
53
Negating Nested Quantifiers
Example 1: Recall the logical expression developed three slides back:
w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Part 1: Use quantifiers to express the statement that “There does not exist a woman who
has taken a flight on every airline in the world.”
Solution: ¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Part 2: Now use De Morgan’s Laws to move the negation as far inwards as possible.
Solution:
1. ¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
2. w ¬ a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for
3. w a ¬ f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for
4. w a f ¬ (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for
5. w a f (¬ P(w,f ) ∨ ¬ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for ∧.
Part 3: Can you translate the result back into English?
Solution:
“For every woman there is an airline such that for all flights, this woman has not taken
that flight or that flight is not on this airline”
54
Return to Calculus and Logic (Opt)
Example : Recall the logical expression developed in the calculus example three slides back.
Use quantifiers and predicates to express that does not exist.
3. Now we can repeatedly apply the rules for negating quantified expressions:
55
Calculus in Predicate Logic
(optional)
4. Therefore, to say that does not exist means
that for all real numbers L, can be
expressed as:
57