Retrieve
Retrieve
Retrieve
FEATURE REVIEW
Today, the study of ethnic conflict is a major growth industry. New journals1and
research centres2 have been launched to study ethnic conflict, while an increasing
number of scholars cast their work in this mould. There have been 43 books
published in English with the term ‘ethnic conflict’ in the title since 1990,
compared with just 17 before then.3 One online database of English-language
scholarly journals lists 249 articles with the term ‘ethnic conflict’ in the title
written since the start of 1990, versus just 23 with the term ‘class conflict’ in the
title over the same period.4 Huntington’s ‘clash of civilisations’, ethnic conflict
writ large, has been deemed the greatest political challenge of our time.
Yet the empirical and theoretical justifications for this approach to the study
of politics are weak. Not only is there insufficient evidence of surging ethnic
conflict globally, but the concept itself is problematic and other approaches are
almost always more fruitful.
Several scholars have taken issue with the term ‘ethnic conflict’ (alternately
‘ethnic war’ or ‘ethnic violence’)—loosely defined as political or social conflict
involving one or more groups which are identified by some marker of ethnic
identity.5 Yet mostly they have done so on empirical grounds, arguing that often
what appears to be ethnic conflict is not actually ethnic conflict. It is time, I
think, to tackle the issue on conceptual grounds, that is, via a purposive
deductive route.
I am not arguing that we should ignore the ethnic (or identity) dimensions of
politics where they are plainly in evidence. Ethnic diversity has clear economic,
political and social consequences.6 I am arguing, however, that rarely if ever is
the ethnic conflict framework the best one for the study of politics. The
Bruce Gilley is the Department of Politics, Princeton University, Corwin Hall, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA.
Email: [email protected].
Empirical problems
It has been said that paradigms in political science reach a peak of popularity just
when their empirical justification is at its weakest.7 This may describe ethnic
conflict theory today. At a time when it is the hottest topic in political science,
there are questions about whether it deserves all this attention. One is told that
ethnic identity, long dormant in the post-World War II era as a result of secular
drives in democracies or top-down control in non-democracies, has erupted like
a volcano. Ethnic conflict is said to be ‘everywhere on the rise‘8 and scholars
must respond. Is it?
There are several ways we might measure levels of ethnic conflict—number
of incidents, casualties, number of people involved, etc. Any plausible claim of
increase would have to take account of increased levels of information as well
as increased levels of interaction. To my knowledge there have been few if any
attempts to show that ethnic conflict has risen on any of these definitions. Fox
shows that ethnic conflict across state borders has not increased in the post-cold
war era, contra Huntington and others.9 To be sure, civil wars have become more
common than inter-state wars and probably a fair proportion of these involve
competing ethnic groups.10 But most evidence suggests an overall decline in
ethnic conflict, as evidenced by indicators like refugees or state failures.11
Co-operation not conflict remains the norm.12
Much of the concern over rising ethnic conflict came from the disputes that
accompanied the collapse of communism in Eastern Europe and the USSR. Van
Evera predicted in 1994 ‘a substantial amount of violence’ across the region for
several decades to come as dozens of additional ethnic groups fought for
statehood or irredentism.13 Snyder said nationalist war had become ‘endemic’
since the fall of the Berlin Wall.14 Yet these upheavals had by the early 2000s
given rise to mostly settled polities—including in countries such as the Ukraine
and Romania long believed to be ripe for ethnic break-up. Elsewhere, predictions
of surging ethnic politics have been confounded by normal not ethnic politics
everywhere on the rise. The Parti Québécois and the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP)
have both been chased from office over old-fashioned economic disgruntlement.
In Africa more people still identify themselves by occupation or class (40%)
than ethnicity (25%).15 Severe political crises in countries like Zimbabwe and
Kenya have notably not led to a rise in ethnic tensions. And, despite more than
a decade of civil strife involving half a dozen ethnic groups, more people in
Somalia still feel threatened by armed thugs (81%) and wild animals like hyenas
(67%) than by ethnic disputes (60%).16
1156
AGAINST THE CONCEPT OF ETHNIC CONFLICT
Conceptual problems
Three decades ago, Philip Schmitter criticised the ‘definitional vagueness, lack
of potential empirical specificity, and circularity of argument’ that surrounded
the concept of ‘corporatism’.21 The concept was being used to describe every-
thing from vague social feelings of community to the Soviet-style imposition of
totalising functional organisation. As a concept, corporatism needed to be
defined so as to be identifiable, measurable and disprovable. At present the
concept of ethnic conflict is none of these things. Definitions range from
competing ‘meta-narratives of meaning’ to violent conflagrations where the
combatants display different cultural symbols.
Some scholars have celebrated the ‘diversity’ of the ethnic conflict literature,
arguing that through it ‘we gain a greater appreciation of the range of variation
of such conflicts and a richer sense of their complex roots’.22 Yet concept
diversity makes for bad social science, or at least bad political science. We need
well specified concepts in order to make valid inferences across cases that can
be the basis of positive policy prescription.
1157
FEATURE REVIEW
Ethnic conflict has been allowed to drift into poor conceptualisation because
of a strange combination of under-conceptualising postmodernism and over-con-
ceptualising quantification. The former has eschewed meaningful comparisons
among cases, and has ‘taken flight from the hard categories of social science to
find refuge in deconstruction, relativism, and meta-narratives’.23 The latter, often
concerned with international security, has gladly lumped together dissimilar
cases, often in order to raise the gloomy spectre of civilisational clash or new
security challenges.24 If political science has a unique role to play, it is providing
good concepts that enjoy both within-case and cross-case validity. It is high time
to engage in what Weber called a ‘reconstruction’ of concepts. The question is:
can it be done? If we wade into the ‘messy center’25 of a proper conceptualisa-
tion of ethnic conflict, can we find anything worth salvaging?
The challenge of making ethnic conflict a useful concept begins with finding
a useful definition of ethnicity itself. Ethnicity is usually defined as that part of
a person’s identity which is drawn from one or more ‘markers’ like race,
religion, shared history, region, social symbols or language. It is distinct from
that part of a person’s identity that comes from, say, personal moral doctrine,
economic status, civic affiliations or personal history. For a start, the mere
existence of ethnic markers in political conflict cannot be the basis of calling
something ‘ethnic conflict’. When the six countries that share the Mekong River
fight over its use, this is not ‘ethnic conflict’ merely because all sides are
ethnically distinct. If this is the only meaning of ethnic conflict then all we have
is a superficial description, not a useful concept. It becomes no more useful than
saying that protests were by fishermen or involved looting. If the concept of
ethnic conflict is to be useful, it must point to a distinctive causal explanation for
given instances of political contention. It must somehow inform us about what
is happening beyond superficial appearances. And, as it does this, we must be
able to measure whether it is or is not apparent and thus to reject it in some
cases, lest it become tautological every time people of distinct ethnicity are on
either side of the barricades.
To do so, we need to consider the nature of ethnicity. Most accounts hold that
ethnicity is a largely cognitive phenomenon, the salience and depth of which will
vary across groups and individuals. Having rejected primordial understandings
of ethnicity, scholars have formulated more plausible constructivist (ethnicity to
satisfy socio-psychological or political-psychological needs),26 or structural (eth-
nicity as a response to economic, rights or security deprivation) approaches.27
We can loosely call these the ‘ends’ and ‘means’ theories of ethnicity.
Parlaying these into a concept of ethnic conflict is tricky. Ethnic conflict as an
ends-based concept only makes sense if the motivating purpose of contention is
some matter of specific relevance to an ethnic group. Yet the inherent com-
plexity and dynamism of ethnicity itself makes proving this difficult. Con-
structed ethnicity is a moving and contested target and so explanations of
political conflict with reference to such ethnicity are liable to be off the mark.28
Unlike ‘class conflict’, which can be proved or disproved by using pretty stable
measures of the people involved (income, education, occupation, etc), the same
cannot be said of ethnicity. Prejudices against other ethnic groups that appear
‘essential’ wax and wane as conditions change.29 The mere existence of conflict
1158
AGAINST THE CONCEPT OF ETHNIC CONFLICT
with other ethnic groups may shift the meaning of ethnicity on all sides.30 Malay
identity may have been constructed in terms of a ‘sons of the soil’ mythology
that justified preferences over Chinese in the past, but today it is an identity that
has shifted to pan-Islamic and modernist features. How would we know ethnic
conflict if we saw it?
The problems of ethnic conflict as a means-based concept are more obvious.
Here ethnicity is found by the entrepreneurs to be a handy device with which to
mobilise supporters in the face of some form of deprivation or repression.31
Ethnicity provides the necessary sense of solidarity within the social movement.
Yet if ethnicity is structurally derived, or made salient, then the critical, as
opposed to proximate, cause are the structural issues themselves. ‘Ethnic
conflict’ in such cases is really ‘structural deprivation’ conflict, whether econ-
omic, political, or social.32 The reason why most of the USSR and Eastern
Europe did not turn to rivers of blood after communism is because in most
places the structural cause of ethnic assertiveness was the lack of ‘democratically
legitimated state structures at the center’.33 This was solved through indepen-
dence and democratisation. The cry ‘Ukraine for the Ukrainians’ fell silent once
the country was free and democratic. Tamils rebelled in Sri Lanka but not in
India’s Tamil Nadu, because they were systematically denied basic political,
economic and cultural rights in the former from the mid-1950s onwards—not
because they were inherently antagonistic to Sinhalese and certainly not because
of democracy per se.34 Chewas and Tumbukas are allies in one country and
enemies in another as a result of different political structures.35 The Muslim
insurgency that began in the southern Philippines in the 1970s was an entirely
predictable response to state-sponsored land evictions and religious freedom
limits, ‘an indirect consequence of risk aversion’, not a Filipino clash of
civilisations.36
If ethnicity is merely a mobilisational focal point in the face of structural
deprivation, notes King, it raises the question of ‘whether a thing called ethnic
war even exists’.37 In such cases there seems little justification for separating
cases of contentious politics where ethnic difference is involved from those
where it is not. Punjabi demands for regional autonomy from Delhi might be
compared with demands for autonomy from Kuala Lumpur from Sabah timber
barons. Protests by Ecuadorian jungle tribes over oil and gas exploitation are
akin to protests over quotas by Nordic fishing communities. Yet the Punjabi and
Ecuadorian cases are lumped together as ‘ethnic conflict’. Case homogeneity is
violated when ethnic difference is the basis of selection.
In both ends and means cases the concept of ethnic conflict leaves us at sea
in explaining what is going on beyond a host of ad hoc appeals to ethnicity.
Good institutions reduce ethnic conflict because they reduce structural injustices
and accommodate shifting identities, ethnic or otherwise, not because ethnicity
is a special form of contentious politics.38 Empirically ethnic civil wars are
associated with largely the same factors as non-ethnic civil wars. As Sarkees and
colleagues note: ‘In the data on “ethnic” wars, it is often difficult to determine
whether ethnicity is the dominant motivating factor for the combatants, whether
the importance given to ethnicity is a constant or varies over time, and whether
“ethnic wars” can be a mutually exclusive category as distinct from’ other forms
1159
FEATURE REVIEW
of pluralism.39 Yet many scholars cling tenaciously to the belief that ‘ethnic civil
war’ exists. To quote one group summarising five years of collaborative
research: ‘No one of us has been able to show precisely how ethnic civil wars
differ from civil wars that have no ethnic component at all. We all intuit that
such a difference must exist; we have not been able to demonstrate how and
where.’40
The concept of ethnic conflict, then, turns out to be merely a holding pen for
a herd of disparate descriptive events. It has become, to use Huntington’s
criticism of another concept, ‘a signal for scholarly preferences rather than a tool
for analytical purposes’.41 As such it is falling outside the realm of social
science, or at least that part which aspires to some level of generality.
A solution?
There seem to be two possible ways to rescue the concept of ethnic conflict, one
for each of the ends- and means-based understanding of ethnicity. An ends-based
concept might be one that meets a series of strict necessary conditions. Ethnic
conflict might be defined as sustained and violent conflict by ethnically distinct
actors in which the issue is integral to one ethnicity.42 It seems at least possible
that some long-standing disputes are enduring enough to qualify. The Ayodhya
temple, the Temple Mount, the Orange Day parades may suggest this kind of
ethnic conflict—purely identificational, often irrational, and deeply impervious
to amelioration. Yet such instances are rare. Explanations of Serbian aggression
against Kosovars in terms of the ‘ancient hatreds’ of Yugoslavia—Clinton’s
words—fell silent when the Serbians voted their tyrant Slobodan Milosevic out
of office in 2000 and sent him to stand trial for war crimes. Exclusive political
systems have spawned religious-based civil wars not because ‘religious identity
is fixed and nonnegotiable’,43 but because basic freedoms are fixed and non-
negotiable. Religious identity is almost certainly dynamic and elastic. Ancient
hatreds are nearly miraculous as social phenomena.
In the means-based case the concept may be useful in those rare instances
where structural deprivation has become so profoundly ethnic-specific that
ethnicity has come to be defined precisely in terms of this deprivation. That is,
it may apply where the mobilisation of ethnicity creates a path dependence
which decisively shapes the movement. Loury has made such an argument about
African Americans in the USA, and Snyder for some nationalist conflicts.44 Yet
evidence for this is at best mixed. The creation of Dravidian (or Tamil)
nationalist parties in India in response to perceived structural deprivations has
lessened not increased the ethnic dimension of conflicts there.45 Without path
dependence, ethnic conflict as a means-based concept loses any distinct use, for
it is just another tool in the repertoire of a social movement. Ethnic mobilisation
caused by a general failure to legitimate inequalities is constantly in danger of
being swallowed by a broader social movement. This has long been the case in
Latin America.46
Alternatively, a structure-based concept might make sense if the structures
that give rise to ethnic mobilisation are in some sense ‘sticky’, that is, not
amenable to easy change. If imperfect democracies usually bring nationalist or
1160
AGAINST THE CONCEPT OF ETHNIC CONFLICT
Normative debates
Abandoning the ethnic conflict framework by no means implies abandoning our
deeply held normative convictions as scholars about ‘what matters’ in politics.
We can retain our differences while jettisoning a concept that only muddles the
debate. In this sense, I see the rejection of the ethnic conflict framework as a way
to increase clarity in fundamental empirical and moral debates.49
The initial reluctance to accept the concept of ethnic conflict came from
Marxist scholars in the 1960s and 1970s who, Horowitz charged, ‘have a
distinctly rationalistic and materialistic bias’.50 Today, a ‘neo-Marxist’ world-
view has emerged. Crawford and Lipshutz, for example, argue that ‘neoliberal
1161
FEATURE REVIEW
economic reforms’, among other things, have broken existing social contracts,
leading to power shifts that ‘are experienced as ethnic and religious discrimi-
nation’.51 The same thesis has been advanced by Yashar with reference to Latin
America and Chua with regard to new democracies.52
An alternative world-view is the ‘liberal’ one. In contrast to the focus on
economic deprivation of the neo-Marxists, the liberal view places emphasis on
the failure to provide basic political and civic freedoms as the most important
cause of ethnic (and other emancipatory) movements. In this view imperfect or
failed democracy, which deprives people of the status they require, is at issue.53
‘The great evils of human history’, said Rawls, ‘follow from political injus-
tice’.54 If, as Horowitz wrote, ‘the rise of ethnic conflict has gone hand in hand
with the decline of democracy in Asia and Africa’,55 then its amelioration is
properly an issue of democratic rights.
Somewhere between these two world-views stands modernisation theory, with
its emphasis on breaking traditional economic relationships and achieving
substantial freedom. From all these viewpoints—Marxist, liberal, and modernis-
ation—conflict involving ethnic groups may be a good or bad thing depending
on the motivations and outcomes. Such conflict is not problematic per se merely
because ethnic difference is involved, any more than are other forms of political
struggle or even violence.
Another perspective is the ‘realist’ worldview, one that is found most
commonly in the field of international relations. Here, the main concern is with
political order, at home and abroad, which takes normative precedence over
‘mushy’ concepts of domestic justice. A wave of current writing about
democratisation and international peace falls into this category.56
It is not the purpose to evaluate the relative merits of these world-views here,
merely to state that they are the proper frameworks for the age-old debate about
how best to ensure the equal treatment of individuals in a political community.
To isolate ethnicity from its context in the hard categories of material, political
and security deprivation, or to essentialise it into immutable doctrines that
actually have a short shelf-life, makes little sense. If the standard categories of
social science are too ‘bloodless’57 for the passion and exotica of ethnicity, then
so be it. As frameworks for valid inference they have proven their worth. Ethnic
conflict, despite its tempting descriptive richness, has not.
Does it matter?
Is it utopian and unnecessary to try to disabuse the academy of the concept of
ethnic conflict? After all, we may want to retain it for those rare cases mentioned
above where the concept applies. More importantly, there is a big industry of
ethnic conflict studies now and it may be that this industry does more good than
harm. Perhaps there is a danger of falling into Hirschman’s ‘mindless theoriz-
ing’,58 demanding that the formulation of elegant theories take precedence over
the performance of useful work.
There are some reasons for thinking the contrary. The proper conceptualisa-
tion of social conflicts is crucial to understanding what policy measures are
appropriate. If economic or political deprivation is at stake in ethnically salient
1162
AGAINST THE CONCEPT OF ETHNIC CONFLICT
Notes
1
Examples include Nations and Nationalism (founded 1995), Ethnicities (2001), Nationalism and Ethnic
Politics (1995) and Ethnic Conflict Research Digest (1995). One older journal on the subject is Ethnic
and Racial Studies (1978).
2
Examples in the USA and UK include those at the University of Notre Dame (www.nd.edu/ ⬃ krocinst/re-
search/rirec.html), Queens University Belfast (www.qub.ac.uk/csec), the University of Washington (http://
depts.washington.edu/ethpeace), the University of Pennsylvania (www.psych.upenn.edu/sacsec/about) and
the multi-university Laboratory in Comparative Ethnic Processes (LICEP) (www.duke.edu/web/licep)
3
Library of Congress online catalogue, accessed 8 April 2004. This of course does not come close to
covering the full range of books on the subject.
4
EBSCO Host Research Database, accessed 8 April 2004.
5
B Crawford & R Lipschutz, The Myth of ‘Ethnic Conflict’: Politics, Economics, and ‘Cultural’ Violence,
University of California International and Area Studies Digital Collection, Research Series, Vol 98, 1998;
J Mueller, ‘The banality of “ethnic war”, International Security, 25 (1), 2000, pp 43–72; N Sambanis,
‘Do ethnic and nonethnic civil wars have the same causes? A theoretical and empirical inquiry’, Journal
of Conflict Resolution, 45 (3), 2001, pp 259–283; VT LeVine, ‘Conceptualizing “ethnicity” and “ethnic
conflict”: a controversy revisited’, Studies in Comparative International Development, 32 (2), 1997,
pp 45–76; and C King, ‘The myth of ethnic warfare’, Foreign Affairs, 80 (6), 2001, pp 165–171.
6
Easterly provides a useful survey of the literature on this point. See ‘Can institutions resolve ethnic
conflict?’, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 49 (4), 2001, pp 687–706.
7
After World War II modernisation theory, dependency theory and then state-centred theory came into
vogue, even as contemporary conditions of the 1950s, 1960s and 1970s, and then the 1980s and 1990s
were at odds with their foundational assumptions. On this see A Kohli & V Shue, ‘State power and social
forces: on political contention and accomodation in the Third World’, in J Migdal, A Kohli & V Shue
1163
FEATURE REVIEW
(eds), State Power and Social Forces: Domination and Transformation in the Third World, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1994, pp 293–326.
8
Crawford & Lipschutz, The Myth of ‘Ethnic Conflict’, p 8.
9
J Fox, ‘Ethnic minorities and the clash of civilizations: a quantitative analysis of Huntington’s thesis’,
British Journal of Political Science, 32 (3), 2002, pp 415–435; and J Fox, Ethnoreligious Conflict in the
Late Twentieth Century, Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2002.
10
MR Sarkees, F Wayman & JD Singer, ‘Inter-state, intra-state, and extra-state wars: a comprehensive look
at their distribution over time, 1816–1997’, International Studies Quarterly, 47, 2003, pp 49–70.
11
TR Gurr, ‘Ethnic warfare on the wane’, Foreign Affairs, 79 (3), 2000, pp 52–65; TR Gurr, MG Marshall
& D Khosla, Peace and Conflict 2001: A Global Survey of Armed Conflicts, Self-Determination
Movements, and Democracy, Center for International Development and Conflict Management, University
of Maryland, 2001; and J Fox, ‘State failure and the clash of civilisations: an examination of the magnitude
and extent of domestic civilisational conflict from 1950 to 1996’, Australian Journal of Political Science,
38 (2), 2003, pp 195–214.
12
D Laitin & J Fearon, ‘Explaining interethnic cooperation’, American Political Science Review, 90 (4),
1996, pp 715–735. Fearon shows that across 160 countries there is a 48% probability that two randomly
selected people in a given country will be ethnically different and a 29% probability that they will be
culturally different. J Fearon, ‘Ethnic structure and cultural diversity around the world: a cross-national
data set on ethnic groups’, paper presented to the American Political Science Association Annual
Conference, 2002.
13
S VanEvera, ‘Hypotheses on nationalism and war’, International Security, 18 (4), 1994, pp 5–39.
14
J Snyder, From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict, New York: WW Norton,
2000, p 17.
15
Afrobarometer, Briefing Paper #1, April 2002, available at www.afrobarometer.org/papers/Afro-
briefNo1.pdf.
16
United Nations Development Programme, Socio-Economic Survey of Somalia 2002, Table 7.12, at
www.so.undp.org/SoconRpt.htm. This is no surprise: before the outbreak of conflict in 1991, most Somalis
saw ethnic diversity as a source of national unity. See A Hashim, ‘Conflicting identities in Somalia’, Peace
Review, 9 (4), 1997, pp 527–532.
17
W Case, ‘Malaysia: aspects and audiences of legitimacy’, in M Alagappa (ed), Political Legitimacy in
Southeast Asia: The Quest for Moral Authority, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995, p 91.
18
H Singh, ‘Ethnic conflict in Malaysia revisited’, Commonwealth and Comparative Politics, 39 (1), 2001,
pp 42–43.
19
By my own calculations, the number killed in communal strife (mostly Hindu–Muslim) per 10 million
people for the worst years of 1964, 1969, 1983 and 1992, respectively are 41, 13, 16 and 12. The figure
for 2002 is just eight. This is based on official figures compiled by the Bureau of Police Research and
Development (BPRD) of the Ministry of Home Affairs. Although considered conservative, the BPRD data
would not affect the comparison if the bias has remained constant over the period. Varshney notes that
the trends in his own data, compiled from reports in the Times of India, closely match the BPRD figures.
A Varshney, Ethnic Conflict and Civil Life: Hindus and Muslims in India, New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 2002 pp 94–95.
20
White, however, has argued that emotive moral revulsion is a poor substitute for sober structural analysis,
if one aims to avoid a repeat of catastrophic political events. See LT White, Policies of Chaos: The
Organizational Causes of Violence in China’s Cultural Revolution, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1989.
21
PC Schmitter, ‘Still the century of corporatism?’, in FB Pike & T Stritch (eds), The New Corporatism,
Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame, 1974, p 91.
22
TD Hall & C Bartalos, ‘Varieties of ethnic conflict in global perspective: a review essay’, Social Science
Quarterly, 77 (2), 1996, p 445.
23
G Singh, Ethnic Conflict in India, New York: St Martin’s Press, 2000, p 22.
24
SM Saideman et al, ‘Democratization, political institutions, and ethnic conflict: a pooled, cross-sectional
time series analysis from 1985–1998’, Comparative Political Studies, 35 (1), 2002, pp 103–129; PF
Trumbore, ‘Victims or aggressors? Ethno-political rebellion and use of force in militarized interstate
disputes’, International Studies Quarterly, 47 (2), 2003, pp 183–202; S Lobell & P Mauceri, Ethnic Conflict
and International Politics: Explaining Diffusion and Escalation, London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004; D
Carment, ‘The international dimensions of ethnic conflict: concepts, indicators and theory’, Journal of
Peace Research, 30 (2), 1993, pp 137–151; D Byman, ‘Forever enemies? The manipulation of ethnic
identities to end ethnic wars’, Security Studies, 9 (3) 2000, pp 149–190; and DL Byman, Keeping the
Peace: Lasting Solutions to Ethnic Conflicts, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2002.
25
P Evans, ’The role of theory in comparative politics: a symposium’, World Politics, 48 (1), 1995, pp 1–9.
26
B Anderson, Imagined Communities, London: Verso, 1983; and K Chandra & D Laitin, A Constructivist
Model of Identity Change, LICEP, 2002.
1164
AGAINST THE CONCEPT OF ETHNIC CONFLICT
27
W Connor, Ethnonationalism: A Quest for Understanding, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press .
28
There is a close parallel here to the constructed nature of moral doctrines and the conclusion by Rawls,
most famously, that the result of this is that theories of justice cannot rely on fixed assumptions about
the nature of those doctrines. See J Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971,
Sec 68.
29
DP Green & RL Seher, ‘What role does prejudice play in ethnic conflict?’ , Annual Review of Political
Science, 6, 2003, pp 509–531.
30
Byman, ‘Forever enemies?’.
31
R Bates, ‘Modernization, ethnic competition, and the rationality of politics in contemporary Africa’, in
D Rothchild & VA Olorunsola (eds), The State Versus Ethnic Claims, Boulder, CO: Westview Press,
1983; SJ Kaufman, Modern Hatreds: The Symbolic Politics of Ethnic War, New York: Cornell University
Press, 2001; and Mueller, ‘The banality of “ethnic war” ’.
32
For example, poverty and political instability are the main culprits cited in Laitin & Fearon, ‘Explaining
interethnic cooperation’. Of course, by rejecting the idea that conflicts that use ethnicity as a tool are
‘ethnic conflicts’, we need not fall into the trap of calling them ‘criminal’, even if they appear to the
contemporary observer as anarchic and individualistic. In rightly questioning ethnicity, Mueller wrongly
does this in ‘The banality of “ethnic war” ’ and ‘Policing the remnants of war’, Journal of Peace Research,
40 (5), 2003, pp 507–518. This point has been made by S Kalyvas, ‘“New” and “old” civil wars: a valid
distinction?’, World Politics, 54 (3), 2001, pp 99–118, and of course earlier by E Hobsbawn, Primitive
Rebels, New York: WW Norton, 1959 and J Scott, Weapons of the Weak: Everyday Forms of Peasant
Resistance, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985.
33
JJ Linz & A Stepan, Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation: Southern Europe, South
America, and Post-Communist Europe, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996; and E
Giuliano, Democratization from the Bottom-Up: Secessionism, Nationalism and Local Accountability in
the Russian Transition, LICEP, 2003 .
34
This repression was of course a fundamental violation of democratic principles, so it is hard to endorse
the claim by Snyder that the Tamil uprising resulted from democracy. J Snyder, From Voting to Violence,
p 5. For a comparison of Tamils in the two places, see L Diamond, Developing Democracy: Toward
Consolidation, 1999, p 156.
35
D Posner, The Political Salience of Cultural Difference: Why Chewas and Tumbukas are Allies in Zambia
and Adversaries in Malawi, LICEP, 2003.
36
H Meadwell, ‘Transitions to independence and ethnic nationalist mobilization’, in WJ Booth, P James
& H Meadwell (eds), Politics and Rationality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, p 196.
37
C King, ‘The myth of ethnic warfare’, Foreign Affairs, 80 (6), 2001, p 167.
38
N Bermeo, ‘The import of institutions’, Journal of Democracy, 13 (2), 2002, pp 96–110; and Easterly,
‘Can institutions resolve ethnic conflict?’.
39
Sarkees et al, Inter-State, Intra-State, and Extra-State Wars, p 55. Sambanis, N., Do Ethnic and Nonethnic
Civil Wars Have the Same Causes? A Theoretical and Empirical Inquiry. Journal of Conflict Resolution,
2001. 45 (3): p. 259-283; Tilly, C., The Politics of Collective Violence. 2003, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press; Henderson, E.A. and J.D. Singer, Civil War in the Post-Colonial World, 1946-92. Journal
of Peace Research, 2000. 37 (3): p. 275-299.
40
Taken from the LICEP group’s website, at www.duke.edu/web/licep/aboutLiCEP.pdf, p 5, emphasis added.
41
S Huntington, ‘The change to change: modernization, development, and politics’, Comparative Politics,
3 (3), 1971, p 304.
42
This is something like the definition of ‘ethnic violence’ given by Brubaker and Laitin: ‘Violence
perpetrated across ethnic lines, in which at least one party is not a state (or representative of a state),
and in which the putative ethnic difference is integral rather than incidental to that violence, that is in
which the violence is meaningfully oriented in some way to the different ethnicity of the target’. R
Brubaker & D Laitin, ‘Ethnic and nationalist violence’, Annual Review of Sociology, 24, 1998, p 428.
43
M Reynal-Querol, ‘Ethnicity, political systems and civil wars’, Journal of Conflict Resolution, 46 (1),
2002, p 29.
44
G Loury, The Anatomy of Racial Inequality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002. Snyder
writes: ‘One does not have to hold primordialist theories of ancient hatreds to believe that, once popular
identities are mobilized to fight along lines defined by cultural differences, it will be difficult to erase
fears and hatreds rooted in the memory of those conflicts’. Snyder, From Voting to Violence, p 325.
45
N Subramanian, Ethnicity and Populist Mobilization, New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1999.
46
C Young, The Politics of Cultural Pluralism, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1976; and D Yashar,
Contesting Citizenship: Indigenous Movements, the State, and the Postliberal Challenge in Latin America,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
47
S Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order, New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1996, pp 165–168.
48
HD Forbes, ‘Toward a Science of Ethnic Conflict’, Journal of Democracy, 14 (4), 2003, p 172.
1165
FEATURE REVIEW
49
There are obvious parallels here with the well known argument of Elkins and Simeon in favour of structural
factors over the resort to ‘political culture’ in explanations. D Elkins & R Simeon, ‘A cause in search
of its effect, or what does political culture explain?’, Comparative Politics, 11 (2), 1979, pp 127–145.
50
D Horowitz, Ethnic Groups in Conflict, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2000, p 14.
51
Crawford & Lipschutz, The Myth of ‘Ethnic Conflict‘, pp 4–5.
52
Yashar, Contesting Citizenship; and A Chua, World on Fire: How Exporting Free Market Democracy
Breeds Ethnic Hatred and Global Instability, New York: Doubleday, 2003.
53
M Ignatieff, The Warrior’s Honor: Ethnic War and the Modern Conscience, New York: Henry Holt, 1998;
E Mansfield & J Snyder, ‘Incomplete democratization and the outbreak of military disputes’, International
Studies Quarterly, 46 (4), 2002, pp 529–550; and A Varshney, Ethnic Conflict and Civil Life.
54
J Rawls, The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999, pp 6–7.
55
Horowitz, Ethnic Groups in Conflict, p xvii.
56
Snyder, From Voting to Violence; Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations; and B Russett, JR O’Neal &
M Cox, ‘Clash of civilizations, or realism and liberalism déjà vu? Some evidence’, Journal of Peace
Research, 37 (5), 2000, pp 583–608.
57
‘A bloody phenomenon cannot be explained by a bloodless theory.’ Horowitz, Ethnic Groups in Conflict,
p140.
58
A Hirschmann, ‘The search for paradigms as a hindrance to understanding’, World Politics, 22 (3), 1970,
pp 329–343.
1166