1AJEL37
1AJEL37
1AJEL37
Citations:
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
GIVING A VOICE TO FUTURE GENERATIONS:
INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY, REPRESENTATIVES OF GENERATIONS TO COME,
AND THE CHALLENGE OF PLANETARY RIGHTS
JANE ANSTEE-WEDDERBURN*
I INTRODUCTION
In September 2013, the Secretary-General of the United Nations delivered a report on the
need for promoting intergenerational solidarity for the achievement of sustainable
development, taking into account the needs of the future.' The report was the culmination
of a process that was revived at the 2012 United Nations Conference on Sustainable
Development ('Rio+20'), 2 in which advocates for future generations challenged the
purported failure of the international community to respect the needs of future generations,
highlighting continued environmental degradation and unsustainable patterns of
* BA LLB (Hons) LLM. This article is based on a research paper originally submitted as part of the Master
of Laws program at Melbourne Law School, University of Melbourne. I am grateful to Alice Palmer for
her helpful comments on an earlier version of this article.
1 IntergenerationalSolidarity and the Needs of Future Generations - Report of the Secretary-General,6 8th
sess, Agenda Item 19, UN Doc A/68/322 (15 August 2013) ('Report of the Secretary-General').
2 United Nations, Rio+20 <http://www.uncsd2012.org/about.html>.
38 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
Humankind possesses the power to cause, and has already caused, great damage to the
environment, including resource depletion, ecosystem degradation, pollution, and a
continued decline in biodiversity.4 Human activity is placing increasing pressure on
environmental conditions and is destabilizing environmental systems. 5 Efforts to reduce
humankind's environmental footprint are proving largely ineffective and the short-term
thinking that characterises contemporary political decision-making has resulted in an ever-
widening gap between necessary protection measures and action. 6 International
environmental law has struggled to respond effectively to contemporary environmental
crises, including climate change. 7 The failure of legal and political systems to assure the
integrity of the planet has given rise to a growing concern about the legacy that present
generations will leave to the future, prompting many to assert that current generations owe
a duty to generations to come and must act, in furtherance of that duty, to ensure the
continued enjoyment of the earth and its resources. 8
While the idea of generations acting as stewards of the earth can be found in many traditions
and cultures, 9 contemporary expression was given to the concept of intertemporal
trusteeship of the planet by Edith Brown Weiss in 1989.10 Her doctrine of intergenerational
equity provides that each generation holds the planet on trust, obliged to pass it to all future
generations in no worse condition than that which they enjoyed and to provide equal access
to its cultural and natural resources." This sharing of the earth's resources is achieved
through a 'planetary trust', and the grant and imposition of 'planetary rights' and 'planetary
obligations'.12
While many regard it as incontrovertible that humankind has a responsibility to take account
of its actions for the future, 13 this moral charge has found only limited recognition in law.
The idea of taking into account the needs of future generations appears in national laws,
constitutions and international instruments - including non-binding declarations,
preambles of multilateral environmental agreements and, most notably, the operative
3 See, eg, Halina Ward, Foundation for Democracy and Sustainable Development and World Future Council,
Committing to the Future We Want: A High Commissionerfor Future Generationsat Rio+20 Discussion
Paper (March 2012) FDSD <http://www.fdsd.org/reports/>.
4 See United Nations Environment Program, GEO-5: Global Environment Outlook (United Nations
Environment Program, 2012) 88.
Ibid 26.
6 Collins describes the privileging of short-term thinking in environmental decision-making as 'the
ascendance of the present', in which 'the concept of long-term often does not seem to go beyond the next
election'. Lynda M Collins, 'Revisiting the Doctrine of Intergenerational Equity in Global Environmental
Governance' (2007) 30 Dalhousie Law Journal79, 96.
7 See, eg, Klaus Bosselmann, "Losing the Forest for the Trees: Environmental Reductionism in the Law'
(2010) 2 Sustainability 2424; Ludvig Beckman, 'Do Global Climate Change and the Interest of Future
Generations Have Implications for Democracy' (2008) 17(4) EnvironmentalPolitics 610.
See Collins, above n 6, 97; Lothar Giindling, 'Our Responsibility to Future Generations' [1990] American
Journalof InternationalLaw 207, 212.
9 Collins, above n 6, 96.
1o Edith Brown Weiss, In Fairness to Future Generations: InternationalLaw, Common Patrimony, and
IntergenerationalEquity (United Nations University, 1989).
" Ibid 21.
12 Ibid.
13 See, eg, Wilfred Beckerman, 'The Impossibility of a Theory of Intergenerational Justice' in Joerg Chet
Tremmel, Handbook of IntergenerationalJustice (Edward Elgar Publishing, 2006) 53, 64.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 39
Although not enjoying legal rights at international law, there have been repeated calls for
future generations to be given a voice, including through the establishment of offices to
represent the future: to advocate, to intervene in policy-making, and to advise on
environmental issues affecting future generations. Proposals for such representatives date
back to the 1992 United Nations Conference on Environment and Development
('UNCED'), 16 with more recent proposals being advanced in the lead up to Rio+20. 17
Stakeholders lobbied for national level ombudspersons and an international 'High
Commissioner for Future Generations'. Certain of the proposals were ambitious,
contemplating an interventionist and enforcement role for the High Commissioner.1 8
Ultimately, they were not taken up by the Member States. 19 The subsequent September
2013 report by the Secretary-General, examining intergenerational solidarity and the
institutional mechanisms for achieving it, contemplates a modest role for any future
generations' representative. 2 0
This article will begin by outlining Brown Weiss' concept of intergenerational equity, with
its emphasis on planetary rights and obligations, before contending that intergenerational
equity does not exist as a binding legal principle at international law and that future
generations do not enjoy legal rights. It will then identify some of the ways in which the
needs of future generations may be given expression, examining the recent calls at Rio+20
to establish a High Commissioner, with powers of monitoring and enforcement similar to
those enjoyed by the human rights Charter-based and treaty-based bodies. The article will
then argue that seeking to enforce purported rights of future generations is problematic, and
that the translation of any current awareness of the interests of future generations into legally
enforceable rights and obligations is complex and appears unlikely to be taken up by the
world's states. This article will argue that, absent legal rights and obligations, a
representative for future generations cannot hope to compel or constrain action but should
assume an educative, consultative and advisory role - interposing the interests of future
generations into decision-making and policy. Although less exacting than the missions
proposed by several future generations' advocates at Rio+20, such a role should be
embraced, in seeking to ensure that the interests of future generations are not undermined
by contemporary wants and needs.
14 UnitedNations Framework Convention on Climate Change, opened for signature 9 May 1992, 1771 UNTS
107 (entered into force 21 March 1994) ('UNFCCC') art 3.
15 Collins, above n 6, 120.
16 See < http://www.un.org/geninfo/bp/enviro.html>.
17 These proposals are discussed in Part III(B) below.
Human kind has caused alarming damage to the environment. Forests are being destroyed,
biodiversity is being lost, vast areas of the earth are polluted, and climate change is projected
to have a devastating impact on the earth's systems. 2 1 Yet the effects of many of these
pressures will not be felt by current generations but by generations to come, with present
generations possessing an unprecedented ability to influence negatively the lives of future
generations through this damning environmental legacy. 22 As Rachel Carson wrote in 1962,
'only within the moment of time represented by the present century has one species - man
- acquired significant power to alter the nature of this world'.2 3
Yet contemporary political institutions are constrained in their ability to respond effectively.
Election cycles and the need to give pre-eminence to the voting present have created a
'democratic deficit', 2 4 with powerful incentives to privilege the needs of the present
generation and to discount the anticipated impacts of current actions on the future.
Awareness of the destructive power of present generations and the inadequacies of short-
term thinking has given rise to calls, anchored in notions of equity and justice, for an
increased intertemporal regard for future generations within international environmental
law.
B IntergenerationalEquity: EarnestPlanetaryTrust
Brown Weiss' theory of intergenerational equity is grounded in diverse cultural and legal
29
traditions and draws from many political theorists and philosophers. 30 It posits that each
generation holds the planet and its natural and cultural resources on trust for future
generations, with each generation a trustee of the earth for future generations and a
beneficiary of the trust settled by previous generations. This dual role, as both trustee and
beneficiary, imposes obligations on each generation - referred to as 'planetary
obligations', and affords certain rights - known as 'planetary rights'. 31 Each generation is
subject to planetary obligations to conserve the diversity of the natural and cultural resource
base, to maintain the planet's quality, and to provide equitable access to the legacy of the
past and conserve future access. 3 2 These planetary obligations are 'integrally linked' with
the collective, planetary rights of future generations, 33 derived from their status as
beneficiaries. These rights are conceived as intergenerational, group rights, held by one
generation as a group in relation to all others - past, present and future. 34 Intergenerational
equity provides that the natural environment and natural and cultural resources may be used
by one generation but this common patrimony must be passed on to future generations in at
least comparable condition to that in which it was received.3 5
By invoking the concept of trusteeship of the earth's resources, Brown Weiss' theoretical
framework of rights and obligations promises to humankind the opportunity to afford
distributive justice to future generations. 3 6 It is a compelling entreaty for further action.
However, while Brown Weiss acknowledged that the doctrine needed to be translated into
positive law, 37 its formal acceptance has been limited and her elaborate concept has been
little advanced as a binding principle at international law.
Brown Weiss' theory of intergenerational equity has not enjoyed widespread support at
international law. No binding international measure has sought to advance intertemporal
legal rights and obligations, and the comprehensive doctrine of intergenerational equity is
not currently a principle of customary international law. 38 While it is possible to identify a
29 The idea of equity between generations and of stewardship of the earth's resources has its roots in the
common and civil law traditions, Islamic law, African customary law, and Asian nontheistic traditions. See
Brown Weiss, above n 10, 18.
30 A consideration of the complex philosophical underpinnings for intergenerational equity is beyond the
scope of this article. For an interesting discussion of Rawl's ideal observer theory, just savings principle
and distributive justice, which are said to explain, in part, intergenerational concerns, see Alexander
Gillespie, 'The Rights of Future Generations as a Justification for Environmental Protection' in Alexander
Gillespie, InternationalEnvironmentalLaw, Policy and Ethics (Oxford Scholarship Online, 2000) 114 and
M Fitzmaurice, Contemporary Issues in International Environmental Law (Edward Elgar Publishing,
2009) 114. See also Jeffrey M Gaba, 'Environmental Ethics and Our Moral Relationship to Future
Generations: Future Rights and Present Virtue' (1999) 24 Columbia Journalof EnvironmentalLaw 249.
31 Brown Weiss, above n 10,
21.
32 Referred to as the 'conservation of options', 'conservation of quality', and 'conservation
of access'. See
Brown Weiss, above n 10, 38.
33 Ibid 45.
34 Ibid 96.
35 Ibid 97.
36 Solum defines 'distributive justice' as being concerned with sharing the benefits and burdens of social co-
operation, and argues that questions of distributive justice are more fundamental to intergenerational justice
than corrective justice, presenting questions about the distribution of rights and obligations across
generations. Lawrence B Solum, 'To Our Children's Children's Children: The Problems of
Intergenerational Ethics' (2001) 35 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 163, 174.
37 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 103.
38 Collins, above n 6,
120.
42 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
concern for future generations in treaties, declarations, and decisions of the International
Court of Justice, none embodies Brown Weiss' vision of intergenerational equity grounded
in a planetary trust, and the extent of state practice and opiniojuris is not yet at a level to
constitute custom. 39
At the national level, numerous legislative instruments seek to protect the environment for
the benefit of present and future generations. A number of federal statutes in the United
States, for example, make express reference to future generations, 40 and Australia's
Environment Protection and Biodiversity Conservation Act also makes reference to the
principle of intergenerational equity. 4 1
A recognition of the needs of future generations has also been codified in various national
constitutions, with a number either imposing obligations on states to protect the environment
for present and future generations or extending constitutional rights to the environment so
39 This article looks to the sources of international law as set out in the ICJ Statute, in particular international
conventions and international custom. Statute of the InternationalCourt of Justice art 38. As to evidence
of state practice and belief necessary to establish a customary law principle, see Jan Klabbers, International
Law (Cambridge University Press, 2013) 26-30; James Crawford, Brownlie 's Principles of Public
InternationalLaw (Oxford University Press, 2012) 24. The ICJ has stated that actions by States 'not only
must amount to a settled practice, but they must also be such, or be carried out in such a way, as to be
evidence of a belief that this practice is rendered obligatory by the existence of the rule of law requiring it.
The need for such a belief, ie the existence of a subjective element, is implicit in the very notion of
the opiniojuris sive necessitatis. The States concerned must therefore feel that they are conforming to what
amounts to a legal obligation'. North Sea Continental Shelf (FederalRepublic of Germany/Denmark;
Federal Republic of Germany/Netherlands) (Judgment) [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 44 ('North Sea Continental
Shelf Cases').
40 The most important, the 1969 National Environment Policy Act, casts the Federal Government as trustee
of the environment for succeeding generations. National EnvironmentalPolicy Act of 1969, 42 U.S.C. §
4321 s 101(a)(1). See International Human Rights Clinic at Harvard Law School, Models for Protecting
the Environment for Future Generations (October 2008) Human Rights @ Harvard Law, 40
<http://www.law.harvard.edu/programs/hrp> for further examples of domestic US statutes protecting
future generations.
41 Environment Protectionand Biodiversity ConservationAct 1999 (Cth) s 3 defines 'ecologically sustainable
development', which is one of the objectives of the Act, by reference to a number of principles, including
the principle of intergenerational equity. Peel criticises the concept of ecologically sustainable
development as a 'vague, contradictory concept', claiming that there are very few examples of its effective
implementation. She contends that, although 'the development of the [ecologically sustainable
development] concept in Australia seems impressive on the surface, there is little underlying substance
when it comes to practical implementation'. Jacqueline Peel, 'Ecologically Sustainable Development:
More than Mere Lip Service' (2008) 12 AustralasianJournalof NaturalResources Land Policy 1, 2. The
principle of intergenerational equity or references to future generations also appear in various state
measures including the Environment Protection Act 1970 (Vic) which provides in section ID that 'the
principle of intergenerational equity should ensure that the ... environment is maintained or enhanced for
the benefit of future generations'; Environment Protection Act 1986 (WA) s 4A; Protection of the
Environment AdministrationAct 1991 (NSW) s 6; Nature ConservationAct 1992 (Qld) s 11; Environment
Protection Act 1993 (SA) s 10; Nature Conservation Act 2002 (Tas) sch 2 item 2. See also, National
Environmental Management Act 1998 (South Africa) preamble. In New Zealand, the Resource
ManagementAct 1991 (NZ) s 3 provides that the purpose of the Act includes sustaining resources to meet
the 'reasonably foreseeable needs of future generations'. It has been argued that courts in New Zealand
have failed adequately to consider the needs of future generations and how best to provide for them in
decision-making on environmental matters. Sacha Hollis, 'Old Solutions to New Problems: Providing for
Intergenerational Equity in National Institutions' (2010) 14 New Zealand Journalof EnvironmentalLaw
25, 36.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 43
There has also been exploration of intertemporal justice and intergenerational equity in
decisions of national courts. The most celebrated is the decision of the Philippines Supreme
Court in Oposa v Factoran, JR, in which the petitioners asserted, and the court accepted,
that they represented both their own interests and those of future generations. 4 3 This decision
is regarded by a number of commentators and scholars as significant, representing a 'future-
oriented and progressive step to implement[ing] and enforc[ing] the principle of
intergenerational equity and responsibility'. 44 Houck goes even further, describing the
decision as one that changed the Philippines 'in ways from which there would be no
return'.45 Other commentators contend, however, that the significance of the case has been
overstated.4 6
42 See, eg, Bolivia's constitution which includes a right to a healthy environment safeguarding the rights of
future generation. PoliticalConstitution of the State 2009 (Bolivia) art 9. Ecuador's constitution provides
that 'the State shall exercise sovereignty over biodiversity, whose administration and management shall be
conducted on the basis of responsibility between generations'. Constitutionof 2008 (Republic of Ecuador)
art 400. Norway's constitution provides for a right to an environment that is conducive to health
safeguarded for future generations. Constitution of Norway 1814 (Norway) art 110(b). South Africa's
constitution provides that 'everyone has the right to have the environment protected for the benefit of
present and future generations'. Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (South Africa) art 24.
Kenya's constitution provides for the right to a 'clean and healthy environment ... protected for the benefit
of present and future generations'. The Constitution of Kenya 2010 (Kenya) art 42. The constitutions of
Guyana (Constitution of the Co-operative Republic of Guyana Act 1980 (Guyana) art 36); Papua New
Guinea (Constitution of the Independent State of Papua New Guinea 1975 (Papua New Guinea) art 4);
Germany (Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany 1949 (Germany) art 20a); and Vanuatu
(Constitutionof the Republic of Vanuatu 1980 (Vanuatu) art 7) impose duties to conserve the environment
including for future generations. See Tremmel, above n 22, 192 for a comprehensive list of constitutional
provisions that refer to the environment and future generations.
43 Oposa v Factoran,JR GR No 101083 July 30, 1993.
44 Alfred Rest, 'Implementing the Principles of Intergenerational Equity and Responsibility' (1994) 24
EnvironmentalPolicy and Law 314, 314.
45 While Houck concedes that, given a liberal view of standing in the Philippines, 'the admission of future
generations as plaintiffs puts no additional bodies into the courtroom', he argues that 'the recognition of
future generations as stakeholders ... challenges a host of assumptions concerning national wealth, the
value of future generations, and whether sustainable development is a nice idea or a legal command'.
Oliver A Houck, 'Light from the Trees: The Stories of Minors Oposa and the Russian Forest Cases' (2007)
19 Georgetown InternationalEnvironmentalLaw Review 321, 341. See also, Ma Socorro Z Manguiat and
Vicente Paolo B Yu III, 'Maximising the Value of Oposa v Factoran' (2003) 15 Georgetown International
EnvironmentalLaw Review 487, 493.
46 Gatmaytan argues that protection of the rights of future generations was 'already inscribed in Philippine
law'; the court's decision did not bring about the desired change (ie the cancellation of Timber Licensing
Agreements); the court's statement recognising standing to sue for future generations was obiter dictum; a
liberal approach has always been adopted in Philippines case law to questions pertaining to standing; and
intergenerational equity was 'ultimately useless in the resolution of the case' as the court would have
decided the case 'exactly the same way had the children filed the case solely on their own behalf'. Dante
B Gatmaytan, 'The Illusion of Intergenerational Equity: Oposa v Factoranas Pyrrhic Victory' (2003) 15
Georgetown InternationalEnvironmentalLaw Review 457, 460. Lowe has characterised the assertion by
the named plaintiffs that they 'represent their generations as well as generations yet unborn' as scarcely
more than a rhetorical device. He argues that it was not the rights of a future generation that were being
enforced, but that the duty of certain members of the present generation was being enforced by other
members of the present generation. Vaughan Lowe 'Sustainable Development and Unsustainable
Arguments' in A Boyle and D Freestone (eds) International Law and Sustainable Development: Past
Achievements and Future Challenges (Oxford University Press, 1999) 19, 27.
44 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
There has also been a series of decisions of State courts and tribunals in Australia (including
the NSW Land and Environment Court, and the Victorian Civil and Administrative
Tribunal) concerning the principle of intergenerational equity as set out in legislation. 47
Courts in India, Kenya, Sri Lanka, and South Africa have mentioned or promoted
intergenerational equity in their decisions. 48
At the international level, there has been a more modest process of 'creeping
intergenerationalisation' than that experienced at the national level. 49 An emerging regard
for future generations can be found in treaties, declarations and decisions of the International
Court of Justice.
This same concern for future generations heavily influenced the 1992 UNCED and the
adoption of the concept of sustainable development, with all three non-binding UNCED
instruments making reference to future generations. 5 2 The Rio Declarationon Environment
47 See, eg, Gray v The Ministerfor Planning [2006] NSWLEC 720; Walker v Ministerfor Planning [2007]
NSWLEC 741.
48 The High Court of Kenya made explicit reference to 'the important principle of intergenerational equity'
in a 2006 case concerning water pollution. The court stated that 'the water table and the river courses
affected are held in trust by the present generation for future generations'. Waweru v Republic of Kenya
(2007) AHRLR 149 (KeHC 2006). See discussion in Rajendra Ramlogan, Sustainable Development:
Towards a JudicialInterpretation(Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2011) 222.
49 Catherine Redgwell, IntergenerationalTrusts and EnvironmentalProtection (Juris Publishing, 1999) 186.
5o United Nations Conference on the Human Environment, Stockholm, Sweden, 5-16 June 1972,
Declaration, UN Doc A/CONF.48/14/Rev.1 (16 June 1972) principle 1. There is an intergenerational
element in the UN Charter, referring in the preamble to the determination of the peoples of the United
Nations to save succeeding generations from the scourge of war. Charterof the UnitedNations, preamble.
However, for the reasons identified in Part IV of this article, there are significant challenges to attempting
to afford rights to future generations, and international human rights law is generally not regarded as
extending rights to future generations.
51 See, eg, the 1982 World Charterfor Nature which reaffirms that natural resources must be used in ways
that ensure 'the preservation of the species and ecosystems for the benefit of present and future
generations'. World Charterfor Nature, UN GAOR, 4 8 th mtg, UN Doc A/RES/37/7 (28 October 1982)
preamble. See also the Earth Charterwhich contains four 'broad commitments' including 'Secure Earth's
bounty and beauty for present and future generations: (a) Recognize that the freedom of action of each
generation is qualified by the needs of future generations; (b) Transmit to future generations values,
traditions, and institutions that support the long-term flourishing of Earth's human and ecological
communities'. Earth Charter Commission, Earth Charter<http://www.earthcharterinaction.org/cpntent/
pages/Read-the-Charter.html>
52 See Report of the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, UN Doc
A/CONF.151/26/REV.1 (Vol. I) (12 August 1992) annex ('Rio Declaration on Environment and
Development') principle 3; Report of the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development,
UN Doc A/CONF.151/26/REV.1 (Vol. I), (12 August 1992) annex II ('Agenda 21') [8.7], [8.31], [33.3],
[33.4], [38.5]; Report of the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, UN Doc
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 45
Several environmental treaties, dating to 1946, recognise the need to protect the
environment and safeguard it for future generations. 5 8 These have included treaties that seek
to preserve particular natural resources and assets, such as endangered species, 59 water
A/CONF.151/26/REV.1 (Vol. I) (12 August 1992) annex III ('Non-Legally Binding Authoritative
Statement of Principlesfor a Global Consensus on the Management, Conservation and Sustainable
Development of all Types of Forests')principle 2(b).
53 Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, UN Doc A/CONF.151/26/REV.1, principle 3. This
language draws from the Brundtland Commission's definition of sustainable development: 'development
that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their
own needs'. World Commission on Environment and Development, Our Common Future, 4 2 nd sess, UN
Doc A/42/25 (1987) Part I [27].
54 See, eg, Philippe Sands and Jacqueline Peel, Principlesof InternationalEnvironmentalLaw (Cambridge
University Press, 2012), 207. The Secretary-General asserts that 'fairness between generations is
embedded in the concept of sustainable development'. Reportof the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322,
[9].
5 UNESCO, Declarationon the Responsibilities of the Present Generations Towards Future Generations,
2 9 th sess (12 November 1997) <http://www.unesco.org/cpp/uk/declarations/generations.pdf> ('UNESCO
Declaration').
56 Ibid art 1.
57 Cf the draft Bill of Rights for Future Generations which preceded the adoption of the UNESCO
Declaration. It was the result of a process begun in the 1990s by the Cousteau Society. Its opening article
declared that 'future generations have a right to an uncontaminated and undamaged earth'. Cousteau
Society, 'Rights for Future Generations' <http://www.cousteau.org/about-us/futuregen>. See the
discussion in Maja GOpel, 'Intergenerational Environmental Justice: Tackling a Democratic Deficit with
Ombudspersons for Future Generations' (2011) 14 Effectius Newsletter 3
<http://www.worldfuturecouncil.org/library.html>. See also the Goa Guidelines on Intergenerational
Equity, which articulate a number of strategies for implementing intergenerational rights and obligations,
which 'will become enforceable as they find expression in customary and conventional law'. Goa
Guidelines on IntergenerationalEquity, adopted by the Advisory Committee to the United Nations
University Project on International Law, Common Patrimony and Intergenerational Equity, adopted in
Goa, 15 February 1988, reprinted in Brown Weiss, above n 10, 293. The Goa Guidelines summarise and
endorse the principles enunciated by Brown Weiss in In Fairnessto Future Generations and were signed
by the members of the Advisory Committee in their personal capacities. Collins concludes that 'though
worthy of mention, the Goa Guidelines have little significance regarding the legal status of
intergenerational equity'. Collins, above n 6, 124.
5 See, eg, International Conventionfor the Regulation of Whaling, opened for signature 2 December 1946,
161 UNTS 72 (entered into force 10 November 1948) preamble.
59 Convention on InternationalTrade in EndangeredSpecies of Wild Fauna and Flora, opened for signature
3 March 1973, 993 UNTS 243 (entered into force 1 July 1975) preamble.
46 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
resources, 60 migratory species, 6 1 and the earth's cultural and natural heritage 62 for the benefit
of present and future generations, and those that seek to address particular threats to human
health and the environment. 63 Importantly, however, these references to future generations
have tended to be confined to the preambles of the various conventions or are otherwise
hortatory in nature. 64
The two binding instruments that were adopted at the UNCED in 1992 represent an
advancement in recognising intertemporal environmental concerns. Rather than making
only passing reference to future generations in preambular provisions, the Convention on
Biodiversity Diversity and the UNFCCC both refer to future generations in the convention
text. 65 The UNFCCC identifies five 'principles' that are intended to guide the states parties
in their actions to achieve the Convention's objectives, with the first providing that parties
should protect the climate system for the benefit of present and future generations on the
basis of equity. 6 6 The inclusion of these 'principles' was, however, resisted by a number
of developed nations, led by the United States. 67
The concept of intergenerational equity has been little advanced by the International Court
of Justice and no legal dispute decided by the Court has been resolved by reference to the
doctrine. However, the Court has made reference to environmental obligations owed to
future generations. A small number of dissenting and concurring opinions refer to the
principle of intergenerational equity, with Justice Weeramantry a notable advocate of future
generations.
Justice Weeramantry's first reference to the principle appears in his separate opinion in
Maritime Delimitationin the Area between Greenland and Jan Mayen, in which he refers,
in a footnote, to the use of equity as providing a basis for developing principles of
intergenerational equity in international law. 68 In the 1995 Nuclear Tests case, two of the
dissenting opinions refer to future generations, with Justice Weeramantry characterising
intergenerational equity as 'an important and rapidly developing principle of contemporary
environmental law'. 69 In the later advisory opinion on the Legality of the Threat or Use of
66 UNFCCC art 3.
67 It is reported that during negotiations, these countries insisted that, if such a 'principles' article were to be
included, it should focus specifically on climate change. Bodansky explains that the United States
successfully pushed for a number of changes to article 3 in order to limit its legal implications. 'First, a
chapeau was added, specifying that the principles are to 'guide' the parties in their actions to achieve the
objectives of the Convention and to implement its priorities. Second, the term 'states' was replaced by
'parties'. Finally, the term 'inter alia' was added to the chapeau to indicate that parties may take into
account principles other than those in article 3. These three modifications were intended to forestall
arguments that the principles in article 3 are part of customary international law and bind states generally.
Instead, the principles clearly apply only to the parties and only in relation to the Convention, not the
general law'. Bodansky also notes that the United States attempted to remove all references to the term
'principles' and, when it failed to delete the term from the title to article 3, it added a footnote stating that
'titles of articles are intended solely to assist the reader', intending this to mean that the titles lacked legal
significance. Daniel Bodansky, 'The United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change: A
Commentary' (1993) 18 Yale Journal of International Law 451, 501. See also, Philippe Sands,
'International Law in the Field of Sustainable Development' (1995) LXVI British Year Book of
InternationalLaw 303, 337 n 140. Redgwell questions whether it is possible to 'ring-fence' article 3 in
this way and argues that the Convention may be viewed as 'beginning the process of defining the obligation
of the present generation to absorb the costs of reducing the risk of global warming for future generations'.
Redgwell, above n 49, 118.
68 Maritime Delimitation in the Area between Greenlandand Jan Mayen (Denmark v. Norway) (Judgment)
[1993] ICJ Rep 38, 83 n 3.
69 Request for an Examination of the Situation in Accordance with Paragraph64 of the Courts Judgment of
20 December 1974 in the Nuclear Tests (New Zealand v France) Case (Judgment) [1995] ICJ Rep 288,
341 ('Nuclear Tests Case'). In his dissenting opinion, Judge Sir Geoffrey Palmer quotes from In Fairness
48 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
Nuclear Weapons the majority of the Court refers to the interests of future generations, 70
with Weeramantry again referring to the 'principle of intergenerational equity' in his
dissenting opinion. 7 1 Importantly, the Court did not go so far as to rely on the principle or
to expressly recognise rights of future generations. In Gabiikovo-Nagymaros Project,
Weeramantry again spoke of the principle of intergenerational equity and of trusteeship of
the earth's resources in his separate opinion.7 2 The majority of the Court made passing
reference only to future generations.73
While advocates for future generations might find it encouraging to see the International
Court of Justice acknowledge the interests of future generations, there has been no
determination by the Court that future generations enjoy rights, except by Justice
Weeramantry, in his separate or dissenting opinions. This sporadic regard for the needs of
future generations falls considerably short of the demanding doctrine of intergenerational
equity.
The references to future generations in municipal laws that are discussed above may be
taken into account in determining the existence of custom. 78 However, the evidential value
of these measures is arguably affected by the extent to which they are implemented and
to Future Generationsand identifies the need to carefully analyse the consequences of mankind's activities
'unless we are to imperil those who come after us': at 419.
70 Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Advisory Opinion) [ 1996] ICJ Rep 226, 244.
71 Ibid 233.
72 Gabaikovo-NagymarosProject (Hungaryv Slovakia) (Judgment) [ 1997] ICJ Rep 7, 110.
73 Ibid 78.
74 With support from Justice Weeramantry, in particular. See above nn 68-72.
75 Collins, above n 6, 120.
76 See above n 39.
77 To the extent that this regard for future generations in environmental matters is one of the elements of
sustainable development, some have argued that it already forms part of customary international law. See
especially, Justice Weeramantry in Gabaikovo-NagymarosProject(Hungary/Slovakia)(1997) ICJ Rep 7,
86. Cf Lowe, above n 46, 31.
78 G M Danilenko, Law-Making in the International Community (Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1993) 84.
FisheriesJurisdiction (United Kingdom v Norway) [1951] ICJ 116.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 49
enforced, rather than remaining 'on paper' and exhortative.7 9 There is also evidence of
intergenerational concern in a number of national constitutions, yet these remain the
exception rather than the rule.80 Those constitutional provisions that include references to
future generations do not purport to grant rights to future generations or attempt to impose
clear obligations owed to future generations. The majority refer to the protection of the
environment for present and future generations and, in a number of cases, express this in
terms of a right held by present generations.8 1 Nevertheless, some commentators look to
these provisions as supporting the emergence of a customary law principle of environmental
responsibility towards future generations 82 while others argue that these references should
be regarded as general political statements. 83
As discussed above, there are numerous international treaties which refer, principally in
their preambles, to future generations. 84 While activities relating to the conclusion of
treaties can be regarded as evidence of state practice,85 these preambular references do not
purport to impose on parties any binding obligations and 'their character is hortatory in
nature'. 86 The references to future generations that appear in operative provisions of
multilateral environmental agreements - in particular, article 3 of the UNFCCC - are
more compelling evidence of an emerging principle of customary international law. 87
However, the influence of article 3 of the UNFCCC is potentially limited by the efforts made
by a number of developed countries to confine the operation of its 'principles' to the
UNFCCC. The protests of the United States and other nations may indicate that the
consensus that is at the core of the development of principles of customary international law
may be lacking. 89
It is necessary to consider whether these references to future generations at the national and
international level evidence the stable and consistent participation necessary to establish
79 A number of scholars contend that a law that exists on paper only and which is not enforced cannot
constitute state practice. See, eg, Karol Wolfke, Custom in Present InternationalLaw (Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers, 1993) 77.
so Collins, above n 6, 137. In addition, the number of states that have established institutional mechanisms
to give voice to the interests of future generations (such as ombudspersons or commissioners) is arguably
too few to justify any claim of general state practice. See Collins, above n 6, 138.
8 See above n 42.
82 Collins, above n 6, 137.
83 Fitzmaurice, above n 30,
151.
84 Further, there is a growing body of non-binding declarations and decisions of international institutions that
make reference to the needs of future generations and of preserving the environment for future generations.
There is support for the idea that these can constitute evidence of custom, to the extent that they provide
indirect evidence of state attitudes. See Brian D Lepard, Customary InternationalLaw: A New Theory
with PracticalApplications (Cambridge University Press, 2010) 180.
1 Ibid 31-3. North Sea ContinentalShelf Cases [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 41.
86 Fitzmaurice, above n 30, 128.
87 It is accepted that a treaty principle can transform into custom. North Sea Continental Shelf
Cases [1969]
ICJ Rep 3, 41.
See above n 67 and accompanying text.
89 As Thirlway observes, 'one State (or a small group of States) may make it clear from the outset that it or
they do not consent to the growth of the customary rule; and in that event, a State in that position will or
may be exempted from the application of the new rule. ... The recognition of this possibility emphasises
the consensual nature of custom'. Hugh Thirlway, The Sources of InternationalLaw (Oxford University
Press, 2014) 13. Further, the opposition of a sufficient number of states to a developing rule will prevent
the rule from coming into existence: at 87. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Advisory
Opinion) [1996] ICJ Rep 226, 255.
50 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
sufficient state practice. 90 The number of states that have adopted national measures is
limited and the references to future generations and intergenerational concerns in treaties
are inconsistent. Certainly, it is not yet possible to claim the participation of 'all or almost
all states who are going to be bound by the emerging customary normative prescription', 9 1
or that the principle has 'generally been adopted in the practice of States'. 9 2 State practice
has not been constant and uniform. 93
In addition, while there is a growing catalogue of laws, declarations and treaties that use the
term 'future generations', there is insufficient evidence that the authors of these measures
held a belief that their practice was rendered obligatory by the existence of a rule of law
requiring it. 94 As Lowe observed in relation to the concept of 'sustainable development',
'there may be evidence of the frequent use of the term but that is by no means the same as
evidence of a general practice accepting the concept as law'. 95
90 Danilenko, above n 78, 94. The ICJ Statute refers to 'general practice accepted as law'. Statute of the
InternationalCourt of Justice art 38.
91 Danilenko, above n 78, 94.
92 Anglo-Norwegian FisheriesCase (United Kingdom v Norway) [1951] ICJ Rep 116, 128. In the North Sea
ContinentalShelf Cases, the ICJ remarked that state practice must be 'extensive'. North Sea Continental
Shelf Cases [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 43.
93 Asylum Case (Colombia v Peru) [ 1950] ICJ Rep 266, 276. Rights ofPassage Over India (Portugalv India)
[1960] ICJ Rep 6, 40.
94 North Sea ContinentalShelf Cases [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 44.
95 Lowe, above n 46, 24.
96 Peter Lawrence, 'Justice for Future Generations: Environment Discourses, International Law and Climate
Change' in Brad Jessup and Kim Rubenstein (eds) EnvironmentalDiscourses in Public and International
Law (Cambridge University Press, 2012) 32, 33.
97 As Sands notes, 'evidence of a broad acceptance of the principle [that the activities of present generations
are limited by the obligation to take account and safeguard the developmental and environmental needs of
future generations] does not however translate easily into prescriptions as to what the principle means in
practice'. Philippe Sands, 'Protecting Future Generations: Precedent and Practicalities' in Emmanuel
Agius, et al (eds), Future Generationsand InternationalLaw (Earthscan Publications Ltd, 1998) 83, 86.
98 Lowe, above n 46, 30. In the North Sea Continental Shelf Cases, the ICJ observed that 'it would in the
first place be necessary that the provision concerned should, at all events potentially, be of a fundamentally
norm-creating character'. The court noted that the 'very considered, and still unresolved controversies' as
to the exact meaning and scope of the equidistance principle denied it the necessary norm-creating
character. North Sea ContinentalShelf Cases [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 42.
99 Lowe, above n 46, 29. See also, Warren who argues that 'if it is a principle, then surely it is an ethical
principle rather than a legal one. Although it has been incorporated in a number of international legal
instruments ... references are aspirational and do not elaborate on how the principle is to be implemented
or enforced'. Lynda M Warren, 'Legislating for Tomorrow's Problems Today - Dealing with
Intergenerational Equity' (2005) 7 EnvironmentalLaw Review 165, 168.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 51
has been expressed at the national and international level can be viewed as possessing the
necessary norm-creating character required to give rise to a principle of customary
international law that is binding on states. While it may be argued that humankind should
owe an obligation to the future, the nature of any such obligation remains undeveloped.
Arguably, it may be characterised as a broad injunction to have regard to the interests of
future generations when undertaking, or permitting others to undertake, activities that have
an effect on the environment. 10 0
The view that the broad concept of intergenerational concern in environmental matters exists
without the imprimatur of law may be contested by some commentators, who argue that
there is evidence of the emergence of a principle of customary international law. 10 1 It is
clear, however, that international law has not moved beyond this general concern for future
generations to recognising the detailed doctrine of intergenerational equity advanced by
Brown Weiss. 102 There is no legally binding international instrument that commits states
specifically to the protection of future generations 103 and the references in laws and treaties
do not demonstrate an endorsement of the generational rights perspective proposed by
Brown Weiss or support the conclusion that future generations have been afforded
justiciable rights under international law. 104 Regrettably, some 25 years after the publication
of Brown Weiss' seminal work, the detailed doctrine of intergenerational equity remains an
inchoate call to action - a 'cultural value' 10 5 - with international law having done little
to promote the comprehensive doctrine of intergenerational justice as a binding principle. 106
Although intergenerational equity does not enjoy the status of a binding legal principle at
international law, and Brown Weiss' vision of planetary rights and obligations does not exist
in enforceable terms, there have been repeated demands to give a voice to future generations.
Commentators have proposed the use of trustees, guardians, ombudspersons, and
commissioners to act as representatives for future generations. 107
Brown Weiss couched her doctrine of intergenerational equity in terms of a planetary trust.
However, it is not clear, as a matter of law, that a trust form yet exists that can accommodate
her notion of trusteeship - unlimited geographically or temporally. Given that the
international community of states has shown little interest in proposals that seek to invoke
SP W Bimie and A E Boyle, InternationalLaw and the Environment (Oxford University Press, 2 nd ed, 2002)
90.
105 Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc A/68/322, [4]. The Secretary-General writes that, 'few would
question the responsibilities that the world owes to its children and grandchildren, at least in the moral
sense if not strictly in the law': at [3] (emphasis added).
106 Interestingly, Brown Weiss commented in 2010 that 'the international legal community has taken
significant steps towards incorporating intergenerational equity into policies, laws and institutions at the
international, national and local levels'. Edith Brown Weiss, 'Implementing Intergenerational Equity' in
Malgosia Fitzmaurice, David M Ong and Panos Merkouris (eds) Research Handbook on International
EnvironmentalLaw (Edward Elgar Publishing Limited, 2010) 100, 108. She goes on to acknowledge that
more is required in order to put in place rights and obligations, and that the advances to which she refers
are 'miniscule in relation to the challenges': at 108.
107 See, eg, International Human Rights Clinic at Harvard Law School, above n 40.
52 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
the trustee-beneficiary relationship for future generations,1 08 this article will focus on the
recent calls for bespoke institutional mechanisms for giving a voice to future generations
that featured at Rio+20. 109
Guardians seek to advocate for the best interests of those who are unable to represent
themselves."' A guardian for future generations would extend this custodial relationship
to those who, for reason of not yet having been born, are incapable of advancing their own
interests. A guardian would give a voice to the otherwise silent future, advocating for their
best interests, and exercising and enforcing any rights they might enjoy. Christopher Stone
has long advocated for the role of the guardian in environmental matters, including the
possibility of appointing guardians to secure an effective voice for the environment itself. 112
While guardians advocate for the best interests of those unable to administer their own
affairs, an ombudsperson is understood to occupy a more investigative and advisory role.
Typically, an ombudsperson is an independent official that acts as a representative of public
interests, scrutinising governmental administration and actions, performing an evaluative
function, and seeking to ensure legality and fairness in public administration. 113
Brown Weiss contemplated an expansive role for ombudspersons for future generations.
She proposed that they would be responsible, at the national level, for ensuring the proper
execution of agreements incorporating planetary obligations and rights, and, at the
international level, for 'monitor[ing] compliance with international agreements,
10 Secretary-General Kofi Annan proposed in 1997 to reconstitute the UN Trusteeship Council 'as the forum
through which member states exercise their collective trusteeship for the integrity of the global
environment and common areas, such as the oceans, atmosphere and outer space'. Renewing the United
Nations: A Programfor Reform - Report of the Secretary-General,51s sess, Agenda Item 168, UN Doc
A/51/950 (14 July 1997) [85]. Justice Weeramantry proposed that the International Court of Justice should
act as the trustee of intergenerational rights, 'in the sense that a domestic court is a trustee of the interests
of an infant unable to speak for itself.' Nuclear Test Case [1995] ICJ Rep 288, 341.
109 For a detailed consideration of the use of intergenerational trusts for environmental protection, see
Redgwell, above n 49.
110 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 124.
" Black'sLaw Dictionarydefines a guardian as 'one who has the legal authority and duty to care for another's
person or property, esp. because of the other's infancy, incapacity or disability'. Bryan A Garner (ed),
Black's Law Dictionary (West Publishing, 9 th ed, 2009) 774.
112 Christopher Stone, Should Trees Have Standing: Towards Legal Rights for Natural Objects (W Kaufmann,
1973) 18.
113 Black's Law Dictionarydefines an ombudsman as 'an official appointed to receive, investigate, and report
on private citizens' complaints about the government [or] a similar appointee in a nongovernmental
organisation'. Garner, above n 111, 1196. See discussion in International Human Rights Clinic at Harvard
Law School, above n 40, 15; and Catherine Pearce, 'Ombudspersons for Future Generations: A Proposal
for Rio+20' (2012) 6 Perspectives <http://www.unep.org/civil-society/DocumentsandResources/
Publications/NewPerspectives/tabid/101098/Default.aspx>.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 53
2 Existing NationalInstitutions
A number of institutions exist at the national level for protecting the interests of future
generations. Each differs in terms of its structure and the powers enjoyed by the office, but
they have tended to be advisory and consultative, playing a more modest role than Brown
Weiss' proposed ombudspersons for future generations.
Israel established the first Commission for Future Generations in 2001. The Commission
acted as a voice for future generations in policy-making, with broad advisory and
investigative powers, reviewing legislation and advising on its effects on future
generations.116 The Commission was disbanded in 2007.117
In 2008, Hungary established a Parliamentary Commissioner for Future Generations, with
power to review and propose legislation, to investigate complaints, to advocate for future
generations' needs and to perform an advisory function. The Commissioner enjoyed
significant independence in advocating for the interests of future generations but the office
was replaced in 2012 by the Office of the Commissioner for Fundamental Rights, with a
Deputy Commissioner charged with protecting future generations' interests.1 18
Governmental agencies and organs with responsibility for sustainable development and for
future generations' interests exist in a number of countries. These include Canada, 1 19
France,12 0 New Zealand,1 2 1 Finland,12 2 Germany 2 3 and Wales.12 4
125 See, eg, the 1992 proposal made by Malta to the UNCED that the Rio Declaration on Environment and
Development recognise the responsibility of each generation to provide access in national and international
fora to guardians for future generations. PreparatoryCommittee for the United Nations Conference on
Environment and Development, Working Group III, Principleson GeneralRights and Obligations, 4 th sess,
A/CONF.151/PC/WG.III/L.8/Rev.1/Add.2 (21 February 1992). The proposal was not adopted and Agenda
21 simply states that UNCED took note of but did not act upon other institutional initiatives, such as the
appointment of a guardian for future generations. Agenda 21, UN Doc A/CONF.151/26/REV.1, [38.45].
The Experts Group on Environmental Law of the Brundtland Commission also recommended the
appointment of an ombudsperson at the international level, charged with protecting the interests of future
generations. World Commission on Environment and Development Experts Group on Environmental
Law, Environmental Protection and Sustainable Development: Legal Principles and Recommendations
(Graham & Trotman, 1986) 16. See discussion in Redgwell, above n 49, 86.
126 United Nations, Rio+20 <http://www.uncsd2012.org/about.html>.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 55
The Major Group for Children and Youth, 127 with support from a number of civil society
organisations 128 and Member States 129 called for the establishment of national
ombudspersons for future generations. Described as 'independent institutions, working
from the heart of government' and in all areas of policy-making, proponents suggested that
ombudspersons should provide 'an assessment of the long-term impacts of public policies
and legislative proposals [and] respond to citizen petitions, investigating claims of
environmental crimes and offences and engaging in either conciliation or litigation'. 130
More controversially, it was proposed that ombudspersons would hold governments
accountable 'if they do not deliver on sustainable development goals'. 13 1
127 Major Group for Children and Youth, Contribution to the Outcome Document of Rio+20 (1 November
2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>.
128 Including the Advisory Group on International Environmental Governance (The UNEP Major Groups and
Stakeholders), Wildlaw UK, Interfaith Consortium, Earth Charter International, Women's Major Group,
World Future Council, Stakeholder Forum for a Sustainable Future, BOND Development and Environment
Group, Environmental Pillar, Eurostep, United Nations Environment Program, and Workers and Trade
Unions Major Group. See Advisory Group on International Environmental Governance (The UNEP Major
Groups and Stakeholders), Submission to the UNCSD Bureau as Input to the Zero Draft Outcome
Document for the UN Conference on Sustainable Development (31 October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>; Wildlaw UK, Submission by Wild Law UK to the United
Nations Conference on Sustainable Development (27 October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>; Interfaith Consortium for Ecological Civilization,
Submission (31 October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>; Earth
Charter International, Earth CharterInternationalRecommendations for the Zero Draft of the UNCSD
(Rio+20) Outcome Document (1 November 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd
2012.org/comp-mgs.html>; Women's Major Group, Women's Major Group Summary Input to "Zero
Draft" Outcome Document UN Conference on Sustainable Development (Rio+20) (1 November 2011)
Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>; World Future Council, Contribution to
Rio+20 Outcomes Theme II, InstitutionalFramework for Sustainable Development Ombudspersons for
Future Generations: Tackling Sustainability Implementation Gaps (1 November 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>; Stakeholder Forum for a Sustainable Future, Rio+20 Zero
Draft Submission (1 November 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>;
BOND Development and Environment Group, UK NGOS's Joint Rio+20Narrative (1 November 2011)
Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>; Environmental Pillar, Rio+20: Taking
Action for a Sustainable Future (October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>; Eurostep, Contribution to the Zero Draft of the Outcome
Document for Rio 2012 (1 November 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd2012.org/
comp-mgs.html>; United Nations Environment Program, Common Statement by the UN System Chief
Executive Boardfor Coordination(CEB) on the Outcome of the United Nations Conference on Sustainable
Development (1 November 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd20l2.org/comp-mgs.html>;
International Trade Unions Confederation, Workers and Trade Unions' ConsolidatedContribution to the
United Nations Conference on Sustainable Development (27 October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>.
129 In particular, support was provided by the EU negotiating group. See HC 172 Outcomes of the UNRio+20
Earth Summit, Written Evidence Submitted by Alliance for Future Generations to UK Parliament
Commons Select Committee (14 September 2012) <http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/
cm201213/cmselect/cmenvaud/writev/172/m02.htm> The proposal was also supported by the European
Economic and Social Committee, Opinion of the European Economic and Social Committee Rio+20:
Towards the Green Economy and Better Governance (21 September 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://
www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>.
130 Major Group for Children and Youth, above n 127, 4.
131 World Future Council, above n 128, 3.
56 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
A second proposal, for a High Commissioner for Future Generations located within the UN
system,132 was advanced by the Alliance for Future Generations. 133 The proposal was
supported by several stakeholders 134 and reportedly received support from a number of
states. 135
The proposal, the detail of which was set out in several discussion papers, 136 contemplated
an ambitious role for the High Commissioner, acting as a 'mechanism to safeguard long-
termism and the needs of future generations at the global level'. 13 7 It was proposed that the
High Commissioner would initially play an advisory and advocacy role, while developing
132 A number of options were proposed for the institutional location of the High Commissioner, which would
be established through a General Assembly resolution: (i) as a subsidiary organ of the General Assembly;
(ii) as an office of the Secretary-General; (iii) within the Economic and Social Council; or (iv) seated in
the High-Level Political Forum. See Marcos Orellana, Catherine Pearce and Yulia Genin, Center for
International Environmental Law and World Future Council, The High Commissioner for Future
Generations: The Future We Want (4 June 2012) World Future Council, 5 <http://
www.worldfuturecouncil.org/library.html>.
133 The Alliance for Future Generations Rio+20 Working Group, Rio+20: Open ChallengePaper(28 October
2011) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>. The Alliance for Future
Generations currently has 19 member organisations and a number of individual members. Member
organisations include the World Future Council and the Foundation for Democracy and Sustainable
Development. Alliance for Future Generations, Our Members <http://www.alliancefor
futuregenerations.org/our-members/>.
134 Including Major Group for Children and Youth, Advisory Group on International Environmental
Governance (The UNEP Major Groups and Stakeholders), Civil Society Reflection Group on Global
Development Perspectives, Wildlaw UK, Interfaith Consortium on Ecological Civilisation, Earth Charter
International, Women's Major Group, World Future Council, European Youth Forum, Stakeholder Forum
for a Sustainable Future, BOND Development and Environment Group, Environmental Pillar, Eurostep,
and Workers and Trade Union Major Group. See Major Group for Children and Youth, above n 128;
Advisory Group on International Environmental Governance (The UNEP Major Groups and
Stakeholders), above n 128; United Nations-NGLS, Summary Report: Civil Society Consultationon Select
Elements of Sustainable Development Governance Conducted by the UN Non-Governmental Liaison
Service (UN-NGLS) for the UN Secretary-General'sHigh-Level Panel on Global Sustainability (13
December 2011) <http://www.un-ngls.org/gsp/docs/SD%20Governance%20Report%20for%20GSP%20-
%20NGLS%2011-2011.pdf>; Wildlaw UK, above n 128; Interfaith Consortium, above n 128; Earth
Charter International, above n 128; Women's Major Group, above n 128; World Future Council, above n
128; European Youth Forum, Contribution to Outcome Document (28 October 2011) Rio+20 UNCSD
<http://www.uncsd2012.org/comp-mgs.html>; BOND Development and Environment Group, above n
128; Environmental Pillar, above n 128; Eurostep, above n 128; Ward, above n 3; ITUC, above n 128.
135 Including the EU negotiating group, with interest from Canada, Australia, Norway and Switzerland. See
Stephen Leahy, Activists Callfor Creation of a High Commissionerfor Future Generationsat Rio+20 (4
June 2012) 2 <http://www.ipsnews.net/2012/06/activists-call-for-creation-of-a-high-commissioner-for-
future-generations-at-rio20/>. There was also considerable activity to promote the idea of a representative
for future generations in the months leading up to Rio+20, including during the Economic Commission for
Europe Regional Preparatory Meeting for UNCSD in which calls for an ombudsperson were favoured by
a number of delegates. See Economic Commission for Europe, Report of the Regional Preparatory
Meetingfor the United Nations Conference on Sustainable Development, UN ESCOR, Agenda Item 8, UN
Doc E/ECE/RPM/2011/2/Add.1 (7 December 2011). See also, the Declaration of the 6 4h Annual UN
DPI/NGO Conference: Sustainable Societies; Responsive Citizens, Bonn, Germany, 3-5 September 2011
<http://www.uncsd2012.org/content/documents/634DPI.pdf>, calling for the establishment of an
ombudsperson at global, national and local levels.
136 See, eg, the discussion paper prepared by Halina Ward for the Foundation for Democracy and Sustainable
Development and World Future Council. Ward, above n 3. See also the paper prepared for the Center for
International Environmental Law and World Future Council by Marcos Orellana, Catherine Pearce and
Yulia Genin. Orellana, Pearce and Genin, above n 132.
137 Alliance for Future Generations, above n 133.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 57
the normative framework for his or her mission. In this capacity, the High Commissioner
would engage in the following:
It was proposed that, even at this initial stage, the High Commissioner should receive
representations, have the ability to investigate complaints, and have the power to request
'reasoned and public responses from states and international institutions'. 1 3 9 The
proponents stated that the responsibilities of the High Commissioner for Human Rights and
the High Commissioner for Refugees offered 'direct inspiration for the powers and
responsibilities of a High Commissioner for Future Generations'. 140
The zero draft of the outcome document that was circulated for negotiation in the lead-up to
Rio+20 went some way towards meeting the demands for a representative for future
generations. It provided, in paragraph 57, that Member States would 'agree to further
consider the establishment of an ombudsperson, or High Commissioner for Future
Generations, to promote sustainable development'. 144
The proposed text had two key shortcomings, however. Firstly, it did not call for the
immediate establishment of such offices but only that they be furthered considered. This
delay was resisted by a number of NGOs and stakeholders. 145 Secondly, concerns were
expressed about the role of the office being framed in terms of the promotion of sustainable
development. Stakeholders insisted that this was inappropriate and that the representatives
should be charged with the promotion of future generations' interests, 146 presumably fearing
that such interests would be lost within the many controversies of the 'notoriously vague' 14 7
concept of sustainable development. 148
The Rio+20 outcome document, The Future We Want, did little to safeguard the interests of
future generations. The zero draft's proposed paragraph 57 did not appear in the final text.
Instead there was a more subdued reference to the interests of future generations in
paragraph 86, in which Member States agreed to 'consider the need for promoting
intergenerational solidarity for the achievement of sustainable development, taking into
account the needs of future generations, including by inviting the Secretary-General to
present a report on this issue'. 14 9 There was no mention of a representative for future
generations.
Informal accounts suggest a number of reasons for the inability to secure agreement for an
ombudsperson or High Commissioner for Future Generations. Reports suggested that the
idea was struck from the document by the Brazilian government, who argued that 'Cuba and
Venezuela would never agree to it'. 150 Others suggested that 'leaders of less industrialised
1 The Future We Want: Zero Draft (10 January 2012) [57] Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd2012.org/
futurewewant.html>.
145 NGOs and Major Groups were invited to suggest amendments to the proposed zero draft. Comments were
submitted on paragraph 57. The Women's Major Group, for example, suggested deleting 'agree to further
consider' and inserting in its place: 'We call for an ombudsperson for future generations'. Similar
amendments were suggested by the Workers and Trade Unions Major Group, and the NGOs group. See
Secretariat United Nations Conference on Sustainable Development, Major Groups' Comments on Section
III Through V, The Future We Want (Received by 29 February 2012) Rio+20 UNCSD, 31
<http://www.uncsd2012.org/resources-mgscomments.html>.
146 Ibid. See also World Future Council, The Mandate of a UN High Commissionerfor Future Generations
(14 February 2012) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://www.uncsd2012.org/index.php?page=view&nr=
867&type=230&menu=38>.
147 Collins, above n 6, 132.
148 As Horn notes, the implementation of sustainable development 'has suffered for a lack of political will,
financial resources and appropriate policies, methods and regulation'. Laura Horn, 'Rio+20 United Nations
Conference on Sustainable Development: Is This The Future We Want?' (2013) 9.1 MacquarieJournalof
Internationaland ComparativeEnvironmentalLaw 1, 26.
149 The Future We Want, GA Res 66/288, UN GAOR, 6 6 th sess, Agenda Item 19, UN Doc A/RES/66/288 (11
September 2012, adopted 27 July 2012) para 86.
15o TimHall, 'Future We (Don't) Want' on The Verb (22 June 2012) <http://www.theverb.org/future-we-dont-
want/>. The World Future Council lamented the Brazilian 'coup' in which Brazil introduced a new text
that removed any reference to intergenerational equity and to representatives of future generations
(referring to text that was subsequently replaced by paragraph 86). World Future Council, 'A Set Back in
Rio: But a Seed is Planted' on Future Justice Blog Post (22 June 2012) <http://www.futurejustice.
org/blog/blog/a-set-back-in-rio-but-a-seed-is-planted/>.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 59
nations opposed the proposal, saying it would disrupt their nations' development',151 with
India expressing the concern that 'such a proposal may open a Pandora's box with similar
demands for other thematic institutions'. 15 2
It is disappointing for advocates of future generations' interests that the attempts to secure
those interests and to pursue justice through the appointment of representatives failed.
However, it is perhaps not surprising that the proposals were defeated, given the very broad
powers contemplated, particularly for the High Commissioner. For states concerned to
avoid incursions on sovereignty, the references in the discussion papers to the High
Commissioner for Human Rights and the High Commissioner for Refugees and the
suggested individual complaints mechanisms and state reporting would likely have been
particularly unpalatable. It is arguable that a more measured strategy, that spoke only of the
consultative and advisory role of the representatives, and that omitted references to the more
adversarial aspects of the representatives' missions, might have enjoyed greater support. 15 3
15 Hirohiko Nakamura and Tetsu Kobayashi, Rio+20: Private Groups Step Up Call to be Heard Before
Rio+20 (20 June 2012) <http://ajw.asahi.com/article/special/rio20/AJ201206200101>. It was claimed by
one commentator that the G77 negotiating group was a 'hindrance' to the establishment of 'a global
ombudsman'. Luke Kemp, 'Reviewing Rio: Lessons for the Future' on The ANURio+20 Project(5 August
2012) <http://anurio20.blogspot.com.au/>.
152 Mira Mehrishi, Comments by Mira Mehrishi, Additional Secretary, Ministry of Environment, Government
of India on the Zero Draft 'The Future We Want' (25 January 2012) Rio+20 UNCSD <http://
www.uncsd2012.org/content/documents/649india.pdf>.
153 Since Rio+20 there have been further calls for representatives for future generations including at the
Budapest Conference of Model Institutions for a Sustainable Future, April 2014, which resulted in the
signing of the Budapest Memorandum < http://www.kas.de/wf/doc/kas_12857-1442-1-30.pdf?140507
135328>.
154 Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc A/68/322. Prior to the publication of the report, the United
Nations Division for Sustainable Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs organised an
Expert Panel on Intergenerational Solidarity on 9 May 2013 to provide an opportunity for stakeholders to
exchange views on intergenerational solidarity and future generations, in order to inform continued
consideration of the topic. See United Nations Sustainable Development Knowledge Platform 'Expert
Panel on Intergenerational Solidarity' <http://www.sustainabledevelopment.un.org>.
155 Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [62]-[67].
156 Ibid. See United Nations Sustainable Development Knowledge Platform 'High-Level Political Forum'
<http://www.sustainabledevelopment.un.org>. For an overview of the circumstances surrounding the
replacement of the Commission on Sustainable Development with the High-Level Political Forum, and the
alternative proposal for a Sustainable Development Council, see Horn, above n 148, 13-16.
157 Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [56].
151 Ibid [63].
60 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
office would not receive reports from states. 159 Importantly, the Report acknowledges the
challenges of defining rights for future generations, 160 and its discussion of the possible role
for a representative does not include those functions that would involve the enforcement of
purported rights of future generations.
159 Ibid. Described as a 'related option, but with a lighter institutional footprint', the 'Special Envoy' would
be a global independent advocate for intergenerational equity; promote and facilitate the inclusion of best
practices in policy-making; conduct public advocacy; and report annually to the General Assembly and on
request to the High-Level Political Forum. Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [65]. This
option has been criticised by representatives of the World Future Council as the 'role risks being too weak,
and since the appointment would be made by the SG, it risks not being legitimately recognised by all MS
- it could be marginalised'. Alice Vincent, 'Future Generations at the Decision-Making Table - The U.N.
SG Report on Intergenerational Solidarity and Future Generations' (17 December 2013) Think Climate
<http://www.thinkclimate.org.uk>.
160 Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [19].
161 Format and OrganizationalAspects of the High-Level PoliticalForum on Sustainable Development, GA
Res 67/290, 6 7 th sess, Agenda item 20(a), UN Doc A/RES/67/290 (23 August 2013, adopted 9 July 2013).
The records of its inaugural meeting make passing reference only to future generations. The report of the
High-Level Political Forum's inaugural meeting says only that 'leaders and other participants echoed that
we have a responsibility to future generations'. The Summary of the First Meeting of the High-Level
Political Forum on Sustainable Development, 6 8 th sess, Agenda Item 19(1), UN Doc A/68/588 (13
November 2013) [15]. The closing statement by Dr John Ashe also contains an explicit reference to future
generations: 'This afternoon's discussion illuminated the fact that we can help break out of poverty, achieve
universal human development and entrust a healthy planet to future generations'. Dr John Ashe, Closing
Remarks at the InauguralMeeting of the High Level Political Forum on Sustainable Development, 24
September 2013 <http://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/content/documents/3818PGA%20closing%20
statement%20FINAL.pdf>.
162 The Secretary-General's Report recommends that states may wish to invite the High-Level Political Forum
to consider the possible institutional arrangements and mechanisms for promoting intergenerational
solidarity at its second meeting in June 2014. Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [68].
The theme of the second meeting, which took place from 30 June 2014 to 9 July 2014, was expressed as
'[a]chieving the Millennium Development Goals and charting the way for an ambitious post-2015
development agenda, including the Sustainable Development Goals'. The 'Integrated Programme' for the
meeting did not include a session dedicated to considering the options outlined in the Secretary-General's
Report for promoting intergenerational solidarity. Instead there was a moderated dialogue on 'Ideas and
trends that can shape the lives of present and future generations', asking 'What critical new trends and
ideas will affect future generations? How should they be reflected in the post-2015 development agenda?'
and 'What are the new trends and emerging challenges on sustainable development the forum should
address?' ECOSOC Bureau, Integrated Programme, 26 June 2014, 3 <http://sustainabledevelopment.
un.org/content/documents/Integrated%20Programme.pdf>. A number of panellists and other participants
expressed support for institutional arrangements for intergenerational solidarity. See <http://www.un.org/
News/Press/docs/2014/ecosoc6633.doc.htm>. As at the date of publication, the High-Level Political
Forum appears not to have formally considered the possible institutional arrangements and mechanisms
for promoting intergenerational solidarity, as contemplated by the Secretary-General's Report. Further,
future generations have featured only briefly in the discussions of the Sustainable Development Goals.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 61
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 61
A ConcretisingFuture Generations'Rights
On one view, affording rights to individuals who do not exist deforms the very idea of
human rights, as without identifiable individuals there can be no rights. 163 While Brown
Weiss counters this concern by characterising future generations' rights as collective or
group rights, 164 it is still not clear how rights can be actualised without knowing who they
One of the key outcomes of Rio+20 was the establishment of an intergovernmental process to develop
Sustainable Development Goals to build upon the Millennium Development Goals. There have been
thirteen sessions of the Open Working Group (charged with presenting a proposal on the Sustainable
Development Goals to the General Assembly at its 6 8th session in September 2014), and a 'Zero Draft',
released on 2 June 2014, included express reference to future generations in proposed goal 16.4: 'By 2030
increase inclusive, participatory and representative decision-making at all levels, taking into
consideration the interests of present and future generations'. However, this reference does not appear
in the final report of the Open Working Group, released on 19 July 2014. Open Working Group on
Sustainable Development Goals, Outcome Document (19 July 2014) <http://sustainabledevelopment
.un.org/focussdgs.html>.
163 See discussion by Christopher D Stone, 'Safeguarding Future Generations' in Emmanuel Agius, et al,
Future Generationsand InternationalLaw (Earthscan Publications Ltd, 1998) 65, 67.
1 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 96.
62 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
A number of commentators have suggested that, given the difficulty of according rights to
future generations, the focus of demands for intergenerational justice should shift to
imposing legal obligations on present generations without correlative rights. 16 8 As
highlighted above, this was the approach ultimately taken by the drafters of the UNESCO
Declaration on the Responsibilities of the Present Generations Towards Future
Generations, which came out of a process intended to draft a bill of rights for future
generations. 169 Brown Weiss did not favour a duty paradigm in In Fairness to Future
Generations, arguing that rights should be advanced given their greater normative force. 170
It seems likely that many advocates of future generations will similarly find it difficult to
resist the 'radical, transformative power' 171 of rights when agitating for intergenerational
justice.
165 In asserting that 'there is no theoretical reason why legal systems cannot recognise future generations to
have claims on the present that can be denominated rights', Shelton argues that 'legal systems recognise
several types of legal persons that are societal fictions', such as corporations, and affords them rights.
While true, this says nothing of the unique intertemporal challenge of granting rights to future generations.
Dinah L Shelton, 'Intergenerational Equity' in Ridige Wolfrum and Chie Kojima (eds) Solidarity: A
Structural Principleof InternationalLaw (GWU Law School Public Law Research Paper No. 2013-53)
127 n 12 <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2234144>.
166 See Supanich for a discussion of the asymmetry of power and influence among generations that do not
overlap. Gary P Supanich, 'The Legal Basis of Intergenerational Responsibility: An Alternative View -
The Sense of Intergenerational Identity' (1992) 3 Yearbook of InternationalEnvironmentalLaw 94, 97.
167 Beckerman, above n 13, 54. See also Lowe, above n 46, 27. There are scholars who contend that it is
possible for future generations to be the holders of human rights. Partridge argues that 'neither temporal
remoteness, lack of direct claims, non-actuality, indeterminacy, nor non-reciprocity disqualify future
persons from our moral community' and that 'we can be assured that the moral categories of rights and
corresponding duties, which morally bind us to our contemporaries, can meaningfully be said to bind us to
our successors as well'. Ernest Partridge, 'On the Rights of Future Generations' in D Scherer (ed)
Upstream Downstream: Issues In EnvironmentalEthics (Temple University Press, 1990) 40. See also Joel
Feinberg, who contends that to acknowledge the rights of animals and future generations 'is the very least
we can do for members of endangered species (including our own)'. Joel Feinberg, 'The Rights of Animals
and Unborn Generations' in William T Blackstone (ed) Philosophy and Environmental Crisis (University
of Georgia Press, 1974) 67. See also the discussion by Bell of human rights and future generations in the
context of climate change. Derek Bell, 'Does Anthropogenic Climate Change Violate Human Rights?'
(2011) 14(2) CriticalReview of InternationalSocial and PoliticalPhilosophy 99, 104-10.
168 See, eg, Collins, above n 6, 111; Beckerman, above n 13, 61. But see Supanich who argues that, instead
of appealing to the legal rights of future generations to ground intergenerational equity, the legal basis of
generational responsibility 'lies in the moral-psychological harm to our self-image as members of a species
whose situation on this planet is unique' that results from a failure to act on behalf of the interests of future
generations. Supanich, above n 166, 95.
169 UNESCO Declaration,above n 55.
170 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 45.
171 Conor Gearty, 'Do Human Rights Help or Hinder Environmental Protection?' (2010) 1 JournaloffHuman
Rights and the Environment 7, 20.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 63
instrument. 172 While a number of national constitutions and regional agreements include a
right to a clean environment1 73 there is no human right to the environment at international
law and purporting to extend a human right to the environment across time and to grant it
to all future generations is extremely problematic. 174
Contemplating justice for those living in the future requires such extensive speculation and
involves so much uncertainty that the very premise of intergenerational equity may be
difficult to justify. A representative charged with protecting the interests of future
generations would be required to speculate in the performance of almost every aspect of his
or her mission.
172 See Malgosia Fitzmaurice, 'Environmental Degradation' in Daniel Moeckli, Sangeeta Shah and Sandesh
Sivakumaran (eds), International Human Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2010) 622, 624;
Fitzmaurice, above n 30, 126.
173 More than 90 national constitutions include explicit environmental rights. John H Knox, Report of the
Independent Expert on the Issue of Human Rights ObligationsRelating to the Enjoyment of a Safe, Clean,
Healthy and Sustainable Environment, 2 2 nd sess, Agenda Item 3, UN Doc A/HRC/22/43 (24 December
2012) [12]. See 'List of Constitutional Provisions Relating to Environmental Rights' in EarthJustice,
Environmental Rights Report 2008 appendix <http://earthjustice.org/features/human-rights-and-the-
environment>. At the regional level, the first human rights instrument to contain an express guarantee of
environmental quality was the African Charteron Human and Peoples' Rights. Organization of African
Unity, African Charter on Human and Peoples' Rights, CAB/LEG/67/3 rev. 5, 21 ILM 58 (27 June
1981) art 24. The right of everyone to live in a healthy environment was later enshrined in the San Salvador
Protocol. Additional Protocol to the American Convention on Human Rights in the Area of Economic,
Social and Cultural Rights OASTS 69, 28 ILM 156 (entered into force 16 November 1999) art 11.
Internationally, article 24 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child recognizes the right of the child to
health, requiring that in taking steps to realize that right states shall take all appropriate measures to combat
disease taking into account environmental pollution: a rather indirect recognition of the role of the
environment in ensuring the right to health, rather than an explicit recognition of the right to a clean
environment. Convention on the Rights of the Child, opened for signature 20 November 1989, 1577 UNTS
3 (entered into force 2 September 1990) art 24.
174 See discussion in Redgwell above n 49, 95-6. A number of commentators have argued that a right to a
clean environment is capable of extension to future generations. See, eg, Symonides, who asserts that 'the
right to the environment assumes solidarity with other human beings and mankind' and '[t]hiis solidarity
extends to future generations'. Janusz Symonides, 'The Human Right to a Clean, Balanced and Protected
Environment' (1992) 20 InternationalJournal of Legal Information 24, 29. See also, Melissa Thorme,
'Establishing Environment as Human Right' (1991) 19(2) Denver JournalofInternationalLaw and Policy
301, 310. Depledge and Carlane acknowledge the complexities inherent in recognising collective rights
for future generations but argue that 'the trans-boundary, inter-generational and cross-sectoral nature of
climate change creates a strong case for developing a new category of right(s) that recognises that
individual human beings are intricately tied to the health of the global commons'. Michael Depledge and
Cinnamon Carlane, 'Sick of the Weather: Climate Change, Human Health and International Law' (2007)
9(4) EnvironmentalLaw Review 231, 239.
175 Collins counters criticisms that a duty to future generations is impractical because we do not know what
the future wants by claiming that this argument ignores the 'biological bottom line of being human' and
that future generations will 'most likely still need to breathe air, drink water and eat'. Collins, above n 6,
111. For an interesting discussion of our ability to identify critical resources and predict physiological
needs, see Kristian Skagen Ekeli, 'Green Constitutionalism: The Constitutional Protection of Future
Generations' (2007) 20(3) Ratio Juris 378, 388. Cf Supanich, above n 166, 98.
64 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
will need to survive and flourish. 176 Any decisions about those needs become increasingly
uncertain the further into the future any representative is required to look. 177 The degree of
speculation required is neatly captured by Gillespie who points out that 'one hundred years
ago, it would have been impossible to predict that petroleum or plutonium would be so
important to this generation. Accordingly, this generation has no idea of what the essentials
of the future will be'. 178
Even if it were possible to discern the preferences of future generations, all generations
across time do not form an undivided whole, and each generation is not itself homogenous.
It is inevitable that conflicts will exist both within generations and between generations. 179
How are these to be resolved within a legal framework of binding rights and obligations?
Arguably, any attempt to ascertain future generations' interests and to resolve these conflicts
is misguided. It is contended by some commentators that attempting to do so is a form of
'intertemporal imperialism',1so with the vagueness of intergenerational equity being used
'to import present values and impose them on the future', 'restrict[ing] the liberty of future
generations by binding them to this concept'. 18 1
While Brown Weiss contends that intergenerational rights should belong to all
generations,182 it is inconceivable that the same environmental conditions and natural
resources can be guaranteed to all future generations without distinction and limit,
particularly as populations continue to grow. 183 Given the contemporary 'pro-growth' and
development paradigm, it might simply be unrealistic to expect current generations to make
sacrifices in order to preserve the environment and its resources for all posterity. 18 4 This
would seem to suggest that intergenerational equity should be recast so as to limit duties to
successive generations only, relying on personal and temporal proximity. 18 5 Such an
approach, however, would be unlikely to promote the material changes needed to address
issues such as climate change, the effects of which will be felt for generations to come. 186
In affording rights to future generations it is necessary to decide exactly how much of current
interests should be sacrificed for the benefit of the future. Such decisions should presumably
not be informed by the 'preservationist model', which dictates that the present generation
does not consume anything but saves all resources for future generations, or the 'opulent
model', which allows the present generation to consume all that it wants and generate as
much wealth as it can.187 However, there is no consensus about where, between these two
extreme positions, the duty to future generations should be fixed.18 8 Brown Weiss favours
an 'equality model' that 'requires that each generation pass the planet on in no worse
condition than it received it and provide equitable access to its resources and benefits'. 1 89
Arguably, this provides only limited guidance in determining, as a practical matter, what
each generation must forgo and assists little in directing how a duty to future generations
would be applied in practice, so as to inform contemporary decision-making. 19 0
Affording enforceable rights to future generations would also require speculation about the
likely impacts of today's actions on future generations and about the future state of the
environment. 19 1 To what extent will future generations be better equipped than present
generations to respond to environmental problems? How can decision-makers be certain
that the choices they make today do not turn out to be irrelevant or ill-conceived? 192
184 As Passmore colourfully writes, 'anything we can do would, over millions of years, be infinitesimal in its
effects; not even by reducing our consumption of petrol to a thimbleful apiece could we ensure the
availability of a similar quantity to our distant descendants'. John Arthur Passmore, Man's Responsibility
for Nature: Ecological Problems and Western Traditions (Duckworth, 1974), 78.
See Gillespie, above n 30, 122.
186 Ibid.
187 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 22.
The Secretary-General's Report offers a narrow conception of the needs of future generations, arguing that
'rather than seeking to identify and promote what might be the good life for future generations, the focus
for policy from a future generations perspective should be guided by avoiding and minimizing harm.
Practically, this would mean avoiding irreversible impacts on the ecosystems that provide the basis for
human life - today, as well as in the future'. Report of the Secretary-General,UN Doc A/68/322, [25].
189 Brown Weiss, above n 10, 24.
190 Brown Weiss does set out a number of strategies for implementing the obligations she regards as owed to
future generations including sustainable use of resources; maintenance of facilities and services;
monitoring of natural and cultural resource diversity and environmental quality; impact assessments;
scientific research and technological development; and global learning and education, Brown Weiss, above
n 10, 119-20.
191 'Parfit's Paradox' goes further, positing that present policies will not just affect the wellbeing of
generations in positive and negative ways, but they will also determine which persons are bom. Derek
Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford University Press, 1984). For an interesting discussion see Per
Ariansen, 'Beyond Parfit's Paradox' in Emmanuel Agius, et al, Future Generationsand InternationalLaw
(Earthscan Publications Ltd, 1998) 13.
192 Ajai Malhotra, 'A Commentary on the Status of Future Generations as a Subject of International Law' in
Emmanuel Agius, et al, Future Generations and InternationalLaw (Earthscan Publications Ltd, 1998) 39,
49.
66 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
Not only is it impossibly demanding to discern and protect the needs of all future generations
because of what is unknown (and unknowable), but the potential for conflicts between
imperatives makes the grant of enforceable rights to future generations highly problematic.
It is arguably misguided and even unjust to voice deep concern and to require sacrifices for
future generations when so many of the present generation live in poverty. 193 As the Rio+20
outcome document states: 'Poverty eradication is the greatest global challenge facing the
world today'. 194 The failure to achieve equity within the current generation must be, for
many, an overriding concern, with the actual needs of 'strangers in space' taking precedence
over the anticipated needs of 'strangers in time'. 1 9 5 While Brown Weiss' doctrine of
intergenerational equity includes an intragenerational element, it is relatively under-
theorised1 9 6 and positioning it as a component of intergenerational equity conceals the risk
of conflict between generations. 197 Most significantly, it risks treating present generations
as an instrument for securing the well-being of future generations. 198
Intergenerational equity is resolutely anthropocentric and has been criticised for its 'species
chauvinism'.199 It positions the environment in instrumental terms, to be preserved and
maintained for its enjoyment by present and future humans. Arguably, when considering
justice in environmental issues, such an anthropocentric approach - that disavows justice
for the non-human natural world and disregards the inherent value of nature - cannot be
sustained. 200 This has led Shelton to suggest that a third dimension of solidarity needs to be
considered, in addition to intergenerational and intragenerational equity: 'the solidarity of
humans with others species, ecosystems and nature as a whole'. 2 0 1
It is also necessary to consider how a right to the environment enjoyed by future generations
could be reconciled with countervailing cultural, economic and developmental concerns, as
well as other fundamental human rights. What is the relative value of each and how are they
to be balanced so as to assure justice to present and future generations? While there is a
balancing required in assuring protection of current human rights and courts have developed
tools to manage competing rights and to balance individuals' rights with the public
interest, 202 the intertemporal nature of intergenerational equity presents a further dimension
of likely conflict. A strategy for protecting purported rights of future generations may
struggle to design effective mechanisms for taking into account these competing
dimensions.
Bosselmann has written of the 'huge and ever-widening gap between the promise of
environmental protection and ecological realities'. 203 He concludes that, when measured
'by their own intentions and purpose descriptions', 'environmental policies and laws . .
have not achieved much at all'.204 The international community seems incapable of reaching
consensus on how best to tackle critical environmental problems, such as climate change, 205
and material impediments arguably exist to individuals making the sacrifices needed to react
effectively to the parlous state of the environment. 206 It is important to acknowledge that a
theory of intergenerational rights and obligations may simply be counter-intuitive and
politically unrealistic.
It is likely that many within present generations, at least in capitalist or Western societies
with advanced economies, will be reluctant to sacrifice their current living standards in the
name of indistinct future generations and expectations that current generations will be
willing to forgo their own needs or desires are increasingly misplaced the more remote the
generation. 207 One commentator has dismissed the notion as 'sheer hypocrisy', insisting that
'human nature will always prevent us from being completely impartial, cosmopolitan beings
who rank the interests of distant people or generations equally with those near and dear to
202 Of particular note is the concept of the margin of appreciation, derived from the practice of the European
Court of Human Rights. See for eg Hatton v United Kingdom [2003] VIII Eur Court HR 189, 217 in which
the Court explained that 'regard must be had to the fair balance that has to be struck between the competing
interests of the individual and of the community as a whole; and ... the State enjoys a certain margin of
appreciation in determining the steps to be taken to ensure compliance with the Convention'. See
discussion in Malgosia Fitzmaurice and Jill Marshall 'The Human Right to a Clean Environment- Phantom
or Reality? The European Court of Human Rights and English Court Perspective on Balancing Rights in
Environmental Cases' (2007) 76 Nordic Journalof InternationalLaw 103.
203 Bosselmann, above n 7.
204 Ibid.
205 See, eg, Beckman, above n 7.
206 In his study of public attitudes to climate change and how to influence those attitudes, Patchen notes that
'a great many people seem to be little concerned about climate change and little inclined to take personal
actions, or to support policies that can counter such change'. Martin Patchen, Public Attitudes and
Behaviour about Climate Change: What Shapes Them and How to Influence Them (Purdue University
Outreach Publication, 2006) 1.
207 Collins writes that 'Western culture is arguably too busy enjoying its opulence to worry about the future.
There is convincing evidence that American culture has adopted a largely present-oriented and
individualistic perspective'. Collins, above n 6, 97. See also, Supanich, above n 166, 102.
68 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1 (1)
us'. 208 Without the potential for reciprocity between generations, it is questionable whether
present generations will ever have the requisite motivation to safeguard the interests of
future generations. 209 Arguably, it is simply inconsistent with human nature to demand that
sacrifices be made for distant generations. 2 10
Intergenerational equity arguably ignores political reality and presupposes a political will
that simply does not exist - as evidenced by the unsuccessful efforts that have been made
at international levels to embed intergenerational equity into contemporary decision-
making. It may be unrealistic to expect that governments, 'increasingly distracted by 24/7
media pressures, election timetables and the "urgency of now"' 2 11 will permit the seizure of
current interests for unknown future generations. 2 12 Further, the political will needed to
realise the vision of intergenerational equity at international law likely does not exist, given
the challenge it presents to fundamental international law principles, such as sovereignty 2 13
and international personality. 2 14 A proposal for rights for future generations may be
politically unmanageable in the current legal and political order.
The doctrine of intergenerational equity poses material challenges for international law, and
the translation of Brown Weiss' planetary rights and obligations into legally enforceable
norms appears unlikely. It is difficult to foresee how the international community might
transition from having regard to the interests of the future, and recognising a general
responsibility to future generations, to giving legal expression to a relationship between
-
they get what they inherit, and should count themselves lucky to get it'. Edward A Page, Climate Change,
Justice and Future Generations (Edward Elgar Publishing, 2006) 105.
210 As Gillespie notes, 'the demands of the present more often than not cloud over any intentions of the long-
term future'. Gillespie, above no 30, 122. Cf Feinberg, who assumes that 'it is psychologically possible
for us to care about our remote descendants, that many of us do in fact care, and indeed that we ought to
care'. Feinberg, above n 167, 67.
211 Oxford Martin Commission for Future Generations, Now for the Long Term-The Report of the Oxford
Martin Commission for Future Generations(October 2013) 45.
212 Tremmel argues that it is 'naive to hope that politicians will act in the interests of future generations in the
same way that they do for those citizens who are alive today'. Tremmel, above n 22, 189.
213 The legal principle of state sovereignty forms part of customary international law and is expressed, inter
alia, in article 2 of the UN Charter. See Military and ParamilitaryActivities in and Against Nicaragua
(Nicaraguav. United States of America) (Judgment) [ 1986] JCJ Rep 14, 111. Article 2(1) Charterof the
United Nations states that 'The Organization is based on the principle of the sovereign equality of all its
Members'. The Charterof the United Nations also protects the reserved domain of sovereign States and
prohibits intervention in the territory of sovereign States: arts 2(4) and (7).
214 See Reparationfor Injuries Suffered in the Service of the United Nations (Advisory Opinion) [ 1949] JCJ
Rep 174, 178 in which the Court described the doctrine of international personality as sometimes giving
rise to controversy, when it was asked whether the United Nations possessed international personality and
was therefore capable of availing itself of obligations incumbent on its members. Portman writes that legal
personality 'is principally employed to distinguish between those social entities relevant to the international
legal system and those excluded from it. There is almost universal agreement that states are international
persons. But it is unresolved whether and according to what criteria entities other than states - individuals,
international and non-governmental organizations, private corporations - can become international persons
and what consequences such international legal status entails'. Roland Portmann, Legal Personality in
InternationalLaw (Cambridge University Press, 2010) 1.
Giving a Voice to Future Generations 69
generations that entails legal rights and obligations. 215 Instead, it might be appropriate for
the proponents of future generations' interests to emphasise the morality that Brown Weiss
and others situate at the heart of intergenerational equity and to promote the objective of
intertemporal equity in states' decision-making. 2 16
States could be urged by advocates to embrace the advisory, consultative and educative role
for future generations' representatives contemplated by the Secretary-General's Report,
rejecting the more intrusive, inquisitorial aspects of the missions proposed at Rio+20.2 17
Such a representative could act as an international advocate and moral persuader, raising
public awareness, generating debate, signalling the importance of considering the long term
effects of actions, and working to enhance intergenerational solidarity. 2 18 The lack of
enforceable rights and obligations would, however, act as an important limit on the functions
and powers of any representative for future generations. Absent legally enforceable rights
and obligations, any continuing calls for enforcement by a representative, including through
a complaints mechanism or state monitoring, would be specious. It must be conceded that
the effectiveness of any such agitator may potentially be limited, with it all too easy for
states to disregard those who attempt to influence through moral pressure and absent a legal
mandate.
V CONCLUSION
The Brundtland Commission observed in 1987 that 'we act as we do because we can get
away with it: future generations do not vote; they have no political or financial power; they
cannot challenge our decisions'. 2 19 As the state of the environment continues to deteriorate,
the moral injunction for present generations to reject such short-sighted self-interest and to
be cognisant of the interests of future generations is significant. It is critical that the
international community embrace intertemporal justice if the needs and interests of future
generations are to be given expression. However, to date, the concept of intergenerational
equity has not realised binding status at international law, and future generations do not
enjoy legally enforceable rights. While this circumscribes the role that any global
representative of future generations can play when seeking to irrupt the interests of the future
215 Boyle has dismissed Brown Weiss' proposed extension of international environmental law to future
generations as 'wildly unrealistic' and 'misplaced utopianism', arguing that 'it is already an intractable
task to reconcile the environmental interests of those here and now . . without also embracing the interests
of the future'. Alan E Boyle, 'Book Review: In Fairness to Future Generations' (1991) 40.1 The
Internationaland ComparativeLaw Quarterly 230, 230.
216 See Beckerman above n 13, 61 for an interesting discussion of the moral obligation owed to future
generations.
217 See eg, presentation made by Catherine Pearce, Director Future Justice, to the High-Level Political Forum
on 1 July 2014, during the moderated dialogue on 'Ideas and trends that can shape the lives of present and
future generations'. <http://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/index.php?page=view&nr=872&type
=12&menu=1807&template=1042&play=904>, summarised in the Future Justice Blog: 'Catherine
Pearce, Director Future Justice at the World Future Council outlined what a High Commissioner for Future
Generations at the UN level could look like: acting as an institutional voice, highlighting the long-term
implications of proposed action and present alternatives. The representative, appointed by Member States
would be low on administration, high on visibility. It would have a small multi-disciplinary staff, with the
power of advocacy: nothing more, nothing less'. Future Justice, 'Blog: Moderated Dialogue at the High
Level Political Forum on "Ideas and trends that can shape the lives of present and future generations"' on
Future Justice Blog Posts (2 July 2014) < http://www.futurejustice.org/blog/category/blog/>.
218 In parallel, civil society may wish to continue to advocate for the appointment of representatives of future
generations at the national level, empowered to play a more interventionist role, particularly in those
countries where future generations enjoy protection through a right to a clean environment.
219 World Commission on Environment and Development, UN Doc A/42/25, [25].
70 AustralianJournalof EnvironmentalLaw 2014 Vol 1(1)
into present decision-making, it does not defeat entirely the possibility of giving voice to
those interests. Rather, a representative of future generations should act as agitator and
advisor, emphasising the present generation's relationship, grounded in morality, with
future generations and urging policy-makers and governments to apprehend the interests of
the future.