Journal of Parapsychology, Vol. 48, June 1984
AGAINST HISTORICISM
CriticaL REMARKS ON THOMAS KUHN’S CONCEPTION OF SCIENCE
AND Its RECEPTION IN PARAPSYCHOLOGY
By Gerp H. HévELMANN
ABSTRACT: The origins and essentials of Thomas Kuhn’s historicist conception of
rise, change, and fall of scientific theories and of entire scientific branches are
described in the first part of this contribution. An attempt is made to show that this
conception has been adopted almost unanimously by scientists engaged in parapsy-
chological research. Some unpleasant consequences and dangers of this one-sided
reception of Kuhnianism are pointed out. It is demonstrated that Kuhn's theory
embodies several serious shortcomings and that it only applies to deductive models
of justification. It is suggested that Kuhn's conception be replaced by an alternative
model that, by means of a recourse to elementary practices of predication and action,
allows for proper foundation and justification of scientific propositions. Some
consequences of this alternative conception are pointed out and contrasted with some
of the disastrous implications and consequences the Kuhnian conception entails for
science in general and parapsychology in particular.
In my comments (Hévelmann, 1981) on K. Ramakrishna Rao’s
attempt to point out a fallacy in David Hume's treatise “Of Miracles”
(Rao, 1981b), I argued that Popper (1934/1959) successfully rejected
as being defective on logical grounds the concept of induction that
was considered appropriate by Logical Positivists of the Vienna Circle
and, especially, in Reichenbach’s probability theory of induction.
Therefore, Popper urged that induction be replaced by his deductive
method of testing. In his reply to my comments, Rao (1981a)
correctly points out, however, that the Popperian program likewise is
not free of serious shortcomings.
For decades, Critical Rationalists, that is, adherents of the
Popperian school of philosophy of science, have been thoroughly
discussing what they call the deductive model of justification. They
This article is a revised and enlarged version of a paper I presented at the
‘Twenty-Sixth Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association held at Fairleigh
Dickinson University, Madison, NJ, August, 1983.
I wish to express my appreciation to the following persons for many critical
comments and helpful suggestions on the earlier version of this paper: John Beloff,
Stephen E. Braude, Richard 8. Broughton, Hoyt L. Edge, Patric V. Giesler, David Hess,
Piet Hein Hocbens, Robert A. McConnell, John Palmer, Rex G. Stanford, Douglas M.
Stokes, and Debra H. Weiner.102 The Journal of Parapsychology
came to the insight that, with regard to the problem of an appropriate
basis of justification, the model runs directly into several insurmount-
able difficulties. It was found that any deductive attempt to pull
oneself out of the swamp of uncertainty and to find a solid basis of
justification leads into a threefold impasse. The deductive model of
foundation and justification (a) must make use of circular argumen-
tation, which is logically faulty (circular argumentation here means that
after invoking a number of successive justificatory statements in
support of a given proposition, one is forced to call in the original
proposition itself to support one of these justificatory statements); or
(b) it leads into an infinite regress of justificatory attempts, which is
practically impossible because human beings are mortal (infinite
regress means that for any justificatory statement that is called in
in support of a scientific proposition, a further justificatory statement
can be requested, and so forth ad infinitum); or (c) it leads to an
arbitrary suspension of the postulate of justification or to the dog-
matic choice of a particular basis of justification that itself is un-
founded (dogmatic choice means that the chain of justificatory state-
ments is arbitrarily broken off at one point and that the latest
statement is chosen as the justificatory basis).
Hans Albert (1980, pp. 11-15), a German adherent of the
Popperian school, aptly called this treble alternative of dead ends
Miinchhausen-Trilemma after Miinchhausen, a (fictive) baron and
notorious liar who reported to have pulled himself out of a swamp by
his own tuft. This trilemma is inescapable if solid foundation and
justification are sought to be reached on the basis of a deductive
model. Therefore, Critical Rationalists decided no longer to judge
theories by their internal (logical) consistency but rather by their
steadfastness to thorough scrutiny.
‘An alternative proposal, which proved to be most influential
among “working scientists” (McConnell, 1983, pp. 192-193) as well
as within the philosophy of science (Lakatos & Musgrave (Eds.],
1970), was put forward by Thomas S. Kuhn in his book The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions, which was first published in 1962 by the Univer-
sity of Chicago Press (Kuhn, 1962). Kuhn, who had initially conceived
his concept as a novel theory of historiography of science,! holds that
theories and entire scientific branches develop beyond and quite
‘Therefore, it is at least questionable to talk about Kuhn's “philosophy” of science as
has become customary in recent years.Against Historicism 103
irrespective of any? attempt at justification. As I will shortly uy to
point out, however, Kuhn's way out of the Miinchhausen-Trilemma
turns out to be hardly more adequate than that of the Critical
Rationalists. To the contrary, it shares many of the major short-
comings of its predecessors and even adds a few further quite
insufficient ideas.
HistoricisM: KuHn’s VIEWS OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF SCIENCE
As most parapsychologists are quite familiar with the Kuhnian
conception of rise, change, and fall of scientific theories and entire
scientific branches (I am also going to deal with this familiarity below),
I will restrict myself to a relatively brief outline of the most important
aspects of this conception.
According to Kuhn (1962), who is considerably influenced by the
work of Fleck (1935/1979, 1983),° there are two alternating phases in
the process of science: normal science and extraordinary science. The
term normal science designates the familiar type of research based on
commonly accepted explanatory models, which are referred to as
paradigms. Such paradigms are conceived as sufficiently unprece-
dented, successfully attracting an enduring group of adherents, and
sufficiently incomplete to leave work for those adherents. Extraordinary
science, on the other hand, takes place in the transitional phases
between two paradigms. The following periods mark the develop-
ment of any scientific discipline:
1. Ina preparadigmatic period, more or less random and casual
data gathering takes place drawing heavily on what is readily at hand
from other disciplines or from everyday or workmanlike experiences.
2. In a normal scientific period, the data gathered in the first
period are arranged in an admittedly incomplete paradigm, which,
*Stephen Braude, chairman of the session at the PA. convention where I presented
the earlier draft of this paper, remarked that he believes that I have misunderstood
Kuhn in this respect. Contrary to my claim, said Braude, Kuhn's theory does allow for a
scientific proposition to be adequately founded and justified within a paradigm once
that paradigm has been accepted by a group of scientists. Braude is quite right, but that
is not what I am talking about. Foundation within a paradigm is foundation in a very
restricted sense at best, because the accepted paradigm itself remains unfounded and,
according to Kuhn, must necessarily remain unfounded.
3 Fleck’s philosophy of sci
nce was much more versatile, however, than Kuhn seems
to have realized (Schafer & Schnelle, 1983, pp. 10 and 19).
4For a discussion of the ambiguity and obscurity of Kuhn's use of the term
paradigm, see Masterman (1970).104 The Journal of Parapsychology
nevertheless, must be more powerful than its eventual competitors.
Research activities as well as political and financial matters are
organized; specialization occurs; important problems are disti
guished from less important ones; results of research are recorded in
textbooks; and so on.
3. Anomalies that are contrary to textbook opinion are discovered.
4. If anomalies question the core of the paradigm, or if they are of
practical importance, or if enough time has passed since the anoma-
lies were first reported, a crisis arrives and results in the sapping of
the paradigm and in the loosening of the rules governing scientific
practice within that paradigm.
5. Extraordinary research is conducted to give structure to the
anomaly, thus (often suddenly) creating an entirely new paradigm.
6. A revolutionary struggle between the old and the new paradigm
takes place, and the older one is eventually replaced in whole or in
part by an incompatible new one. That means: revolutions of this
kind are noncumulative changes. The field is completely recon-
structed from its foundations. Because each group of researchers
argues on the basis of its own paradigm in that paradigm’s defense,
paradigms remain totally incompatible, and mutual factual agree-
ment proves to be impossible. In some sense, groups who accept
different paradigms live in different worlds. Besides logic and
experiment, force is needed to settle the issue.
7. After one paradigm has won the struggle, scientists return to
normal science. Textbooks are rewritten, which causes the false
impression of a cumulatively advancing science. Science is conceived
as a nonteleological, rule-guided, puzzle-solving activity, the develop-
ment of which must not be described in terms of foundation and
justification but in those of sociology or social psychology.
HisToricisM IN PARAPSYCHOLOGY
In 1968, Robert McConnell was the first one to bring Kuhn's
model, which is out to replace foundation and justification by ques-
tionable historicism, to the attention of scientists engaged in parapsy-
chological research (McConnell, 1968; also see McConnell, 1966,
1976). McConnell’s 1968 paper was introduced by an editorial note,
which I would like to quote full length here. It reads:
We are privileged to present a hitherto unpublished synopsis of an
important contribution to the understanding of science and particularly
to the understanding of the beginnings of any new field. Although psiAgainst Historicism 105
phenomena are not discussed in this book, we believe that attitudes
toward them will be profoundly influenced by the study and acceptance of
Professor Kuhn's ideas. (p. 321; italics added)
In the light of the seven points just listed, it is quite obvious why
the editor of the Journal of the A.S.PR., the late Laura A. Dale, was so
enthusiastic about the Kuhnian conception: parapsychology was and
remains a “new field,” opposition was and remains strong, and
because parapsychologists wish their field to get a firm footing in the
world of science, they sooner or later need an adequate understand-
ing of the way science develops.
To cut a long story short, parapsychologists took the above
suggestion to heart. They did study Kuhn's ideas and, instead of
calling them scandalous as, in my opinion, they should have done,
they did accept them. A factor further accelerating this one-sided
acceptance has certainly been that several leading figures in the field
set an example by readily adopting Kuhn's conception (Pratt, 1974, in
toto; Thouless, 1972, pp. 100-102). Pratt (1979, p. 26) used Kuhnian
concepts and Kuhnian terminology to identify “a paradigm crisis
within parapsychology.” As far as I can see, today the vast majority of
parapsychologists still highly esteem or more or less explicitly sub-
scribe to Kuhnian opinions, as for instance Kornwachs (1975),
McClenon (1982), Nilsson (1975, 1976), or Winkelman (1980). Others,
such as Edge (1976, 1977, 1978a, 1978b), Stanford (1977), and
Thakur (1977), who find themselves in basic agreement with Kuhn's
opinions, have tried to apply more or less modified versions of the
Kuhnian conception of a paradigm and of his views of scientific
change to the internal and external sociological and political circum-
stances of parapsychological research.
More than a dozen years after he epitomized the Kuhnian
conception for the information of the parapsychological community,
McConnell (1981) briefly recapitulates its influence on the discussions
within the field, and he states:
Kuhn's elucidation of “preparadigm science” has brought a new undet-
standing of parapsychology as an emerging field. (p. 225)
And in his latest book, McConnell (1983, p. 198), for whose contribu-
tions to parapsychology I otherwise have nothing but the highest
respect, assures us that “Kuhn’s basic idea seems inescapable.” It is
obvious that McConnell’s whole book is strongly influenced by Kuhn's
views of development in science. In chapter 18 of that book,
McConnell (1983, pp. 192-207), under the heading “Thomas Kuhn,
Historian and Heretic,” provides a new introduction to Kuhnian106 The Journal of Parapsychology
thoughts. In part, it closely resembles his 1968 paper. This chapter
starts with the following paragraph:
In the present chapter, I shalll ask you to examine the nature of progress
in science, beginning with the following long-established ideas. As you
read these statements, are there any with which you would disagree?
Think about each one for a moment as you go down the list.
1. Science is the accumulation of truth concerning nature.
2. As science progresses, our total understanding converges toward
reality.
3. The unchanging laws of nature are waiting to be discovered (by some
combination of luck, diligence, and insight).
4. The purpose of scientific research is to make new discoveries.
5. The past accomplishments of science are described in its textbooks (by
which each new generation of scientists takes its task from its
predecessors).
In some important aspect, each of these five statements is untrue. Or at
least, there is a historian of science . . . who says they are untrue. His
name is Thomas Kuhn. (p. 192)
Like Kuhn (and maybe McConnell) and to McConnell’s probable
surprise, I very strongly disagree at least with the first four of these
statements. I disagree with them because they merely reflect com-
monly accepted, but nevertheless highly naive and short-sighted
empiristic and realistic misconceptions of the goals of science.
However, these four statements can all be rejected very easily on the
basis of rational counterarguments, which need not make any use of
Kuhnian opinions.
Parapsychologists’ tendency to comfort themselves by subscribing
to Kuhn's historicistic views has not gone unnoticed by the outside
world: a caricature in New Scientist (1979) features a parapsychologist
who, leaning out of a window of his institute, is desperately asking all
passers-by: “Buddy, can you spare a paradigm?” (p. 311). Finally, it
can be inferred from a paper by Reber (1982-1983), which contains
several serious misconceptions of science as well as of parapsychology,
that this critic, at least, also shares Kuhnian views. And even an
unrestrainedly radicalized version of the Kuhnian conception of the
development of science is now available in the works of the British
sociologists Collins and Pinch (1979, 1981, 1982).
Besides two of my own papers (Hévelmann, 1983b, in press), I
came across only very few pieces in the parapsychological literature
appearing to express at least moderate disagreement with Kuhn's
historico-sociological views of science. By far the most unmistakable
rejection of parapsychologists’ enthusiasm about Kuhn's conception is
to be found in John Beloff’s reaction to the paper by Thakur (1977):Against Historicism 107
I would like to go on record as a skeptic with regard to the Kuhnian
concept of a paradigm. For that reason I rather regretted that Professor
Thakur spent so much of his paper discussing what I consider to be
essentially the idle question of whether parapsychology is or would
become a normal science in the Kuhnian sense. ... There has been an
enormous amount of controversy, of a rather tedious kind, as to whether
psychology has ever acquired a paradigm, whether behaviorism was a
paradigm, and so on. None of this debate, it seems to me, led anywhere
and I think it would be far better to simply skip this whole approach and
ask more important questions. (Beloff, 1977, p. 210)
Moreover, I found three book reviews in the parapsychological
literature in which the authors are criticizing the consequences of
uncritically adopting Kuhn’s conception. It may be an overinterpre-
tation to say that they are critical of Kuhn, but they doubtlessly are
highly skeptical about Collins and Pinch’s radicalization of Kuhn's
approach. Thus, Gregory (1982) writes:
There are problems and ambiguities about paradigmatic language, now
well recognized . . ., but unceremoniously brushed aside by Collins and
Pinch, . . . If things are as Collins and Pinch say, then the whole endeavor
of psychical research, of judging carefully whether and when and under
what conditions and why something happens, is a futile waste of time, or
at any rate a rather masochistic game perpetuating a sort of Sartresque
huis clos in which parapsychologists explain away their failures and skeptics
explain away parapsychologists’ successes, the two sides fruitlessly chas-
ing each other's tails for ever and ever and ev . There is, we are told,
no such thing as rational argument over and above social convention.
(Gregory's italics; pp. 310-311)
Similarly, in a review of the same book, Stokes (1983) writes:
The authors themselves adopt the relativistic view of rationality (i.
there is no demonstrably correct form of reasoning), and they
explicitly espouse a radical interpretation of Kuhn’s theory of scientific
revolutions. . . . Their position in this regard seems far too radical. (p. 84)
And Stokes continues:
It should be noted that the relativism proposed by Collins and Pinch
constitutes a danger to parapsychology. If parapsychologists in large
numbers were to adopt such a relativistic position, the field would be in
danger of isolating itself from science and diverging from acceptable
scientific practices. It would then truly deserve to be a laughing stock for
the orthodox scientific community. Finally, if the authors’ relativistic
position is correct, what reason does a reader have for accepting their
arguments as valid or the form of rationality employed by them as the
correct one? In this respect, the relativistic position in some sense refutes
itself. (p. 85)108 The Journal of Parapsychology
Stokes had already criticized Collins and Pinch’s relativistic posi-
tion in an earlier review, where he wrote:
According to Collins and Pinch, what is a scientific truth depends as
much on power struggles and fund raising as on rational argument and
empirical evidence. This is social determinism taken to its most absurd
extreme. If this view is accepted, then the world really was flat a
millenium ago. (Stokes, 1980, p. 370)
Despite these rare exceptions, which exhibit a basically critical atti-
tude toward Kuhnian ideas or their radicalization, at least Kuhn's
own somewhat less radical conception has been avidly seized on by a
very great number of parapsychologists. The high esteem of the
Kuhnian way of looking at science appears to be almost omnipresent
and unanimously shared by the people engaged in parapsychology. It
is fairly obvious that parapsychologists feel very well understood by
this historian of science. Now it is my aim here to thwart this total
agreement a bit. My criticism will turn not only against the obscurity
of parts of the Kuhnian conception—as, among others, Masterman
(1970) has done>—butalso against the conception as a whole. As faras I
can see, parapsychologists’ appeal to Kuhnianism serves (or may be
serving) several functions for their field. I will only mention three of
them:
1. Many parapsychologists seem to believe that Kuhn is picturing
a pathway—and some parapsychologists may even consider this the
only possible pathway—to future legitimacy of parapsychological
research. Obviously, they think that Kuhn has adequately described
the way science develops, and they hope that, after a future paradigm
shift, they will be the adherents of the paradigm that has won the
“struggle for life” Accordingly, many seem to be less concerned with
scientific truth and rational argumentation than with ways to find the
most strategic position on the battlefield of science, which they hope
to reach in time to avoid a Custerian Little Big Horn. I think that this
attitude involves a twofold naiveté and shortsightedness, as it is not
only based on Kuhn's theory of developments in science but, even
worse, on a serious misunderstanding of that defective theory.
Parapsychologists, who appeal to Kuhnian historicism in this way, are
> Margaret Masterman's paper was one of the most important criticisms of the 1962
edition of Kuhn's book. It had a considerable influence on Kuhn's “Postscript” of 1969,
in which he suggested several terminological clarifications (Kuhn, 1970, 1974). In this
postscript, paradigm is used in two major senses: in a global sense, relabeled disciplinary
matrix, it includes paradigms and other aspects of scientific activity; and in a particular
sense, relabeled exemplars, paradigms are aspects of the disciplinary matrix.Against Historicism 109
courting disaster: according to Kuhn, it is, by definition, impossible to
predict future paradigm shifts. Because the very nature of paradigm
shifts lies in their success, they can only be observed after the fact.
Therefore, appeals to Kuhn cannot give any comfort to emerging
scientific disciplines. Quite to the contrary—and that is why I think
that these parapsychologists are throwing boomerangs— Kuhnianism
can even be used to justify orthodox intolerance toward such emerg-
ing fields, as it provides establishment science with a historicist pretext
for its constant refusal to take deviant claims seriously.
2. Inthe opinions of some parapsychologists, the Kuhnian concep-
tion may readily serve as a welcome excuse for the fact that, hitherto,
they have constantly failed in all their attempts to establish their field
as a legitimate and well-recognized branch of science. Thus, the ways
science is believed to develop can be held responsible for all such
failures; and parapsychologists can consider themselves the innocent
and defenseless victims of a ruthless and merciless social and/or
political process. Moreover, the critics of the field can be viewed as
being those people who just happen to be adherents of a fully
developed paradigm that is (still) disposing of the power to success-
fully combat against aspiring preparadigmatic fields such as para-
psychology. One can even afford to more or less politely ask the critics
to “eventually die out,” as Max Planck put it in his autobiography.
3. Adherence to the Kuhnian model seems to dispense scientists
(and parapsychologists, for that matter) from the obligation to ad-
vance tightly reasoned scientific propositions, because development
of science and acceptance of supposed scientific truths need no longer
be regarded as a question of foundation and justification but as one of
social power. Thus, proper justification of scientific propositions can
be viewed as being secondary or even an unnecessary accessory.
SciIENTIFIC PRoposiTIONS: FACTUAL Success VERSUS FOUNDATION
AND JUSTIFICATION
As I have tried to demonstrate in my brief summary of the
Kuhnian conception, sociological and historical reflections in science
and the recourse to factual developments are now to replace founda-
tion and justification of scientific propositions. ‘This is surprising, at
first sight, because “foundation” and “justification” traditionally were
supposed to denote methodical or systematical rather than mere
historical securing of such propositions. Where previously a recourse
to (relatively) safe starting points was thought to be possible, it is now110 The Journal of Parapsychology
enough simply to make reference to the factual course of theory
building and theory enforcement. As I have emphasized in the
beginning, this is a symptom of the apparent crisis in those concepts
of foundation and justification as they are held by the “analytically”
oriented schools in philosophy of science (logical positivism, critical
rationalism, structuralism, and their various offspring). Strictly
speaking: after Kuhn, valid justification in a strict sense does no
longer exist in science. Questions as to whether a theory is a good and
sound one are now answered by making reference to the fact that this
theory did factually prevail (or fail).
In my view, this Kuhnian criticism of the concept of justification is
nothing but a highly intelligent excuse for the failure of the deductive
model of justification. Kuhn's conception, which was intended to
avoid the dogmatism with which the third lemma of the aforemen-
tioned Miinchhausen-Trilemma is unsolvably connected, and accord-
ing to which every possible statement that may be called in for
justificatory purposes is to be viewed as “theory-laden” and, hence,
itself in need of adequate justification, is itself dogmatic. The Kuhnian
criticism of justification only applies to deductive models of justifica-
tion. By definition, deduction necessarily implies that certain linguisti-
cally composed statements, sentences, propositions are derived from
other, more general statements, sentences, propositions that of course
are linguistically composed themselves. That means that, in the last
resort, the unavoidability of this linguistic composition of all possible
statements in the process of deduction is the reason why the deductive
model of justification runs directly into the unpleasant Miinchhausen-
Trilemma: on the one hand, “language-free deduction” is contradic-
tory in terms; on the other hand, adequate justification of any
linguistically composed statement is obligatory.
As I observed in the preceding, Kuhn's criticism of the concept of
justification only applies to such deductive models. It completely loses
sight of the fact that adequate foundation and justification of scientific
propositions are well possible by means of a recourse to elementary
practices of predication and action which, on the most basic level, can
dispense with linguistically composed statements and therefore do
not lead into the Miinchhausen-Trilemma. For obvious reasons it is
impossible here to go into the details of a theory of elementary
predication and a theory of action (Kamlah & Lorenzen, 1973;
Lorenzen, 1969) or to develop a whole theory of foundation and
justification. But the following outline should suffice to explain the
essentials in the present context.
In science, human beings, who are able to act, to speak, and toAgainst Historicism 11
learn by way of acting and speaking, are trying to solve problems that
they and other human beings are confronted with. In the ideal case,
scientists are directly or indirectly attempting to help their fellow
human beings to live a better, an easier, or a healthier life. What else
should be the purpose of scientific research?® These goals can only be
reached if the actions scientists perform are successful. So, why not, in
a pragmatic’ sense, base our scientific propositions on what scientists
are actually doing when they do scientific research? Why not base
them on the actions they perform, as, for instance, their experimental
actions in the experimental sciences? The problems the deductive
model is confronted with can easily be avoided that way. That is
because, in the last resort, any scientific proposition, say, in the
experimental sciences can be reduced in a finite number of steps to
the actions the experimenter performs. The success of these experi-
mental actions functions as the criterion of the truth of scientific
propositions about the experiment in question. In this sense, the
action of scientists can serve as the justificatory basis for scientific
propositions. If the utility of a certain action is also questioned by an
incredulous objector (as the propositions based on this action may
have been), then this action must simply be performed to demon-
strate whether it is appropriate for reaching the success (producing an
effect, and so forth) that has been claimed in the propositions that
were based on that action. If this action succeeds, the propositions are
justified. In everyday life, we all do not have the slightest problem
with this procedure of justifying our claims. If, to use a very
primitive example, our claim that under such and such circum-
stances it is possible to light a candle is questioned by someone, then,
in the last resort, we are forced to actually perform the action of
lighting a candle under the specified circumstances to demonstrate
whether our claim was justified. If this action succeeds, our claim is
justified. With a recourse to the actions scientists perform, which can
always be reached by a finite number of steps, we are equipped with a
reliable, language-free basis for a proper justification of scientific
propositions, which cannot be subjected to further justificatory
®Some critical comments on claims to the effect that the purpose of science is to
“discern reality,” or to explain the world, the universe, human destination, and what
not, are to be found in Hévelmann (in press, section IIL.3).
7] am somewhat hesitating to use the term pragmatic in this context, as it is liable to
be misunderstood as a reference to William James's pragmatism or Charles Sanders
Peirce’s pragmaticism. While the position outlined in this paper is doubtlessly influ-
enced to some degree by the philosophies of Peirce, James, and Dewey, there are also a
lot of very important differences.112 The Journal of Parapsychology
requirements. Kuhn clearly fails to consider this way out of the
Minchhausen-Trilemma. The problem of foundation and justifica-
tion of scientific propositions is solvable. Kuhn has only shifted and
obscured it.
An historically organized practice as that advocated by Kuhn is
continually in danger of privately becoming a stylish, but cheap,
defense of poor science. If the quality of a theory is not primarily
judged by the justification of that theory but rather by the way it has
superseded competing ones, then it becomes possible that a theory is
considered a proper one simply because it superseded rivaling ones
that way. Considerable parts of current philosophy of science as well
as of current practice in various scientific branches indicate that many
philosophers and scientists have already ceased from striving for a
constructive means of theory building in favor of a mere analysis of
factually existing theories, which seem to be conceived as natural
necessities. Many philosophers of science have obviously chosen to
resign themselves to being mere chroniclers of science. Proposals of a
better, methodically proceeding theory building are no longer taken
into consideration. The validity of theories, thus, becomes dependent
on factual agreement based merely on the alleged fact that “the
scientific community knows what the world is like” (Kuhn, 1962, p. 5).
‘That would mean that the dispute about the claim that, say, “theory A
is valid whereas theory B is not” is finally settled by a majority vote of
the “scientific community.”
Kuhn assumes that science, which for him always means factually
prevailing scientific theories and orientations, is accomplishing its
tasks. In his view, however, neither these tasks themselves nor the
methodical way they are accomplished require critical judgment.
Thus, foundation and justification turn out to be mere historical
coincidences. Methodological rules as well as standards and criteria of
the distinction between “rational” and “irrational” are regarded as
repressive curtailment of scientific practice. Evidently, this kind of
argumentation helps the scientist and the philosopher to get over any
deficiency in the justification of their theories. Justificatory judgment
of scientific undertakings is thus replaced by an internal, historicist
judgment of the historical process of gaining scientific knowledge.
Doubtlessly, study of the history of scientific disciplines can be of
the utmost importance to these disciplines—I wholeheartedly agree
with Alvarado (1982) on this question; and Kuhn himself has shown
in some of his case studies that scientific changes frequently occur in a
way that is anything but rational. The question is, however, whether
we content ourselves with this unpleasant fact and view it as anAgainst Historicism 113
indispensable necessity or look for ways to avoid such developments
in the future. In Kuhn's conception, the valuable insight into the
importance of the history of science comes down to a practice that
restricts itself to merely recording and analyzing historically contin-
gent factual developments. In the end, even historical laws are being
formulated. History of science is seen as conforming to laws of the
history of theories and theory building, and this history of theories, in
turn, is conceived as a succession of systematical concepts that
presupposes genetic regularities and rests especially on the consider-
ation of normal and revolutionary phases in the development of
science. From this point of view, the prevailing of a theory appears
similar to a natural selection. The “struggle for life” of theories is
described in terms of variation and selection of competing theories
relative to the underlying conditions of a common historical practice,
which, in turn, is thought to be a natural necessity. No wonder that
Toulmin (1961, pp. 110-111) recommends that historians and philos-
ophers learn from biology;® and Kuhn (1962, p. 146) expresses
himself in a very similar way. Here, the history of criteria and
standards of rationality, which are cultural products, is written in
terms of a natural history of scientific developments. That is the
reason why, in contexts relevant to and in need of adequate founda-
tion and justification, one is simply referred to factual developments.
Systematic argumentation, which once has been obligatory in cases
where the validity of theories was at issue, is no longer required.
Ultimately, science completely renounces the distinction between
well-founded and justified scientific theories on the one hand and
those that factually prevail on the other.
Contrary to this Kuhnian conception, I would hold that it is well
possible to reconstruct (in the sense just specified) justificatory steps
of a theoretical development, instead of merely looking at the results
of such a development. Because each form of scientific knowledge
necessarily points to a more or less strictly performed methodical and
stepwise construction (otherwise, we would not at all speak of scien-
tific knowledge!) and because, as a matter of course, questions as to
Elsewhere (1982, 1984), I have comprehensively criticized the use of natural
scientific concepts, theories, and terminologies for the description and explanation of
cultural developments. The way such concepts are used in so-called evolutionary
epistemology is particularly irresponsible. People tend to forget that scientific research
is a cultural activity; even the development of a natural science is a cultural (not a
natural) event. Therefore, it cannot be described and explained in terms of natural
scientific theories, which are intended for application to entirely different objects and,
thus, are subjected to different criteria of validity.14 The Journal of Parapsychology
the validity of our propositions are unavoidable, such endeavors to
reconstruct justificatory steps of theory building must primarily aim
ata critical judgment of the practical orientations that are at the roots
of the development of scientific knowledge. Then it becomes possible
not only to find out such orientations, but also to critically argue
against or in favor of them and their expediency. Thus, the Kuhnian
historiography of theoretical developments can, at least in large parts,
be replaced by a critical foundation and justification of these
developments. Among others, this view implies the following interre-
lated advantages for a rational understanding of science in general
and of parapsychology and its position vis-a-vis the established
sciences in particular:
1. A very essential part of human work need not be conceived as
being ruled by more or less contingent and irrevocable natural
necessities. This implies that human beings engaged in scientific
research (rather than some mysterious mechanisms underlying and
governing scientific developments) are responsible for what they are
doing and saying: in concreto, this means that they are obliged to
provide adequate justification of the propositions resulting from their
research upon request. Scientific research can be performed in a
rational and reasonable way, and proper justification can be given to
scientific propositions. Rational argumentation based on propositions
that have been justified in the way sketched above rather than
Kuhn-type_historico-sociological processes should guide scientific
research activities.
9. Historically contingent scientific developments for which one
cannot argue systematically need not be conceived as governing the
process of science.
3. Limited contingent parts of theories, which may nevertheless
exist, can be distinguished from well-founded and justified ones. Such
parts must either be given up or reformulated in a rationally
justifiable way.
4. Faulty developments (in parapsychology as well as in the
established sciences) can be characterized as such. As long as all
possible developments of scientific disciplines and theories are taken
to be equally valid—as implied in the Kuhnian conception of rise,
change, and fall of scientific theories and explicitly stated in an
entirely unsupportable way by Collins and Pinch—such characteriza-
tion proves impracticable.
5. Central parts of predominating scientific theories and practices
can be substantially criticized and improved by means of appropriate
suggestions for reorganization.Against Historicism 115
6. The Kuhnian as well as the Popperian analytico-descriptive
conceptions are totally lacking any normative or prescriptive aspects.®
The aforementioned alternative proposal, however, not only implies
that it is possible to criticize scientific orientations, practices, and
theories; it also implies that such orientations, practices, and theories
can be subjected to rational discourses'® in the interest of reaching a
mutually agreeable description of the goals scientists wish to pursue
and to set norms as to how such orientations, practices, and theories
should look relative to these mutually agreed upon goals and
relative to the postulate to guarantee scientifically acceptable research.
That means that even more can be done than criticizing logical faults
or lacking falsifiability of theories.
7. All revolutionary pretensions can be given up, because even
very important scientific changes can only be based on rationally
justifiable arguments in favor of such changes. The frequently heard
argument that parapsychologists were forced into the role of scientific
revolutionaries by the revolutionary character of their subject matter
and their findings, is rooted in a simple linguistic slovenliness. Subject
matter or scientific findings are never revolutionary sui generis; what
can be revolutionary are actions. If these actions, however, make
use of a commonly accepted methodological canon, they are, by
definition, unrevolutionary (see Hévelmann, 1983b, pp. 128-129;
in press).
From my argumentation so far, it may be concluded that in
parapsychology (as in any other branch of science) we can learn from
our history not only in the sense that we will eventually know how the
present situation has come about, but also in a sense closely connected
with our actions as scientists, that is, in a sense that enables us to
critically change our own practice where this turns out to be desirable
in order to guarantee rational scientific conduct. Moreover, we will
certainly be better able to point out to the critics of the field by means
°In this respect, I do not agree with Douglas Stokes, who believes that “Popper's
falsifiability theory” belongs to the “prescriptive philosophies of science” (Stokes, 1983,
p. 92; his italics). Popper is very clear about his opinion that his falsifiability theory is an
adequate description of how science actually proceeds. What is “prescriptive” in
Popper's philosophy is a limited part of the language in which he describes what he
believes scientists are actually doing. He completely shares the view of logical positivists
that factual scientific practice at any given time is to be viewed as the best justified
practice at that time. He was (and apparently still is) con
phers of science can do is to analyze, describe, and affirm what scientists (and physicists,
in particular) are actually doing.
‘For a definition of rational discourse, see Hévelmann (1983a, pp. 496-499).116 The Journal of Parapsychology
of well-founded arguments not only that they are wrong (in case they
are wrong), but also why they are wrong (in case they are wrong).
As far as I can see, especially in parapsychology there is no reason
for dispensing with solid foundation and justification of our practices,
our theories, and our argumentation in favor of an obscure historicist
conception according to which relatively contingent historical con-
straints are telling us what to do next.
REFERE!
s
Axserr, H. (1980). Traktat iiber kritische Vernunft [Treatise on critical reason]
(4th, improved edition). Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).
Atvarapo, C. S. (1982). Historical perspective in parapsychology: Some
practical considerations. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 51,
265-271.
BELorF, J. (1977). Discussion. In B. Shapin & L. Coly (Eds.), The philosophy of
parapsychology (p. 210). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
Couuins, H. M., & Pincu, T. J. (1979). The construction of the paranormal:
Nothing unscientific is happening. In R. Wallis (Ed.), On the margins of
science. The social construction of rejected knowledge (pp. 237-270). Keele,
Staffordshire: University of Keele.
Couns, H. M., & Piven, T. J. (1981). Rationalitat and Paradigmabindung
in der auBerordentlichen Wissenschaft [Rationality and commitment to
paradigms in extraordinary science]. In H. B Duerr (Ed.), Der Wissen-
schaftler und das Irrationale. Zweiter Band [The scientist and the irrational.
Second Volume] (pp. 284-306). Frankfur/M.: Syndikat.
Coutins, H. M., & Pincit, T. J. (1982). Frames of meaning: The social construc-
tion of extraordinary science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Epce, H. L. (1976). Rejoinder to Dr. Wheatley’s note on “Do spirits matter?”
Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 402-407.
Epce, H. L. (1977). The place of paradigms in parapsychology. In B. Shapin
& L. Coly (Eds.), The philosophy of parapsychology (pp. 106-120). New
York: Parapsychology Foundation.
Epce, H. L. (1978a). Paradigmata und Parapsychologie [Paradigms and para-
psychology]. In H. PB Duerr (Ed.), Unter dem Plaster liegt der Strand,
Band 5 (pp. 53-70). Berlin: Karin Kramer Verlag.
Epce, H. L. (1978b). A philosophical justification for the conformance be-
havior model. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 72,
215-231.
Freck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact (I. J. Trenn &
R.K. Merton, Eds.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original
work published in German, 1935)
Fueck, L. (1983). Erfahrung und Tatsache: Gesammelte Aujsiitze (Experience
and fact: Collected papers) (L. Schafer & T. Schnelle, Eds.). FrankfurvM.:
Suhrkamp Verlag.Against Historicism 7
Grecory, A. (1982). Book review [of Frames of meaning, by Collins & Pinch).
Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 51, 309-314.
Hovetmann, G. H. (1981). Correspondence: On “Hume's fallacy.” Journal of
Parapsychology, 45, 367-369.
Hovelmann, G.H. (1982). Natur and Kultur—oder: Von den Tiicken einer ver-
{feblten Sprachauffassung (Nature and culture—or: On the malice of a false
conception of language]. Paper presented at the 15th Workshop on
Phylogenetics and Systematics, Biebergemiind im Spessart.
Hoveimann, G. H. (1983a). Cooperation versus competition: In defense of
rational argument in parapsychology. European Journal of Parapsychology,
4, 483-505.
Hovetmann, G. H. (1983b). Seven recommendations for the future practice
of parapsychology. Zetetic Scholar, No. 11, 128-138.
Hoveimann, G. H. (1984). Sprachkritische Bemerkungen zur evolutionren
Erkenntnistheorie [A language-critical investigation of evolutionary epis-
temology]. Zeitschrift fiir allgemeine Wissenschafistheorie/ Journal for General
Philosophy of Science, 15, 92-121.
Hoveimann, G. H. (in press). A constructively rational approach to para-
psychology and scientific methodology (Responses to my commentators
and some further attempts at clarification). Zetetic Scholar, No. 12.
Kamian, W., & Lorenzen, P (1973). Logische Propadeutih: Vorschule des ver-
niinftigen Redens (Logical propedeutics: Pre-school of talking sense] (2nd,
improved ed.). Mannheim, Vienna, & Zurich: Bibliographisches Institut.
Kornwacus, K. (1975). “Parascience” und Wissenschaftstheorie (“Parascience”
and philosophy of science]. Zeitschrift fiir Parapsychologie und Grenzgebiete
der Psychologie. 17, 125-142.
Kuan, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Kun, T.S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd revised and
enlarged ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kun, T. S. (1974). Second thoughts on paradigms. In F Suppe (Ed.), The
structure of scientific theories (pp. 459-482). Urbana, IL: University of
Illinois Press.
LakaTos, L., & Musrave, A. (Eds.). (1970). Criticism and the growth of knowl-
edge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lorenzen, P (1969). Normative logic and ethics. Mannheim, Vienna, & Zurich:
Bibliographisches Institut.
Masrerman, M. (1970). The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A
Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 59-89).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McCuenon, J. (1982). Rejected anomalies and deviant science. Unpublished
manuscript (modified version of “Psi as a rejected anomaly: Social
patterns surrounding deviant sciences.” Journal of Parapsychology, 1982,
46, 63 [Abstract]).
McConneLt, R. A. (1966). ESP research at three levels of method. Journal of
Parapsychology, 30, 195-207.118 The Journal of Parapsychology
McConnett, R. A. (1968). The structure of scientific revolutions: An epitome.
Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 62, 321-327.
McConnext, R. A. (1976). Areas of agreement between the parapsychologist
and the skeptic. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70,
303-308.
McConneLt, R. A. (1981). Annotated socio-historical bibliography of para-
psychology. In R. A. McConnell (Ed.), Encounters with parapsychology (pp.
223-228). Pittsburgh: Author.
McConneLL, R. A. (1983). An introduction to parapsychology in the context of
science, Pittsburgh: Author.
New Scientist. (1979, July 26). [Caricature.] 83, 311.
Nitsson, I. (1975). The paradigm of the Rhinean school: Part I. European
Journal of Parapsychology, 1 (1), 45-59.
Nisson, 1. (1976). The paradigm of the Rhinean school: Part Il. European
Journal of Parapsychology, 1 (2), 45-56.
Popper, K.R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.
(Original work published in German, 1934 [with the imprint “1935"))
Pratt, J. G. (1974). Some notes for the future Einstein for parapsychology.
Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 68, 133-155.
Prarr, J. G. (1979). Parapsychology, normal science, and paradigm change.
Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 17-28.
Rao, K. R. (1981a). Correspondence (Reply to G. H. Hévelmann). Journal of
Parapsychology, 45, 369-370.
Rao, K. R. (1981b). Hume's fallacy. Journal of Parapsychology, 45, 147-152.
Reser, A. S, (1982-1983). On the paranormal: In defense of skepticism.
Skeptical Inquirer, 7 (2), 55-64.
Scurer, L., & SCHNELLE, T. (1983). Die Aktualitat Ludwik Flecks in Wissen-
schaftssoziologie und Erkenntnistheorie (Ludwik Fleck’s importance for
current sociology of science and epistemology]. In L. Fleck, Erfahrung
und Tatsache: Gesammelte Aufsdtze [Experience and fact: Collected
papers]; (L. Schafer & T. Schnelle, Eds.; pp. 9-34). Frankfurt/M.:
Suhrkamp Verlag.
Sranrorp, R. G. (1977). Are parapsychologists paradigmless in psiland? In
B, Shapin & L. Coly (Eds.), The philosophy of parapsychology (pp. 1-16).
New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
Sroxes, D.M. (1980). Book review (of On the margins of science edited
by R. Wallis). Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74,
363-372.
Sroxes, D. M. (1983). Book review (of Frames of meaning, by H. M. Collins &
‘T.J. Pinch). Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 77,
83-92.
Tuaxur, S. C. (1977). Parapsychology in search of a paradigm. In B. Shapin
& L. Coly (Eds.), The philosophy of parapsychology (pp. 198-208). New York:
Parapsychology Foundation.
Tuoutess, R. H. (1972). From anecdote to experiment in psychical research, Lon-
don: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Against Historicism 119
Toutmin, S. E. (1961). Foresight and understanding: An inquiry into the aims of
science. London: Hutchinson.
WINKELMAN, M. (1980). Science and parapsychology: An ideological revo-
lution. In W.G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology, 1979 (pp. 2-5).
Metuchen, NJ, & London: Scarecrow Press. .
Rollwiesenweg 42
3550 MarburgiLahn
West GermanyJournal of Parapsychology, Vol. 48, June 1984
KUHN AND PARAPSYCHOLOGY
Some Criticat ReMaRKs ON HOVELMANN
By T. J. Pinc
Thomas Kuhn's seminal writings in the history and philosophy of
science have had an enormous impact on how we have come to
understand the development of science. As John Ziman (1983)
remarked recently when presenting Kuhn with the J. D. Bernal medal
at the Society for Social Studies of Science: “We are all Kuhnians
nowadays.” This points not only to the extraordinary extent of Kuhn's
influence but also to the remarkable property of his ideas—they tend
to mean all things to all men! Kuhn himself has become all too aware
of this latter facet of his work, having spent the last decade trying to
distance himself from self-styled “Kuhnians” (including Collins and
Pinch).! This led us to comment in our recent book on the appli
tion of Kuhn's ideas to parapsychology that “Kuhn n'est pas Kuhnian!”
(Collins & Pinch, 1982).
It is clear that in any discussion of Kuhn's ideas or their influence
we should be careful about which reading of Kuhn is being referred
to. Throughout our own work in the sociology of science, we hope to
have made it clear that it is Kuhn's ideas interpreted through the
writings of Winch and Wittgenstein that have informed our analysis.
Hévelmann is correct in describing our views as “radical,” but it is
misleading to suggest that this is an “uncritical” reading of Kuhn.
Indeed, we have argued that it is the uncritical reader of Kuhn who is
led into apparent paradoxes. The need for care in interpreting Kuhn
is obvious when it is recalled that Kuhn himself in a recent essay has
argued that his ideas are quite consistent with the critical-rationalist
tradition in the philosophy of science of which Hévelmann stands in
such awe (Kuhn, 1977).
The fact that Kuhn’s ideas can be seen to be quite consistent with
the creeds of the best rationalist philosophers alerts us to the dangers
of imputing any straightforward influence to Kuhn's ideas. Pre-
sumably, if the rationalist interpretation of Kuhn was widespread in
parapsychology then Hévelmann, rather than offering condemnation,
'For reviews of Kuhn's work in the sociology of science, see Pinch, 1979, 1982.122 The Journal of Parapsychology
would be full of praise for Kuhn-inspired parapsychologists and their
enlightened attitude toward epistemology.
What type of influence does Hévelmann impute to Kuhn’s ideas in
the case of parapsychology? He writes that Kuhn's ideas can lead
parapsychologists to become “less concerned with scientific truth and
rational argumentation” and “to dispense scientists (and parapsycholo-
gists for that matter) from the obligation to advance tightly reasoned
scientific propositions.” In short, it seems that under the influence of
Kuhn scientific standards will drop and scientific reasoning may be
abandoned altogether. This, however, is a reading of Kuhn with which
we would disagree. Nowhere does Kuhn suggest that there is any
justification to act in any other manner than to follow the accepted
canons of scientific evidence and methodology shared by the scientific
community. Such canons and methods may not be decisive (especially
during moments of paradigm revolution), but to abandon them is
clearly to abandon any chance of being accepted as part of science.
The difficulty here comes from the stark choice that Hévelmann
presents as arising from Kuhn's work; namely, that scientists must
either exercise rationality or crass social power. The subtlety of Kuhn’s
argument is that the canons of scientific method are the means by
which social power is exercised. If power did lie outside of scientific
method, then clearly it would be possible to bring about a scientific
revolution with just money and influence. And no one (apart perhaps
from Hévelmann) suggests that this has occurred in the history of
science or indeed that it is a serious possibility.
Given the variety of interpretations of Kuhn, it is, of course,
possible that Hévelmann’s point still stands and that some (misguided)
parapsychologists have read Kuhn in this way. Hovelmann, however,
does not persuade us that this is the case. He presents not a single
example of such sloppy Kuhn-inspired practice in parapsychology.
Indeed, he actually praises the work of one of the parapsychologists
who is most inspired by Kuhn, R. A. McConnell. He writes that for his
“contributions to parapsychology I otherwise have nothing but the
highest respect.” Perhaps Kuhn's ideas have influenced parapsychologi-
cal practice a little less than Hévelmann suggests.
This leads us to ask the more interesting question, which is what
exactly has the influence of Kuhn been on parapsychology? And here
we would suggest that it is rather similar to the influence Kuhn has
had on psychology, sociology, and anthropology. In all these fields,
Kuhn's work has been avidly read and discussed. All these disciplines
have questioned whether they were going through a crisis, undergoing
a revolutionary paradigm shift, or whether they were merely in aKuhn and Parapsychology 123,
preparadigmatic state.” In short, there has been a lot of “paradigm
agonizing” but little else. We can do no better than quote Beloff
(1977) on this point:
There has been an enormous amount of controversy, of a rather tedious
kind, as to whether psychology has ever acquired a paradigm, whether
behaviorism was a paradigm and so on. None of this debate, it seems to
me, led anywhere... . (p. 210)
For psychology, could be read sociology, anthropology, or indeed
parapsychology.
It is in the realm of ideology where Kuhn's ideas have been
influential. Indeed, a point made by Hévelmann about Kuhn's ideas
being used as an excuse seems to be about right. What Kuhn conven-
iently provided was a resource to be drawn on, particularly by those
who felt overshadowed by the physical sciences. They either felt that
their ideas had been unreasonably rejected by an established ortho-
doxy or that, if only they had a paradigm, then scientific progress
would follow. Such ideas could be used to justify their perceptions of
the status of their science, but this is not the same as the ideas being
used to distort their science. Indeed, it is the remarkably unproductive
nature of debates over paradigms and the like that deserves attention
rather than their subversive potential. Hévelmann seems to have
overestimated the impact any philosopher or sociologist can make
on actual scientific practice. Such ideas may be important for scientific
ideology, but they are hardly likely to bring significant changes in a
body of practices built up in an ongoing research tradition.
Hévelmann also seems to be confused over the issue of analytical
intention. The analytical intentions of sociologists in their attempts to
understand scientific development are different from the intentions
of scientists in carrying out science. For example, we have argued in
our own writings in the sociology of science that sociologists should
suspend judgment as to the truth or falsity of the beliefs being
studied. We seek a symmetrical, impartial explanation for both “true”
and “false” beliefs, and we do not want to fall into the trap of assuming
that adherence to “true” ideas needs no explanation whereas adher-
ence to “false” ideas is to be explained in terms of social epidemiology
or “false consciousness.” The wisdom of adopting such an approach,
especially in areas like parapsychology where the “truth” of matters is
yet to be settled, is obvious. However, because we, as analysts, are
?For a discussion of Kuhn’s impact in sociology, see Martins, 1972. The most useful
general extens leas to sociology of science is to be found in Barnes, 1982124
The Journal of Parapsychology
truth-neutral does not mean that scientists should not look for what
they regard as true belief. After all, the job of scientists is to find out
what the truth of the natural world is! Hévelmann simply seems to
have confused the analytical aims of our work (and more pertinently
Kuhn's) in understanding science with the aims of the scientists of
doing science. Thus, when he suggests that Kuhn's analysis and our
own writings mean that parapsychologists can no longer distinguish
mistakes in their own field, he confuses the differing analytical
endeavors of sociologists and scientists.
Finally, it should be noted that a section of Hévelmann’s paper is
used for the purposes of arguing for a philosophical theory of science
based on predication and action. This, it is claimed, is to be preferred
to the “obscure” writings of Kuhn. Parapsychologists, it seems, are to
be chastised for neglecting this theory in favor of Kuhn. This seems to
be somewhat absurd since this particular theory can hardly have been
available to most parapsychologists. Indeed the theory appears to be
of such obscurity that it cannot be spelled out clearly in Hévelmann’s
paper.
But from what Hévelmann does say about the theory, it would
seem to have at least one major shortcoming. It does not solve the very |
problem that Hévelmann notes to be the major difficulty of critical-
rationalism—the infinite regress caused by the theory-ladenness of
observation statements. As we understand it, the theory he advocates |
stresses that ultimately it is performance that counts in science. The
emphasis is put on action and performance to avoid references to |
theory-laden propositions. For example, the performance of the
action of lighting a candle under specified circumstances demon-
strates whether a claim about candle lighting is verified. The problem
with this is that performances have to be interpreted and given meaning.
In interpreting the outcome of a performance there is nothing to stop
the “specified conditions” being challenged. For example, if we try to
demonstrate candle lighting and we fail, one possible meaning is that
we have found a new property of candle lighting; on the other hand,
it is more likely that we did not allow for the background conditions
such as the wind. When a new discovery is claimed in science, there is
no way of telling whether it is a genuine discovery or some property of
the background conditions. This, of course, is the Duhem-Quine
thesis and, because all tests designed to resolve the issue further
themselves involve background assumptions, no test can resolve the
dilemma. Recent studies of physics seem to indicate that this question-
ing of background assumptions is just what does occur when a new
discovery is claimed (see Collins, 1981). Thus, the appeal to perfor-Kuhn and Parapsychology 125
mance does not seem to remove the infinite regress of the theory-
ladenness problem that has besotted the critical-rationalist philosophy
of science.
In conclusion, we welcome parapsychologists’ enthusiasm toward
ideas in the sociology of science. If this enthusiasm, however, leads
parapsychologists to believe that they can dispense with scientific
method, they are misreading our work. But because Hévelmann
presents no evidence that any reputable parapsychologists have taken
Kuhn or ourselves as warrant to abandon scientific method, our
advice is probably redundant. Hévelmann seems to have constructed
a straw man in an attempt to persuade parapsychologists to adopt his
own obscure and inadequate philosophy of science.
REFERENCES
Barnes, B. (1982). Z. S. Kuhn and social science. London: Macmillan.
BeLorr, J. (1977). Discussion. In B. Shapin & L. Coly (Eds.), The philosophy
of parapsychology (p. 210). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
Couns, H. M. (Ed.). (1981). Knowledge and controversy: Studies of modern
natural science [Special issue]. Social Studies of Science, 11, 1-158.
Couutys, H. M., & Pincu, T. J. (1982). Frames of meaning. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Kun, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgement, and theory choice. In T. S.
Kuhn (Ed.), The essential tension (pp. 320-339). Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Martins, H. (1972). The Kuhnian “revolution” and its implications for
sociology. In Nossiter et al. (Eds.), Imagination and precision in political
analysis. London: Faber & Faber.
Pinca, T. J. (1979). Paradigm lost? A review symposium. Isis, 70, 429-440.
Pincu, T. J. (1982, December). Kuhn—the conservative and radical inter-
pretations. 45 Newsletter, 7(1), 10-25.
Ziman, J. (1983, Winter). Introduction of Thomas S. Kuhn. 4S Review, p. 24.
Department of Sociology
University of York
Heslington, York YOI 5DD
England