Harding Urban Theory

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 23

Alan Harding & Talja Blokland

Urban A critical introduction to


power, cities and urbanism

Theory
in the 21st century

Harding_Urban Theory_AW.indd 8 27/02/2014 12:08

00_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Prelims.indd 3 12-Apr-14 1:54:51 PM


1

What is urban theory?

Learning objectives
• To understand the conceptual dilemmas that come with attempts to define
‘the urban’
• To see how classical scholars have thought about the urban and rural in the
context of modernity
• To understand what ‘theory’ is and learn about the various epistemological
and ontological perspectives that inform theory

Urban studies and urban theory


People are entitled to be confused, even a little intimidated, by the way towns
and cities are studied today. Contemporary courses in urban studies cover just
about every conceivable aspect of the urban experience. Some approaches are
relatively self-contained and coherent, but most tend to shade into each other.
In an age in which more than half of the global population is living in urban
areas for the first time in human history, there are no easily defined conceptual
boundaries that can allow us to designate everything on one side of an imagi-
nary line as urban studies and everything on the other side as something else.
Neither are urban studies the property of a single academic discipline. Claims
are made for a distinctive urban sociology, an urban politics, geography, eco-
nomics, planning and so on, but in practice it is hard to distinguish one from
another. The ‘urban’ components of these disciplines are not very self-contained
either. It is difficult, for example, to say what differentiates urban geography
from human geography, or urban sociology from more general social theory.
And it is far from clear which of the standard academic disciplines ‘owns’ the

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 1 12-Apr-14 1:56:10 PM


2 Urban theory

more specific subject matter that often surfaces in the literature; urban archi-
tecture, conservation, design, ecology, economic development, environment,
landscape, management, morphology, policy and so on.

Urban subdisciplines
Urban studies are eclectic; they bring together and build upon knowledge,
understandings and approaches from a wide range of subject areas. Recounting
his experience of urban sociology as an undergraduate in 1970, Peter Saunders
could remember little coherence in his chosen course of study other than the fact
that ‘if you could find it happening in cities, then you could find it discussed
somewhere in the … literature’ (Saunders, 1986: 7). Little has changed since
Saunders’ undergraduate days in this respect. If anything, urban studies have
become still more eclectic and fragmented. So, for example, it has been argued
that Saunders’ field concerns itself with the following: how the urban experience
feels; if and how places acquire distinctive identities; how urban life is affected
by a person’s gender, class, and ethnic group or the sort of housing he/she lives
in; the effect of different urban environments on social relationships and bonds;
the history of urbanisation; the ‘spatial structures’ of cities; the nature of, and
solutions to, urban problems; and political participation and local governance
(Savage, Warde & Ward, 2003: 2–3). And that is just urban sociology.
A list of issues claimed to be central to urban geography is equally eclectic and
shows a fair degree of overlap: the causes of urbanisation; the national and
international urban hierarchy; the ‘urban system’; the determinants of land use
within cities; urban investment patterns; town planning; urban transport; social
and residential areas within cities; the role of social class, gender, ethnicity and
sexual identity in urban affairs; the problems of inner cities, peripheral urban
areas and suburbs; urban policy ‘solutions’ to urban problems; images of cities;
and cities in the developing world and post-communist eastern Europe (Carter,
1995; Short, 1984, 1996; Herbert & Thomas, 1982; Johnston, 1980). Urban
politics, on the other hand, spans issues such as the role of elites and regimes in
urban development, intergovernmental relations and urban policies, the role of
bureaucratic and political leadership in urban change, the autonomy of city
governments, citizenship, urban social movements, gender and race relations in
cities, and the design and operation of the institutions of urban governance
(Judge et al, 1995; Davies & Imbroscio, 2009). A resurgent urban economics, on
the other hand, concerns itself with the urbanisation process, alternative
approaches to locational analysis, the characteristics of urban markets (housing,
transportation, facilities), urban labour markets, the behaviour of urban govern-
ments and their implications for urban public economics, and the quality of
urban life (Arnott & McMillen, 2006; Mills, 2004).

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 2 12-Apr-14 1:56:10 PM


What is urban theory? 3

The fact that urban studies do not have an obvious centre of gravity or an
essential and shared core of ideas has occasionally been seen as a source of con-
cern by some scholars, particularly amongst those who argue that they should
play a role in underpinning desirable economic, social, environmental, cultural
or political change, however defined. For at least the last 40 years there have
been sporadic but fierce debates about the nature, status, relevance and useful-
ness of urban studies. It has been argued, particularly following periods of eco-
nomic crisis and social and political upheaval, that urban studies, and by
implication the conceptual tools on which they draw, are ‘in crisis’.
Thus, for example, some of the most noted contributions to the evolution of
‘urban theory’ (e.g. Castells, 1972; Harvey, 1973) have resolutely rejected what
their authors perceived to be the dominant, pre-existing paradigm(s) within
urban studies and argued for fresh thinking that could overturn the scholarly
status quo and, ideally, help transform the broader conditions that gave rise to
them. The (urban) impacts of the global financial crisis in 2008, and the wave
of austerity budgeting by national governments that followed in its wake, wit-
nessed a similar outpouring of (self-) criticism along the lines that ‘theory’, and
the work based upon it, no longer seemed to underpin the political action that
is necessary to achieving substantive change, even when it aspired to do so (see
Swyngedouw, 2009: 603–4). Similarly, as noted in the Foreword, claims have
occasionally been made that urban studies are somehow ‘captured’ by public
funding that is only made available for ‘practical’ research that is unthreatening
to policy elites (Forrest, Henderson, & Williams, 1982) and that some of its key
exponents are therefore ‘neutralised’ and incorporated into closed, elite policy
circles, thereby providing legitimacy rather than knowledge that may challenge
received wisdoms and conventional practices (Boland, 2007).
It must be noted, however, that neither the eclecticism of urban studies nor the
concerns that are sometimes expressed as to whether they are effective in fulfill-
ing a perceived ‘mission’ seem to affect their popularity. Their appeal to students
and their importance for academics and policy-makers has, we would argue,
continued to grow.

Metaphorical cities
Urban studies do not just cover a broad canvas. They utilise many different con-
cepts in exploring their wide-ranging subject matter. One indication of the sheer
variety of approaches upon which they draw is the range of characterisations and
metaphors academics have used to understand and describe cities and processes
of urban change. Cities are analysed in terms of their size and status. There has
been work on global (Sassen, 1991), world (Hall, 1984; Friedmann, 1986) and
mega-cities (Gilbert, 1996), as well as regional (Calthorpe & Fulton, 2001),

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 3 12-Apr-14 1:56:10 PM


4 Urban theory

provincial (Skeldon, 1997), intermediate (Bolay & Rabinovich, 2004), small and
medium-sized cities (Erickcek & McKinney, 2006). Cities are seen as characteris-
ing different epochs and stages of development. There are old (Ashworth &
Tunbridge, 1999), new (Mullins, 1990), modern and postmodern cities (Watson
& Gibson, 1995); imperial and postimperial, colonial and postcolonial cities
(Driver & Gilbert, 1999; Betts, Ross, & Telkamp, 1985); pre-industrial, industrial
and postindustrial cities (Savitch, 1988); yesterday’s, today’s and tomorrow’s cities
(Hall, 2002); ‘successful’ cities in the sunbelt and ‘declining’ cities in the rustbelt.
Cities and their neighbourhoods are distinguished according to location. There are
inner cities, outer cities, suburban or edge cities (Garreau, 1991), central and
peripheral cities, frontier and border cities. Cities are said to specialise in different
functions: there are technopoles (Castells & Hall, 1994); commercial, manufactur-
ing, tourist (Judd & Fainstein, 1999) and service cities; airport, maritime and
university cities. Politically and ideologically, cities are characterised as communist
or capitalist (Smith & Feagin, 1987), socialist and post-socialist, liberal, progres-
sive (Clavel, 1986), conservative or pluralist. There are public and private cities.
On the outer edge of our perceptions there are symbolic or virtual cities and ‘the
city as text’ (Donald, 1992).
The variety of city types described in the urban literature is matched by the
range of experiences cities are claimed to undergo. We hear, for example, about
urban crisis (Cloward & Piven, 1975), decline, decay and poverty. Cities are
said to be divided (Fainstein, Gordon, & Harloe, 1992), unequal (Hamnett,
2003), sick, unfairly structured (Badcock, 1984), heartless, captive (Harloe,
1977), dependent (Kantor & David, 1988; Kantor, 1995), dispossessed, ungov-
ernable (Cannato, 2001), unheavenly (Banfield, 1970) and contested
(Mollenkopf, 1983). They are, or have been, in recession, in stress (Gottdiener,
1986), in trouble, in revolt, at risk or under siege (Graham, 2011). At the same
time, we hear of urban innovation (Clark, 1994), redevelopment, regeneration,
renewal, renaissance and revitalisation. Cities are, or can be, healthy (Ashton,
1992), liveable, intelligent (Komninos, 2012), humane (Short, 1989), just
(Fainstein, 2010), ideal (Eaton, 2001), safe, creative (Cooke & Lazzeretti,
2008), accessible, good, free, compact (Jenks & Burgess, 2000) or sustainable
(Haughton & Hunter, 2003). There are cities that have shrunk (Glock, 2006;
Hannemann, 2003; Galster, 2012a) but refused to die (Keating, 1988), and oth-
ers that have been reborn (Levitt, 1987), saved or transformed. There are uto-
pian possibilities: cities that are perfect (Gilbert, 1991), heavenly, ideal, magical
(Davis, 2001), beautiful, triumphant, radiant or visionary. In between urban
heaven and hell, cities have more prosaic attributes: they are ordinary (Robinson,
2006), planned (Corden, 1977), informational (Castells, 1989), cultural,
rational, organic, developing, globalising (Marcuse & van Kempen, 2000),
emerging or evolving. There are cities in transition, in competition (Brotchie,
1995) or on the move.

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 4 12-Apr-14 1:56:10 PM


What is urban theory? 5

This brief illustration of the enormous variety in the way cities and urban pro-
cesses are characterised is enough to warn us that there is no consensus in urban
studies, not just about what is the appropriate focus for analysis but on the broader
question of whether towns and cities are ‘good’ for human life. On the one hand,
cities are seen as quintessential sites where freedom of lifestyle or subcultures can
be practised; as places where multiple ways of being can each find their own niches.
On the other, they are also seen, in what Lofland (1998) describes as the anti-urban
discourse, as places of problems, of vice and moral decay. Especially in the US, the
countryside, with its natural wilderness and its ostensible freedom, provides a pas-
toral image in contrast to the cold, anonymous, rational city, as is visible in the
Hudson River landscape paintings of artists such as Thomas Cole (Figure 1.1).
Partly this can be explained by the different places that the process of urban-
isation occupies within distinct national histories. In both the relatively ‘young’
US and the older UK, the city has tended to be associated, rightly or wrongly,
with industrialisation and with the ‘shocking’ and socially dislocating aspects of
early industrial cities such as Manchester and Chicago. In areas of the world
with longer, pre-industrial urban histories – Greece and China are good exam-
ples, as are the principle pre-industrial trading centres of Europe – the absence
of such a strong association between urbanity and industrialisation encourages
a different ‘take’ on the city as a centre, variously, of democracy, enlightenment,

Figure 1.1 A View of the Mountain Pass Called the Notch of the White Mountains (Crawford Notch),
Thomas Cole, 1939
Source: Wikimedia Commons:
http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/9/93/Thomas_Cole_-_A_View_of_the_Mountain_Pass_Called_
the_Notch_of_the_White_Mountains.jpg

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 5 12-Apr-14 1:56:11 PM


6 Urban theory

innovation and technological and artistic development. Partly, though, it is


about radically different ways of seeing. Storper and Manville (2006: 1269)
summarise the persistence of double vision when suggesting that:

Urban studies have always been shot through with a curious mix of pes-
simism and utopianism. For almost as long as we have had cities, we have
had predictions of their decline and, for almost as long as we have had talk
of decline, we have had prophecies of resurgence.

In using metaphors to describe the conditions of cities and how they change,
urban commentators necessarily draw upon a more or less coherent set of con-
cepts; that is, upon one or more theories. Take the notion of the ‘dependent city’.
Having invented this label, Paul Kantor (Kantor & David, 1988; Kantor, 1995)
naturally had to say what he meant by cities and who or what he considered
them dependent upon. In fact Kantor equated cities with city governments. He
explained how decision-makers in US city governments cannot do as they please
but are dependent in the sense that their choices are constrained by their need
to take into account the actions and preferences of other decision-makers in the
business community and in state and federal governments. Kantor’s argument
therefore drew upon theories about the relationship between levels of govern-
ment (‘intergovernmental theory’) and between the public and private sectors
(‘political economy’). In Kantor’s case, the choice of theoretical perspectives was
made explicit. He made reference to a number of theories he felt could not
entirely answer the questions he posed but, in combination, shed helpful concep-
tual light upon them.

The role of theory in urban studies


Not all commentators within urban studies are as obliging as Kantor when it
comes to outlining the theoretical foundations of their work. Indeed urban stud-
ies, especially in the UK and Europe, are sometimes saddled with a reputation
for occupying a ‘theory-free zone’ by some critics precisely because their expo-
nents are said not to draw explicitly or fruitfully upon relevant theories and
concepts, or at least not enough. It is also argued that literatures which concep-
tualise the urban form and change on a theoretical level find little resonance with
either the literature that studies social problems in the city or those scholars who
work outside of academia in policy-oriented professions. Here, research is being
used, and this research is increasingly conducted by consultancy firms and semi-
commercial university research institutes or foundations. As far as there is urban
theory, then, we signal a distance between those who do ‘urban theory’ and those
who draw on empirical studies, often commissioned, for actual practice of urban

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 6 12-Apr-14 1:56:11 PM


What is urban theory? 7

policy. This division seems to be on the rise and creates two issues. First, it makes
part of urban studies obsolete, and the world would not look any different if
their theories did not exist. Second, it creates poor knowledge about the urban
world, as nothing is as practical as good theory (Pawson, 2003). Unreflexive
data-collection and report-writing may legitimise specific policies, but will not
provide much of an understanding of the processes and mechanisms one would
need to understand in order to be able to strive for social change to begin with – in
policy, but also in non-governmental organisations and activism.
These three key features of the urban studies literature – the limited degree of
explicit theorisation, the wide range of subject matter covered and the discon-
nection between urban theory and empirical research – do not appear to put
academic researchers and students off the subject. They nonetheless generate
questions about the role of theory in urban studies. Can we even talk of urban
theory in any meaningful sense? Can urban theories be distinguished from
broader theoretical developments in the social sciences, or do they simply entail
the application of general theories to urban phenomena? Are there even such
things as distinctively urban phenomena? If not, what objects do urban theories
focus upon? How have urban theories developed and how do they relate to one
another? Is there such a thing as contemporary urban theory and, if so, what
differentiates it from previous approaches? How are urban theories used, by
whom and for what purpose? Do they have any impact upon popular debates
about cities? These are the central questions this book grapples with. Before
proceeding to them, however, we need to elaborate a little on the term ‘urban’
and on the general nature of theory, whether or not it is described as urban. This
discussion helps clarify what is and can be meant by ‘urban theory’.

What is urban?
The Oxford English Dictionary defines urban as ‘of, living in, or situated in, city
or town’. For everyday purposes that is a perfectly adequate definition. Like most
dictionary entries, however, it only begs further questions. In this case the first obvi-
ous question is what is meant by a city or town, and how do they differ from other
sorts of place? Whilst the average Briton might intuitively know when he or she
passes through Loughborough or Mansfield that they are towns, not cities, and
that Liverpool (Figure 1.2) or Manchester certainly do qualify as ‘cities’, what
exactly makes him or her know that this is the case? A related but more searching
question concerns what ‘of’ means in the above definition. How do we define what
is ‘of’ cities and towns? What is specifically urban? What is urban different from?
All of these questions cause problems for social scientists, but the difficulties pre-
sented by the first are overcome rather more easily than the latter.

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 7 12-Apr-14 1:56:11 PM


8 Urban theory

Figure 1.2 Liverpool Skyline with HMS Ark Royal docked at cruise terminal
Source : Wikimedia Commons
http://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Liverpool_Skyline_with_HMS_Ark_Royal.jpg.

Figure 1.3 Plauen skyline


Plauen, Germany. Picture taken from the Bärensteinturm., Christopher Voitus, 2006.
Source : Wikimedia Commons: http://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Plauen-Overview.JPG.

If the (Anglo-Saxon) meanings of city and town are probed further, they are
found to depend upon arbitrary categorisations that only make sense relative to
other, equally arbitrary ones. A town, for example, is defined as a collection of
dwellings bigger than a village that, in turn, is bigger than a hamlet. A city,
meanwhile, is either an important town or a town awarded privileged status by
charter, especially if it also contains a cathedral (although, just to confuse mat-
ters, not all cities have cathedrals, nor have all towns with cathedrals become
cities!). Different definitions apply in different countries. In Dutch and German,
no linguistic distinction is drawn between city and town (with stad and Stadt

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 8 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


What is urban theory? 9

meaning both town and city, and defined by rights of government and tax-
collection of the feudal times, so that the contract between land and stad is derived
from the power division between the European gentry and merchant citizens).
German and Dutch added Großstadt and grote stad when the industrial revolu-
tion and accompanying demographic growth of cities started to set them apart
from other towns. In some cases, Australia being one example, messy conceptual
dilemmas are sidestepped through conventions whereby a minimum population
size or density is defined, above which a settlement is automatically classified as a
town or city (Carter, 1995: 10–12). As with most ‘technical’ methods of designat-
ing towns or cities, this convention provides the categorical clarity needed by
national states, but it does not always make sense in people’s daily experiences.
The way social scientists have dealt with issues concerning the definition of
cities and towns is a good example of how empirical work often proceeds in the
absence of precise concepts. Academics have not let the fact that there are no
universally agreed, watertight definitions of city and town prevent them from
undertaking urban research. For the most part they have simply lived with a
particular society’s conventional labels, drawing attention to their limitations as
necessary. Political scientists, for example, have tended to proceed on the basis
that cities can be defined, however imperfectly, by the boundaries that are rele-
vant to political decision-­making; that is, by areas covered by a local or metro-
politan government. Studies that required a broader focus have embraced other
definitions such as a ‘travel-to-work area’, a ‘standard metropolitan statistical
area’, a conurbation, a ‘functional urban region’ or other territories defined for
the purposes of statistics.
Urban sociologists have tended to eschew geographical definitions of cities
and often taken the city as a container of other sociological phenomena and
questions studied within the city, contributing to the common understanding
that cities pose ‘urban problems’. In US English, ‘urban’ and especially ‘inner
city’ have taken on the connotation of referring to minorities, especially
African-Americans and Latinos, and refer to crime, drugs, pregnancies out of
wedlock among teenagers and other forms of behaviour labelled in main-
stream discourse as ‘deviant’, if not ‘immoral’. ‘Urban music’, usually referring
to one or other form of hip-hop, and ‘urban clothing’ associated with this
subculture spring from an understanding of ‘urban’ as linked to certain types
of neighbourhoods in cities which are seen as both the stage and the site that
generates an ‘urban’ subculture.
The second set of questions, about what is urban and how it differs from the
‘non-urban’, goes to the heart of what urban studies and urban theory are and
can be about. The answers, again, are disappointing for those who prefer clear
definitions and solid conceptual platforms on which to build. The simplest
answer to the question ‘what is urban?’ is ‘that which is not rural’.

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 9 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


10 Urban theory

Rural and urban


The urban–rural distinction has a long tradition within social science and
there is no doubt that at one time it drew attention to some crucial differences
between town and country. Most leading social theorists recognise the critical
place of towns and cities in the process of industrialisation and the transition
from the largely agrarian feudalist system to the largely urbanised capitalist
one (Saunders, 1986: 13–51). Weber (1958), for example, argued that the
characteristics of certain medieval European cities stood in stark contrast to
those of rural population centres in that they contained concentrations of
alternative political and economic power and had very different social struc-
tures based on comparatively complex divisions of labour. Moreover, Weber
identified the market place as the crucial element that differentiates the city
from other forms of settlements. In his view, the social action of exchange cre-
ated an equality among partially integrated actors based on accidental and
superficial contacts and hence organised the earliest form of ‘public space’,
sociologically meant (see also Bahrdt, 1998).
Marx agreed on the importance of the division of labour. Indeed, he positively
welcomed the destructive effect urbanisation had on pre-existing social struc-
tures and the fact that it freed the labouring classes from ‘the idiocy of rural life’.
Marx and Weber saw conceptual benefits in the use of the terms ‘urban’ and
‘rural’ in the period before the industrial age, a time when the city was a rela-
tively distinctive and fruitful unit for analysis.
The usefulness of the urban–rural distinction for social scientists, however,
declined steadily with increasing industrialisation. Sociologists became
increasingly critical of the bipolar juxtaposition of the urban and the rural,
not least because ‘the rural’, as discussed in the work of Ferdinand Tönnies
and others, was associated with a romanticised vision of social life that soci-
ologists wanted to move away from (e.g. Mazlish, 1989). Urbanisation in the
Global North came to be seen as synonymous with, but dependent upon,
industrialisation so it was the latter concept that dominated explanations of
social change.
An everyday distinction between urban and rural persisted because the two
terms still conjure up contrasting visions of the way space is used; dense, built-
up, ‘man-made’ areas on the one hand, sparsely populated, ‘natural’ country-
side on the other. But the utility of ‘urban’ as an everyday term has been
devalued too. Urbanisation does not just mean that the great majority of
people come to live in or near towns and cities whilst ‘ruralism’ is concen-
trated into ever-smaller geographical areas inhabited by proportionately fewer
people. It affects rural life in much more profound ways. The countryside is
fundamentally shaped by and managed for the benefit of urban populations,

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 10 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


What is urban theory? 11

be it through servicing their demand for food through intensive agricultural


production methods or the provision of homes or retail and leisure opportuni-
ties for city workers and residents. Whatever happens in cities also happens
outside them and it has become virtually impossible to isolate urban from
rural ways of life. Ray Pahl’s (1970: 209) comment that ‘in an urbanised
world, “urban” is everywhere and nowhere; the city cannot be defined’ sum-
marises the conventional wisdom about the universal nature of ‘the urban’
and the redundancy of the urban–rural distinction, at least in the ‘developed’
world.
Two important consequences flow from the doubts that have been cast on
the importance of the urban–rural dichotomy. One is that it has become very
difficult to define ‘urban’ in a way that is sufficiently distinctive for it to be
useful for social scientists. If ‘urban’ is everywhere, isn’t ‘urban geography’
simply ‘geography’, ‘urban politics’ just ‘politics’ and so on across subject
areas? The line advocated by the likes of Pahl is now accepted by most aca-
demics, even if they are convinced of the importance of urban studies. Savage,
Warde and Ward, for example, felt motivated to write an urban sociology
textbook but had to concede that ‘there is no solid definition of the urban. …
The label “urban” sociology is mostly a flag of convenience’ (Savage et al.,
2003: 2). Similarly, Carter accepted that urban geography ‘cannot claim to be
a systematic study’ but simply ‘considers [economic, socio-cultural and politi-
cal] processes in relation to one phenomenon, the city’ (Carter, 1995: 1).
Dunleavy, on the other hand, opted for a relatively arbitrary ‘content defini-
tion’ of the urban field, based upon particular social and political processes,
because he adjudged as failures alternative attempts to define it geographically
or institutionally (Dunleavy, 1980: 21–55).
The other implication is that the town or city, as an entity, long ago ceased
to be particularly distinctive for social scientists. As Saunders (1986: ii)
argued:
[t]he city is not a theoretically significant unit of analysis in advanced capi-
talist societies … Marx and Engels, Weber and Durkheim … saw the city
as important historically in the development of industrial capitalist society,
but none of them saw it as significant for an analysis of such societies once
they had become established.

Evidence for this argument can be found in a curious contemporary paradox.


Whereas the more general concepts developed by those path-breaking social
theorists in their analyses of industrialised societies continue to exert an
important influence on many aspects of urban studies, those parts of their
work that dealt specifically with cities are ignored by all but a few commenta-
tors (e.g. Elliott & McCrone, 1982, on Weber), with the exception of Georg

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 11 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


12 Urban theory

Simmel (1950), whose essay on the ‘mental life’ of cities has seen a revival
especially since what we will later discuss as the cultural turn in urban studies.
What is left is, first, a rather abstract discussion on space, including arguments
that space is produced and therefore not a container concept (Gottdiener &
Hutchison, 2011), which has consequences for defining ‘city’, and second, a
large field of studies called ‘urban’ that focuses on social questions located in
cities, but not addressing the specificity of the urban of these questions in any
great theoretical depth.

What is theory?
Dictionaries generally define theory as a body or system of ideas that explains one
or more aspects of reality. This conjures up a picture of the theorist as someone with
throbbing temples who spends his or her time dreaming up and applying formalised
sets of rules through disciplined, abstract thought. Social science theory would,
however, stop being social science the moment it lost all connection to the empirical,
that is, to the realm of experienced reality (in contrast to metaphysics).
We are all theorists at some level. We use theory routinely and flexibly, even if
we are not always aware of it. As Charles Lemert (1995: 14–15) writes, ‘everyone
knows, beyond much reasonable doubt, that there is a sphere of social things out
there that affects human life in powerful ways’, and theory in its everyday sense
is little more than the stories we tell about what we have figured out about our
experiences in social life. In order to analyse or to act, we need to process large
amounts of information such that the focus for our analysis or our practical
options are simplified and made manageable, and in order to do so, we draw,
often though not always, on theories of what matters, how things work and what
causes what.
Not just in academia, but also in the fields of policy and practice, nothing is
as practical as a good theory (Zijderveld, 1991: 15). Theory is derived from the
Greek theorein, meaning ‘observing’ or ‘considering’ (ibid.). Theories, then, are
the outcomes of reflection that sharpen our understanding of the world. They
use relatively coherent, connected concepts and statements about the social that
help us understand what matters, how things work and what causes what. In
philosophical parlance, we make use of two tools that help us impose order on
our experiences: an ontology and an epistemology.

Ontology and epistemology


An ontology is a view about ‘essences’; about what are the basic, indivisible
building blocks from which our understanding of ourselves and the world we

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 12 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


What is urban theory? 13

inhabit is constructed, about what is ‘real’. ‘Humans are naturally co-­operative’


is an ontological position that makes a substantial difference to the way peo-
ple who share it see the world. It leads to particular ways of behaving or
interpreting events that contrast in potentially fundamental ways with those
of people who believe humans are essentially competitive. An epistemology, by
contrast, is a view about the nature of knowledge; about how we know what
we know and what counts as evidence in confirming or refuting claims to
knowledge. One simple epistemological position is that we can only truly
know that which we experience through our physical senses, whereas the
interpretations of such experiences, for example how we make sense of them,
are assumed to be more or less similar to different individuals. This position
has very different implications from one which has it that the same physical
sensations mean completely different things to different people, depending
upon the way they have come to understand and conceptualise them. Within
the social sciences, more than in the natural sciences, different ontological and
epistemological positions have given rise to a great variety of theoretical
approaches.
These different approaches can be reconciled with one another to some
extent, depending on what sort of questions we want to pose, utilising a par-
ticular theory. If we are mainly concerned with ‘what’ questions, for example,
we will be drawn to exploratory, descriptive and evaluative approaches that
present the fullest possible picture of the issue we are interested in. Such
approaches, however, do little to help understand how and why things work. If
‘why’ questions are uppermost, then we will more likely look to explanatory
approaches that grapple with the issue of causation in some, possibly mild,
form. It can be argued that as nobody can describe everything social, description
involves theories about what matters and what does not, behind which lie ideas
about how things work. Interpretations of the social, however, imply a more
visible, stronger presence of theory. If ‘how’ is the primary question, we will
gravitate toward normative and prescriptive approaches, that is, those dealing
with the way things should be and the best ways of ensuring they are as we
would want them. The degree to which theoretical perspectives can be combined
and integrated, however, is strictly limited. Whilst some theories are readily
acknowledged to perform better than others, for example in answering ‘what’
as opposed to ‘why’ questions, by their very nature theories claim that their
particular knowledge is universally true. Even the claim that ‘no truth is univer-
sal’ is itself universal; it is true everywhere, at all times, or it is meaningless. It is
‘truth claims’, and the evidence upon which they rest, that fuel the many internal
disputes within social science.
Urban studies, for all their eclecticism, concentrate upon analysing various
aspects of a particular historical form of human settlement. They therefore fall

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 13 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


14 Urban theory

squarely within the social sciences. As a result, urban theory has inevitably been
touched by the major controversies within social science more generally about
its epistemological status.
Epistemological questions include whether social sciences can legitimately
draw upon the ideas and methods of the natural sciences or must develop their
own; what counts as knowledge and how it is gained; whether the main aim
of inquiry should be understanding or prediction; whether objectivity is pos-
sible; what, if anything, is the difference between facts and values and which
are the more ‘real’; what is the relationship between researcher and researched,
and so on. To enumerate all the possible approaches to these issues would
mean trawling through a huge variety of ‘isms’ – from Althusserianism,
through materialism, to Weberianism – which might claim the status of theory.
To simplify, however, let us start from the observation that the key schools of
social science since the beginning of the twentieth century have stemmed from,
or can roughly be linked to, three overarching approaches; positivism, herme-
neutics and realism (Bhaskar, 1993). These approaches make different claims
about what is real and about the nature of knowledge and how it should be
gained.

Positivism
Positivism draws most directly on the natural sciences. It has traditionally
formed the basis of most social science, although its pre-eminence has declined
over time as its relevance to the study of human affairs – and even its domi-
nance within the natural sciences – has increasingly come under attack. For
positivists, theories are laws that accurately describe regularities in events and
phenomena. They explain things in that they might show, for example, that
event B always follows event A but never happens when A does not. They also
facilitate predictions; positivists would expect B to follow A in the future just
as it has in the past. Positivist theories therefore suggest causation, but A could
be said to ‘cause’ B only in so far as B’s relation to A is regular and predictable.
Positivist theories do not involve an understanding of how A causes B, only a
demonstration that it appears to do so. If A were not followed by B under cer-
tain circumstances, the theory would fall and another would be needed. It
comes as no surprise that the attempts to create a social science modelled after
the natural sciences came up during the high days of industrialisation and the
expansion of industrial capitalism, in turn related to modernity with its core
element of rationalisation: the turn towards a world of Entzauberung (disen-
chantment: Weber, 1988: 594) opened up the possibility of seeing the world as
having a rational rather than divine order to it, an order that humans hence
could understand and explain thoroughly without having to draw on the meta-
physical. While this stream of thought of course as an intellectual project found

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 14 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


What is urban theory? 15

its basis in the Enlightenment, its social consequences became most pronounced
in the times of rapid urbanisation in the Global North, to which industrial
capitalism was closely related. The belief in a rational social science was based
on the positivist premise that scientific knowledge about the world is possible
and can be based on the non-normative, rational registration of facts.
For positivists, the only phenomena about which scientific knowledge is pos-
sible are those that can be observed directly. Such phenomena are ‘facts’,
whereas those that cannot be observed are ‘values’ or abstractions that can have
no scientific status. Consequently, positivists have no scientific interest in the
motivations underlying human actions or in abstract concepts – God, justice,
love, and so on – that have no observable form. They are only concerned with
the actions themselves and the effects that abstract concepts have on observable
behaviour. In principle, positivist theories should be based only upon ‘value-free’
observations gathered from experiments or comparisons by objective and disin-
terested observers. Strictly speaking, they should also rely upon inductive
research methods; that is, they should start with the particular (empirical obser-
vations) and move to the general (theoretical statements).
The commitment to inductive methods reflected positivism’s original mission
to avoid two perceived weaknesses in pre-existing social inquiry. One was the
tendency to ‘prove’ pet theories with reference only to a few examples. The other
was reliance upon non-verifiable religious or metaphysical arguments. However,
critiques of early positivism resulted in the role of abstractions in theory-­
building being recognised even within broadly positivist schools of thought. As
a result, the commitment to base everything upon empirical facts, however
defined, softened over time. The critical rationalist school inspired by Popper, for
example, provided a powerful case for using deductive rather than inductive
research methods. Deduction – the move from the general (theory) to the par-
ticular (evidence) – demands that researchers put forward hypotheses and see
whether ‘facts’ corroborate them. It allows researchers to guess what they might
find before they look for it and to amend their hypotheses if they do not find it.
All that is required for scientific truths to emerge deductively, Popper argued, is
that theoretical statements can be proven wrong by empirical evidence – that
they are falsifiable. If we agree with Popper, however, we must accept that all
‘truths’ are tentative since all scientific ‘laws’ are simply hypotheses that have yet
to be falsified (Popper, 1934).
Positivist-inspired approaches within social science are many, varied and
by no means mutually compatible. However, all attribute great importance
to objectivity on the part of researchers and their methods, a distinction
between facts and values, and a central role for observable empirical evi-
dence in the development of theory. For positivists, a social ‘science’ that
lacks these characteristics is not truly scientific. Ranged against this view
are alternatives that insist that social science is only possible if it is based

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 15 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


16 Urban theory

upon a different view of science than that borrowed by positivism from the
natural sciences.

Hermeneutics
Positivism has long been counterposed to hermeneutics, whose principal char-
acteristics are in many respects the negation of the fundamentals of positivism.
Whereas positivists attempt to explain and predict human action by observing
behavioural outcomes, hermeneutic approaches look to understand human
actions and events with reference to the interpretations people apply to them;
that is, by looking at the reasons underlying behaviour. Rather than assuming,
as do positivists, that the vagaries of human consciousness can safely be
ignored when formulating theories, hermeneutics puts it at the very centre of
its concerns.
The hermeneutic theorist/researcher does not merely observe and record
‘external’ events. He/she must understand both the meanings of actions and
events for those involved – as influenced by their desires, beliefs and intentions
as well as their memories from previous, similar experiences that provide the
scripts for interpreting new encounters – and the context within which partici-
pants act and the way this affects their desires, beliefs and intentions. The role
of theory, then, is to make sense of events and processes by developing a full
understanding of how the meanings that underpin them come to be attributed
within particular contexts. Theories developed from such a perspective put
much more emphasis upon interpretation and understanding than upon expla-
nation and prediction. Prediction, in particular, is seen as virtually impossible in
the social sciences because people are part of ‘open systems’, where change is
constant and the combination of circumstances leading to particular actions and
events is rarely repeated, rather than the ‘closed systems’ of the natural sciences
where many fundamental factors do not vary.
Hermeneutics sees no sense in a distinction between facts and values because
the meaning of all things, whether they are directly observable or not, is neces-
sarily a matter of interpretation. People do not simply receive raw sensory data;
they experience things and interpret them simultaneously. ‘Reality’, within her-
meneutics, is therefore inseparable from subjective human perceptions. It is not
something independent of human experience. The importance of subjectivity
and interpretation within hermeneutics helps explain its strong focus upon
issues of communication, be it through language, texts or behaviour. More
important to this discussion, it also raises questions about whether objective
knowledge is possible. Can one person or group’s subjectivity be ‘right’, scien-
tifically, and another’s ‘wrong’? If not, what distinguishes ‘theory’ from ‘opinion’
and how can we adjudicate between theories that are based upon subjective
meanings but contradict one another? There are two schools of thought, here.

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 16 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


What is urban theory? 17

Both concede that theorists are no more objective than those they observe and
that their prejudices will always inform their observations. Both suggest, though,
that the choice of research methods can minimise any theoretical bias that
results from this fact.
Both strands within hermeneutics tend to subscribe to what have been called
abductive research strategies (Blaikie, 1993: 176–90). Abduction involves four
stages. First, so as not to impose their own view of reality on their task, researchers
ask ‘how are things perceived?’ and try to understand the everyday concepts and
meanings that are attached to the particular issue or phenomenon they are inter-
ested in. Second, they ask ‘so what?’ and examine the actions and interactions to
which these meanings give rise. Third, they ask ‘what does this mean for partici-
pants?’ and gather subjective accounts of how perceptions and actions are linked
in everyday life. It is at the fourth stage – that of theory-building, when the
observer stands back and attempts to impose order upon the results of the first
three stages – that the two strands diverge. The first believes that the hermeneutic
method, because it encourages the theorist to resolve the creative tension between
the subjective accounts of those he/she observes and his/her own prejudices, results
in understandings which transcend both and can therefore claim to be objective.
The other argues that ‘truth’ can only lie in a clear, codified and intelligible render-
ing of subjective views. The latter is a relativist position which forces the theorist
to accept there are no universal criteria that can adjudicate between different
‘truths’ and alternative ‘realities’.

Realism
Realism is a relatively new rival to positivism and hermeneutics. It tries to marry
positivism’s commitment to causal explanation and the possibility of prediction
with the hermeneutic principle that much of what is important within the social
sciences cannot be directly observed. Realists agree with positivists that there is
a reality that is independent of human perceptions. Proceeding from this posi-
tion, they have to argue that objective knowledge of that reality is possible;
otherwise their position would be meaningless. (Scientifically speaking, it would
be less than helpful to suggest that something other than our subjective percep-
tions exists but we cannot know what it is.) Realists therefore challenge at least
one strand within hermeneutics in arguing that subjective perceptions might not
only fail to grasp reality, but also grasp ‘realities’ that do not exist; in other
words, they can be wrong. At the same time, realism also challenges the positiv-
ist view that only that which can be observed is real. Realists therefore have to
come up with a way of knowing and understanding reality that is not just based
on empirical observations.
The realist approach to ‘facts and values’ that emerges from this basic position
is a complex one. On the one hand, realists insist that empirical observation has

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 17 12-Apr-14 1:56:13 PM


18 Urban theory

an important role to play in developing and testing theories. On the other hand,
they accept that abstract concepts are fundamental to the way we all view the
external world. This circle is squared in two ways. First, it is argued that the
realist theorist/researcher’s job is to link empirical observations with abstract
arguments in such a way that he/she gains privileged insights that are denied to
those who rely upon empirical observation or subjective interpretation alone.
Second, the rather indeterminate status of facts and values is linked to the argu-
ment that there are different levels of reality that are perceived in different ways
and provide different elements of ‘truth’. On the surface there is the empirical
domain of observable experiences. At a deeper level is the actual domain consist-
ing of events, whether or not they are observed. At the deepest level is the real
domain that is made up of the structures and mechanisms that cause events.
The primary job that realist theory sets itself is to identify the unobservable
but nonetheless ‘necessary’ and ‘real’ mechanisms which underlie and cause
events in particular circumstances. Realist explanation therefore attempts to go
a stage further than positivism. It aims to show how A causes B and not just to
describe patterns that indicate there are causal relations between the two. This
goal is achieved, realists argue, through the use of retroductive research strate-
gies that combine empirical and theoretical forms of inquiry. Retroduction pro-
ceeds in three stages. In the first, empirical observations are made, as in
positivist approaches, which identify patterns in the particular events or actions
that require explanation. In the second, theory-building stage, the theorist/
researcher asks ‘what sort of mechanisms would be necessary to bring about
these patterns?’. He/she then comes up with conjectures about these mechanisms
that stand as a tentative theory. In the third stage, an attempt is made to estab-
lish the validity of the theory by checking whether a larger body of evidence,
conceptual and empirical, is consistent with the existence of the theoretical
mechanism(s).
There is enormous controversy within the social sciences as to the strengths
and weaknesses of these three approaches. There is no agreement about which,
if any, is most consistent, has superior methods, or is most useful. The picture is
complicated still further by the fact that different theoretical traditions and the
schools of thought that develop around particular theorists do not necessarily
fall entirely within any one of the three overall approaches. For instance,
Weberianism – the concepts and theories associated with the sociologist Max
Weber – draws upon hermeneutic and positivist approaches. By contrast, critical
theory – an approach associated with the ‘Frankfurt School’ in general and with
Jürgen Habermas in particular – draws upon insights and methods from herme-
neutics and realism. Variants of Marxism, on the other hand, would be ‘claimed’
by positivists and realists. Boundary disputes within social theory represent a
fascinating field of study in themselves, but they need not detain us. All we need

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 18 12-Apr-14 1:56:14 PM


What is urban theory? 19

note here is that there are some fundamental differences within the social sciences
when it comes to defining what theory is and how it should be constructed and
used, and that these differences are inevitably reflected in urban theory.

And so what on earth is urban theory?


Combining the definitions we have unearthed so far, we might describe urban
theory as ‘a body of ideas explaining one or more aspects of reality within, or
of, towns and cities’. We have seen, however, that towns and cities in themselves
are no longer seen as particularly useful units for social scientific analysis. It is
also apparent that ‘urban’ is defined in such general terms that it is difficult to
contrast it with anything. It therefore cannot help us greatly in isolating a field
of study. What, then, does this simple definition of urban theory mean? The his-
tory of the last hundred years of social science provides two answers to that
question. The more relaxed view is that it is perfectly permissible to say there
are theories on the one hand and urban areas on the other and that urban theory
is simply the first applied to or deduced from aspects of the second. The alterna-
tive view takes the much stricter line that each school within social science must
clarify its core concepts and define its field of study carefully. If ‘the urban’ is not
specific enough to define such a field then the theorist must come up with defini-
tions that identify the ‘theoretical object’ of urban studies more precisely.
Nowadays the relaxed position is by far the most common. It is typified by
Savage et al. (2003: 2) who claim that ‘the fact that the urban cannot be defined
in a general way does not mean that important things cannot be said about
specific processes in particular cities!’ The implication of this position is that
urban theories are generated in one of two ways. In the first, theories that con-
cern themselves with general social processes are applied – by the original theo-
rists or others – to (or within) towns and cities. In the alternative, theories grow
out of specific and consciously chosen ‘urban’ observations. There is no reason
to believe, though, that theories derived from this second route will necessarily
be any more ‘urban’ than those generated by the first. As we shall see, cities are
sometimes seen as microcosms of societies, and there are examples of theoretical
debates that had their origins in urban observations becoming more general and
universal in scope.
No distinction is generally made between these two forms of urban theory.
Michael Peter Smith’s (1980) review of urban social theory, for example, dis-
cusses theorists such as Wirth, who devoted much of his time to urban analysis
and research, and Simmel, who wrote specifically (but only in one of his many
publications) on cities as the ultimate expression of modernity, where his main
interests lay, in a relatively minor part of his contribution to the development of

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 19 12-Apr-14 1:56:14 PM


20 Urban theory

sociological theory more generally. But it also includes Freud, whose work made
very few references to cities and towns or to urbanism. Smith justifies the latter
choice by arguing that when Freud talks of civilisation, he is not just referring
to an advanced state of social development but is dealing specifically with urban
civilisation: ‘Freud treats as indicators of “civilization” a variety of different …
socio-economic developments that originated or occurred almost exclusively in
cities’ (Smith, 1980: 50).
If Freud can be considered an urban theorist, or if Freudian psychoanalytic
theory can at least be considered ‘urban’ when refocused and adapted by the
likes of Smith, it is clear that the relaxed approach to the definition of urban
theory – that it encompasses any application of concepts to urban phenomena –
results in it covering a very broad canvas indeed. If we adopt this first position,
though, such an eventuality cannot be avoided. The decision not to impose a
tighter, limiting definition on ‘the urban’ means the range of issues that might be
covered by urban theory is huge. The field expands every time there is a novel
meeting between theory and urban phenomena and there are no conceptual
boundaries other than those that theorists as a group effectively choose, through
their work, to accept. Judge, Stoker and Wolman found this to be the case even
within the single subdiscipline of urban politics: ‘[t]here are now so many theo-
ries that it is increasingly difficult for scholar and student alike to keep pace with
them’ (Judge et al., 1995: 1; emphasis in original).
The second, less relaxed position offers the prospect of a more restrictive and,
arguably, more manageable focus for urban theory. Saunders (1985; 1986:
52–182) identifies a number of attempts to provide urban studies with a dis-
tinct theoretical focus. Each of them is reviewed briefly in the next chapter.
Saunders concludes (1986: 51), however, that ‘[t]he result has, in most cases,
been conceptual confusion and a series of theoretical dead-ends’. Not everyone
would agree with this conclusion. Nor would it be fair to argue that conceptual
confusion and theoretical dead-ends are limited to explorations within urban
theory. For the purposes of this book, though, we will accept the view of
Saunders and others that urban theory is not adequately defined by those
attempts to provide urban studies with its own distinctive theoretical object.
Such a focus would be too restrictive. In particular, it would exclude many
recent theoretical debates that have important implications for cities but were
not designed primarily as contributions to urban theory.
Accepting the relaxed position on the nature of urban theory, however, means
a choice has to be made about which theories the book should cover and which
should be excluded. Ultimately, this choice has to be based upon personal values
and preferences about what is important. Nonetheless, it is easier to make with
regard to older, more established theoretical approaches than it is with recent
contributions. Previous reviews of the various urban subdisciplines impose a

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 20 12-Apr-14 1:56:14 PM


What is urban theory? 21

semblance of order upon theoretical debates that occurred up until the early
1980s. History has not pronounced so conclusively on more recent debates,
however. The choice here will therefore need to be justified on the basis of some
key propositions about what separates recent debates from previous ones. We
return to this issue in the latter part of Chapter 2. In the first sections of that
chapter, though, a brief review of the historical development of urban theory
helps put the choice made here into perspective.

Questions for discussion


• Urban sociologists have tended to avoid geographical definitions of the city. Discuss
the advantages and disadvantages of doing this.
• This chapter has identified a gap between urban theory and applied urban studies.
What elements should theory include, in your view, to overcome this gap?
• Some scholars have argued that the urban is everywhere and that the rural or coun-
try has become obsolete as a concept. What arguments can you think of in favour or
against this position?

Further reading

The philosophy of science/social science

The literature in this area is notoriously hard going. Blaikie’s Approaches to Social Enquiry
(1993) is an unusually lucid and readable introduction to the field and would be a good
starting point for the uninitiated. Outhwaite’s New Philosophies of Social Science (1987)
offers a good overview of recent developments but is less user-friendly. Delanty’s Social
Science (1997), similarly, is up to date and includes useful sections on positivism and herme-
neutics. Readers interested in learning more about one of the three approaches outlined
above might start with Bryant’s Positivism in Social Theory and Research (1985), Bauman’s
Hermeneutics and Social Science (1978) or, on realism, Sayer’s Method in Social Science (1992).

Overviews of urban theory

As reported in the text, the better contributions tend to focus upon a single academic
subject area rather than present an interdisciplinary picture. Saunders’ Social Theory and
the Urban Question (1986) is comprehensive and clearly written, but concentrates upon
urban sociology and is now somewhat out of date. For those interested in the way indi-
vidual theorists’ understandings evolve over time, the 1981 version of that book provides
interesting reading. Saunders’ work might usefully be read in conjunction with Savage and

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 21 12-Apr-14 1:56:14 PM


22 Urban theory

Warde’s Urban Sociology, Capitalism and Modernity (2003) which is more eclectic but covers
more recent material. Judge, Stoker, and Wolman’s Theories of Urban Politics (1995) is a com-
prehensive, more up-to-date, edited volume covering the urban politics subfield. The early
chapters of Dunleavy’s Urban Political Analysis (1980) also contain a good, if dated, review of
theoretical literature and discuss the validity of the urban’ from a political science perspec-
tive. Theoretical approaches within urban geography can be covered by a selective reading
of Carter’s The Study of Urban Geography (1995), Herbert and Thomas’ Urban Geography
(1982), Hall’s Urban Geography (2007), Johnston’s City and Society (1980) and two books by
Short, An Introduction to Urban Geography (1984) and The Urban Order (1996).Various recent
readers assemble diverse writings from different disciplines. LeGates and Stout’s The City
Reader (2011) is a collection of twentieth-century writings on cities, grouped thematically,
that includes some key theoretical contributions. Fainstein and Campbell’s Readings in Urban
Theory (2011) is more contemporary and explicitly theory-based but narrower in its cover-
age and dominated by US writers and has a focus on urban planning.

01_Harding & Blokland_BAB1401B0005_Ch-01.indd 22 12-Apr-14 1:56:14 PM

You might also like