Mainline Economics
Mainline Economics
Mainline Economics
Economics
Six Nobel Lectures
in the Tradition of Adam Smith
Edited by
Peter J. Boettke,
Stefanie Haeffele-Balch,
and Virgil Henry Storr
Arlington, Virginia
ABOUT THE MERCATUS CENTER AT GEORGE MASON UNIVERSITY
The Mercatus Center at George Mason University is the world’s premier university source for
market-oriented ideas—bridging the gap between academic ideas and real-world problems.
A university-based research center, Mercatus advances knowledge about how markets work to
improve people’s lives by training graduate students, conducting research, and applying eco-
nomics to offer solutions to society’s most pressing problems.
Our mission is to generate knowledge and understanding of the institutions that affect the
freedom to prosper and to find sustainable solutions that overcome the barriers preventing
individuals from living free, prosperous, and peaceful lives.
Introduction and Conclusion © 2016 by Peter J. Boettke, Stefanie Haeffele-Balch, and Virgil
Henry Storr
Friedrich August von Hayek’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation
(1974)
James M. Buchanan Jr.’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation (1986)
Ronald H. Coase’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation (1991)
Douglass C. North’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation (1993)
Vernon L. Smith’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation (2002)
Elinor C. Ostrom’s Prize Lecture in Economic Sciences © The Nobel Foundation (2009)
Editorial note: All lectures reflect the final versions that were reprinted in the American Economic
Review, which kindly granted Mercatus permission to reprint the figures that appeared in those
versions.
Index 261
- vi -
In t r o d u c t i o n : Wh at Is
Ma i n l i n e Ec o n o m i c s ?
P e t e r J. B o e t t k e , St e fa n i e H a e f f e l e - B a l c h ,
a n d Vi r g i l He n r y St o r r
labor. According to Smith ([1776] 1981: 13), “the greatest improve-
ment in the productive powers of labour, and the greater part of the
skill, dexterity, and judgment with which it is any where directed, or
applied, seem to have been the effects of the division of labour.” It is,
Smith argues, our propensity to trade that gives occasion to the divi-
sion of labor. It is our propensity to “truck, barter, and exchange” that
allows both for you to satisfy your need for food and for me to satisfy
my need for farming instruments even when you have focused solely
on developing farming instruments and I have focused all of my efforts
on farming. “As it is the power of exchanging that gives occasion to
the division of labour,” Smith (ibid.: 31) explains, “so to the extent of
this division must always be limited by that power, or, in other words,
by the extent of the market.” The richest societies are, therefore, those
whose formal and informal institutions allow for and protect an open
and expansive market sphere.
In addition to articulating the key question in modern economics
and offering a compelling and still well-regarded answer to that ques-
tion, Adam Smith also anticipated and inspired a number of the major
theoretical developments in several branches of economics, includ-
ing price theory, market process economics, economic development,
industrial organ ization, public economics, institutional economics,
experimental economics, and behavioral economics. But, while many
economists w ill trace the profession back to the tomes of Adam Smith
and admit to finding inspiration in Smith for their theoretical and
empirical projects, it is sometimes quite difficult to identify Smith’s
direct influence in many of the branches of modern economics. In
fact, the propositions regarding the nature of human action, the place
of institutions, and the role of government articulated by the main-
stream of economics has sometimes deviated quite significantly from
those advanced by the mainline of economics that descended from
Adam Smith.
- 2 -
Introduction
hose economists outside the most prestigious places who take their
T
scientific cues, as it were, from those at the most prestigious settings,
would also be considered mainstream economists.
It is important to note that there have been significant shifts
over time in what constitutes mainstream economics. For instance, the
Keynesian revolution in macroeconomics gave rise to the Neoclassical
Synthesis, which in turn lost ground to the Neo-Keynesians, who were
then replaced by monetarism and New Classical Economics, which
gave way to New Keynesian Economics, which has lost ground to the
New Neoclassical Synthesis. The same has happened in institutional
economics, where the Old Institutionalism of Thorstein Veblen has
been replaced by the New Institutional Economics of North.
It is also important to note that mainline economics sometimes
represents the mainstream and sometimes it does not. As Boettke (ibid.)
notes, “Often the mainline and the mainstream dovetail, but at other
times they deviate from one another.” Keynes’ theory, for instance,
replaced an older mainline monetary theory advanced by Knut Wicksell,
Hayek, and others as the mainstream view. Similarly, as noted above, the
institutionalism of Veblen was replaced by the mainline institutional
views of North.
Arguably, there are at least three propositions regarding the nature
of human action and the role of institutions that mainline economics
critically adopt and advance: (1) there are limits to the benevolence that
individuals can rely on and therefore they face cognitive and epistemic
limits as they negotiate the social world, but (2) formal and informal
institutions guide and direct human activity, and, so (3) social coop-
eration is possible without central direction. Stated another way, by
relying on the emergent and human-devised rules of conduct, agents
possessing both the capacities and the failings of the typical human
being can nonetheless work together to achieve their individual and
collective goals.
- 4 -
Introduction
The man of system inexorably faces what Don Lavoie ([1985] 2015;
[1985] 2016) has characterized as a “knowledge problem.” Every h uman
being has a principle of motion of her own that the central authority
could never know, much less marshal to control human society.
That we must cooperate with countless others to satisfy our needs,
and that t hese o thers cannot be made to do so by some central author-
ity nor compelled to do so because of their intimate connection to us,
need not paralyze us. Individuals are able to negotiate the social world
because there are formal and informal rules of just conduct on which
they can rely.
Institutions m atter for Smith. As Smith ([1776] 1981: 910) notes,
“commerce and manufactures can seldom flourish long in any state
which does not enjoy a regular administration of justice, in which the
people do not feel themselves secure in the possession of their property,
in which the faith of contracts is not supported by law, and in which the
authority of the state is not supposed to be regularly employed in enforc-
ing the payment of debts from all those who are able to pay.” Consider,
also, Smith’s discussion of how different institutional arrangements in
two universities can actually alter the quality of teaching in those set-
tings (ibid.: 760). While teachers in Scotland were paid primarily from
fees from students, teachers in Oxford w ere paid from endowments
and w ere prohibited from receiving fees from their pupils. As such,
in Scottish universities (such as Glasgow), teachers could incur mone-
tary losses if student enrollment dropped, whereas in Oxford, teachers
were paid the same w hether their lectures were well attended or not.
- 6 -
Introduction
In the race for wealth, and honours, and preferments, he may run as
hard as he can, and strain every nerve and every muscle, in order to
outstrip all his competitors. But if he should justle, or throw down
any of them, the indulgence of the spectators is entirely at an end.
It is a violation of fair play, which they cannot admit of. This man is
to them, in every respect, as good as he: they do not enter into that
self–love by which he prefers himself so much to this other, and
cannot go along with the motive from which he hurt him.
- 7 -
Introduction
The produce of the soil maintains at all times nearly that number
of inhabitants which it is capable of maintaining. The rich only
select from the heap what is most precious and agreeable. They
consume little more than the poor; and in spite of their natural
selfishness and rapacity, though they mean only their own conve-
niency, though the sole end which they propose from the labours
of all the thousands whom they employ be the gratification of
their own vain and insatiable desires, they divide with the poor the
produce of all their improvements. They are led by an invisible
hand to make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of
life which would have been made had the earth been divided into
- 9 -
Introduction
equal portions among all its inhabitants; and thus, without intend-
ing it, without knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and
afford means to the multiplication of the species. When Provi-
dence divided the earth among a few lordly masters, it neither for-
got nor abandoned t hose who seemed to have been left out in the
partition. These last too enjoy their share of all that it produces.
- 12 -
Introduction
political process and his emphasis on the importance of the rules of the
game in determining the success or failure of political action.
Buchanan used his Nobel lecture to remind economists that indi-
viduals in politics, just as in markets, act purposively, pursue their
own interests, and engage in exchange in order to secure the (politi
cal) goods and services for themselves or others. As such, economists
would do well to heed the guidance of Wicksell. “Stripped to its
essentials,” Buchanan (see page 44) asserts, “Wicksell’s message was
clear, elementary, and self-evident. Economists should cease proffer-
ing policy advice as if they were employed by a benevolent despot,
and they should look to the structure within which political deci-
sions are made.”
The nature of the institutions that govern political decision-making
and the difference between political and market institutions m atter
a g reat deal to Buchanan. For Buchanan, the differences we observe
between politics and markets (which we can think of as two games we
chose to play) have more to do with the different rules governing action
within the two games and less to do with any differences in the players
who are attracted to those games. As Buchanan (see page 50) asserts,
“The relevant difference between markets and politics does not lie in
the kinds of values/interest that persons pursue, but in the c onditions
under which they pursue their various interests.”
Buchanan believes that a focus on the rules of the political pro
cess, the processes by which citizens can alter these rules, and the likely
consequences of any policy proposal, given the existing or likely institu-
tional environment in which it w ill be implemented, rather than advo-
cacy of specific policies and interventions, should become the central
focus of the political economist. Like Hayek, then, Buchanan (see page
58) argues for a more humble role for the political economist: “Posi-
tively, this role involves analysis of the working properties of alternative
- 13 -
Introduction
- 14 -
Introduction
- 15 -
Introduction
- 19 -
Introduction
Notes
- 20 -
Introduction
- 21 -
Introduction
References
Boettke, Peter J. 2012. Living Economics: Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow. Oakland, CA: The
Independent Institute.
Boettke, Peter J., Christopher J. Coyne, and Peter T. Leeson. 2014. “Earw(h)ig:
I Can’t Hear You Because Your Ideas Are Old.” Cambridge Journal of Economics 38:
531– 44.
Boulding, Kenneth E. 1971. “After Samuelson, Who Needs Adam Smith?” History of
Political Economy, 3(2): 225–237.
Lavoie, Don. 2015. Rivalry and Central Planning: The Socialist Calculation Debate Reconsidered.
Arlington, VA: Mercatus Center. (Orig. pub. 1985.)
———. 2016. National Economic Planning: What Is Left? Arlington, VA: Mercatus Center.
(Orig. pub. 1985.)
Read, Leonard E. 1958. I, Pencil: My Family Tree as Told to Leonard E. Read. Irvington-on-
Hudson, NY: The Foundation for Economic Education.
Smith, Adam. 1981. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Vols. 1
and 2. Edited by R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
(Orig. pub. 1776.)
———. 1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie.
Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. (Orig. pub. 1759.)
- 22 -