Finding Ultimate Reality - David Gooding & John Lennox
Finding Ultimate Reality - David Gooding & John Lennox
Finding Ultimate Reality - David Gooding & John Lennox
RE A L IT Y
THE QUEST FOR REALITY AND SIGNIFICANCE
FI N D I N G U LTI M ATE
RE A L IT Y
IN SEARCH OF THE BEST ANSWERS
TO THE BIGGEST QUESTIONS
DAV I D G O O D I N G
J O H N LEN N OX
Myrtlefield House
Belfast, Northern Ireland
David Gooding and John Lennox have asserted their right under the Copyright,
Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Authors of this work.
Finding Ultimate Reality: In Search of the Best Answers to the Biggest Questions
Book 2, The Quest for Reality and Significance
Copyright © Myrtlefield Trust, 2018
All Scripture quotations, unless otherwise indicated, are taken from The Holy
Bible, English Standard Version, copyright © 2001 by Crossway Bibles, a division
of Good News Publishers. Used by permission. Scripture quotations marked NIV
are from the Holy Bible, New International Version® Anglicized, NIV® Copyright
© 1979, 1984, 2011 by Biblica, Inc.® Used by permission. All rights reserved
worldwide. Italics within Scripture quotations indicate emphasis added. Scripture
quotations marked (our trans.) are as translated by David Gooding. Foreign
language quotations marked (our trans.) are as translated by John Lennox.
23 22 21 20 19 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2
DEDICATED TO OUR YOUNGER FELLOW STUDENTS,
Series Preface xi
Analytical Outline xv
Series Introduction 1
4 Christian Theism:
The Search for Ultimate Reality in God’s Self-revelation 125
I.1. A Rose 5
I.4. A Touchstone 32
I.5. An Apple 35
xii
SERIES PREFACE
xiii
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
xiv
ANALYTICAL OUTLINE
xvi
ANALYTICAL OUTLINE
xvii
FI N D I N G
U LT I M AT E R E A L I T Y
SERIES INTRODUCTION
1 Please note this Introduction is the same for each book in the series, except for the final sec-
tion—Our Aim.
3
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
the background of the traditions we have inherited from the past and
that will mean that we need to have a good grasp of history.
Sometimes we forget that ancient philosophers faced and
thought deeply about the basic philosophical principles that underlie
all science and came up with answers from which we can still profit.
If we forget this, we might spend a lot of time and effort thinking
through the same problems and not coming up with as good answers
as they did.
Moreover, the role of education is surely to try and understand
how all the various fields of knowledge and experience in life fit to-
gether. To understand a grand painting one needs to see the picture
as a whole and understand the interrelationship of all its details and
not simply concentrate on one of its features.
Moreover, while we rightly insist on the objectivity of science we
must not forget that it is we who are doing the science. And therefore,
sooner or later, we must come to ask how we ourselves fit into the uni-
verse that we are studying. We must not allow ourselves to become
so engrossed in our material world and its related technologies that
we neglect our fellow human beings; for they, as we shall later see, are
more important than the rest of the universe put together.2 The study
of ourselves and our fellow human beings will, of course, take more
than a knowledge of science. It will involve the worlds of philosophy,
sociology, literature, art, music, history and much more besides.
Educationally, therefore, it is an important thing to remember—
and a thrilling thing to discover—the interrelation and the unity of
all knowledge. Take, for example, what it means to know what a rose
is: What is the truth about a rose?
To answer the question adequately, we shall have to consult a
whole array of people. First the scientists. We begin with the bota-
nists, who are constantly compiling and revising lists of all the known
plants and flowers in the world and then classifying them in terms of
families and groups. They help us to appreciate our rose by telling us
what family it belongs to and what are its distinctive features.
Next, the plant breeders and gardeners will inform us of the his-
tory of our particular rose, how it was bred from other kinds, and the
conditions under which its sort can best be cultivated.
4
SERIES INTRODUCTION
5
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
about roses. Indeed, they have not explained what perhaps most of
us would think is the most important thing about roses: the beauty
of their form, colour and fragrance.
Now here is a very significant thing: scientists can explain the as-
tonishing complexity of the mechanisms which lie behind our senses
of vision and smell that enable us to see roses and detect their scent.
But we don’t need to ask the scientists whether we ought to consider
roses beautiful or not: we can see and smell that for ourselves! We
perceive this by intuition. We just look at the rose and we can at once
see that it is beautiful. We do not need anyone to tell us that it is
beautiful. If anyone were so foolish as to suggest that because science
cannot measure beauty, therefore beauty does not exist, we should
simply say: ‘Don’t be silly.’
But the perception of beauty does not rest on our own intuition
alone. We could also consult the artists. With their highly developed
sense of colour, light and form, they will help us to perceive a depth
and intensity of beauty in a rose that otherwise we might miss. They
can educate our eyes.
Likewise, there are the poets. They, with their finely honed abil-
ity as word artists, will use imagery, metaphor, allusion, rhythm and
rhyme to help us formulate and articulate the feelings we experience
when we look at roses, feelings that otherwise might remain vague
and difficult to express.
Finally, if we wanted to pursue this matter of the beauty of a
rose deeper still, we could talk to the philosophers, especially experts
in aesthetics. For each of us, perceiving that a rose is beautiful is a
highly subjective experience, something that we see and feel at a deep
level inside ourselves. Nevertheless, when we show a rose to other
people, we expect them too to agree that it is beautiful. They usually
have no difficulty in doing so.
From this it would seem that, though the appreciation of beauty
is a highly subjective experience, yet we observe:
1. there are some objective criteria for deciding what is beauti-
ful and what is not;
2. there is in each person an inbuilt aesthetic sense, a capacity
for perceiving beauty; and
3. where some people cannot, or will not, see beauty, in, say,
6
SERIES INTRODUCTION
7
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
8
SERIES INTRODUCTION
‘He who will succeed’, said Aristotle, ‘must ask the right questions’;
and so, when it comes to forming a worldview, must we.
It is at least comforting to know that we are not the first people to
have asked such questions. Many others have done so in the past (and
continue to do so in the present). That means they have done some
of the work for us! In order to profit from their thinking and experi-
ence, it will be helpful for us to collect some of those fundamental
questions which have been and are on practically everybody’s list.
We shall then ask why these particular questions have been thought
to be important. After that we shall briefly survey some of the varied
answers that have been given, before we tackle the task of forming
our own answers. So let’s get down to compiling a list of ‘worldview
questions’. First of all there are questions about the universe in gen-
eral and about our home planet Earth in particular.
The Greeks were the first people in Europe to ask scientific ques-
tions about what the earth and the universe are made of, and how
they work. It would appear that they asked their questions for no
other reason than sheer intellectual curiosity. Their research was, as
we would nowadays describe it, disinterested. They were not at first
concerned with any technology that might result from it. Theirs was
pure, not applied, science. We pause to point out that it is still a very
healthy thing for any educational system to maintain a place for pure
science in its curriculum and to foster an attitude of intellectual cu-
riosity for its own sake.
But we cannot afford to limit ourselves to pure science (and even
less to technology, marvellous though it is). Centuries ago Socrates
perceived that. He was initially curious about the universe, but grad-
ually came to feel that studying how human beings ought to behave
9
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
10
SERIES INTRODUCTION
11
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
was far more important than finding out what the moon was made
of. He therefore abandoned physics and immersed himself in moral
philosophy.
On the other hand, the leaders of the major philosophical schools
in ancient Greece came to see that you could not form an adequate
doctrine of human moral behaviour without understanding how hu-
man beings are related both to their cosmic environment and to the
powers and principles that control the universe. In this they were
surely right, which brings us to what was and still is the first funda-
mental question.3
What lies behind the observable universe? Physics has taught us that
things are not quite what they seem to be. A wooden table, which
looks solid, turns out to be composed of atoms bound together by
powerful forces which operate in the otherwise empty space between
them. Each atom turns out also to be mostly empty space and can be
modelled from one point of view as a nucleus surrounded by orbit-
ing electrons. The nucleus only occupies about one billionth of the
space of the atom. Split the nucleus and we find protons and neutrons.
They turn out to be composed of even stranger quarks and gluons.
Are these the basic building blocks of matter, or are there other even
more mysterious elementary building blocks to be found? That is one
of the exciting quests of modern physics. And even as the search goes
on, another question keeps nagging: what lies behind basic matter
anyway?
The answers that are given to this question fall roughly into two
groups: those that suggest that there is nothing ‘behind’ the basic
matter of the universe, and those that maintain that there certainly
is something.
12
SERIES INTRODUCTION
13
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Group A. Human nature. Human beings are nothing but matter. They
have no spirit and their powers of rational thought have
arisen out of mindless matter by non-rational processes.
Morality. Man’s sense of morality and duty arise solely out
of social interactions between him and his fellow humans.
Human rights. Human beings have no inherent, natural
rights, but only those that are granted by society or the
government of the day.
Purpose in life. Man makes his own purpose.
The future. The utopia dreamed of and longed for will be
brought about, either by the irresistible outworking of the
forces inherent in matter and/or history; or, alternatively,
as human beings learn to direct and control the biological
processes of evolution itself.
Death and beyond. Death for each individual means total
extinction. Nothing survives.
14
SERIES INTRODUCTION
Now it is obvious that the two groups of answers given above are dia-
metrically opposed; but we ought to pause here to make sure that we
have understood what exactly the nature and cause of the opposition
is. If we were not thinking carefully, we might jump to the conclusion
that the answers in the A-groups are those given by science, while the
answers in the B-groups are those given by religion. But that would
be a fundamental misunderstanding of the situation. It is true that
the majority of scientists today would agree with the answers given in
the A-groups; but there is a growing number of scientists who would
agree with the answers given in the B-groups. It is not therefore a con-
flict between science and religion. It is a difference in the basic phi-
losophies which determine the interpretation of the evidence which
science provides. Atheists will interpret that evidence in one way;
theists (or pantheists) will interpret it in another.
This is understandable. No scientist comes to the task of doing
15
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
VOICES TO BE LISTENED TO
16
SERIES INTRODUCTION
Our worldview must be our own, in the sense that we have per-
sonally thought it through and adopted it of our own free will. No
one has the right to impose his or her worldview on us by force. The
days are rightly gone when the church could force Galileo to deny
what science had plainly taught him. Gone, too, for the most part,
are the days when the State could force an atheistic worldview on
people on pain of prison and even death. Human rights demand that
people should be free to hold and to propagate by reasoned argument
whatever worldview they believe in—so long, of course, that their
view does not injure other people. We, the authors of this book, hold
a theistic worldview. But we shall not attempt to force our view down
anybody’s throat. We come from a tradition whose basic principle is
‘Let everyone be persuaded in his own mind.’
So we must all make up our own minds and form our own world-
view. In the process of doing so there are a number of voices that we
must listen to.
The first voice we must listen to is intuition. There are things in life
that we see and know, not as the result of lengthy philosophical rea-
soning, nor as a result of rigorous scientific experimentation, but by
direct, instinctive intuition. We ‘see’ that a rose is beautiful. We in-
stinctively ‘know’ that child abuse is wrong. A scientist can some-
times ‘see’ what the solution to a problem is going to be even before
he has worked out the scientific technique that will eventually provide
formal proof of it.
A few scientists and philosophers still try to persuade us that the
laws of cause and effect operating in the human brain are completely
deterministic so that our decisions are predetermined: real choice is
not possible. But, say what they will, we ourselves intuitively know
that we do have the ability to make a free choice, whether, say, to read
a book, or to go for a walk, whether to tell the truth or to tell a lie. We
know we are free to take either course of action, and everyone else
knows it too, and acts accordingly. This freedom is such a part of our
innate concept of human dignity and value that we (for the most part)
insist on being treated as responsible human beings and on treating
others as such. For that reason, if we commit a crime, the magistrate
17
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
will first enquire (a) if, when we committed the crime, we knew we
were doing wrong; and (b) whether or not we were acting under du-
ress. The answer to these questions will determine the verdict.
We must, therefore, give due attention to intuition, and not allow
ourselves to be persuaded by pseudo-intellectual arguments to deny
(or affirm) what we intuitively know to be true (or false).
On the other hand, intuition has its limits. It can be mistaken.
When ancient scientists first suggested that the world was a sphere,
even some otherwise great thinkers rejected the idea. They intui-
tively felt that it was absurd to think that there were human beings
on the opposite side of the earth to us, walking ‘upside-down’, their
feet pointed towards our feet (hence the term ‘antipodean’) and their
heads hanging perilously down into empty space! But intuition had
misled them. The scientists who believed in a spherical earth were
right, intuition was wrong.
The lesson is that we need both intuition and science, acting as
checks and balances, the one on the other.
Science speaks to our modern world with a very powerful and au-
thoritative voice. It can proudly point to a string of scintillating theo-
retical breakthroughs which have spawned an almost endless array of
technological spin-offs: from the invention of the light bulb to virtual-
reality environments; from the wheel to the moon-landing vehicle;
from the discovery of aspirin and antibiotics to the cracking of the
genetic code; from the vacuum cleaner to the smartphone; from the
abacus to the parallel computer; from the bicycle to the self-driving
car. The benefits that come from these achievements of science are
self-evident, and they both excite our admiration and give to science
an immense credibility.
Yet for many people the voice of science has a certain ambiva-
lence about it, for the achievements of science are not invariably used
for the good of humanity. Indeed, in the past century science has
produced the most hideously efficient weapons of destruction that
the world has ever seen. The laser that is used to restore vision to the
eye can be used to guide missiles with deadly efficiency. This devel-
opment has led in recent times to a strong anti-scientific reaction.
18
SERIES INTRODUCTION
19
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
7 Those who wish to study the topic further are directed to the Appendix in this book: ‘The
20
SERIES INTRODUCTION
21
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
adopt; but it can and will help us to see if the belief system which we
build on those axioms is logically consistent.
There is yet a third benefit to be gained from philosophy. The his-
tory of philosophy shows that, of all the many different philosophical
systems, or worldviews, that have been built up by rigorous philoso-
phers on the basis of human reasoning alone, none has proved con-
vincing to all other philosophers, let alone to the general public. None
has achieved permanence, a fact which can seem very frustrating.
But perhaps the frustration is not altogether bad in that it might lead
us to ask whether there could just be another source of information
without which human reason alone is by definition inadequate. And
if our very frustration with philosophy for having seemed at first to
promise so much satisfaction, and then in the end to have delivered
so little, disposes us to look around for that other source of informa-
tion, even our frustration could turn out to be a supreme benefit.
22
SERIES INTRODUCTION
23
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
24
SERIES INTRODUCTION
25
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
26
SERIES INTRODUCTION
FIGURE I.3.
On the Origin of Species (1859)
by Charles Darwin.
One of the book epigraphs
Charles Darwin selected for
his magnum opus is from
Francis Bacon’s Advancement
of Learning (1605).
27
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
All of these famous men would have agreed with Einstein: ‘Sci-
ence without religion is lame, religion without science is blind.’13 His-
tory shows us very clearly, then, that far from belief in God being a
hindrance to science, it has provided one of the main impulses for its
development.
Still today there are many first-rate scientists who are believers in
God. For example, Professor William D. Phillips, Nobel laureate for
Physics 1997, is an active Christian, as is the world-famous botanist
and former Director of the Royal Botanic Gardens, Kew in London,
Sir Ghillean Prance, and so is the geneticist Francis S. Collins, who
was the Director of the National Institutes of Health in the United
States who gained recognition for his leadership of the international
Human Genome Project which culminated in 2003 with the comple-
tion of a finished sequence of human DNA.14
But with many people another objection arises: if one is not sure
that God even exists, would it not be unscientific to go looking for
evidence for God’s existence? Surely not. Take the late Professor Carl
Sagan and the Search for Extra Terrestrial Intelligence (the SETI pro-
ject), which he promoted. Sagan was a famous astronomer, but when
he began this search he had no hard-and-fast proven facts to go on.
He proceeded simply on the basis of a hypothesis. If intelligent life
has evolved on earth, then it would be possible, perhaps even likely,
that it would have developed on other suitable planets elsewhere in
the universe. He had no guarantee that it was so, or that he would
find it, even if it existed. But even so both he and NASA (the National
Aeronautics and Space Administration) thought it worth spending
great effort, time and considerable sums of money to employ radio
telescopes to listen to remote galaxies for evidence of intelligent life
elsewhere in the universe.
Why, then, should it be thought any less scientific to look for an
intelligent creator, especially when there is evidence that the universe
bears the imprint of his mind? The only valid excuse for not seeking
for God would be the possession of convincing evidence that God
does not, and could not, exist. No one has such proof.
But for many people divine revelation seems, nonetheless, an utter
28
SERIES INTRODUCTION
One of the central questions we are setting out to examine is: can we
know the ultimate truth about reality? Before we consider different
aspects of reality, we need to determine what we mean by ‘reality’.
For that purpose let’s start with the way we use the term in ordinary,
everyday language. After that we can move on to consider its use at
higher levels.
In everyday language the noun ‘reality’, the adjective ‘real’, and
the adverb ‘really’ have several different connotations according to
the contexts in which they are used. Let’s think about some examples.
First, in some situations the opposite of ‘real’ is ‘imaginary’ or ‘illu-
sory’. So, for instance, a thirsty traveller in the Sahara may see in the
distance what looks to him like an oasis with water and palm trees,
when in fact there is no oasis there at all. What he thinks he sees is
a mirage, an optical illusion. The oasis is not real, we say; it does not
actually exist.15 Similarly a patient, having been injected with power-
ful drugs in the course of a serious operation, may upon waking up
from the anaesthetic suffer hallucinations, and imagine she sees all
kinds of weird creatures stalking round her room. But if we say, as
we do, that these things which she imagines she sees, are not real, we
15 Mirages occur ‘when sharp differences in temperature and therefore in density develop be-
tween thin layers of air at and immediately above the ground. This causes light to be bent, or
refracted, as it travels through one layer to the next. . . . During the day, when a warm layer
occurs next to the ground, objects near the horizon often appear to be reflected in flat sur-
faces, such as beaches, deserts, roads and water. This produces the shimmering, floating im-
ages which are commonly observed on very hot days.’ Oxford Reference Encyclopaedia, 913.
29
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
mean that they do not in actual fact exist. We could argue, of course,
that something is going on in the patient’s brain, and she is experi-
encing impressions similar to those she would have received if the
weird creatures had been real. Her impressions, then, are real in the
sense that they exist in her brain; but they do not correspond with
the external reality that the patient supposes is creating these sense
impressions. The mechanisms of her brain are presenting her with a
false picture: the weird creatures do not exist. She is not seeing them.
They are not real. On the basis of examples like this (the traveller and
the patient) some philosophers have argued that none of us can ever
be sure that the sense impressions which we think we receive from
the external world are true representations of the external world, and
not illusions. We consider their arguments in detail in Book 3 in this
series, Questioning Our Knowledge, dealing with epistemology and
related matters.
To sum up so far, then: neither the traveller nor the patient was per-
ceiving external reality as it really was. But the reasons for their failure
were different: with the traveller it was an external illusion (possibly
reinforced by his thirst) that made him misread reality and imagine
there was a real oasis there, when there wasn’t. With the patient there
was nothing unusual in the appearance of her room to cause her dis-
ordered perception. The difficulty was altogether internal to her. The
drugs had distorted the perception mechanisms of her brain.
From these two examples we can learn some practical lessons:
1. It is important for us all to question from time to time
whether what we unthinkingly take to be reality is in fact
reality.
2. In cases like these it is external reality that has to be the
standard by which we judge whether our sense perceptions
are true or not.
3. Setting people free from their internal subjective misper-
ceptions will depend on getting them, by some means or
other, to face and perceive the external, objective reality.
Second, in other situations the opposite of ‘real’, in everyday lan-
guage, is ‘counterfeit’, ‘spurious’, ‘ fraudulent’. So if we describe a
piece of metal as being ‘real gold’, we mean that it is genuine gold,
and not something such as brass that looks like gold, but isn’t. The
30
SERIES INTRODUCTION
31
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
imitation gems, all existed in the external world. In that sense, there-
fore, they were all real, part of the external reality, actual pieces of
matter.
What, then, was the trouble with them? It was that the fraudsters
had claimed for the coins and the bank notes a value and a buying
power that they did not actually possess; and in the case of the two
necklaces the unscrupulous jewellers had on both occasions misrep-
resented the nature of the matter of which the gems were composed.
The question arises: how can people avoid being taken in by such
spurious claims and misrepresentations of matter? It is not difficult
to see how questions like this will become important when we come
to consider the matter of the universe and its properties.
In modern, as in ancient, times, to test whether an object is made
of pure gold or not, use is made of a black, fine-grained, siliceous
stone, called a touchstone. When pure gold is rubbed on this touch-
stone, it leaves behind on the stone streaks of a certain character;
whereas objects made of adulterated gold, or of some baser metal,
will leave behind streaks of a different character.
32
SERIES INTRODUCTION
cide which experts to trust? Is there any kind of touchstone that or-
dinary people can use on the experts themselves, or at least on their
interpretations?
There is one more situation worth investigating at this point be-
fore we begin our main study.
Third, when we are confronted with what purports to be an ac-
count of something that happened in the past and of the causes that
led to its happening, we rightly ask questions: ‘Did this event really
take place? Did it take place in the way that this account says it did?
Was the alleged cause the real cause?’ The difficulty with things that
happened in the past is that we cannot get them to repeat themselves
in the present, and watch them happening all over again in our labo-
ratories. We have therefore to search out and study what evidence is
available and then decide which interpretation of the evidence best
explains what actually happened.
This, of course, is no unusual situation to be in. Detectives, seek-
ing to solve a murder mystery and to discover the real criminal, are
constantly in this situation; and this is what historians and archaeol-
ogists and palaeontologists do all the time. But mistakes can be made
in handling and interpreting the evidence. For instance, in 1980
a man and his wife were camping in the Australian outback, when
a dingo (an Australian wild dog) suddenly attacked and killed their
little child. When, however, the police investigated the matter, they
did not believe the parents’ story; they alleged that the woman herself
had actually killed the child. The courts found her guilty and she was
duly sentenced. But new evidence was discovered that corroborated
the parents’ story, and proved that it really was a dingo that killed the
infant. The couple was not fully and finally exonerated until 2012.
Does this kind of case mean, then, that we cannot ever be certain
that any historical event really happened? Or that we can never be
sure as to its real causes? Of course not! It is beyond all doubt that, for
instance, Napoleon invaded Russia, and that Genghis Khan besieged
Beijing (then called Zhongdu). The question is, as we considered ear-
lier: what kind of evidence must we have in order to be sure that a
historical event really happened?
But enough of these preliminary exercises. It is time now to take
our first step towards answering the question: can we know the ulti-
mate truth about reality?
33
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Ourselves as individuals
34
SERIES INTRODUCTION
We know that we did not always exist. We can remember being little
children. We have watched ourselves growing up to full manhood
and womanhood. We have also observed that sooner or later people
die, and the unthinking earth, unknowingly, becomes their grave.
What then is the significance of the individual human person, and of
his or her comparatively short life on earth?
Some think that it is Mankind, the human race as a whole, that
is the significant phenomenon: the individual counts for very little.
On this view, the human race is like a great fruit tree. Each year it
produces a large crop of apples. All of them are more or less alike.
None is of any particular significance as an individual. Everyone is
35
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
destined for a very short life before, like the rest of the crop, it is
consumed and forgotten; and so makes room for next year’s crop.
The tree itself lives on, producing crops year after year, in a seemingly
endless cycle of birth, growth and disappearance. On this view
then, the tree is the permanent, significant phenomenon; any one
individual apple is of comparatively little value.
Our origin
But this view of the individual in relation to the race does not get us to
the root of our question; for the human race too did not always exist,
but had a beginning, and so did the universe itself. This, therefore,
only pushes the question one stage further back: to what ultimately
do the human race as a whole and the universe itself owe their exist-
ence? What is the Great Reality behind the non-rational matter of
the universe, and behind us rational, personal, individual members
of the human race?
Before we begin to survey the answers that have been given to
this question over the centuries, we should notice that though sci-
ence can point towards an answer, it cannot finally give us a complete
answer. That is not because there is something wrong with science;
the difficulty lies in the nature of things. The most widely accepted
scientific theory nowadays (but not the only one) is that the universe
came into being at the so-called Big Bang. But the theory tells us that
here we encounter a singularity, that is, a point at which the laws of
physics all break down. If that is true, it follows that science by itself
cannot give a scientific account of what lay before, and led to, the Big
Bang, and thus to the universe, and eventually to ourselves as indi-
vidual human beings.
Our purpose
The fact that science cannot answer these questions does not mean, of
course, that they are pseudo-questions and not worth asking. Adam
Schaff, the Polish Marxist philosopher, long ago observed:
What is the meaning of life? What is man’s place in the uni-
verse? It seems difficult to express oneself scientifically on such
36
SERIES INTRODUCTION
hazy topics. And yet if one should assert ten times over that
these are typical pseudo-problems, problems would remain.18
Yes, surely problems would remain; and they are life’s most im-
portant questions. Suppose by the help of science we could come to
know everything about every atom, every molecule, every cell, every
electrical current, every mechanism in our body and brain. How
much further forward should we be? We should now know what we
are made of, and how we work. But we should still not know what
we are made for.
Suppose for analogy’s sake we woke up one morning to find a
new, empty jeep parked outside our house, with our name written
on it, by some anonymous donor, specifying that it was for our use.
Scientists could describe every atom and molecule it was made of.
Engineers could explain how it worked, and that it was designed
for transporting people. It was obviously intended, therefore, to go
places. But where? Neither science as such, nor engineering as such,
could tell us where we were meant to drive the jeep to. Should we not
then need to discover who the anonymous donor was, and whether
the jeep was ours to do what we liked with, answerable to nobody: or
whether the jeep had been given to us on permanent loan by its maker
and owner with the expectation that we should consult the donor’s
intentions, follow the rules in the driver’s handbook, and in the end
be answerable to the donor for how we had used it?
That surely is the situation we find ourselves in
as human beings. We are equipped with a magnifi- Must we not ask
cent piece of physical and biological engineering, what our relationship
that is, our body and brain; and we are in the driv- is to whatever we
er’s seat, behind the steering wheel. But we did not owe our existence
make ourselves, nor the ‘machine’ we are in charge to? After all, what
of. Must we not ask what our relationship is to if it turned out to be
whatever we owe our existence to? After all, what if that we owe our
it turned out to be that we owe our existence not to existence not to an
an impersonal what but to a personal who? impersonal what but
To some the latter possibility is instinctively to a personal who?
unattractive if not frightening; they would prefer
37
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Our search
38
SERIES INTRODUCTION
does humanity as a whole owe its existence, but what is the status of
the individual human being in relation to the race as a whole and to
the uncountable myriads of individual phenomena that go to make
up the universe? Or, we might ask it another way: what is our sig-
nificance within the reality in which we find ourselves? This is the
ultimate question hanging over every one of our lives, whether we
seek answers or we don’t. The answers we have for it will affect our
thinking in every significant area of life.
These, then, are not merely academic questions irrelevant to
practical living. They lie at the heart of life itself; and naturally in
the course of the centuries notable answers to them have been given,
many of which are held still today around the world.
If we are to try to understand something of the seriously held
views of our fellow human beings, we must try to understand their
views and the reasons for which they hold them. But just here we
must sound a warning that will be necessary to repeat again in the
course of these books: those who start out seriously enquiring for
truth will find that at however lowly a level they start, they will not be
logically able to resist asking what the Ultimate Truth about every-
thing is!
In the spirit of truthfulness and honesty, then, let us say directly
that we, the authors of this book, are Christians. We do not pretend
to be indifferent guides; we commend to you wholeheartedly the an-
swers we have discovered and will tell you why we think the claims
of the Christian gospel are valid, and the help it offers real. This does
not, however, preclude the possibility of our approaching other views
in a spirit of honesty and fairness. We hope that those who do not
share our views will approach them in the same spirit. We can ask
nothing more as we set out together on this quest—in search of real-
ity and significance.
OUR AIM
Our small contribution to this quest is set out in the 6 volumes of this
series. In this, the second book in the series, we propose to select four
broadly representative answers to the big questions about the reality
in which we find ourselves. They are representative in the sense that
39
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
40
SERIES INTRODUCTION
These then are the questions; and as we survey the various answers
that are given, we shall naturally be looking to see on what authority
they are based. The answers will be given by:
(a) Indian pantheistic monism
(b) Greek philosophy and mysticism
(c) Naturalism and atheistic materialism
(d) Christian theism
And now let’s begin.
41
CHAPTER 1
45
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
which may well have intermingled with the later Aryan systems.2 In
addition it must be realised that Hinduism is an umbrella term cov-
ering not only a non-unified religion but also a whole way of life, a
richly variegated national culture built up of many elements.
Its sacred books fall into two groups:
1. The Vedas and the Upanishads. These are referred to as
Shruti (‘what is heard’) and are said to contain truths di-
vinely revealed to the early sages and later written down
between 1500 and 300 bc.
2. A collection of texts, said to be based upon revealed truth,
but of human composition. They are referred to as Smriti,
meaning ‘remembered’ or ‘handed’ down, i.e. they are re-
garded as tradition rather than revelation.
According to Kim Knott ‘Most Hindus accept the status and
authority of the Veda’, though he adds: ‘but very few have read it’.3
V. P. (Hemant) Kanitkar (a Hindu priest) and W. Owen Cole in their
book4 state that ‘When questioned about the beliefs which an ortho-
dox Hindu should hold, the reply tends to include:
• belief in one ultimate reality;
• belief in the authority of the Vedas (which includes the
Upanishads);
• belief in the principles of karma and samsara, and the even-
tual attainment of moksha; to these might often be added
the performance of dharma, right conduct, and the obser-
vance of caste duties.’ 5
In the course of the centuries, however, in addition to the cultic
side of Hindu religion, a more philosophical approach was devel-
oped; and the result has been the formation of six orthodox schools
of philosophy based on the Vedas.6 The six philosophical systems are:
6 Kanitkar and Cole (Hinduism, 184–5) state that all these systems can be traced back to
times bc. The unorthodox schools are the Carvakas, Buddhism and Jainism; they reject the
authority of the Vedas.
46
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
47
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
that the human soul, or self, and the Ultimate Reality, Brahman, are
one and the same thing—not two entities, but one.10
Here is a short glossary 11 giving the meaning of other Indian
technical terms that we shall encounter:
1. BRAHMAN [Brahman, from bṛh ‘grow, expand’: that
which expands, bursts into growth]. The Supreme Godhead,
beyond all distinctions or forms; Ultimate Reality.
2. BRAHMA [Brahmā]. The Creator; in the Upanishads,
a secondary deity of the Vedic pantheon. Not to be con-
fused with Brahman.
3. ATMAN [ātman, ‘self’]. Self; the innermost soul in every
creature, which is divine.
4. SAMSARA [saṃsāra] ‘That which is constantly chang-
ing’; the phenomenal world; the cycle of birth, death, and
rebirth.
5. MOKSHA [mok ṣa]. Liberation (from samsara, the cycle
of birth, death and rebirth).
6. KARMA [karma, ‘something done’]. Action, work, behav-
iour; also the consequences of action, spiritually and men-
tally, as well as physically.
48
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
human form, and in human form, as in Rama and Krishna. All three
gods of the Triad are frequently spoken of as performing more or less
the same functions.
This idea that the Supreme Godhead is not the Creator, but that
the Creator is some lesser god, is not exclusive to Hinduism. It occurs
also in Greek thought. To see its significance, we should perhaps con-
trast it with the very different Hebrew, Christian
and Islamic doctrine of creation in which the one
and only God is himself the Creator and there This idea that the
are no other gods: cf. ‘I am the Lord, and there is Supreme Godhead
no other, besides me there is no God . . . I made is not the Creator,
the earth and created man on it; it was my hands but that the Creator is
that stretched out the heavens . . . For thus says some lesser god, is not
the Lord, who created the heavens . . . “I am the exclusive to Hinduism.
Lord, and there is no other”’ (Isa 45:5, 12, 18).
49
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
An explanation
In saying that the Self, the Atman, in each individual person is Brah-
man, Shankara is not claiming that this Self in the individual person
is the sum total of Brahman. On the other hand, since Brahman is be-
lieved to be non-complex, and indivisible, one cannot speak of a part
of Brahman being present in one individual. Rather one must say that
the Self of the individual is like a drop of water in the Atlantic Ocean,
of the same essence as the ocean, and only logically, but not actually,
distinct from the undivided waters of the ocean itself.
One of the Upanishads contains a number of parables told by a
father to his son, Svetaketu, in order to teach him that Atman, the
Self, is Brahman. In one of them the father says to his son:
‘Bring me a fruit from this banyan tree.’
‘Here it is, father.’
‘Break it.’
‘It is broken, Sir.’
‘What do you see in it?’
‘Very small seeds, Sir.’
‘Break one of them, my son.’
‘It is broken, Sir.’
‘What do you see in it?’
‘Nothing at all, Sir.’
12 See Shvetashvatara Upanishad, 5.11–12, Easawaran (tr.), Upanishads, 131–2.
50
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
Then his father spoke to him: ‘My son, from the very essence in the
seed which you cannot see comes in truth this vast banyan tree.
‘Believe me, my son, an invisible and subtle essence is the Spirit
of the whole universe. That is Reality. That is Atman. thou art
that.’ 13
Shankara himself says:
In the same way as those parts of ethereal space which are lim-
ited by jars and water pots are not really different from the uni-
versal ethereal space . . . so this manifold world with its objects
of enjoyment, enjoyers and so on has no existence apart from
Brahman.14
What he means by the phrase ‘has no existence apart from Brah-
man’ he further illustrates by an analogy. Take a number of objects
made of clay, a pot, say, or a jar or a dish. We differentiate them and
use different words to denote these things that to us at first sight ap-
pear to be different. But in reality, he claims, they are not different:
they are all made of exactly the same substance, namely clay. In this
way the objects in this world, and the persons, are not different from
Brahman:
The individual soul and the highest Self differ in name only, it
being a settled matter that perfect knowledge has for its object
the absolute oneness of the two.15
Brahman, then, is Atman, the Self of every human being; and
therefore every human being is God.
The question naturally arises, how can anyone know for certain that
all this is in fact so? The answer given is ‘by meditation’.16 But it is a
very special kind of meditation. We are told that it is not intellectual
study, nor intuition, nor imagination. It is not concentration on a
51
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
topic, not even on the mind itself, for in the process the ‘I’ deliber-
ately withdraws awareness from the mind that it regards as a mere,
constantly changing, mechanism. It is said to be a concentration on
consciousness, as Easwaran explains:
When awareness has been consolidated even beyond the mind,
little remains except the awareness of the ‘I’. Concentration
is so profound that the mind-process has almost come to a
standstill. . . . gradually you become aware of the presence of
something vast, intimately your own but not at all the finite,
limited self you had been calling ‘I’. All that divides us from
the sea of infinite consciousness at this point is a thin envelope
of personal identity. That envelope cannot be removed by any
amount of will; the ‘I’ cannot erase itself. Yet, abruptly, it does
vanish. . . . the barrier of individuality disappears, dissolving
in a sea of pure, undifferentiated awareness. . . . What remains
when every trace of individuality is removed? We call it pure
being . . . The sages called it Brahman . . . the irreducible ground
of existence, the essence of every thing—of the earth and sun
and all creatures, of gods and human beings, of every power of
life. . . . this unitary awareness is also the ground of one’s own
being, the core of personality. This divine ground the Upani-
shads call simply Atman, ‘the Self’—spelled with a capital to
distinguish it from the individual personality. . . . In all per-
sons, all creatures, the Self is the innermost essence. And it is
identical with Brahman: our real Self is not different from the
ultimate Reality called God. This tremendous equation—‘the
Self is Brahman’—is the central discovery of the Upanishads.
Its most famous formulation is . . . : Tat tvam asi ‘You are That’.
‘That’ is . . . a Reality that cannot be described; and ‘you’, of
course, is not the petty, finite personality, but that pure con-
sciousness . . . the Self. . . . there is no time, no space, no causal-
ity. These are forms imposed by the mind, and the mind is still.
Nor is there awareness of any object; even the thought of ‘I’ has
dissolved. Yet awareness remains.17
52
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
18 Upanishads, 31.
53
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
If the real Self in everyone and everything is one and the same Brahman,
how do we explain the myriad, individual, distinct, particular phe-
nomena in the universe? (And how do normal people have such strong
conviction that we are different from one another and from God?)
Shankara’s answer to the question is that all this apparent indi-
viduality is an illusion (maya). What he means by illusion is some-
thing like the impressions created by a skilful magician. Or take
54
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
55
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
An appeal to science
Now modern followers of Shankara’s system claim that it agrees with
contemporary physics. Speaking of the ancient Hindu sages Eas-
waran says:
Penetrating below the senses, they found not a world of solid,
separate objects but a ceaseless process of change—matter com-
ing together, dissolving, and coming together again in a different
form. Below this flux of things with ‘name and form’, however,
they found something changeless: an infinite, indivisible reality
in which the transient data of the world cohere. They called this
reality Brahman: the Godhead, the divine ground of existence.
This analysis of the phenomenal world tallies well enough
with contemporary physics. A physicist would remind us that
the things we see ‘out there’ are not ultimately separate from
each other and from us; we perceive them as separate because
56
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
57
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
58
INDIAN PANTHEISTIC MONISM
59
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
60
CHAPTER 2
GREEK PHILOSOPHY
AND MYSTICISM
AN INTELLECTUAL SEARCH FOR ULTIMATE REALITY
Perhaps the most significant thing about it is, not so much the re-
sults it achieved, but the new approach it brought to the question
of man’s relation to Ultimate Reality. Abandoning mythological and
1 The ancient Greek word mystēs (from which ‘mysticism’ derives) was originally a religious
term. It denoted someone who had been initiated into one of the so-called ‘mystery’ religions.
Such initiates, after preparatory ceremonies, were said to witness manifestations of a god or
goddess or to learn secret, and supposedly powerful, names, spells and charms. Nowadays
the term is often applied to what is more accurately called ‘spiritism’ or ‘occultism’, in which
people claim that they can be put in touch with the spirits of the dead (see the biblical prohi-
bition of this practice in Isa 8:9–20). In this section, however, we shall be concerned not with
mysticism in either of these senses, but with the particular form of philosophical mysticism
advocated by the Neoplatonist Plotinus.
63
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
PRECAUTIONARY OBSERVATIONS
We have said that the early Greek philosophers abandoned the tradi-
tional mythological interpretations of the universe, and relied simply
upon observation and reason. But that does not mean that they all
64
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
forthwith abandoned faith in, or worship of, the gods. It simply means
that when it came to their ‘scientific’ investigations, some of them—
particularly the Ionian philosophers—felt the gods to be irrelevant.
For example, Xenophanes (b. 570 bc) lampooned the anthropo-
morphic gods of mythology:
The Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black,
the Thracians that theirs have light blue eyes and red hair.2
But if cattle and horses or lions had hands, or were able to draw
with their hands and do the works that men can do, horses
would draw the forms of the gods like horses, and cattle like
cattle, and they would make their bodies such as they each had
themselves.3
This lampoon is well known, and is often quoted nowadays to
support the contention that the very idea of God is a human inven-
tion. But that is unfair to Xenophanes who appears to have been al-
most a monotheist when he spoke of:
One god, greatest among gods and men, in no way similar to
mortals either in body or in thought.4
Always he remains in the same place, moving not at all; nor is
it fitting for him to go to different places at different times, but
without toil he shakes [or, ‘controls’] all things by the thought
of his mind.5
Nor did the majority of his fellow philosophers forthwith aban-
don all talk of God. Thales, the first of the Ionian philosophers, is
reported to have remarked: ‘everything is full of gods’. But here we
must be careful to understand precisely what he means, since the
word ‘god’ did not necessarily mean to the Greeks what it means to
us today. For instance, someone brought up in the Judaeo-Christian
tradition may well say ‘God is love’. He expects you to know what he
means by ‘God’, namely, the One True God, Creator of the universe;
and then he mentions one of God’s attributes, namely, love. But an
65
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
ancient Greek, using his Greek word theos (god) is more likely to say
‘Love is theos’. What he means by that is that love is a wonderful,
mysterious, ‘divine’, power—but only one such power among many.
Nor did all these philosophers abandon every preconception that
stemmed from the earlier mythologies. Far from it. There are three
basic concepts from Greek mythology that recur time and time again
in many of even the more advanced philosophers. They are: (1) that
matter existed before the gods; (2) that some one or other of the gods
imposed order and form on the basic stuff of the universe, and in that
sense, but only in that sense, can be talked of as a creator; and (3) that
even this god, like all the others, arose out of original matter, and is
part of the stuff, or one of the forces, of the universe.
The mythologist Hesiod (c.700 bc), for example, in his poem The-
ogony (‘genealogy of the gods’) speaks of:
The august race of first-born gods, whom Earth
Bore to broad Heaven.6
And again:
Olympian Muses, tell
From the beginning which first came to be? 7
And the answer is given:
Chaos was first of all, but next appeared
Broad-bosomed Earth.8
And misty Tartarus, in a recess
Of broad-pathed earth, and Love [Eros], most beautiful
Of all the deathless gods.9
Commenting on Hesiod’s poem Professor Werner Jaeger wrote:
If we compare this Greek hypostasis of the world-creative Eros
with that of the Logos in the Hebrew account of creation, we
may observe a deep-lying difference in the outlook of the two
peoples. The Logos is a substantialization of an intellectual prop-
66
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
67
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
The interesting thing is that right from the very start the Greek phi-
losophers appear to have assumed that the seemingly endless mul-
tiplicity of things must have stemmed from one primal substance,
unknowingly anticipating an aspect of modern scientific methodol-
ogy. They set themselves to discover this primal stuff—the archē as
they called it.
Naturally enough, the early thinkers did not all agree on what
the primal stuff was.
Thales (c. mid sixth century bc). For him the primal stuff was
water. Some scholars have suggested that this idea was prompted by
his observation that water could exist in three different forms: gas
(steam), liquid (water) and solid (ice). Others, with perhaps more
plausibility, suggest that he noticed that throughout nature moisture
is always connected with the processes by which seed germinates and
brings forth life. Thales held that the earth floated on water. He is fa-
mous for having been able to predict the eclipse which took place in
585 bc. (It would be worthwhile looking up this story in Herodotus,
The Histories, i.74.)
Anaximander (611–547/6 bc). For him the primal stuff was what
he called in Greek apeiron, that is, ‘indeterminate’, ‘without bounda-
ries’. Some scholars think he meant that this primal stuff had no ex-
ternal boundaries, and was therefore infinite in extent. Others hold
that he meant that the primal stuff contained in itself all those things
and states which now seem to be different, or even opposites—hot
and cold, moist and dry, etc.—but with no internal boundaries be-
68
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
Somewhat different was Heraclitus (about 40 years old c.500 bc), who
has become famous for his saying that ‘everything is in flux’. He de-
serves to be known rather for another, more important insight. The
unity he looked for behind the multiplicity of things
was not so much that of the primal stuff of the uni-
verse, as that of the one basic principle—the logos Heraclitus has
as he called it in Greek—which held it all together become famous
and made it work. He decided that the world in its for his saying that
working is held together by the interactive tension ‘everything is in
between opposites; and that these opposites con- flux’. He deserves
stantly turning into one another, like day and night, to be known rather
cannot exist separately. for another, more
To illustrate his theory he used the analogy of a important insight.
bow and its bowstring. The wood of the bow, drawn
into an arc by the bowstring, is all the while pulling
against the string in an attempt to return to its own original straight-
ness. The bowstring, stretched and held taut by the bow, is all the
while pulling in the opposite direction against the wood of the bow.
It is this interactive tension between the bow and the string, however,
11 Hippolytus Ref. i.6.3 in Kirk and Raven, Presocratic Philosophers, 134.
69
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
that keeps the two opposite forces working together and thus enables
the instrument to function. It is also the stretching of the bow by
the archer, and then its sudden relaxation that sends the arrow on
its way.
Heraclitus suggested that there were many such opposites-in-
tension at work in the universe, with one alternately giving way to
the other, and then the other to the one, so restoring the balance and
coherence of the forces of nature, and thus maintaining the general
harmony of the universe. He cited hot and cold, moist and dry, day
and night, up and down, etc. It was much like the principle of yin and
yang, the two opposing forces that by their complementary interac-
tion form and maintain the workings of the universe, according to
Eastern thought. Still today scientists talk of matter and anti-matter,
centripetal and centrifugal forces, gravity and anti-gravity.
Empedocles (c. middle of the fifth century bc) made the inno-
vative suggestion that there never was an original unity. There were
four basic substances in the universe—Fire, Air, Earth and Water.
Between them they filled the whole of space. But they were perpetu-
ally shifting, now coming together in different proportions, now sep-
arating. Empedocles, however, realised that he had to explain what
caused this motion. Motion is something that has to be accounted
for: it cannot be taken for granted. He came to the conclusion that
the power of love which draws human beings together, and the power
of hate that drives them apart, are in fact two forces that operate
throughout the universe, and affect matter as well as animate beings.
Anaxagoras (c.500/499–428/7 bc) went further. He proposed
that the source of movement was the single intellectual force of Mind.
When we read this we could easily forget that we are reading
the thoughts of a philosopher who lived two and a half millennia
ago. We could rather imagine that we are reading the recent sugges-
tions of some of the world’s leading modern scientists. The fantas-
tic fine-tuning of the universe and the irreducible complexity of the
cell make it virtually impossible for them to go on believing that the
whole universe, including human intellect and reason, have arisen by
mindless processes from mindless matter.
Of course, we have to ask how Anaxagoras conceived of this
‘Mind’. Was it part of the matter of the universe? Or was it a truly
incorporeal entity? G. S. Kirk and J. E. Raven comment:
70
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
71
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
72
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
73
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
them, the atoms were of different shapes, there would result multitu-
dinous conglomerations that for a while would stick together. Thus
evolved worlds and beings of all kinds, both human and animal.
These conglomerations would hold together by their interlocking
shapes, helped by the continual external bombardment by the other
atoms that surrounded them.
But eventually the atoms in the conglomerations would come
unstuck and would disperse. Then whatever these conglomerates had
been, whether universes, or individual human beings, or anything
else, they would cease to exist; and their component atoms, being
themselves indestructible, would go off and
become part of other conglomerates.
To have conceived of They were dualists, then, to this extent at
even their version of the least that they believed in both space and at-
atomic theory in those oms. Modern atomic theory, as we all know,
early centuries was, is very different from theirs. But to have con-
it must be said, brilliant, ceived of even their version of the atomic the-
all the more so because ory in those early centuries was, it must be said,
it was arrived at, not brilliant, all the more so because it was arrived
empirically through the at, not empirically through the senses—in
senses—in their day their day even their kind of atoms could not be
even their kind of atoms seen or individually touched—but by reason.
could not be seen or Yet in another sense they were monists,
individually touched— for their theory was unrelievedly materialistic:
but by reason. matter was everything. For them there was no
Mind behind the world’s, or man’s, existence,
not even with the limited function that Anax-
agoras gave to Mind of getting the original cosmic motion going.
There was, therefore, no purpose behind the human race’s existence.
All happened by a mixture of necessity and chance. The mindless
laws of physics (necessity) would remorselessly draw the atoms into a
vortex. Which atoms then collided with which might well be due to
chance. But the shape and size of the atoms would necessarily dictate
the formation of the conglomerations. (Similar arguments are still
used in connection with evolutionary theory.)
The human soul, moreover, was made of atoms, finer than other
atoms, but still nothing but matter, like all other atoms. At death
the atoms dispersed: nothing of the man or his personality survived.
74
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
75
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Socrates (470–399 BC )
16 Phaedo 97c–99d.
76
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
his friends would gladly have supplied the money to bribe his way
out of prison. But he refused their offer, and that for two reasons.
First, he had taught others that as citizens of a state, if they could
not get the laws changed by democratic means, they ought to submit
to the laws of the state, and not act as anarchists. He would not now
disobey those laws himself, simply for his own advantage. Secondly,
he believed that god had appointed him to act as his fellow-citizens’
moral mentor, and he would not desert his god-given charge just to
save his life. Truth and justice, he held, were more important than
physical life.
If, then, someone asked ‘Why is Socrates sitting in prison, and not
trying to escape execution?’ it would be silly, Socrates maintained,
to answer in terms of what Socrates was made of: arms, legs, spine,
joints and muscles, and to point out that all those things were at this
moment bent in the right position for sitting. It was his mind—his
profoundly intellectual and moral mind—that controlled his body
and directed him to stay in prison. And it was Socrates’ belief that
mind in man, which is meant to control his body, must be akin to the
Mind that controls the universe.
77
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
the universe, then man’s function would be to fulfil the purpose for
which the Mind created him.
The Old Testament would here agree with Socrates. It says for in-
stance, that man was made in the image of God to act as God’s stew-
ard and manager of earth’s ecosystem (Gen 1).
This is a function and responsibility that peo-
The Old Testament ple of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries
would here agree with have woken up to, more perhaps than previous
Socrates. It says for generations; and they have become aware that
instance, that man was the proper discharge of this function raises pro-
made in the image of found moral questions. Is it morally right, for
God to act as God’s the sake of maximising profits, to destroy the
steward and manager fish stocks in the sea by overfishing? Is it just
of earth’s ecosystem. to pollute the rivers and oceans with poisonous
industrial discharges? Is it morally justifiable to
hunt rhinoceros almost to extinction in order
to get their horns for superstitious customers in wealthy countries?
Is it fair for one industrial nation to pollute the atmosphere, increase
global warming, and destroy the forest in neighbouring countries by
acid rain, or radiation fallout?
The second key word in Socrates’ thought was ‘virtue’ (Gk. aretē).
As Socrates used it, it did not denote moral virtue so much as the
quality of being good at something. So the aretē of a farmer was to
produce good crops. The aretē of a shoemaker was to be good at mak-
ing shoes. And to be good at that a shoemaker would have to have
precise knowledge about feet, their shape and action, and about the
component parts of a shoe, and how to fit a shoe comfortably to a
foot, so that the foot could function properly.
The human race’s aretē, then, was to be good at the proper devel-
opment of that part of him that distinguishes man from animal, that
is, his soul; and for that purpose he would need to have precise and
accurate knowledge about such things as justice, and courage, and
self-control, and piety, etc.
78
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
or that act was courageous, or this law was more just than that one.
He was looking for definitions. (See, as a good example of this, his
questioning of Euthyphro in Plato’s dialogue of that name.)
This, in itself was a great contribution to clear thinking, to get
people to distinguish between properties of a thing, and definitions
of that thing. If, for instance, someone is asked to say what ice cream
is, and replies that ice cream is something which little boys like, what
he says is certainly true in itself; but it is not a definition of ice cream.
It is simply one of the properties that ice cream happens to have, an
‘accidental’ property, as we say. There are many other things that lit-
tle boys like, and the property of being liked by little boys, doesn’t
tell us what ice cream is in itself, nor distinguish it from other things
liked by small boys.
But in insisting on the search for definitions, Socrates was not
teaching logic for the sake of abstract reasoning. In his society, what
was held by some people to be just, was regarded by others as totally
unjust; and the conventional exercise of justice was often distorted.
It was Socrates’ contention that one cannot rightly decide whether a
particular law, or a particular business deal, is
just or not, if one does not know what justice is.
Socrates himself seems not to have discov- Socrates exposed
ered the definitions he was seeking for, though the fact that many of
in the process of searching for them in his con- his city’s conventional
versations with his fellow citizens he exposed ideas on such things
the fact that many of his city’s conventional as justice, were not
ideas on such things as justice were not ration- rationally thought
ally thought through, but seriously defective. through, but seriously
Calling attention to that was what in the end defective.
caused his death at the hands of the State.
79
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Plato (C.428–347 BC )
Plato was not only a philosopher and a fervent moralist but a literary
artist with a poet’s imaginative powers. His influence on subsequent
thought has been massive. We cannot here even begin to comment on
the vast range of his philosophical system. Our particular interest lies
in his answer to our double question: What is the nature of Ultimate
Reality and how are we related to it? To understand Plato’s answer we
80
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
must recall the teachings of earlier philosophers and mark how Plato
developed and modified them.
Heraclitus had taught that everything in the universe is continu-
ally changing and in a constant state of flux. If, then, one regards
reality as that which really exists, and then one has to admit that that
which really exists is constantly changing, it would follow that one
could not have complete and permanent knowledge of reality, but
only tentative impressions and opinions of it.
Parmenides had taught the opposite. Change, becoming, i.e. com-
ing into existence, perishing, i.e. passing out of existence, and move-
ment of any kind, were illusions, not real, mere appearances that
deceive our senses. Only intellect and reason could tell us the truth.
Reality, that is what really exists, is one solid undifferentiated whole,
eternally existing, unchanging, in which there is
no motion, no ‘becoming’, but only ‘Being’.
Plato’s reaction to these two sets of doctrines Particular instances
was to develop Socrates’ insistence on the differ- of, say, beauty can
ence between particular instances of a quality, like vary in duration and
beauty or justice, and the definition of that qual- extent; by contrast
ity. Particular instances of, say, beauty can vary in the definition of
duration and extent; by contrast the definition of beauty will be
beauty will be always the same. always the same.
In our changing world, such as Heraclitus saw
it, a particular example of, say, beauty can be mixed
in with other qualities. Beauty can be seen in a woman who is tall,
blonde, young, with long hair, or in a woman who is short, brunette,
middle-aged, and close-cropped. By contrast, the definition of beauty
must describe beauty itself apart from any other qualities.
In our changing and imperfect world various objects show vary-
ing degrees of beauty. But beauty itself, as truly defined, must admit
of no degrees.
Again in our changing world beauty can gradually increase and
then subsequently decay and perish. A plain child may develop into
a beautiful adult, and then in old age become ugly. Beauty itself, as
truly defined, must be unchanging and eternal.
Now there is no evidence to suggest that Socrates ever gave
thought to the question what kind of entities beauty itself, justice it-
self, courage itself, piety itself might be. He seemed to have looked on
81
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
them simply as definitions. But Plato came to think that they were
substantial entities—he called them ‘Forms’ or ‘Ideas’ 21 and he made
the following distinctions:
1. The Forms, Beauty itself, Justice itself, etc., exist, not in
our changing world but in an eternal, unchanging world
such as Parmenides imagined our world to be; and they are
themselves eternal and unchanging. They are ‘really real’.22
Particular things or acts are beautiful or just, as long as,
and to the extent that, they ‘share in’ the Form of Beauty or
the Form of Justice. Being part of this changing world, they
have some kind of reality but they are not ‘really real’, like
the Forms are.
2. Since the Forms and the world they exist in are eternal and
unchanging, we can arrive at true knowledge of them by
means of reason, after suitable education to awaken mem-
ory of the Forms that Plato believed the soul had seen be-
fore birth. But of particular things in this changing world,
we cannot have true knowledge, but only more or less tenta-
tive opinion.
21 Hence the philosophical term ‘idealism’ as distinct from ‘realism’. Plato’s ‘Forms’ raise simi-
lar questions to those raised by the problem of ‘universals’ in modern philosophy. Wittgenstein
denied their existence; D. H. Armstrong argues for universals that play a role in scientific laws.
22 Some mathematicians, like Penrose of Oxford, still think that the great truths of mathemat-
ics exist independently of us. We discover them but do not invent them.
82
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
The human race’s activities in art, design, engineering and law are
secondary phenomena, not necessarily inherent in nature, and often
contrary to it. The gods are merely products of the human mind.
Plato countered those assertions by calling attention to move-
ment in the world and in the universe. Like Empedocles and Anax-
agoras, he felt that motion has to be accounted for;
it cannot just be taken for granted. Some things
communicate to other things the motion that they The sophists held
first receive from some other source. They, there- that the universe
fore, cannot be the original source of motion. That itself and all its most
original source must be something that can move important contents
other things but did not itself receive its motion are the product
from any other source. It has the source of motion of nature, nature
in itself. being understood
The only thing, Plato argued, that has the as an inanimate
source of motion in itself is what the Greeks called mindless force.
soul, or life-principle, psychē. Therefore, he went
on to argue, the human soul must come before the
body, and its powers of mind, morality and intelligent design before
the body’s merely material powers of strength and size. From this he
concluded that while there are evil powers at work in the world, the
Prime Mover and Subsequent Controller of the universe must like-
wise be an Intelligent, Moral World Soul infinitely superior to the
human soul. For how could the Prime Mover and Controller of the
universe be less intelligent than man?
The question naturally arises: how did Plato conceive of this World
Soul? To answer that, we must return to his theory of the Forms.
83
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
84
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
and reality; yet it is not itself that reality, but is beyond it, and
superior to it in dignity and power.28
Finally, though the Good is the cause of knowledge and truth
and is itself known, yet it is something other than, and even more
splendid than, knowledge and truth.29
What, then, does Plato say that the Form of the Good is? He says
it is beyond Being; so obviously he is not thinking, like the early Ion-
ian philosophers, that it is some primal stuff of which the universe is
made. But by ‘beyond Being’, he may also mean that while one may
rightly ask what is the good of, say, justice or beauty, one cannot, with
any sense, ask what is the good of the Good. While the Good is the
reason why all else exists, the Good itself does not need any reason
for its existence. Uncaused itself, it is, as Aristotle will say, the Final
Cause of everything else. It is the Ultimate Reality.
Now the thought process by which Plato reached these conclu-
sions may seem to us moderns somewhat tortuous. But the question
he raises is still for us of the highest practical importance. If there
is some supreme good that we are meant to serve in life, that su-
preme good must have been the cause of our existence in the first
place. What then is the Good? All the major philosophical schools in
Greece—Platonists, Aristotelians, Stoics, Epicureans—all asked this
question, and gave their various answers. We should be wise to ask
the same questions ourselves.
What, then, was Plato’s answer?
85
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Aristotle (384–322 BC )
86
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
87
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
a potential oak tree. What is more, it already has within it the ‘form’
of an oak tree that will control its development so that it eventually
develops into an oak tree, and not into, say, a silver birch or a palm
tree. And the moving cause is the life that is in it, moving it along
towards the fully-grown oak tree that it unconsciously aspires to be.
Aristotle noticed that in living things the form is contributed
to the seed by a fully-grown and mature specimen of the species.
It requires an oak tree to produce an acorn and to contribute to the
acorn the ‘form’ that will eventually de-
velop the acorn into an oak tree. The
One cannot help observing chicken has to supply the egg with its in-
how close Aristotle came to herent chicken form within it; adult hu-
the modern theory according man beings have to produce the human
to which the information embryo with its inherent human form.
necessary for developing a The human embryo is therefore already
human being from embryo, a potential human being, since it already
through birth, to adulthood contains the ‘form’ of a human being;
and beyond, is carried by the and this ‘form’ will develop the embryo
chemicals of the genes; and eventually into an actual, mature hu-
while the original chemicals man being. What is more the ‘form’ will
perish, the information remains be passed on and persist through many
constant and is passed on to subsequent generations. One cannot help
subsequent generations. observing how close Aristotle came to
the modern theory according to which
the information necessary for developing
a human being from embryo, through birth, to adulthood and be-
yond, is carried by the chemicals of the genes; and while the original
chemicals perish, the information remains constant and is passed on
to subsequent generations.
88
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
of any sort. But he did; and it will be interesting to see why, and what
kind of a Being he imagined God to be.
89
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
what kind of thinking that was. The thinking of, say, a builder is not
an end in itself: its goal is the building of houses. The thinking of a
politician is not an end in itself. It does not manufacture anything;
but it has as its goal the ordering and governing of society. But genu-
ine theoretical thinking is an end in itself. It is not aimed at produc-
ing, or managing, anything. It is engaged in thinking for its own
sake. It is the highest kind of happiness (see the final chapters of his
Nicomachean Ethics). It was the kind of thinking that Aristotle him-
self enjoyed most.
Aristotle concluded therefore that the divine Mind, the Un-
moved Mover, is eternally engaged in the highest kind of thinking.
But thinking about what?
He (or it) could not be engaged in creating things, for that in-
volved a lower kind of thinking, and meant beginning with mere po-
tential and proceeding to actuality. Nor could he be concerned with,
or care about, things in this world, not even about human beings,
because they were all in the process of moving from potential to ac-
tuality, through birth, maturity, and then to old age and death. The
Unmoved Mover, Aristotle concluded, was pure thought, thinking
about itself, thinking about thinking; ‘for’, said Aristotle, ‘the activ-
ity of mind is life’.
If then, the divine Unmoved Mover is not interested in the uni-
verse of men and things, how does he move anything? Aristotle an-
swers that the sheer activity of his pure thought exerts a powerful
attractive power that instigates and maintains motion in the rest of
the universe. It is, as some have said, like a beautiful woman whose
beauty attracts many admirers to aspire after her, while she herself is
not interested in any of them.
90
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
91
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
NEOPLATONIC MYSTICISM
We now leave Socrates, Plato and Aristotle, and travel through the
centuries to Plotinus (ad 204/5–270), the founder of so-called Neo-
platonism. On the way we can afford, for our present purposes, to
bypass the Stoics and the Epicureans. Both of these systems of phi-
losophy were forms of monistic materialism. True, the Stoics believed
that there was Reason behind the universe; but that Reason was part
of the stuff of the universe (though a very refined form of stuff like
fire), and it was immanent in everything. Stoics were panentheists.
Epicureans, for their part, adopted the atomism of Leucippus and
Democritus (see above); they were virtual atheists.
We pass on, then, to Plotinus. He was the last of the great Greek
philosophers, and in him we meet something that we, in this study
of Greek philosophy, have not so far encountered, namely a vigorous
intellectualism, equal or even excelling that of the previous Greek
philosophers, yet coupled with a kind of religious mysticism.35 His
writings are known as The Enneads.36
Plotinus on reality
92
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
93
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
experience ‘The One’ is good for us; we are not thereby saying any-
thing about ‘The One’ itself.
But in spite of that Plotinus identifies ‘the One’ with the Platonic
Form of the Good (see above on Plato), which provokes from Profes-
sor Anthony Kenny the comment: ‘In a way which remains mysteri-
ous, The One is identical with the Platonic Idea of the Good. As The
One, it is the basis of all reality; as the Good, it is the standard of all
value; but it is itself beyond being and beyond goodness.’ 37
Here is a sample of Plotinus’ own exposition of the nature of
‘The One’:
How then do we ourselves speak about it? We do indeed say
something about it, but we certainly do not speak it, and we
have neither knowledge nor thought of it. . . . But we have it in
such a way that we speak about it, but we do not speak it. For we
say what it is not, but we do not say what it is; so that we speak
about it from what comes after it.38
Christians will feel a certain sympathy for Plotinus in his diffi-
culty. He is coming to the question of Ultimate Reality, that is, God,
by means of pure, unaided reason. He can therefore deduce certain
things about the One ‘from what comes after it’, that is, from observ-
ing the effects of God’s power seen in creation. The New Testament
says the same thing: ‘For his invisible attributes, namely, his eternal
power and divine nature, have been clearly perceived, ever since the
creation of the world, in the things that have been made’ (Rom 1:20).
But when it comes to saying what God himself is like, all Plotinus can
do, on the basis of his unaided reason without the light of revelation,
is to resort to what has come to be called ‘negative theology’, that is,
to say not what God is, but what he is not: he is not this, he is not that.
In this Plotinus is in the same position as exponents of Shanka-
ra’s non-dualist Hindu philosophy who when asked to give a precise
definition of Brahman reply ‘Neti, neti’, i.e. (He is) not this, not that.
It is not, then, in any disdainful spirit, but simply as stating the
sheer fact of the matter, that the Christian Apostle Paul remarks:
‘the world did not know God through wisdom [i.e. philosophy]’
(1 Cor 1:21). The living God is not the end product of a chain of syl-
37 A Brief History of Western Philosophy, 97.
38 Enneads, v.3.14.1–8.
94
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
39 Miracles, 144–5.
95
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
40 Enneads, v.1.6.
41 Enneads, v.1.6 (MacKenna).
42 Plotinus imagined that the sun is not in any way diminished by its vast output of energy.
96
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
cally what He was before He brought it into being. So too, had the
secondary never existed, He would have been unconcerned.43
Or again:
It is not that the Supreme reaches out to us seeking our com-
munion: we reach towards the Supreme.44
Once more this contrasts vividly with the God revealed in Christ,
who became man that he might ‘seek and save the lost’ (Luke 19:10),
and of whom it is said ‘This is love: not that we loved God, but that he
loved us and sent his Son as an atoning sacrifice for our sins’ (1 John
4:10). R. T. Wallis’s comment on Plotinus’ exposition of the motives
of the One is apposite: ‘not even here is the One said to love anything
other than itself’.45
Plotinus’ mysticism
97
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
akin in substance to the One, and since his intellect comes via Mind
from the One itself, his intellect, too, is akin to the One. Therefore, as
Plotinus points out elsewhere, to turn to the One is actually to turn
inwards and upwards to yourself. This is what we found Hindu phi-
losophy saying: a man’s own true Self is Brahman.
To look to God, then, according to this theory, is to look, not out-
side of oneself but to something within oneself. This stands in vivid
contrast to the Bible, which exhorts its followers: ‘Seek the things
that are above, where Christ is, seated at the right hand of God. Set
your minds on things that are above, not on things that are on earth’
(Col 3:1–2), or again ‘Looking to Jesus’ (Heb 12:2).
Anyone, not already convinced of Plotinus’ philosophy, might
very well wonder how one could be sure that what one eventually
saw, by this method, would be anything more than, say, an electrical
discharge in the depths of one’s brain.
But to continue with the quotation from Plotinus:
we are near now, the next is That and it is close at hand, radiant
above the Intellectual.
Here, we put aside all learning . . . the quester holds knowledge
still of the ground he rests on, but, suddenly, swept beyond it all
by the very crest of the wave of Intellect surging beneath, he is
lifted and sees, never knowing how; the vision floods the eyes
with light, but it is not a light showing some other object, the
light is itself the vision. No longer is there something seen and
light to show it, no longer Intellect and object of Intellection;
this is the very radiance that brought both Intellect and Intel-
lectual object into being. . . . With This he [the viewer] himself
becomes identical.47
We notice three elements in this experience:
1. To achieve it Plotinus had to put aside, or leave behind, all his
learning.
2. He saw nothing but light. There was no voice, no message from
the One, no communication of itself, no hint that the One was even
aware of Plotinus.
98
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
99
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
not have cared if Plotinus had never existed; could not think of any
object, not even of itself; and would never have taken any notice of
Plotinus even were he merged with the One.
Plotinus’ ‘God’ had never hitherto spoken to Plotinus and never
would to all eternity. An abstract idea, of course, cannot speak. Only
the living God, creator of the human heart as well as of their intel-
lect, could do that. Perhaps, the Spanish philosopher, Don Miguel de
Unamuno, was not too severe when, having spoken of the God of the
Old Testament, he remarked:
Subsequently reason—that is, philosophy—took possession of
this God . . . and tended to define him and convert him into
an idea. For to define a thing is to idealize it, a process which
necessitates the abstraction from it of its incommensurable or
irrational element, its vital essence. Thus the God of feeling, the
divinity felt as a unique person and consciousness external to
us, although at the same time enveloping and sustaining us,
was converted into the idea of God.
The logical, rational God . . . the Supreme Being of theological
philosophy . . . is nothing but an idea of God, a dead thing.50
100
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
ical evil like the material chaos that in Greek thought existed eter-
nally before God imposed order on it.
But even at this level Plotinus had a problem, because according to
his scheme matter emanated from the One; not directly, but through
the agency of Mind and then of Soul, Matter was created by the One.
How then could the Absolute Good create the Absolute Evil?
Matter is also the cause of moral evil. This comes about because
when the human soul gets too involved with matter it gets enslaved
and corrupted by the evil of matter, and forgets the One.
The New Testament likewise warns us that if we allow the attrac-
tive things of life to make our hearts forget God, then this is sinful.
But that is not because these things are material and matter itself is
evil. According to the New Testament matter is not evil in itself. But
in Plotinus matter is evil in itself, and yet, as we have seen, emanates
from the One.
Moreover, the Bible teaches that both matter and humans, like
the rest of the universe, were created out of nothing, not out of God
himself. They are not emanations out of God, like sunbeams are em-
anations from the sun and therefore of the same substance as the
sun. But in Plotinus, the soul of man is part of the World Soul (as in
Hinduism) and an emanation out of God himself. How could such a
soul emanating from God be overcome by evil matter which likewise
has ultimately emanated from God?
Plotinus never really comes to grips with this problem. It is a
problem that haunts all versions of pantheism.
101
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
53 Enneads, ii.9.9.
54 Enneads, iii.2.13 (MacKenna).
102
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
Islamic philosophers
The early Islamic philosophers were indebted to Plato and above all to
Aristotle. But they also knew and studied a work entitled Theology of
Aristotle. It was not in fact by Aristotle: it was Porphyry’s paraphrase
of Plotinus’ Enneads. From this work some of the early Islamic phi-
losophers took over markedly Neoplatonic ideas: (1) Plotinus’ typical
approach to the knowledge of God by so-called ‘negative theology’ (as
distinct from faith in divine revelation); and (2) his theory of emana-
tion rather than creation out of nothing (which latter was, and still is,
the orthodox Islamic doctrine. We may cite just two examples.
Al-Kindī (died c.866–73) is generally regarded as the first Is-
lamic philosopher; he commissioned a translation of the Greek phi-
losophers into Arabic. Of him Felix Klein Franke says:
According to al-Kindī, the philosopher is unable to make any
positive statement concerning God. All he is able to state is in
the negative: that ‘He is no element, no genus, no species, no
individual person, no part (of something), no attribute, no con-
tingent accident.’ Thus al-Kindī’s philosophy leads to a negative
theology, i.e. where God is described only in negative terms. In
this he followed Plotinus.55
Similarly, Al-Fārābī (c.870–950), embraced the emanational cos-
mology of Neoplatonism, even though, in his case, he was aware that the
so-called Theology of Aristotle, was not Aristotle’s work but stemmed
originally from Plotinus. Following Th.-A. Druart,56 Deborah L. Black
writes:
al-Fārābī personally upheld the emanational cosmology cen-
tral to Neoplatonism, even while he recognised that it was not
103
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
104
GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MYSTICISM
Christianity was already two hundred years old by the time of Ploti-
nus. His successors, Porphyry and Proclus, were energetically hostile
to Christianity. Of the Neoplatonist schools, the Athenian school was
the most avowedly pagan. In the late fifth, or early sixth, century a
member of that school (apparently) wrote a work
entitled Mystical Theology in which he tried to
combine his pagan doctrines and negative theol- The Cloud of Unknow-
ogy with the positive declaration of God by Christ. ing continues to foster
He published this work pseudonymously, making in various countries
out that it came from the pen of the Apostle Paul’s the practice of Plotinus’
Athenian convert, Dionysius the Areopagite (see pagan mysticism as
Acts 17). Strangely enough, it was later received though it were Christian.
into some sections of the Christian church as
though it were truly Christian. Subsequently it
was translated into Latin by the Irish scholar, John Scotus Eriugena
(c.810–c.877). In the late fourteenth century it was translated into a
modified English version by the anonymous author of The Cloud of
Unknowing; and this work in turn59 continues to foster in various
countries the practice of Plotinus’ pagan mysticism as though it were
Christian.60
105
CHAPTER 3
1 Cosmos, 20.
2 ‘The Nature of Naturalism’, 358.
3 In saying this we are not referring to the New Age Movement with its Earth goddess and
its supposed planetary influences, and occult practices; for these are but a recrudescence of
ancient pagan superstitions, and in some cases, demonism. We are talking about scientific and
philosophical worldviews.
109
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Those who hold this view do so for two main reasons among others.
First, they feel that there is no valid evidence for the existence of a
supernatural or transcendent realm, and that in the absence of such
evidence they are entitled to hold, as a fallback position, the view that
Nature is all there is.4
The second major reason that atheists give for not believing in
the existence of God is the prevalence of evil and suffering in the
world. If there is an all-loving, all-powerful, all-wise creator, they say,
why do so many people suffer such bad things? Why did God allow
evil in the first place? And why does he not put an end to it?
This, we admit, is a genuine problem, which weighs heavily with
many people, and not just with atheists. It is too large to be dealt with
here; but we shall devote the last book in this series to it.5
4 See, by contrast, the cumulative evidence that there is a Creator God behind the universe,
as discussed in the books God’s Undertaker and Gunning for God, both by John Lennox.
5 Book 6: Suffering Life’s Pain.
6 For a critique of the view that quantum cosmology has proved that in theory at least, sci-
ence will one day be able to explain how the universe came to exist out of nothing without any
supernatural Creator, see John Lennox’s Gunning for God, Ch. 4 – ‘Designer Universe?’.
110
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
111
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
8 See Russell and Adebiyi, Classical Thermodynamics, 5: ‘As stated earlier, the only basis of
thermodynamics is the observation of the physical world and the experimental measurements
related to the observation. No other theoretical proof exists for thermodynamics. Thus, if a
case were observed in nature that was contrary to what is implied by an existing law of thermo-
dynamics, the law would be declared invalid.’
112
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
This time the difficulty is information; and once more we shall let
Professor Davies tell us about it:
there is not the slightest shred of scientific evidence that life is
anything other than a stupendously improbable accident. It’s of-
ten said that life is written into the laws of physics; well, it’s not—
any more than houses or television sets are. It is consistent with
those laws, but they alone will not explain how it came to exist.
For a hundred years the debate has been dominated by chem-
ists, who think it’s like baking a cake: if you know the recipe,
you can just mix the ingredients, simmer for a million years,
9 From an interview by David Wilkinson published in Third Way, ‘Found in space?’, 18–19.
113
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
add a pinch of salt, and life emerges. I don’t think that is ever
going to be the explanation, because life is not about stuff, about
magic matter; it’s about a very special type of information pro-
cessing system. And the whole subjects of information theory
and complexity theory are very much in their infancy.10
Now this is refreshingly different from fashionable materialis-
tic naturalism. The rationality behind the basic laws of physics, the
genes as carriers of the coded information necessary for the produc-
tion of life, and the astonishing complexity of the biochemical ma-
chinery within each cell which is self-evidently designed to achieve
a foreseen end—all this constitutes severe difficulties for supporters
of that form of naturalism which declares mindless matter to be the
Ultimate Reality.
But it also constitutes grave difficulty for those who wish on the
one hand to recognise the evident intelligence behind the universe
and yet on the other hand to retain naturalism’s basic contention that
neither the universe nor life within the universe was created by the
direct action of a personal creator.
Presently we shall investigate examples of this particular diffi-
culty, one from the ancient world and two others from the modern.
But for the moment let us pause and ask ourselves some questions.
114
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
115
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
God and matter are always conjoined. God, who is Logos, is in every-
thing in the world, both in matter and in man. God is spoken of as
breath (Gk. pneuma), but this breath likewise is always embodied in
matter. In that sense the whole universe can be called God, or Cos-
mic Nature, since in Stoic thought, Nature and God refer to the same
thing. Hence Professor A. A. Long can write:
They were convinced that the universe is amenable to rational
explanation, and is itself a rationally organised structure. The
faculty in man which enables him to think, to plan and to
speak—which the Stoics called logos—is literally embodied in
the universe at large. The individual human being at the es-
sence of his nature shares a property which belongs to Nature in
the cosmic sense. And because cosmic Nature embraces all that
there is, the human individual is a part of the world in a pre-
cise and integral sense. Cosmic events and human actions are
therefore not happenings of two quite different orders: in the
last analysis they are both alike consequences of one thing—
logos. To put it another way, cosmic Nature or God (the terms
refer to the same thing in Stoicism) and man are related to each
other at the heart of their being as rational agents.12
In the end, then, Stoicism reduced everything to Nature. Nature,
or Logos, or God—it did not matter which term you used—was in
everything, in matter and in man. Man’s ideal, therefore, was to live
according to Nature (Gk. physis), that is, according to the Cosmic
Reason. But whether an individual cooperated with this Cosmic Rea-
son or not, Cosmic Reason was ultimately in control. Therefore the
evil behaviour of wicked men had to be regarded as part of the all-
controlling rational Logos. It meant also, for instance, that if you saw
a man abusing a child, or a dictator gassing six million Jews, it was a
reasonable thing to do to attempt to stop the outrage. But if you failed
to stop it, it would be unreasonable to grieve over it. You had to ac-
cept that this outrage, too, was ultimately the work of Cosmic Logos,
that is, God.
The Stoics, then, as we have said, reduced everything to Nature—
rational Nature, not materialistic Nature, but in the end simply all-
116
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
13 Cosmos, 305.
14 Cosmos, 309.
15 Cosmos, 20.
16 Augustine of Hippo, Confessions, i.1.
17 Cosmos, 20.
117
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
118
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
119
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
I’m assuming that God did not intervene to make life. I don’t
want that.26
To that extent, life and mind are written into the underlying
laws of physics: the tendency for them to emerge is there at the
beginning.27
It’s very hard to see how God could be any sort of a being who
could bring about a revelation without coming back to moving
atoms around. I mean if someone’s going to implant a thought
in your mind that would not be there otherwise, they have got
to move atoms around.29
There is something very odd about this. We grant, of course, that
if we implant a thought in a friend’s mind—as we very frequently
do—it has the effect that in so doing we ‘move atoms around in our
friend’s head’. But if we are allowed to do this, and can do it without
breaking the laws of physics, why can’t God be allowed to do it? Even
Davies’s ‘God’ was responsible for creating atoms in the first place
and for their ceaseless movements throughout the universe. Why
must God be forbidden to implant thoughts in people’s mind because
it would involve moving a few atoms around?
count of creation. The Bible says that God created the world by his Word, thus supplying the
information necessary for the formation of life, which information, we now know, is carried
by the genes.
29 Wilkinson, ‘Found in space?’, 20.
120
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
121
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
122
NATURALISM AND ATHEISM
123
CHAPTER 4
CHRISTIAN THEISM
THE SEARCH FOR ULTIMATE REALITY IN GOD’S SELF-REVELATION
At its best, abstract human reasoning can only produce an idea of God.
Now, in any subject an idea of a thing is always substantially less than
the thing itself. An idea of a thing is only a mental concept; the thing
itself is the reality. So an idea of God, arrived at by abstract philosophi-
cal reasoning, is a very different thing from the living God himself in
active self-revelation through the word and person of the incarnate
Son of God and through the illumination of the Spirit of God.
127
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
which we know by experience, and God and his world, which is alto-
gether different? The language Christianity uses to talk of God, they
say, is all metaphorical and analogical. But those metaphors and anal-
ogies are not valid. They are based on experience of this world; and we
have no rational ground for supposing that they can tell us anything
about the realities of God and that other world—even if such exist.
The gulf between the two worlds is conceptually and linguistically
uncrossable. So runs the criticism.
Christian theism admits the gulf but asserts that, by the incar-
nation, God has himself crossed the gulf, and entered our time and
space. Not only has he spoken to us in human language, but he has
himself become man without ceasing to be
God. In his self-communication he of course
Unless God had first uses metaphors and analogies drawn from our
revealed himself to us, world in order to facilitate our understanding.
we would have nothing But those metaphors and analogies are valid,
to use our intellects on. since he came from the other side of the gulf
It is with the knowledge and knows that world, and knows what meta-
of God as it is in phors can reliably be used to describe it (John
science: God had first 3:12–13; 6:62; 8:14, 23, 26; 16:28).
to create the universe Now when we point to the inadequacy of
before the human unaided human reason to decide what God is
intellect could study it. like, we are not implying that reason has no
place in our knowing and understanding of
God. The Bible itself commands us to love the
Lord our God with all our mind as well as with our heart (see Mark
12:30). ‘In your thinking be mature’, says 1 Corinthians 14:20. But
unless God had first revealed himself to us, we would have nothing
to use our intellects on. It is with the knowledge of God as it is in sci-
ence: God had first to create the universe before the human intellect
could study it.
Here to start with, then, is a key passage in the New Testament
that declares not only that God does communicate himself to hu-
manity, but that it is part of his very nature to do so. Let’s first read it
through and then study its main features:
In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God,
and the Word was God. He was in the beginning with God. All
128
CHRISTIAN THEISM
things were made through him, and without him was not any
thing made that was made. In him was life, and the life was the
light of men. The light shines in the darkness, and the darkness
has not overcome it.
There was a man sent from God, whose name was John. He
came as a witness, to bear witness about the light, that all might
believe through him. He was not the light, but came to bear
witness about the light.
The true light, which enlightens everyone, was coming
into the world. He was in the world, and the world was made
through him, yet the world did not know him. He came to his
own, and his own people did not receive him. But to all who
did receive him, who believed in his name, he gave the right to
become children of God, who were born, not of blood nor of the
will of the flesh nor of the will of man, but of God.
And the Word became flesh and dwelt among us, and we
have seen his glory, glory as of the only Son from the Father,
full of grace and truth. (John bore witness about him, and cried
out, ‘This was he of whom I said, “He who comes after me ranks
before me, because he was before me.”’) And from his fullness
we have all received, grace upon grace. For the law was given
through Moses; grace and truth came through Jesus Christ. No
one has ever seen God; the only God, who is at the Father’s side,
he has made him known. . . . The next day he saw Jesus coming
towards him, and said, ‘Behold, the Lamb of God, who takes
away the sin of the world!’ (John 1:1–18; 29)
This passage makes a number of assertions. Let’s first list them
and then comment on the detail of the passage.
1. God exists. He is eternal, uncreated and distinct from the
contingent, created universe.
2. God speaks. It is part of his essential nature to speak and to
communicate himself.
3. The creation of the universe was by the Word of God, and is
an expression of his mind.
4. Humanity’s original rejection of God’s word resulted in a
universal darkness. Yet God continued to speak, and his
light to shine.
129
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
130
CHRISTIAN THEISM
Matter is not eternal. It had a beginning. Unlike God, there was a time
when it did not exist.
1 Cf. ‘Are not his sisters here with us?’ (Mark 6:3); ‘Day after day I was with you’ (Mark 14:49);
‘at home with the Lord’ (2 Cor 5:8); ‘I would have been glad to keep him with me’ (Phlm 13);
‘the eternal life, which was with the Father’ (1 John 1:2).
131
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
132
CHRISTIAN THEISM
133
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
134
CHRISTIAN THEISM
135
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
136
CHRISTIAN THEISM
fact that the Word, who was eternally with God and was God, has
not only talked to us about God, but has himself become man, and
thus fully expressed God in human form and human terms, without
ceasing to be God. ‘Whoever has seen me’, he declared, ‘has seen the
Father’ (John 14:9).
Moreover, since the one who became man was eternally with
God and was God, yet spoke also of the Father, and the Spirit of God,
his incarnation has given us genuine insight into the nature of God.
Christian theism does not believe in three Gods. It proclaims as vig-
orously as Judaism and Islam do, that there is only one God (1 Tim
2:5). But that one God is not simplex.
Relying simply on their human concept of ultimate perfection,
Greek philosophers could not conceive of Ultimate Reality being any
thing other than an absolute, simplex, Oneness; so much so that both
Aristotle and Plotinus argued that the One could not think of any-
one or anything outside of Itself—for that would imply a duality: the
Thinker and the thing thought. Mere reason pushed Plotinus even
further: he argued that the One could not even think about Itself—for
that same reason: it would imply the same duality: the Thinker and
the Thing thought (see Ch. 2). Reason thus concluded that Ultimate
Reality was something that had less powers than human beings have!
The Godhead revealed to us through the incarnation of the
Word, then, is a triunity of Father, Son and Holy Spirit. Not three
Gods, but three centres of relationship within the One God. It has
been customary, in Christian theology, to speak of these three rela-
tionships as three persons. But in this context ‘three persons’ does
not mean ‘three separate people’. Yet each centre of relationship is
distinct, and thus the Godhead is a divine fellowship.
God is love, says the Bible. He not only loves his creatures, but
long before any creatures existed, the Godhead was a fellowship of
love. Moreover, when it comes to God’s attitude and activities to-
wards us his creatures, the Bible makes it clear that each person in
the Godhead is involved in what is nonetheless the distinctive work
of the other two.3
3 Christian theologians refer to this phenomenon as the ‘Coinherence of the Trinity’, the
technical term for which is the Greek word perichōrēsis. Examples are: The miracles that the
Son did were done by him (John 5:35); yet he could also say that it was the Father abiding in
him that did the miracles (John 14:10). What the Son speaks to his churches (Rev 2:1) is what
the Spirit speaks to the churches (Rev 2:11).
137
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Some people think that all talk about the Trinity is idealistic
nonsense. But it is interesting to notice that in a completely different
sphere scientists who investigate the quantum behaviour of particles
report that at this level particles can no longer be understood as iso-
lated, unrelated, individual things. They appear to sustain ongoing
relationships with one another in an interconnected continuous field,
witness quantum entanglement. We are not saying, of course, that
the persons of the Trinity are like particles in a quantum field. The
Holy Trinity is unique, and cannot be compared with anything else,
except in the vaguest of senses. But what we are
saying is that if matter at the quantum level be-
We cannot, and shall haves in this mysterious and counter-intuitive
never, know everything way, it is not to be wondered at if the facts that
about God. In his God has revealed to us about the interrelation-
infinity, he will always ships of the persons of the Trinity very soon
go beyond our full exceed our ability to visualise them or to under-
understanding. But we stand them fully.
can know a great deal We cannot, and shall never, know every-
about him. thing about God. In his infinity, he will always
go beyond our full understanding. But we can
know a great deal about him. Moreover, what
he has made known to us about the persons of the Trinity, is of fun-
damental practical importance for us in the process of getting to
know God personally. We may map out that process in three parts:
1. God the Father. He is the one who is to be known, and it is the
Son of God who has made him known (John 1:18; 17:26).
2. God the Son. As the Word he is the message, the full declara-
tion of God, told out not only in words, but by his virgin birth, life,
works, death, burial and resurrection.
3. God the Holy Spirit. He is not the message. He has never been
incarnated in human form, nor was he ever crucified for us. He is not
the subject matter of the gospel. On the other hand we are not left to
our own unaided powers to perceive the truth of the message, to un-
derstand it, to receive it and to be transformed by it. According to the
New Testament it is the ministry of God, the Holy Spirit to convict
the world of sin (John 16:8–9); to convince them of Christ’s resurrec-
tion (Acts 2); to glorify Christ so that people’s hearts and faith are
138
CHRISTIAN THEISM
drawn out to him (John 16:14–15); to effect within them that spiritual
renewal that Christ spoke of as being born from above (John 3); to
pour out God’s love in the hearts of those who receive Christ (Rom
5:5); to empower them to develop, bit by bit, a truly Christian style
of living (Rom 8:1–17); to make it possible for them to explore even
more fully the deep things of God (1 Cor 2:1–12); to be with them and
in them (John 14:17); to guide their prayers and deepest longings and
aspirations (Rom 8:26–27); and thus to be for them their foretaste
and guarantee of their eventual eternal inheritance (Eph 1:13–14).
Knowledge of God, then, according to Christian theism, cer-
tainly involves the reception and understanding of much informa-
tion. But it is not just a matter of assimilating facts. The ever-present
danger with theology is that it can tend to objectivise the knowledge
of God so that it becomes nothing more than a system of abstract
truths. It is the work of the living, personal, Holy Spirit of God to
maintain the process of getting to know God as an ever-deepening
personal relationship between the creature and the Creator.
139
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
140
CHRISTIAN THEISM
art that’, asserts this very thing, that a human’s inner self is God,
part of God’s very substance (see Ch. 1).
If that were true, it would have some strange implications. It
would mean that part of us, at least, existed eternally even before we
were born, and never had a beginning. It would also mean that our
ignorance and evil behaviour would be attributable to God.
Sri Ramakrishna, a pantheist, spelled out the implications of em-
anational pantheism when he remarked:
God alone is, and it is He who has become this universe. . . . ‘As
the snake, I bite, as the healer I cure.’ God is the ignorant man
and God is the enlightened man. God as the ignorant man re-
mains deluded. Again, He as the guru gives enlightenment to
God in the ignorant.4
On this basis one could presumably say that God in Adolf Hitler
was a diabolical fiend, and God in the Jews whom Hitler gassed was
gassed by God.
The Bible denies this outright. God had occasion to remark at
one point in history: ‘The Egyptians are man, and not God’ (Isa 31:3);
and that is true of all of us. God alone has immortality, says the Bible
(1 Tim 6:16). The idea that matter is an emanation from God’s own
substance and is indestructible, coupled with the twin idea that ‘soul’
has existed eternally without beginning, is the reason why in ema-
national thought history just goes round in endless circles—birth,
life, death, reincarnation, life, death, rebirth—and never reaches any
goal. By contrast the Bible teaches that the progress of history is lin-
ear; one day it will reach its destined goal.
According to the Bible, then, the universe is not an emanation
from God, and neither are we. God created the universe out of noth-
ing. As C. S. Lewis put it: ‘He is so brim-full of existence that He can
give existence away, can cause things to be, and to be really other
than Himself, can make it untrue to say that He is everything.’ 5
141
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
For by him all things were created, in heaven and on earth, vis-
ible and invisible . . . all things were created through him and
for him. And he is before all things, and in him all things hold
together. (Col 1:16–17)
The universe had its beginning, then, in the Son of God, as, say, a
hospital can be said to have had its beginning in the mind of the per-
son, or persons, who first thought it up and in the mind of the archi-
tect. But the hospital was not built out of the ‘stuff’ of the architect,
nor the universe out of the substance of God.
The Son of God was also the agent in the creation of the universe.
What is more, he is the goal for which it was created; and he holds the
universe together until it reaches its designed goal.
142
CHRISTIAN THEISM
EPILOGUE
Now that we have reached the end of this discussion of physical and
metaphysical concerns, a question naturally arises: Which, if any, of
these systems of thought that we have covered seems likely to be any-
where near the truth?
That in turn raises a second question: How could we know which,
if any, was true?
And that raises a third question: How can we know the truth about
anything?
143
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
144
APPENDIX:
THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
Science rightly has the power to fire the imagination. Who could read
the story of how Francis Crick and James D. Watson unravelled the
double helix structure of DNA without entering at least a little into
the almost unbearable joy that they experienced at this discovery?
Who could watch an operation to repair someone’s eye with a del-
icately controlled laser beam without a sense of wonder at human
creativity and invention? Who could see pictures from space show-
ing astronauts floating weightless in the cabin of the International
Space Station or watch them repair the Hubble telescope against the
background of the almost tangible blackness of space without a feel-
ing akin to awe? Science has a right to our respect and to our active
encouragement. Getting young people into science and giving them
the training and facilities to develop their intellectual potential is a
clear priority for any nation. It would be an incalculable loss if the
scientific instinct were in any way stifled by philosophical, economic
or political considerations.
But since one of the most powerful and influential voices to
which we want to listen is the voice of science, it will be very impor-
tant for us, whether we are scientists or not, to have some idea of what
science is and what the scientific method is before we try to evaluate
what science says to us on any particular issue. Our aim, therefore,
first of all is to remind ourselves of some of the basic principles of
scientific thinking, some of which we may already know. Following
this, we shall think about the nature of scientific explanation and
we shall examine some of the assumptions that underlie scientific
activity—basic beliefs without which science cannot be done.
Then what is science? It tends to be one of those things that we
all know what it means until we come to try to define it. And then
we find that precise definition eludes us. The difficulty arises because
we use the word in different ways. First of all, science is used as short-
hand for:
147
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
SCIENTIFIC METHOD
148
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
149
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
150
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
Induction
1 The terms hypothesis and theory are in fact almost indistinguishable, the only difference in
normal usage being that a hypothesis is sometimes regarded as more tentative than a theory.
2 Note for mathematicians: the process of induction described above is not the same as the
principle of mathematical induction by which (typically) the truth of a statement P(n) is estab-
lished for all positive integers n from two propositions:
(1) P(1) is true;
(2) for any positive integer k, we can prove that the truth of P(k+1) follows from the truth
of P(k).
The key difference is that (2) describes an infinite set of hypotheses, one for each positive
integer, whereas in philosophical induction we are generalising from a finite set of hypotheses.
151
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
152
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
particular places, is claimed to hold for all acids at all times in all
places. The problem with induction is, how can we be sure that such a
general statement is valid, when, in the very nature of things, we can
only make a finite number of observations of litmus paper turning
red on the application of acid? The story of the black swan makes us
aware of the difficulty.
Well, we cannot be absolutely sure, it is true. But every time we
do the experiment and find it works, our confidence in the litmus
test is increased to the extent that if we dipped some paper in a liquid
and found it did not go red we would be likely to conclude, not that
the litmus test did not work, but that either the paper we had was
not litmus paper or the liquid was not acid! Of course it is true that
underlying our confidence is the assumption that nature behaves in
a uniform way, that if I repeat an experiment tomorrow under the
same conditions as I did it today, I will get the same results.
Let’s take another example that Bertrand Russell used to illus-
trate the problem of induction in a more complex situation: Bertrand
Russell’s inductivist turkey. A turkey observes that on its first day at
the turkey farm it was fed at 9 a.m. For two months it collects obser-
vations and notes that even if it chooses days at random, it is fed at
9 a.m. It finally concludes by induction that it always will be fed at 9
a.m. It therefore gets an awful shock on Christmas Eve when, instead
of being fed, it is taken out and killed for Christmas dinner!
So how can we know for certain that we have made enough ob-
servations in an experiment? How many times do we have to check
that particular metals expand on heating to conclude that all metals
expand on heating? How do we avoid the inductivist turkey shock?
Of course we can see that the problem with the turkey is that it did
not have (indeed could not have) the wider experience of the tur-
key farmer who could replace the turkey’s incorrect inductivist con-
clusion with a more complicated correct one: namely the law that
each turkey will experience a sequence of days of feeding followed
by execution!
The point of what we are saying here is not to undermine science
by suggesting that induction is useless, nor that science in itself can-
not lead us to any firm conclusions. It simply teaches us to recognise
the limits of any one method and to found our conclusions, wherever
possible, on a combination of them.
153
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Once a law has been formulated by induction, we can test the valid-
ity of the law by using it to make predictions. For example, assuming
Mendel’s laws to be true, we can deduce from them a prediction as to
what the relative frequency of occurrence, say, of blue eyes in differ-
ent generations of a family, should be. When we find by direct obser-
vation that the occurrence of blue eyes is what we predicted it to be,
our observations are said to confirm the theory, al-
though this sort of confirmation can never amount
Deduction plays to total certainty. Thus deduction plays an impor-
an important role tant role in the confirmation of induction.
in the confirmation It may be that what we have said about induc-
of induction. tion has given the impression that scientific work
always starts by looking at data and reasoning to
some inductive hypothesis that accounts for those
data. However, in reality, scientific method tends to be somewhat
more complicated than this. Frequently, scientists start by deciding
what kind of data they are looking for. That is, they already have in
their mind some hypothesis or theory they want to test, and they
look for data that will confirm that theory. In this situation deduc-
tion will play a dominant role.
For example, as we mentioned above regarding observation and
experimentation, in the ancient world, Greek philosophers supposed
as a hypothesis that the planets must move in circular orbits around
the earth, since, for them, the circle was the perfect shape. They then
deduced what their hypothesis should lead them to observe in the
heavens. When their observations did not appear to confirm their
original hypothesis completely, they modified it. They did this by re-
placing the original hypothesis by one in which other circular mo-
tions are imposed on top of the original one (epicycles, they were
called). They then used this more complicated hypothesis from which
to deduce their predictions. This theory of epicycles dominated as-
tronomy for a long time, and was overturned and replaced by the
revolutionary suggestions of Copernicus and Kepler.
Kepler’s work in turn again illustrates the deductive method. Us-
ing the observations the astronomer Tycho Brahe had made avail-
able, Kepler tried to work out the shape that the orbit of Mars traced
154
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
against the background of ‘fixed’ stars. He did not get anywhere un-
til he hit on an idea that was prompted by geometrical work he had
done on the ellipse. That idea was to suppose as a hypothesis that the
orbit of Mars was an ellipse, then to use mathematical calculations to
deduce what should be observed on the basis of that hypothesis, and
finally to compare those predictions with the actual observations.
The validity of the elliptical orbit hypothesis would then be judged by
how closely the predictions fit the observations.
This method of inference is called the deductive or hypothetico-
deductive method of reasoning: deducing predictions from a hy-
pothesis, and then comparing them with actual observations.
Since deduction is such an important procedure it is worth con-
sidering it briefly. Deduction is a logical process by which an asser-
tion we want to prove (the conclusion) is logically deduced from
things we already accept (the premises). Here is an example of logical
deduction, usually called a syllogism:
P1: All dogs have four legs.
P2: Fido is a dog.
C: Fido has four legs.
155
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
But here we should notice that when it comes to interpreting the data
we have collected, different hypotheses can be constructed to cover
that data. We have two illustrations of this.
Illustration from astronomy. Under the role of deduction above
we discussed two hypotheses from ancient astronomy that were put
156
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
157
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
the straight line? That is, in the situation just described, there are
many different hypotheses that cover the same set of data. How do
you choose between them?
Application of Occam’s razor would lead to choosing the most el-
egant or economical solution—a straight line is simpler than a com-
plicated curve. We could also repeat the experiment with 100 points,
200 points, etc. The results would build up our confidence that the
straight line was the correct answer. When we build up evidence in
this way, we say that we have cumulative evidence for the validity of
our hypothesis.
So far we have been looking at various methods employed by sci-
entists and have seen that none of them yields 100% certainty, ex-
cept in deductive proofs in mathematics where the certainty is that
particular conclusions follow from particular axioms. However, we
would emphasise once more that this does not mean that the scien-
tific enterprise is about to collapse! Far from it. What we mean by
‘not giving 100% certainty’ can be interpreted as saying that there is
a small probability that a particular result or theory is false. But that
does not mean that we cannot have confidence in the theory.
Indeed there are some situations, as in the litmus-paper test for
acid where there has been 100% success in the past. Now whereas this
does not formally guarantee 100% success in the future, scientists
will say that it is a fact that litmus paper turns red on being dipped
in acid. By a ‘fact’, they mean, as palaeontologist Stephen Jay Gould
has delightfully put it, ‘confirmed to such a degree that it would be
perverse to withhold provisional assent to it’.3
On other occasions we are prepared to trust our lives to the find-
ings of science and technology even though we know we do not have
100% certainty. For example, before we travel by train, we know that
it is theoretically possible for something to go wrong, maybe for the
brakes or signalling to fail and cause the train to crash. But we also
know from the statistics of rail travel that the probability of such an
event is very small indeed (though it is not zero—trains have from
time to time crashed). Since the probability of a crash is so small, most
of us who travel by train do so without even thinking about the risk.
On the other hand we must not assume that we can accept all
158
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
Falsifiability
159
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
160
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
161
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
162
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
EXPLAINING EXPLANATIONS
Levels of explanation
Science explains. This, for many people encapsulates the power and
the fascination of science. Science enables us to understand what we
did not understand before and, by giving us understanding, it gives
us power over nature. But what do we mean by saying that ‘science
explains’?
In informal language we take an explanation of something to be
adequate when the person to whom the explanation is given under-
stands plainly what he or she did not understand before. However,
we must try to be more precise about what we mean by the process
of ‘explanation’, since it has different aspects that are often confused.
An illustration can help us. We have considered a similar idea in rela-
tion to roses. Let’s now take further examples.
Suppose Aunt Olga has baked a beautiful cake. She displays it
to a gathering of the world’s top scientists and we ask them for an
explanation of the cake. The nutrition scientists will tell us about the
number of calories in the cake and its nutritional effect; the biochem-
ists will inform us about the structure of the proteins, fats, etc. in the
cake and what it is that causes them to hold together; the chemists
will enumerate the elements involved and describe their bonding;
the physicists will be able to analyse the cake in terms of fundamen-
tal particles; and the mathematicians will offer us a set of beauti-
ful equations to describe the behaviour of those particles. Suppose,
163
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
164
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
165
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
5 Lennox’s response to Dawkins’s first thesis ‘Faith is blind; science is evidence-based’, ‘The
God Delusion Debate’, hosted by Fixed Point Foundation, University of Alabama at Bir-
mingham, filmed and broadcast live 3 October 2007, http://fixed-point.org/index.php/video/
35-full-length/164-the-dawkins-lennox-debate. Transcript provided courtesy of ProTorah,
http://www.protorah.com/god-delusion-debate-dawkins-lennox-transcript/.
166
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
Reductionism
167
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
168
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
169
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
11 Whether matter and energy do have this capacity is another matter that is discussed in the
books noted at the end of this appendix.
12 Dawkins, Growing Up in the Universe (study guide), 21.
170
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
171
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
have formed some idea or theory about the nature of what they are
about to study.
172
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
173
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
axioms. This is true, not only at the worldview level but also in all of
our individual disciplines. We retain those axioms that prove useful
in the sense that they lead to theories which show a better ‘fit’ with
nature and experience, and we abandon or modify those which do
not fit so well. One thing is absolutely clear: none of us can avoid
starting with assumptions.
174
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
We all take so much for granted the fact that we can use human rea-
son as a probe to investigate the universe that we can fail to see that
this is really something to be wondered at. For once we begin to think
about the intelligibility of the universe, our minds demand an expla-
nation. But where can we find one? Science cannot give it to us, for
the very simple reason that science has to assume the rational intel-
ligibility of the universe in order to get started. Einstein himself, in
the same article we quoted earlier, makes this very clear in saying that
the scientist’s belief in the rational intelligibility of the universe goes
beyond science and is in its very nature essentially religious:
Science can only be created by those who are thoroughly im-
bued with the aspiration toward truth and understanding. This
source of feeling, however, springs from the sphere of religion.
To this there also belongs the faith in the possibility that the
regulations valid for the world of existence are rational, that is,
comprehensible to reason. I cannot conceive of a genuine scien-
tist without that profound faith.18
Einstein saw no reason to be embarrassed by the fact that sci-
ence involves at its root belief in something that science itself cannot
justify.
Allied to belief in the rational intelligibility of the universe is
the belief that patterns and law-like behaviour are to be expected in
nature. The Greeks expressed this by using the word cosmos which
means ‘ordered’. It is this underlying expectation of order that lies be-
hind the confidence with which scientists use the inductive method.
Scientists speak of their belief in the uniformity of nature—the idea
that the order in nature and the laws that describe it are valid at all
times and in all parts of the universe.
Many theists from the Jewish, Islamic or Christian tradition
would want to modify this concept of the uniformity of nature by
adding their conviction that God the Creator has built regularities
175
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
FIGURE Ap.3. Milky Way Galaxy.
The Milky Way galaxy is visible from earth on clear nights
away from urban areas. Appearing as a cloud in the night
sky, our galaxy’s spiral bands of dust and glowing nebulae
consist of billions of stars as seen from the inside.
176
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
177
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
178
APPENDIX: THE SCIENTIFIC ENDEAVOUR
not contradict the laws of physics. Indeed it will make use of the laws
of physics, and nothing more than the laws of physics.’ 20 It is the
words ‘nothing more than’ that show that Dawkins is only prepared
to accept reductionist, materialistic explanations.
Further reading
Books by John Lennox:
God and Stephen Hawking: Whose Design Is It Anyway? (Lion, 2011)
God’s Undertaker: Has Science Buried God? (Lion, 2009)
Gunning for God: A Critique of the New Atheism (Lion, 2011)
Miracles: Is Belief in the Supernatural Irrational? VeriTalks Vol. 2. (The Veritas
Forum, 2013)
Seven Days That Divide the World (Zondervan, 2011)
179
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
BOOKS
A
Abbott, Edwin. Flatland: A Romance of Many Dimensions. London, 1884. Repr.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Ambrose, E. J. The Nature and Origin of the Biological World. New York: Halsted
Press, 1982.
Ammon, Otto. Die Gesellschaftsordnung und ihre natürlichen Grundlagen. Jena:
Gustav Fisher, 1895.
Anderson, J. N. D. (Norman). Christianity: The Witness of History. London: Tyndale
Press, 1969.
Anderson, J. N. D. (Norman). The Evidence for the Resurrection. 1950. Leicester:
InterVarsity Press, 1990.
Anderson, J. N. D. (Norman). Islam in the Modern World. Leicester: Apollos, 1990.
Andreyev, G. L. What Kind of Morality Does Religion Teach? Moscow: ‘Znaniye’,
1959.
Aristotle. Metaphysics. Tr. W. D. Ross, Aristotle’s Metaphysics: A Revised Text with
Introduction and Commentary. Vol. 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924.
Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Tr. W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1925.
Repr. Kitchener, Ont.: Batoche Books, 1999. Also tr. David Ross. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1980.
Arnold, Thomas. Christian Life, Its Hopes, Its Fears, and Its Close: Sermons
preached mostly in the chapel of Rugby School, 1841–1842. 1842. New edn,
London: Longmans, 1878.
Ashman, Keith M. and Philip S. Baringer, eds. After the Science Wars. London:
Routledge, 2001.
Atkins, Peter. Creation Revisited. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1994.
Augustine of Hippo. Confessions. ad 397–400. Tr. Henry Chadwick, The Confessions.
Oxford, 1991. Repr. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2008.
Avise, John C. The Genetic Gods, Evolution and Belief in Human Affairs. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998.
Ayer, A. J., ed. The Humanist Outlook. London: Pemberton, 1968.
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
B
Bacon, Francis. Advancement of Learning. 1605. Ed. G. W. Kitchin, 1915. Repr.
London: Dent, 1930. Online at http://archive.org/details/
advancementlearn00bacouoft (facsimile of 1915 edn).
Bādarāyana, Śankarācārya and George Thibaut. The Vedānta Sūtras of Bādarāyana.
Vol. 34 of Sacred books of the East. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1890.
Baier, Kurt. The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1958.
Behe, Michael J. Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution. 1988.
10th ann. edn with new Afterword, New York: Simon & Schuster, 2006.
Bentham, Jeremy. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. 1780,
1789. Dover Philosophical Classics. Repr. of Bentham’s 1823 rev. edn, Mineola,
N.Y.: Dover Publications, 2007.
Berdyaev, N. A. The Beginning and The End. Tr. R. M. French. London: Geoffrey
Bles, 1952.
Berlinski, David. The Deniable Darwin and Other Essays. Seattle, Wash.: Discovery
Institute, 2009.
Bickerton, Derek. Language and Species. 1990. Repr. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1992.
Biddiss, M. D. Father of Racist Ideology: The Social and Political Thought of Count
Gobineau. New York: Weybright & Talley, 1970.
Bouquet, A. C. Comparative Religion. Harmondsworth: Penguin (Pelican), 1962.
Breck, John. The Sacred Gift of Life: Orthodox Christianity and Bioethics.
Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1998.
Bronowski, Jacob. The Identity of Man. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967.
Brow, Robert. Religion, Origins and Ideas. London: Tyndale Press, 1966.
Bruce, F. F. 1 and 2 Corinthians. New Century Bible Commentary. London:
Oliphants, 1971.
Bruce, F. F. The New Testament Documents: Are They Reliable? 1943. 6th edn,
Nottingham: Inter-Varsity Press, 2000.
Butterfield, Herbert. Christianity and History. London: Bell, 1949. Repr. London:
Fontana, 1958.
C
Cairns-Smith, A. G. The Life Puzzle. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd, 1971.
Caputo, John D., ed. Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jacques
Derrida. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy No. 1. 1997. Repr. New York:
Fordham University Press, 2004.
Cary, M. and T. J. Haarhoff. Life and Thought in the Greek and Roman World.
5th edn, London: Methuen, 1951.
Chalmers, David J. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
182
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
D
Darwin, Charles. The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. 1871. 2nd
edn, New York: A. L. Burt, 1874. Ed. James Moore and Adrian Desmond,
Penguin Classics, London: Penguin Books, 2004.
183
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Darwin, Charles. On the Origin of Species. 1859. Repr. World’s Classics Edition,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008. Also cited is the 6th edn (1872)
reprinted by New York University Press, 1988. Citations to one or the other
edition are indicated as such.
Darwin, Francis. The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin. London: John Murray,
1887. doi: 10.5962/bhl.title.1416, accessed 29 June 2015.
Davies, Paul. The Cosmic Blueprint: New Discoveries in Nature’s Creative Ability
to Order the Universe. 1988. Repr. West Conshohocken, Pa.: Templeton
Foundation Press, 2004.
Davies, Paul. The Fifth Miracle: The Search for the Origin and Meaning of Life. 1999.
Repr. New York: Touchstone, 2000.
Davies, Paul. God and the New Physics. London: J. M. Dent, 1983. Repr. London:
Penguin Books, 1990.
Davies, Paul. The Mind of God: Science and the Search for Ultimate Meaning. 1992.
Repr. London: Simon & Schuster, 2005.
Davies, Paul and John Gribbin. The Matter Myth: Dramatic Discoveries that
Challenge Our Understanding of Physical Reality. London, 1991. Repr. London:
Simon & Schuster, 2007.
Davis, Percival and Dean H. Kenyon. Of Pandas and People: The Central Question
of Biological Origins. 1989. 2nd edn, Dallas, Tex.: Haughton Publishing, 1993.
Dawkins, Richard. The Blind Watchmaker. 1986. Rev. edn, 2006. Repr. London:
Penguin, 2013.
Dawkins, Richard. Climbing Mount Improbable. New York: Norton, 1996.
Dawkins, Richard. Growing Up in the Universe. The Royal Institution Christmas
Lectures for Children, 1991. Five one-hour episodes directed by Stuart
McDonald for the BBC. 2-Disc DVD set released 20 April 2007 by the Richard
Dawkins Foundation. Available on the Ri Channel, http://www.rigb.org/
christmas-lectures/watch/1991/growing-up-in-the-universe. Study Guide with
the same title. London: BBC Education, 1991.
Dawkins, Richard. River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life. 1995. Repr.
London: Phoenix, 2004.
Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. 1976. Repr. 30th ann. edn, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006.
Dawkins, Richard. Unweaving the Rainbow: Science, Delusion and the Appetite for
Wonder. 1998. Repr. London: Penguin Books, 2006.
Dawkins, Richard and John Lennox. ‘The God Delusion Debate’, hosted by
Fixed Point Foundation, University of Alabama at Birmingham, filmed
and broadcast live 3 October 2007, online at http://fixed-point.org/
video/richard-dawkins-vs-john-lennox-the-god-delusion-debate/.
Transcript provided courtesy of ProTorah.com, http://www.protorah.com/
god-delusion-debate-dawkins-lennox-transcript/.
Deacon, Terrence. The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the
Human Brain. London: Allen Lane, 1997.
Dembski, William A. Being as Communion: A Metaphysics of Information. Ashgate
Science and Religion. Farnham, Surrey: Ashgate, 2014.
184
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
E
Eastwood, C. Cyril. Life and Thought in the Ancient World. Derby: Peter Smith, 1964.
Easwaran, Eknath. The Bhagavad Gita. 1985. Berkeley, Calif.: Nilgiri Press, 2007.
Easwaran, Eknath. The Upanishads. 1987. Berkeley, Calif.: Nilgiri Press, 2007.
Eccles, John C. Evolution of the Brain, Creation of the Self. 1989. Repr. London:
Routledge, 2005.
Einstein, A. Letters to Solovine: 1906–1955. New York: Philosophical Library, 1987.
Einstein, A. Out of My Later Years: The Scientist, Philosopher, and Man Portrayed
Through His Own Words. 1956. Secaucus, N.J.: Carol Publishing, 1995.
Eldredge, Niles. Reinventing Darwin: The Great Debate at the High Table of
Evolutionary Theory. New York: Wiley, 1995.
Eldredge, Niles. Time Frames: The Evolution of Punctuated Equilibria. 1985. Corr.
edn, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1989.
Ellis, John M. Against Deconstruction. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press,
1989.
The Encyclopedia Britannica. 15th edn (Britannica 3), ed. Warren E. Preece and
Philip W. Goetz. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1974–2012.
185
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Engels, Friedrich. Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy.
German original first published in 1886, in Die Neue Zeit. Moscow: Progress
Publishers, 1946.
Erbrich, Paul. Zufall: Eine Naturwissenschaftlich-Philosophische Untersuchung.
Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1988.
Euripides. The Bacchae. Tr. James Morwood, Bacchae and Other Plays. Oxford
World’s Classics. 1999. Repr. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. Nuer Religion. 1956. 2nd edn, London: Oxford University
Press, 1971.
F
Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Essence of Christianity. 1841. Ed. and tr. George Eliot
(Mary Ann Evans). New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1957.
Feynman, Richard. Six Easy Pieces. 1963. Repr. London: Penguin Books, 1995.
Fischer, Ernst. Marx in His Own Words. Tr. Anna Bostock. London: Penguin
Books, 1973.
Fish, Stanley. Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive
Communities. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980.
Fish, Stanley. There’s No Such Thing as Free Speech, and It’s a Good Thing Too. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1994.
Flew, Antony with Roy Abraham Varghese. There Is a God: How the World’s Most
Notorious Atheist Changed His Mind. London: HarperCollins, 2007.
Fox, S. W., ed. The Origins of Prebiological Systems and of Their Molecular Matrices.
New York: Academic Press, 1965.
Frazer, J. G. The Golden Bough. 1890, 1900, 1906–15, 1937.
Fromm, Erich. You Shall be as Gods: A Radical Interpretation of the Old Testament
and its Tradition. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1966.
G
Gates, Bill. The Road Ahead. 1995. Rev. edn, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1996.
Geisler, Norman L., and William E. Nix, A General Introduction to the Bible
(Chicago: Moody Press, 1986), 475. Gerson, Lloyd P. Plotinus. London:
Routledge, 1994.
Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s
Development. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982.
Goldschmidt, Richard. The Material Basis of Evolution. The Silliman Memorial
Lectures Series. 1940. Repr. Yale University Press, 1982.
Gooding, David W. and John C. Lennox. The Human Quest for Significance:
Forming a Worldview [in Russian]. Minsk: Myrtlefield Trust, 1999.
Gould, Stephen Jay. The Lying Stones of Marrakech: Penultimate Reflections in
Natural History. 2000. Repr. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2011.
Gould, Stephen Jay. Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History.
1989. Repr. London: Vintage, 2000.
186
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
Grant, Michael. Jesus: An Historian’s Review of the Gospels. New York: Scribner, 1977.
Grene, Marjorie. A Portrait of Aristotle. London: Faber & Faber, 1963.
Groothuis, Douglas. Truth Decay: Defending Christianity against the Challenges
of Postmodernism. Leicester: Inter-Varsity Press, 2000.
Guthrie, W. K. C. The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle. 1950. Repr.
London: Methuen, 2013.
Guthrie, W. K. C. Plato: the man and his dialogues, earlier period. Vol. 4 of A
History of Greek Philosophy. 1875. Repr. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2000.
H
Haldane, J. B. S. Possible Worlds. 1927. London: Chatto & Windus, 1945.
Harrison, E. Masks of the Universe. 1985. 2nd edn, New York: Macmillan, 2003.
Citations are to the first Macmillan edition.
Harvey, William. On the Motion of the Heart and the Blood of Animals. 1628.
Online at https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/harvey/william/motion/complete
.html, accessed 4 Sept. 2018.
Hawking, Stephen. A Brief History of Time. 1988. Updated and expanded 10th ann.
edn, London: Bantam Press, 1998.
Hawking, Stephen and Leonard Mlodinow. The Grand Design. New York: Bantam
Books, 2010.
Hegel, G. W. F. Hegel’s Logic. Being Part One of the Encyclopaedia of the
Philosophical Sciences (1830). Tr. William Wallace, 1892. Repr. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1984–87.
Hegel, G. W. F. The Phenomenology of the Mind (Spirit). 1807. 2nd edn 1841. Tr.
J. B. Baillie, London, 1910. Repr. Dover Philosophical Classics, New York: Dover
Publications, 2003.
Hegel, G. W. F. The Philosophy of History. 1861. Tr. J. Sibree, 1857. Repr. New York:
Dover Publications, 1956. Repr. Kitchener, Ont.: Batoche Books, 2001. Online
at Internet Archive: https://archive.org/details/lecturesonphilos00hegerich/,
accessed 19 Oct. 2018.
Hegel, G. W. F. Wissenschaft der Logik [The Science of Logic]. Nurnberg, 1812–16.
Hemer, Colin. The Book of Acts in the Setting of Hellenistic History. Tübingen:
J. C. B. Mohr, Paul Siebeck, 1989.
Hengel, Martin. Judaism and Hellenism: Studies in their Encounter in Palestine
during the Early Hellenistic Period. Tr. John Bowden. London: SCM Press, 1974.
Repr. Eugene, Oreg.: Wipf & Stock, 2003.
Hengel, Martin. Studies in Early Christology. Tr. Rollin Kearns. Edinburgh: T&T
Clark, 1995.
Herodotus. The Histories. Tr. Robin Waterfield, 1998, Oxford World’s Classics.
Repr. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Herzen, Alexander Ivanovich. Byloe i dumy. London, 1853. Tr. C. Garnett, My
Past and Thoughts, The Memoirs of Alexander Herzen. Revised by H. Higgens,
introduced by I. Berlin, 1968. Repr. London: Chatto and Windus, 2008.
187
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Hesiod. Theogony. In Charles Abraham Elton, tr. The remains of Hesiod. London:
Lackington, Allen, 1812. Also in Dorothea Wender, tr. Hesiod and Theognis.
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973.
Hippolytus, Refutation of all Heresies. In Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven and M. Schofield.
The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts. 1957.
Rev. edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Holmes, Arthur F. Ethics. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1984; 2nd edn,
2007.
Honderich, Ted, ed. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Hooper, Judith. Of Moths and Men. New York: Norton, 2002.
Hooykaas, R. Religion and the Rise of Modern Science. 1972. Repr. Edinbugh:
Scottish Academic Press, 2000.
Hospers, John. An Introduction to Philosophical Analysis. 1953. 4th edn, Abingdon:
Routledge, 1997.
Houghton, John. The Search for God—Can Science Help? Oxford: Lion Publishing,
1995.
Hoyle, Fred. The Intelligent Universe. London: Joseph, 1983.
Hoyle, Fred and Chandra Wickramasinghe. Cosmic Life-Force, the Power of Life
Across the Universe. London: Dent, 1988.
Hoyle, Fred and Chandra Wickramasinghe. Evolution from Space: A Theory of
Cosmic Creationism. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1984.
Hume, David. David Hume: A Treatise of Human Nature. 1739–40. Ed. Lewis
Amherst Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888.
Repr. 1978. Repr. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. doi: 10.1093/
actrade/9780198245872.book.1, accessed 11 Sept. 2015; also online at
https://davidhume.org/texts/t/, accessed 4 Sept.2018.
Hume, David. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. 1779. Repr. ed. J. C. A.
Gaskin, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, and The Natural History of
Religion. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Online at https://davidhume.org/texts/d/, accessed 2 Aug. 2017. (Abbreviated as
DNR.)
Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. London: A. Millar,
1748. Repr. Dover Philosophical Classics, Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications,
2012. Online at http://www.davidhume.org/texts/e, accessed 2 Aug. 2017.
(Abbreviated as EHU.)
Hume, David. Treatise of Human Nature. 1739–40. Eds. David Norton and Mary
J. Norton, David Hume: A Treatise of Human Nature: A critical edition. Vol.
1 of The Clarendon Edition of The Works Of David Hume. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2007. Online at http://www.davidhume.org/texts/t/, accessed
2 Aug. 2017. (Abbreviated as THN.)
Hunt, R. N. Carew. The Theory and Practice of Communism. Baltimore: Penguin
Books, 1966.
Hurley, Thomas. Method and Results: Collected Essays. Vol. I. London: Macmillan,
1898.
188
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
I
Isherwood, Christopher, ed. Vedanta for Modern Man. 1951. Repr. New York: New
American Library, 1972.
J
Jacob, François. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of
Modern Biology. Tr. Austryn Wainhouse. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971.
Jacob, François. The Logic of Life: A History of Heredity. Tr. Betty E. Spillman. New
York: Pantheon Books, 1973.
Jaeger, Werner. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. The Gifford Lectures,
1936. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967.
James, E. O. Christianity and Other Religions. London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1968.
Jaroszwski, T. M. and P. A. Ignatovsky, eds. Socialism as a Social System. Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1981.
Jeremias, J. New Testament Theology: The Proclamation of Jesus. Tr. John Bowden.
New York: Scribner, 1971.
Joad, C. E. M. The Book of Joad: A Belligerent Autobiography [= Under the Fifth Rib].
London: Faber & Faber, 1944.
Johnson, Phillip E. Objections Sustained: Subversive Essays on Evolution, Law and
Culture. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1998.
Jones, Steve. In the Blood: God, Genes and Destiny. London: Harper Collins, 1996.
Josephus, Flavius. Antiquities of the Jews. Tr. William Whiston, The Works of
Flavius Josephus. 1737. Repr. Grand Rapids: Kregel, 1974. Repr. Peabody, Mass.:
Hendrickson, 1995.
K
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason. 1788. Tr. and ed. Mary Gregor.
Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. 1997. Repr. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. 1781. 2nd edn, 1787. Tr. Norman Kemp
Smith. London: Macmillan, 1929. Repr. Blunt Press, 2007. Also Paul Guyer and
Allen Wood, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. 1785. In H. J. Paton, tr.
The Moral Law. London: Hutchinson, 1972.
189
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysics of Morals. 1797. Tr. and ed. Mary J. Gregor.
Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996.
Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. 1783. Tr. and ed. Gary
Hatfield, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics with Selections from the
Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. 1997.
Rev. edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Kantikar, V. P. (Hemant) and W. Owen. Hinduism—An Introduction: Teach
Yourself. 1995. Repr. London: Hodder Headline, 2010.
Kaye, Howard L. The Social Meaning of Modern Biology, From Social Darwinism to
Sociobiology. 1986. Repr. with a new epilogue, New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction
Publishers, 1997.
Kenny, Anthony. An Illustrated Brief History of Western Philosophy. Oxford:
Blackwell, 2006. First published as A Brief History of Western Philosophy, 1998.
Kenyon, D. H. and G. Steinman. Biochemical Predestination. New York: McGraw-
Hill, 1969.
Kenyon, Frederic. Our Bible and the Ancient Manuscripts. 1895. 4th edn, 1938.
Repr. Eugene, Oreg.: Wipf & Stock, 2011.
Kilner, J. F., C. C. Hook and D. B. Uustal, eds. Cutting-Edge Bioethics: A Christian
Exploration of Technologies and Trends. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2002.
Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical
History with a Selection of Texts. 1957. Rev. edn, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1983.
Kirk, M. and H. Madsen. After the Ball. New York: Plume Books, 1989.
Knott, Kim. Hinduism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1998.
Koertge, Noretta, ed. A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths About
Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Kolbanovskiy, V. N. Communist Morality. Moscow, 1951.
Krikorian, Yervant H., ed. Naturalism and the Human Spirit. 1944. Repr. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1969.
Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 1962. 3rd edn, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Kurtz, Paul. The Fullness of Life. New York: Horizon Press, 1974.
Kurtz, Paul. The Humanist Alternative. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus, 1973.
Kurtz, Paul, ed. Humanist Manifestos I & II. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus, 1980.
Kurtz, Paul, ed. Humanist Manifesto II. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1980.
Online at https://americanhumanist.org/what-is-humanism/manifesto2/,
accessed 11 Sept. 2105.
L
Lamont, Corliss. A Lifetime of Dissent. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1988.
Lamont, Corliss. The Philosophy of Humanism. 1947. 8th edn, Emherst, N.Y.:
Humanist Press, 1997.
190
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
191
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
M
Mabbott, J. D. An Introduction to Ethics. Hutchinson University Library. London:
Hutchinson, 1966.
McKay, Donald. The Clockwork Image: A Christian Perspective on Science. London:
Inter-Varsity Press, 1974.
Majerus, Michael. Melanism: Evolution in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1998.
Margenau, Henry and Roy Abraham Varghese, eds. Cosmos, Bios, and Theos:
Scientists Reflect on Science, God, and the Origins of the Universe, Life, and
Homo Sapiens. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1992.
Marx, Karl. Marx’s Theses on Feuerbach. 1845.
Mascall, E. L. Words and Images, a study in the Possibility of Religious Discourse.
London: Longmans, 1957.
Mascarō, Juan, tr. The Upanishads. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1965.
Maslow, Abraham. Towards a Psychology of Being. New York: Van Nostrand
Reinhold, 1968.
Masterson, Patrick. Atheism and Alienation. Harmondsworth: Pelican Books, 1972.
May, Rollo. Psychology and the Human Dilemma. Princeton, N.J., 1967. Repr. New
York: Norton, 1996.
Medawar, Peter. Advice to a Young Scientist. New York: Harper & Row, 1979.
Medawar, Peter. The Limits of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Medawar, Peter and Jean Medawar. The Life Science. London: Wildwood House, 1977.
Metzger, Bruce. The Text of the New Testament, its Transmission, Corruption and
Restoration. 1964. 3rd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992.
Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1861, 1863. Repr. Mineola, N.Y.: Dover
Publications, 2007.
Millard, Alan. Reading and Writing in the Time of Jesus. Sheffield: Sheffield
Academic Press, 2000.
Miller, David, Janet Coleman, William Connolly, and Alan Ryan, eds. The Blackwell
Encyclopaedia of Political Thought. 1987. Repr. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
Monod, Jacques. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of
Modern Biology. 1970 (French). Tr. Austryn Wainhouse, 1971. Repr. London:
Penguin Books, 1997. Citations are from Vintage Books 1972 edn.
Monod, Jacques. From Biology to Ethics. San Diego: Salk Institute for Biological
Studies, 1969.
Morris, Simon Conway. The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale and the Rise
of Animals. 1998. New edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
Mossner, Ernest C., ed. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature. London:
Penguin Classics, 1985.
Moule, C. F. D. The Phenomenon of the New Testament: An Inquiry into the
Implications of Certain Features of the New Testament. London: SCM, 1967.
Murphy, John P. Pragmatism: From Peirce to Davidson. Boulder, Colo.: Westview
Press, 1990.
192
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
N
Nagel, Thomas. The Last Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
Nagel, Thomas. Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1979.
Nahem, Joseph. Psychology and Psychiatry Today: A Marxist View. New York:
International Publishers, 1981.
Nasr, Seyyed Hossein, and Oliver Leaman, eds. History of Islamic Philosophy.
Part 1, Vol. 1 of Routledge History of World Philosophies. 1996. Repr. London:
Routledge, 2001.
Nettleship, R. L. Lectures on the Republic of Plato. London: Macmillan, 1922.
Newton, Isaac. Principia Mathematica. London, 1687.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future.
Leipzig, 1886. 1973. Repr. tr. R. J. Hollingdale, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975.
Noddings, Nel. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. 1984.
Repr. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 2013.
Norris, Christopher. Deconstruction: Theory and Practice. 1982. 3rd edn, London:
Methuen, 2002.
O
Olivelle, Patrick. The Early Upanishads: Annotated Text and Translation. 1996.
Repr. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
O’Meara, Dominic J. Plotinus: An Introduction to the Enneads. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1993.
P
Paley, William. Natural Theology on Evidence and Attributes of Deity. 1802. Repr.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Patterson, Colin. Evolution. 1978. 2nd edn, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornstock Publishing
Associates, 1999.
Peacocke, Arthur. The Experiment of Life. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1983.
Pearsall, Judy and Bill Trumble, eds. The Oxford English Reference Dictionary. 2nd
edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Pearse, E. K. Victor. Evidence for Truth: Science. Guildford: Eagle, 1998.
Penfield, Wilder. The Mystery of the Mind. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1975.
Penrose, Roger. The Emperor’s New Mind. 1986. Repr. with new preface, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1999.
Penrose, Roger. The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe.
London: Jonathan Cape, 2004.
Peterson, Houston, ed. Essays in Philosophy. New York: Pocket Library, 1959.
Pinker, Steven. The Language Instinct: How the Mind Creates Language. New York:
Morrow, 1994.
193
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
194
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
R
Rachels, James. Elements of Moral Philosophy. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1986.
Ragg, Lonsdale and Laura Ragg, eds. The Gospel of Barnabas. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1907.
Ramsay, William. St. Paul the Traveller and the Roman Citizen. London: Hodder &
Stoughton, 1895.
Randall, John H. Cosmos. New York: Random House, 1980.
Raphael, D. D. Moral Philosophy. 1981. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1994.
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Redford, Donald B., ed. The Oxford Encyclopaedia of Ancient Egypt. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2001. doi: 10.1093/acref/9780195102345.001.0001.
Reid, Thomas. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1777.
Reid, Thomas. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense.
1764. Repr. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
Renfrew, Colin. Archaeology and Language: The Puzzle of Indo-European Origins.
1987. Repr. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Ricoeur, Paul. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. 1981. Ed. and tr. J. B.
Thompson. Repr. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Ricoeur, Paul. Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning. Fort
Worth, Tex.: Texas Christian University Press, 1976.
Ridley, Mark. The Problems of Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Rodwell, J. M., tr. The Koran. Ed. Alan Jones. London: Phoenix, 2011.
Rorty, Richard. Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972–1980. Minneapolis,
Minn.: University of Minnesota Press, 1982.
Rose, Steven. Lifelines: Biology, Freedom, Determinism. 1998. Repr. New York:
Oxford University Press, 2003.
Ross, Hugh. The Creator and the Cosmos. Colorado Springs: NavPress, 1995.
Ross, W. D. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930. Repr. 2002.
Rousseau, Jean Jacques. The Social Contract. 1762.
Russell, Bertrand. The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell. 1967–69. Repr. London:
Routledge, 1998.
Russell, Bertrand. History of Western Philosophy. 1946. New edn, London:
Routledge, 2004.
Russell, Bertrand. Human Society in Ethics and Politics. New York: Mentor, 1962.
Russell, Bertrand. The Problems of Philosophy. 1912. Repr. New York: Cosimo
Classics, 2010.
Russell, Bertrand. Religion and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970.
Russell, Bertrand. Understanding History. 1943. New York: Philosophical Library,
1957.
Russell, Bertrand. Why I Am Not a Christian and Other Essays on Religion and
Related Subjects. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1957.
195
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
S
Sagan, Carl. The Cosmic Connection: An Extraterrestrial Perspective. New York:
Anchor Press, 1973.
Sagan, Carl. Cosmos: The Story of Cosmic Evolution, Science and Civilisation. 1980.
Repr. London: Abacus, 2003.
Sagan, Carl. The Demon-Haunted World: Science as a Candle in the Dark. London:
Headline, 1996.
Sandbach, F. H. The Stoics. 1975. Rev. edn, London: Bloomsbury, 2013.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology.
1943. Tr. Hazel E. Barnes. 1956. Repr. New York: Pocket Books, 1984.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism and Human Emotions. Tr. Bernard Frechtman.
New York: Philosophical Library, 1957.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism and Humanism. Tr. and ed. P. Mairet. London:
Methuen, 1948.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. The Flies. 1943 (French). Tr. Stuart Gilbert. New York: Knopf,
1947.
Schaff, Adam. A Philosophy of Man. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1963.
Scherer, Siegfried. Evolution. Ein kritisches Lehrbuch. Weyel Biologie, Giessen:
Weyel Lehrmittelverlag, 1998.
Schmidt, W. The Origin and Growth of Religion. Tr. J. Rose. London: Methuen, 1931.
Scruton, Roger. Modern Philosophy. 1994; London: Arrow Books, 1996.
Searle, John R. The Construction of Social Reality. London: Penguin, 1995.
Searle, John R. Minds, Brains and Science. 1984 Reith Lectures. London: British
Broadcasting Corporation, 1984.
Selsam, Howard. Socialism and Ethics. New York: International Publishers, 1943.
Sen, Amartya and Bernard Williams, eds. Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1982. 8th repr. in association with La Maison Des
Sciences De L’Homme, Paris, 1999.
Shakespeare, William. As You Like It.
Sherrington, Charles S. The Integrative Action of the Nervous System. 1906. Repr.
with new preface, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1947.
Sherwin-White, A. N. Roman Society and Roman Law in the New Testament. The
Sarum Lectures 1960–61. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963. Repr. Eugene, Oreg.:
Wipf & Stock, 2004.
Simplicius. Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics [or, Miscellanies]. In Kirk, G. S.,
J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History
with a Selection of Texts. 1957. Rev. edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1983.
196
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
Simpson, George Gaylord. The Meaning of Evolution: A Study of the History of Life
and of Its Significance for Man. The Terry Lectures Series. 1949. Rev. edn, New
Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1967.
Singer, Peter. Practical Ethics. 1979. 2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
Singer, Peter. Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of Our Traditional Ethics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.
Singer, Peter and Helga Kuhse. Should the Baby Live?: The Problem of Handicapped
Infants (Studies in Bioethics). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Sire, James. The Universe Next Door. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1988.
Skinner, B. F. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. 1971; Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974.
Skinner, B. F. Lectures on Conditioned Reflexes. New York: International Publishers,
1963.
Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behaviour. New York: Macmillan, 1953.
Sleeper, Raymond S. A Lexicon of Marxist-Leninist Semantics. Alexandria, Va.:
Western Goals, 1983.
Smart, J. J. C. and Bernard Williams. Utilitarianism For and Against. 1973. Repr.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Smith, Adam. An Enquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations.
1776. With introduction by Mark G. Spencer, Ware, UK: Wordsworth Editions,
2012.
Smith, John Maynard and Eörs Szathmary. The Major Transitions in Evolution.
1995. Repr. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
Smith, Wilbur. Therefore Stand. Grand Rapids: Baker, 1965.
Sober, E. Philosophy of Biology. 1993. Rev. 2nd edn, Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press,
2000.
Social Exclusion Unit. Teenage Pregnancy. Cmnd 4342. London: The Stationery
Office, 1999.
Sophocles. Antigone. Tr. F. H. Storr, Sophocles Vol. 1. London: Heinemann, 1912.
Spencer, Herbert. Social Statics. New York: D. Appleton, 1851.
Stalin, Joseph. J. Stalin Works. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1953.
Stam, James H. Inquiries into the Origin of Language: The Fate of a Question. New
York: Harper & Row, 1976.
Starkey, Mike. God, Sex, and the Search for Lost Wonder: For Those Looking
for Something to Believe In. 1997. 2nd edn, Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity
Press, 1998.
Stauber, Ethelbert. Jesus—Gestalt und Geschichte. Bern: Francke Verlag, 1957.
Storer, Morris B., ed. Humanist Ethics: Dialogue on Basics. Buffalo, N.Y.:
Prometheus Books, 1980.
Stott, John R. W. The Message of Romans. Leicester: Inter-Varsity Press, 1994.
Strabo. Geography. Tr. with introduction Duane W. Roller as The Geography of
Strabo, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014. Tr. H. C. Hamilton and
W. Falconer, London, 1903. Online at Perseus, Tufts University, http://www.
197
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0239, accessed
11 Sept. 2015.
Strickberger, Monroe. Evolution. 1990. 3rd edn, London: Jones and Bartlett, 2000.
Strobel, Lee. The Case for Christ: A Journalist’s Personal Investigation of the
Evidence for Jesus. Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1998.
Suetonius. Lives of the Caesars. Tr. Catharine Edwards. 2000. Repr. Oxford World’s
Classics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Sunderland, Luther D. Darwin’s Enigma. Green Forest, Ark.: Master Books, 1998.
Swinburne, Richard. The Existence of God. 1979. Repr. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2004.
Swinburne, Richard. Faith and Reason. 1981. Repr. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
Swinburne, Richard. Is There a God? Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Swinburne, Richard. Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1998.
T
Tacitus, Cornelius. Annals. Tr. Alfred John Church and William Jackson Brodribb
as Complete Works of Tacitus. New York: Random House, 1872. Repr. 1942.
Online at Sara Byrant, ed., Perseus Digital Library, Tufts University, Medford,
MA: http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:1999.02.0078,
accessed 2 Aug. 2017.
Tada, Joni Eareckson and Steven Estes. When God Weeps: Why Our Sufferings
Matter to the Almighty. Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1997.
Tax, Sol and Charles Callender, eds. Issues in Evolution. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1960.
Thaxton, Charles B., Walter L. Bradley and Roger L. Olsen. The Mystery of Life’s
Origin. Dallas: Lewis & Stanley, 1992.
Thibaut, George, tr. The Vedānta Sūtras of Bādarāyana with the Commentary by
Śankara, 2 Parts. New York: Dover, 1962.
Torrance, T. F. The Ground and Grammar of Theology. Belfast: Christian Journals
Limited, 1980; and Charlottesville: The University Press of Virginia, 1980. Repr.
with new preface, Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 2001.
Torrance, T. F. Theological Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978.
U
Unamuno, Don Miguel de. The Tragic Sense of Life. Tr. J. E. Crawford. 1921. Repr.
Charleston, S.C.: BiblioBazaar, 2007.
V
Von Neumann, John. Theory of Self-Reproducing Automata. Ed. and completed by
Arthur W. Burks, Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1966.
198
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
W
Waddington, C. H., ed. Science and Ethics: An Essay. London: Allen & Unwin, 1942.
Wallis, R. T. Neoplatonism. 1972. Repr. London: Duckworth, 1985.
Ward, Keith. God, Chance and Necessity. 1996. Repr. Oxford: Oneworld Publications,
2001.
Warner, Richard, and Tadeusz Szubka. The Mind-Body Problem. Oxford: Blackwell,
1994.
Weiner, Jonathan. The Beak of the Finch. London: Cape, 1994.
Welch, I. David, George A. Tate and Fred Richards, eds. Humanistic Psychology.
Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1978.
Wenham, John. Easter Enigma—Do the Resurrection Stories Contradict One
Another? Exeter: Paternoster Press, 1984. Repr. as Easter Enigma: Are the
Resurrection Accounts in Conflict?, Eugene, Oreg.: Wipf & Stock, 2005.
Wesson, Paul. Beyond Natural Selection. 1991. Repr. Cambridge, Mass.:
Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1997.
Westminster Shorter Catechism. 1647. [Widely available in print and online.]
Wetter, Gustav A. Dialectical Materialism. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1977.
Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality. Gifford Lectures 1927–28. London:
Macmillan, 1929. Repr. New York: The Free Press, 1978.
Wilson, Edward O. Consilience. London: Little, Brown, 1998.
Wilson, Edward O. Genes, Mind and Culture. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1981.
Wilson, Edward O. On Human Nature. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1978.
Wilson, Edward O. Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1975.
Wimsatt, William K. and Monroe Beardsley. The Verbal Icon: Studies in the Meaning
of Poetry. 1954. Repr. Lexington, Ky.: University of Kentucky Press, 1982.
Wippel, John F., ed. Studies in Medieval Philosophy. Vol. 17 of Studies in Philosophy
and the History of Philosophy. Washington D.C.: Catholic University of America
Press, 1987.
Wittgenstein, L. On Certainty. Ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright; tr.
Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford, 1969. Repr. New York: Harper &
Row, 1972.
Wolpert, Lewis. The Unnatural Nature of Science. London: Faber & Faber, 1992.
Wolstenholme, Gordon, ed. Man and His Future. A Ciba Foundation Volume.
London: J. & A. Churchill, 1963.
Wolters, Clifton, tr. The Cloud of Unknowing. 1961. Repr. London: Penguin, 1978.
Wolterstorff, Nicholas. Divine Discourse: Philosophical Reflections on the Claim that
God Speaks. 1995. Repr. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
199
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
X
Xenophon. Memorabilia. Tr. E. C. Marchant. Memorabilia. Oeconomicus.
Symposium. Apology. Vol. 4. Loeb Classical Library, Vol. 168. 1923. Repr.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1997.
Y
Yancey, Philip. Soul Survivor: How my Faith Survived the Church. London: Hodder
& Stoughton, 2001.
Yockey, Hubert. Information Theory and Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1992.
Z
Zacharias, Ravi. Jesus Among Other Gods: The Absolute Claims of the Christian
Message. Nashville, Tenn.: Thomas Nelson, 2000.
Zacharias, Ravi. The Real Face of Atheism. Grand Rapids: Baker, 2004.
Zaehner, Z. C., ed. The Concise Encyclopedia of Living Faiths. 1959. 2nd edn, 1971.
Repr. London: Hutchinson, 1982.
200
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
A
Adams, R. M. ‘Religious Ethics in a Pluralistic Society.’ In G. Outka and J. P.
Reeder, Jr., eds. Prospects for a Common Morality. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press, 1993.
Alberts, Bruce. ‘The Cell as a Collection of Protein Machines: Preparing the Next
Generation of Molecular Biologists.’ Cell 92/3 (6 Feb. 1998), 291–4. doi: 10.1016/
S0092-8674(00)80922-8.
Almond, Brenda. ‘Liberty or Community? Defining the Post-Marxist Agenda.’ In
Brenda Almond, ed. Introducing Applied Ethics. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell, 1995.
Alpher, R. A., H. Bethe and G. Gamow. ‘The Origin of Chemical Elements.’ Physical
Review 73/7 (Apr. 1948), 803–4. doi: 10.1103/PhysRev.73.803.
Anscombe, G. E. M. ‘Modern Moral Philosophy.’ Philosophy 33 (1958), 1–19.
Asimov, Isaac (interview by Paul Kurtz). ‘An Interview with Isaac Asimov on
Science and the Bible.’ Free Enquiry 2/2 (Spring 1982), 6–10.
Auer, J. A. C. F. ‘Religion as the Integration of Human Life.’ The Humanist (Spring
1947).
Austin, J. L., P. F. Strawson and D. R. Cousin. ‘Truth.’ Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 24, Physical Research, Ethics
and Logic (1950), 111–72. Online at http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106745. Repr. in
Paul Horwich, ed. Theories of Truth. Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing, 1994.
B
Bada, Jeffrey L. ‘Stanley Miller’s 70th Birthday.’ Origins of Life and Evolution of
Biospheres 30/2 (2000), 107–12. doi: 10.1023/A:1006746205180.
Baier, Kurt E. M. ‘Egoism.’ In P. Singer, ed. A Companion to Ethics. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1991. Repr. 2000, 197–204.
Baier, Kurt E. M. ‘Freedom, Obligation, and Responsibility.’ In Morris B. Storer, ed.
Humanist Ethics: Dialogue on Basics. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1980,
75–92.
Baier, Kurt E. M. ‘The Meaning of Life.’ 1947. In Peter Angeles, ed. Critiques of God,
Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1976. Repr. in E. D. Klemke, ed. The Meaning
of Life. New York: Oxford University Press, 1981, 81–117.
Baker, S. W. ‘Albert Nyanza, Account of the Discovery of the Second Great
Lake of the Nile.’ Journal of the Royal Geographical Society 36 (1866). Also in
Proceedings of the Royal Geographical Society of London 10 (13 Nov. 1856), 6–27.
Bates, Elizabeth, Donna Thal and Virginia Marchman. ‘Symbols and Syntax:
A Darwinian Approach to Language Development.’ In Norman A. Krasnegor,
Duane M. Rumbaugh, Richard L. Schiefelbusch and Michael Studdert-Kennedy,
eds. Biological and Behavioural Determinants of Language Development. 1991.
Repr. New York: Psychology Press, 2014, 29–65.
Behe, Michael J. ‘Reply to My Critics: A Response to Reviews of Darwin’s Black Box:
The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution.’ Biology and Philosophy 16 (2001), 685–709.
201
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
C
Caputo, John D. ‘The End of Ethics.’ In Hugh LaFollette, ed. The Blackwell Guide to
Ethical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999, 111–28.
Cartmill, Matt. ‘Oppressed by Evolution.’ Discover Magazine 19/3 (Mar. 1998), 78–83.
Reprinted in L. Polnac, ed. Purpose, Pattern, and Process. 6th edn, Dubuque:
Kendall-Hunt, 2002, 389–97.
Cavalier-Smith, T. ‘The Blind Biochemist.’ Trends in Ecology and Evolution 12
(1997), 162–3.
Chaitin, Gregory J. ‘Randomness in Arithmetic and the Decline and Fall of
Reductionism in Pure Mathematics.’ Ch. 3 in John Cornwell, ed. Nature’s
Imagination: The Frontiers of Scientific Vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1995, 27–44.
Chomsky, Noam. ‘Review of B. F. Skinner.’ Verbal Behavior. Language 35/1 (1959),
26–58.
Chomsky, Noam. ‘Science, Mind, and Limits of Understanding.’ Transcript of talk
given at the Science and Faith Foundation (STOQ), The Vatican (Jan. 2014). No
pages. Online at https://chomsky.info/201401__/, accessed 3 Aug. 2017.
Coghlan, Andy. ‘Selling the family secrets.’ New Scientist 160/2163 (5 Dec. 1998),
20–1.
Collins, Harry. ‘Introduction: Stages in the Empirical Programme of Relativism.’
Social Studies of Science 11/1 (Feb. 1981), 3–10. Online at http://www.jstor.org/
stable/284733, accessed 11 Sept. 2015.
Collins, R. ‘A Physician’s View of College Sex.’ Journal of the American Medical
Association 232 (1975), 392.
Cook, Sidney. ‘Solzhenitsyn and Secular Humanism: A Response.’ The Humanist
(Nov./Dec. 1978), 6.
202
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
Cookson, Clive. ‘Scientist Who Glimpsed God.’ Financial Times (29 Apr. 1995), 20.
Cottingham, John. ‘Descartes, René.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford Companion
to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Crick, Francis. ‘Lessons from Biology.’ Natural History 97 (Nov. 1988), 32–9.
Crosman, Robert. ‘Do Readers Make Meaning?’ In Susan R. Suleiman and Inge
Crosman, eds. The Reader in the Text: Essays on Audience and Interpretation.
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980.
D
Davies, Paul. ‘Bit before It?’ New Scientist 2171 (30 Jan. 1999), 3.
Dawkins, Richard. ‘Put Your Money on Evolution.’ Review of Maitland A. Edey
and Donald C. Johanson. Blueprint: Solving the Mystery of Evolution. Penguin,
1989. The New York Times Review of Books (9 Apr. 1989), sec. 7, 34–5.
Dembski, William. ‘Intelligent Design as a Theory of Information.’ Perspectives on
Science and Christian Faith 49/3 (Sept. 1997), 180–90.
Derrida, Jacques. ‘Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundation of Authority”.’ In
Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld and David Gray Carlson, eds. Deconstruction
and the Possibility of Justice. 1992. Repr. Abingdon: Routledge, 2008.
Dirac, P. A. M. ‘The Evolution of the Physicist’s Picture of Nature.’ Scientific
American 208/5 (1963), 45–53. doi: 10.1038/scientificamerican0563-45.
Dobzhansky, Theodosius. ‘Chance and Creativity in Evolution.’ Ch. 18 in Francisco
J. Ayala and Theodosius Dobzhansky, eds. Studies in the Philosophy of Biology:
Reduction and Related Problems. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press,
1974, 307–36.
Dobzhansky, Theodosius. Discussion of paper by Gerhard Schramm, ‘Synthesis
of Nucleosides and Polynucleotide with Metaphosphate Esters.’ In Sidney W.
Fox, ed. The Origins of Prebiological Systems and of Their Molecular Matrices,
299–315. Proceedings of a Conference Conducted at Wakulla Springs, Florida,
on 20–30 October 1963 under the auspices of the Institute for Space Biosciences,
the Florida State University and the National Aeronautics and Space
Administration. New York: Academic Press, 1965.
Dobzhansky, Theodosius. ‘Evolutionary Roots of Family Ethics and Group
Ethics.’ In The Centrality of Science and Absolute Values, Vol. I of Proceedings
of the Fourth International Conference on the Unity of the Sciences. New York:
International Cultural Foundation, 1975.
Documents of the 22nd Congress of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union. 2 vols.
Documents of Current History, nos. 18–19. New York: Crosscurrents Press,
1961.
Dose, Klaus. ‘The Origin of Life: More Questions Than Answers.’ Interdisciplinary
Science Reviews 13 (Dec. 1988), 348–56.
Druart, Th.-A. ‘Al-Fārābī and Emanationism.’ In J. F. Wippel, ed. Studies in
Medieval Philosophy. Vol. 17 of Studies in Philosophy and the History of
Philosophy. Washington D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1987,
23–43.
Dyson, Freeman. ‘Energy in the Universe.’ Scientific American 225/3 (1971), 50–9.
203
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
E
Eddington, Arthur. ‘The End of the World: From the Standpoint of Mathematical
Physics.’ Nature 127 (21 Mar. 1931), 447–53. doi: 10.1038/127447a0.
Edwards, William. ‘On the Physical Death of Jesus Christ.’ Journal of the American
Medical Association 255/11 (21 Mar. 1986), 1455–63.
Eigen, Manfred, Christof K. Biebricher, Michael Gebinoga and William C.
Gardiner. ‘The Hypercycle: Coupling of RNA and Protein Biosynthesis in the
Infection Cycle of an RNA Bacteriophage.’ Biochemistry 30/46 (1991), 11005–18.
doi: 10.1021/bi00110a001.
Einstein, Albert. ‘Physics and Reality.’ 1936. In Sonja Bargmann, tr. Ideas and
Opinions. New York: Bonanza, 1954.
Einstein, Albert. ‘Science and Religion.’ 1941. Published in Science, Philosophy and
Religion, A Symposium. New York: The Conference on Science, Philosophy and
Religion in Their Relation to the Democratic Way of Life, 1941. Repr. in Out of
My Later Years, 1950, 1956. Repr. New York: Open Road Media, 2011.
Eysenck, H. J. ‘A Reason with Compassion.’ In Paul Kurtz, ed. The Humanist
Alternative. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1973.
F
Feynman, Richard P. ‘Cargo Cult Science.’ Repr. in Engineering and Science 37/7
(1974), 10–13. Online at http://calteches.library.caltech.edu/51/2/CargoCult.
pdf (facsimile), accessed 11 Sept. 2015. (Originally delivered as Caltech’s 1974
commencement address in Pasadena, Calif.)
Fletcher, J. ‘Comment by Joseph Fletcher on Nielsen Article.’ In Morris B. Storer, ed.
Humanist Ethics: Dialogue on Basics. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1980, 70.
Flew, Anthony. ‘Miracles.’ In Paul Edwards, ed. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
New York: Macmillan, 1967, 5:346–53.
Flew, Anthony. ‘Neo-Humean Arguments about the Miraculous.’ In R. D. Geivett
and G. R. Habermas, eds. In Defence of Miracles. Leicester: Apollos, 1997, 45–57.
Flieger, Jerry Aline. ‘The Art of Being Taken by Surprise.’ Destructive Criticism:
Directions. SCE Reports 8 (Fall 1980), 54–67.
Fodor, J. A. ‘Fixation of Belief and Concept Acquisition.’ In M. Piattelli-Palmarini,
ed., Language and Learning: The Debate Between Jean Piaget and Noam
Chomsky. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980, 143–9.
Fotion, Nicholas G. ‘Logical Positivism.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford
Companion to Philosophy. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Frank, Lawrence K. ‘Potentialities of Human Nature.’ The Humanist (Apr. 1951).
Frankena, William K. ‘Is morality logically dependent on religion?’ In G. Outka
and J. P. Reeder, Jr., eds. Religion and Morality. Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1973.
G
Genequand, Charles. ‘Metaphysics.’ Ch. 47 in Seyyed Nossein Nasr and Oliver
Leaman, eds. History of Islamic Philosophy. Vol. 1 of Routledge History of World
Philosophies. London: Routledge, 1996, 783–801.
204
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
H
Haldane, J. B. S. ‘When I am Dead.’ In Possible Worlds. [1927] London: Chatto &
Windus, 1945, 204–11.
Hansen, Michèle; Jennifer J. Kurinczuk, Carol Bower and Sandra Webb. ‘The
Risk of Major Birth Defects after Intracytoplasmic Sperm Injection and in
Vitro Fertilization.’ New England Journal of Medicine 346 (2002), 725–30.
doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa010035.
Hardwig, John. ‘Dying at the Right Time: Reflections on (Un)Assisted Suicide.’ In
Hugh LaFollette, ed. Ethics In Practice. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies. 2nd
edn, Oxford: Blackwell, 1997, 101–11.
Hawking, S. W. ‘The Edge of Spacetime: Does the universe have an edge and time a
beginning, as Einstein’s general relativity predicts, or is spacetime finite without
boundary, as quantum mechanics suggests?’ American Scientist 72/4 (1984),
355–9. Online at http://www.jstor.org/stable/27852759, accessed 15 Sept. 2015.
Hawking, S. W. Letters to the Editors. Reply to letter by J. J. Tanner relating to
article ‘The Edge of Spacetime’. American Scientist 73/1 (1985), 12. Online at
http://www.jstor.org/stable/27853056, accessed 15 Sept. 2015.
205
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
I
Inwood, M. J. ‘Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford
Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005.
J
Jeeves, Malcolm. ‘Brain, Mind, and Behaviour.’ In Warren S. Brown, Nancey
Murphy and H. Newton Malony, eds. Whatever Happened to the Soul: Scientific
and Theological Portraits of Human Nature. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1998.
Johnson, Barbara. ‘Nothing Fails Like Success.’ Deconstructive Criticism:
Directions. SCE Reports 8 (Fall 1980), 7–16.
Josephson, Brian. Letters to the Editor. The Independent (12 Jan. 1997), London.
K
Kant, Immanuel. ‘Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?’ Berlinische
Monatsschrift 4 (Dec. 1784), 481–94. Repr. in Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften.
Berlin: Akademie Ausgabe, 1923, 8:33–42.
Khrushchev, Nikita. Ukrainian Bulletin (1–15 Aug. 1960), 12.
Klein-Franke, Felix. ‘Al-Kindī.’ In Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman,
eds. History of Islamic Philosophy. Vol. 1, Part 1 of Routledge History of World
Philosophies. 1996. Repr. London: Routledge, 2001, 165–77.
206
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
L
Lamont, Corliss. ‘The Ethics of Humanism.’ In Frederick C. Dommeyer, ed. In
Quest of Value: Readings in Philosophy and Personal Values. San Francisco:
Chandler, 1963, 46–59. Repr. from ch. 6 of Corliss Lamont. Humanism as a
Philosophy. Philosophical Library, 273–97.
Larson, Erik. ‘Looking for the Mind.’ (Review of David J. Chalmers. The Conscious
Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory.) Origins & Design 18/1(34) (Winter
1997), Colorado Springs: Access Research Network, 28–9.
Leitch, Vincent B. ‘The Book of Deconstructive Criticism.’ Studies in the Literary
Imagination 12/1 (Spring 1979), 19–39.
Lewis, C. S. ‘The Funeral of a Great Myth.’ In Walter Hooper, ed. Christian
Reflections. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1967, 102–116.
Lewis, C. S. ‘The Weight of Glory.’ In Transposition and other Addresses. London:
Geoffrey Bles, 1949. Repr. in The Weight of Glory and Other Addresses.
HarperOne, 2001.
Lewontin, Richard C. ‘Billions and Billions of Demons.’ The New York Review of
Books 44/1 (9 Jan. 1997).
Lewontin, Richard C. ‘Evolution/Creation Debate: A Time for Truth.’ BioScience
31/8 (Sept. 1981), 559. Reprinted in J. Peter Zetterberg, ed. Evolution versus
Creationism. Phoenix, Ariz.: Oryx Press, 1983. doi: 10.1093/bioscience/31.8.559,
accessed 15 Sept. 2015.
Lieberman, Philip and E. S. Crelin. ‘On the Speech of Neanderthal Man.’ Linguistic
Inquiry 2/2 (Mar. 1971), 203–22.
Louden, Robert. ‘On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics.’ Ch. 10 in R. Crisp and M. Slote,
eds. Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
M
Mackie, J. L. ‘Evil and Omnipotence.’ Mind 64/254 (Apr. 1955), 200–12.
McNaughton, David and Piers Rawling. ‘Intuitionism.’ Ch. 13 in Hugh LaFollette,
ed. The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 268–87.
Ch. 14 in 2nd edn, Wiley Blackwell, 2013, 287–310.
Maddox, John. ‘Down with the Big Bang.’ Nature 340 (1989), 425. doi: 10.1038/
340425a0.
207
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Marx, Karl. ‘The Difference between the Natural Philosophy of Democritus and the
Natural Philosophy of Epicurus.’ In K. Marx and F. Engels on Religion. Moscow:
Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1955.
Marx, Karl. ‘Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts.’ In T. B. Bottomore, tr. and
ed. Karl Marx: Early Writings. London: Watts, 1963.
Marx, Karl. ‘Theses on Feuerback.’ In Frederick Engels, Ludwig Feuerback. New
York: International Publishers, 1941.
May, Rollo. ‘The Problem of Evil: An Open Letter to Carl Rogers.’ Journal of
Humanistic Psychology (Summer 1982).
Merezhkovsky, Dmitry. ‘On the Reasons for the Decline and on the New Currents
in Contemporary Russian Literature.’ 1892 lecture. In Dmitry Merezhkovsky.
On the reasons for the decline and on the new currents in contemporary Russian
literature. Petersburg, 1893.
Meyer, Stephen C. ‘The Explanatory Power of Design: DNA and the Origin of
Information.’ In William A. Dembski, ed. Mere Creation: Science, Faith and
Intelligent Design. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1998, 114–47.
Meyer, Stephen C. ‘The Methodological Equivalence of Design and Descent.’ In J. P.
Moreland, ed. The Creation Hypothesis. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press,
1994, 67–112.
Meyer, Stephen C. ‘Qualified Agreement: Modern Science and the Return of the
“God Hypothesis”.’ In Richard F. Carlson, ed. Science and Christianity: Four
Views. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 2000, 129–75.
Meyer, Stephen C. ‘The Return of the God Hypothesis.’ Journal of Interdisciplinary
Studies 11/1&2 (Jan. 1999), 1–38. Online at http://www.discovery.org/a/642,
accessed 3 Aug. 2017. Citations are to the archived version, which is repaginated,
and online at http://www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.
php?command=download&id=12006, accessed 3 Aug. 2017.
Miller, J. Hillis. ‘Deconstructing the Deconstructors.’ Review of Joseph N. Riddel.
The Inverted Bell: Modernism and the Counterpoetics of William Carlos
Williams. Diacritics 5/2 (Summer 1975), 24–31. Online at http://www.jstor.org/
stable/464639, accessed 3 Aug. 2017. doi: 10.2307/464639.
Monod, Jacques. ‘On the Logical Relationship between Knowledge and Values.’ In
Watson Fuller, ed. The Biological Revolution. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1972.
N
Nagel, Ernest. ‘Naturalism Reconsidered.’ 1954. In Houston Peterson, ed. Essays in
Philosophy. New York: Pocket Books, 1959. Repr. New York: Pocket Books, 1974.
Nagel, Thomas. ‘Rawls, John.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford Companion to
Philosophy. 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Nagler, Michael N. ‘Reading the Upanishads.’ In Eknath Easwaran. The
Upanishads. 1987. Repr. Berkeley, Calif.: Nilgiri Press, 2007.
Neill, Stephen. ‘The Wrath of God and the Peace of God.’ In Max Warren,
Interpreting the Cross. London: SCM Press, 1966.
Newing, Edward G. ‘Religions of pre-literary societies.’ In Sir Norman Anderson,
ed. The World’s Religions. 4th edn, London: Inter-Varsity Press, 1975.
208
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
O
The Oxford Reference Encyclopaedia. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
P
Palmer, Alasdair. ‘Must Knowledge Gained Mean Paradise Lost?’ Sunday Telegraph.
London (6 Apr. 1997).
Penzias, Arno. ‘Creation is Supported by all the Data So Far.’ In Henry Margenau
and Roy Abraham Varghese, eds. Cosmos, Bios, Theos: Scientists Reflect on
Science, God, and the Origins of the Universe, Life, and Homo Sapiens. La Salle,
Ill.: Open Court, 1992.
Pinker, Steven, and Paul Bloom. ‘Natural Language and Natural Selection.’
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13/4 (Dec. 1990), 707–27. doi: 10.1017/
S0140525X00081061.
Polanyi, Michael. ‘Life’s Irreducible Structure. Live mechanisms and information
in DNA are boundary conditions with a sequence of boundaries above
them.’ Science 160/3834 (1968), 1308–12. Online at http://www.jstor.org/
stable/1724152, accessed 3 Aug. 2017.
Poole, Michael. ‘A Critique of Aspects of the Philosophy and Theology of
Richard Dawkins.’ Christians and Science 6/1 (1994), 41–59. Online at http://
www.scienceandchristianbelief.org/serve_pdf_free.php?filename=SCB+6-
1+Poole.pdf, accessed 3 Aug. 2017.
Popper, Karl. ‘Scientific Reduction and the Essential Incompleteness of All Science.’
In F. J. Ayala and T. Dobzhansky, ed. Studies in the Philosophy of Biology,
Reduction and Related Problems. London: MacMillan, 1974.
Premack, David. ‘“Gavagai!” or The Future History of the Animal Controversy.’
Cognition 19/3 (1985), 207–96. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(85)90036-8.
Provine, William B. ‘Evolution and the Foundation of Ethics.’ Marine Biological
Laboratory Science 3 (1988), 27–8.
Provine, William B. ‘Scientists, Face it! Science and Religion are Incompatible.’ The
Scientist (5 Sept. 1988), 10–11.
R
Rachels, James. ‘Naturalism.’ In Hugh LaFollette, ed. The Blackwell Guide to Ethical
Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 74–91.
Randall, John H. ‘The Nature of Naturalism.’ In Yervant H. Krikorian, ed.
Naturalism, 354–82.
Raup, David. ‘Conflicts between Darwin and Palaeontology.’ Field Museum of
Natural History Bulletin 50/1 (Jan. 1979), 22–9.
Reidhaar-Olson, John F. and Robert T. Sauer. ‘Functionally Acceptable
Substitutions in Two α-helical Regions of λ Repressor.’ Proteins: Structure,
Function, and Genetics 7/4 (1990), 306–16. doi: 10.1002/prot.340070403.
209
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Rescher, Nicholas. ‘Idealism.’ In Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa, eds. A Companion
to Epistemology. 1992. Repr. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000.
Ridley, Mark. ‘Who Doubts Evolution?’ New Scientist 90 (25 June 1981), 830–2.
Rogers, Carl. ‘Notes on Rollo May.’ Journal of Humanistic Psychology 22/3 (Summer
1982), 8–9. doi: 10.1177/0022167882223002.
Rorty, Richard. ‘Untruth and Consequences.’ The New Republic (31 July 1995),
32–6.
Ruse, Michael. ‘Is Rape Wrong on Andromeda?’ In E. Regis Jr., ed. Extraterrestrials.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Ruse, Michael. ‘Transcript: Speech by Professor Michael Ruse,’ Symposium, ‘The
New Antievolutionism’, 1993 Annual Meeting of the American Association for
the Advancement of Science, 13 Feb. 1993. Online at http://www.arn.org/docs/
orpages/or151/mr93tran.htm, accessed 3 Aug. 2017.
Ruse, Michael and Edward O. Wilson. ‘The Evolution of Ethics.’ New Scientist
108/1478 (17 Oct. 1985), 50–2.
Russell, Bertrand. ‘A Free Man’s Worship.’ 1903. In Why I Am Not a Christian. New
York: Simon & Schuster, 1957. Also in Mysticism and Logic Including A Free
Man’s Worship. London: Unwin, 1986.
Russell, Colin. ‘The Conflict Metaphor and its Social Origins.’ Science and
Christian Belief 1/1 (1989), 3–26.
S
Sanders, Blanche. The Humanist 5 (1945).
Sanders, Peter. ‘Eutychus.’ Triple Helix (Summer 2002), 17.
Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. ‘Contractarianism.’ In Hugh LaFollette, ed. The Blackwell
Guide to Ethical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 247–67. 2nd edn, Wiley
Blackwell, 2013, 332–53.
Scruton, Roger. The Times (Dec. 1997), London.
Searle, John. ‘Minds, Brains and Programs.’ In John Haugeland, ed. Mind Design.
Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Sedgh, Gilda, et al., ‘Abortion incidence between 1990 and 2014: global, regional,
and subregional levels and trends.’ The Lancet 388/10041 (16 July 2016), 258–67.
doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(16)30380-4.
Shapiro, James A. ‘In the Details . . . What?’ National Review (16 Sept. 1996), 62–5.
Simpson, George Gaylord. ‘The Biological Nature of Man.’ Science 152/3721
(22 Apr. 1966), 472–8.
Singer, Peter. ‘Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford
Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005.
Skorupski, John. ‘Mill, John Stuart.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford Companion
to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Slote, Michael. ‘Utilitarianism.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The Oxford Companion
to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
210
SERIES BIBLIOGRAPHY
Slote, Michael. ‘Virtue Ethics.’ In Hugh LaFollette, ed. The Blackwell Guide to
Ethical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 325–47.
Sokal, Alan D. ‘Transgressing the boundaries: towards a transformative
hermeneutic of Quantum Gravity.’ Social Text (Spring/Summer 1996), 217–52.
Sokal, Alan D. ‘What the Social Text Affair Does and Does Not Prove.’ In Noretta
Koertge, ed. A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths About
Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998, 9–22.
Solzhenitsyn, Alexander. ‘Alexandr Solzhenitsyn—Nobel Lecture.’ Nobelprize.org.
Nobel Media AB 2014. Online at https://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/
literature/laureates/1970/solzhenitsyn-lecture.html, accessed 15 Aug. 2017.
Spetner, L. M. ‘Natural selection: An information-transmission mechanism for
evolution.’ Journal of Theoretical Biology 7/3 (Nov. 1964), 412–29.
Stalin, Joseph. Speech delivered 24 April 1924. New York, International Publishers,
1934.
Stolzenberg, Gabriel. ‘Reading and relativism: an introduction to the science
wars.’ In Keith M. Ashman and Philip S. Baringer, eds. After the Science Wars.
London: Routledge, 2001, 33–63.
T
Tarkunde, V. M. ‘Comment by V. M. Tarkunde on Hocutt Article.’ In Morris B.
Storer, ed. Humanist Ethics: Dialogue on Basics. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus
Books, 1980, 147–8.
Taylor, Robert. ‘Evolution is Dead.’ New Scientist 160/2154 (3 Oct. 1998), 25–9.
W
Walicki, Andrzej. ‘Hegelianism, Russian.’ In Edward Craig, gen. ed. Concise
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 2000.
Wallace, Daniel, “The Majority Text and the Original Text: Are They Identical?,”
Bibliotheca Sacra, April-June, 1991, 157-8.
Walton, J. C. ‘Organization and the Origin of Life.’ Origins 4 (1977), 16–35.
Warren, Mary Ann. ‘On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion.’ Ch. 11 in Hugh
LaFollette, ed. Ethics in Practice: An Anthology, 1997, 72–82. 4th edn, Oxford:
Blackwell, 2014, 132–40.
Watters, Wendell W. ‘Christianity and Mental Health.’ The Humanist 37 (Nov./Dec.
1987).
Weatherford, Roy C. ‘Freedom and Determinism.’ In Ted Honderich, ed. The
Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, 1995. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2005.
Wheeler, John A. ‘Information, Physics, Quantum: The Search for Links.’ In
Wojciech Hubert Zurek. Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information.
The Proceedings of the 1988 Workshop on Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics
of Information, held May–June, 1989, in Santa Fe, N. Mex. Redwood City, Calif.:
Addison-Wesley, 1990.
211
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Y
Yockey, Hubert. ‘A Calculation of the Probability of Spontaneous Biogenesis by
Information Theory.’ Journal of Theoretical Biology 67 (1977), 377–98.
Yockey, Hubert. ‘Self-Organisation Origin of Life Scenarios and Information
Theory.’ Journal of Theoretical Biology 91 (1981), 13–31.
212
STUDY QUESTIONS FOR TEACHERS AND STUDENTS
214
STUDY QUESTIONS FOR TEACHERS AND STUDENTS
2.21 The sophists said that there was no Mind behind the universe. Plato argued
that there must be Mind behind the universe. What would you say?
2.22 What do you think justice is? And how should we decide what it is? Is it:
(a) a standard that each one of us decides for himself or herself?
(b) a standard that is set by the majority of the people in a nation?
(c) a standard that should be set by some international body like the United
Nations?
(d) a standard that exists independently of what individuals or nations
think, but to which the whole world should submit?
2.23 Is there one Chief Good that we should all seek in life? If so, what is it? Aris-
totle said it was happiness. Epicureans said it was pleasure. Stoics said it was
‘to live according to reason’. Christians say it is to serve God and to enjoy
him forever. What do you say?
2.24 List and explain the meaning of Aristotle’s Four Causes.
2.25 Consider a telescope:
If the Material Cause is the material(s) it is made of;
If the Efficient Cause is the manufacturer;
If the Formal Cause is its design, shape and the arrangement of its lenses,
What is its Final Cause?
2.26 Is it true that the Final Cause had to be in the mind of the maker before the
telescope began to be made? Would that be true of the universe as well?
2.27 Explain the meaning of the terms ‘potential’ and ‘actual’ in Aristotle’s
philosophy.
2.28 Is a human embryo already a human being? And ought it to be treated
as such?
2.29 Socrates, Plato and Aristotle all considered that there must be a Mind behind
the universe. Were they right?
2.30 What criticisms have been made of Aristotle’s concept of God? Are they fair?
Neoplatonic mysticism
2.31 What is meant by describing Plotinus’ philosophy as ‘negative theology’?
2.32 What, according to Plotinus, is the attitude of the One to human beings?
2.33 Why is reason, by itself, inadequate to discover what God is like?
2.34 In what respects is Plotinus’ philosophy similar to Hinduism?
2.35 Plotinus gained no knowledge of what God is like by his mysticism. Discuss.
2.36 What are the moral implications of Plotinus’ doctrine of reincarnation?
215
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
3.3 What is the difference between evidence that suggests that something may
be true and proof that something is true?
3.4 Would you agree that materialistic naturalism is an article of faith? Or do
you think that it can be proved that there is no supernatural realm? And if
so, how?
3.5 If mindless matter is the Ultimate Reality, how, do you think, did human
reason come to be? Do you think that your mind is composed of nothing
but mindless matter?
3.6 In a class or group study setting, debate the propositions set out against
materialistic naturalism on page 111.
3.7 What does Prof. Davies mean by ‘information theory’ and ‘complexity
theory’?
3.8 Where do you think the basic laws of physics come from originally? It has
taken great intelligence to discover and understand them; and it takes highly
sophisticated mathematics to express them. Do you agree with Prof. Davies
that they must have come from some intelligent source? Or do you find it
easier to suppose that they simply exist apart from reason?
Reactions to materialistic naturalism
3.9 Who were the Stoics? What attitude did they take to the atomic theory
of Leucippus and Democritus, and why?
3.10 What are some of the meanings of the Greek word logos?
3.11 What was the Stoic concept of God?
3.12 What does the New Testament mean by calling Jesus the Logos (John 1:1–3)?
How is this different from what the Stoics meant by logos?
3.13 The Stoic ideal was that human beings should live ‘according to Nature’.
What did they mean by that?
3.14 What moral difficulty is entailed in the Stoic idea that God is in everything?
3.15 ‘For Carl Sagan the Cosmos is a surrogate god’: What does this mean?
Do you agree?
3.16 What makes Prof. Davies describe life as a stupendously improbable
accident?
3.17 What is it about God that Prof. Davies doesn’t like? And why? What kind
of a God does he believe in?
3.18 Mathematical laws can help us to understand how the world works. Why
is it difficult to think that they could have created the world?
3.19 When it comes to whether we believe in God or not, to what extent are we
influenced by our personal likes and dislikes?
216
STUDY QUESTIONS FOR TEACHERS AND STUDENTS
4.3 According to the Bible, by what means was the universe made, and by what
means is it maintained?
4.4 What is meant by saying ‘In him was life, and the life was the light of men’
(John 1:4)?
4.5 In what various ways did God speak to the human race before the coming
of Christ?
4.6 Read from the Old Testament Isaiah 53. Discover when it was written. How
accurately, in your opinion, did it predict what happened to Jesus?
4.7 What evidence do the Old and New Testaments give that God is personal?
4.8 Do Christians believe in three Gods?
4.9 Jesus was certainly a man. Did he himself claim to be God as well?
4.10 What does the New Testament say is the significance of Christ’s death on the
cross?
4.11 According to the Bible, why do we need the Holy Spirit? What does he do
for us?
How we are related to Ultimate Reality
4.12 What is different between the Bible’s view of creation, and the other views
that we have covered in this section?
4.13 What is the Bible’s attitude to matter and to the human body?
4.14 What does the Bible mean by saying that man and woman were made in the
image of God? How should that affect our attitude to people?
4.15 What are the implications of saying that human beings are emanations
from God?
4.16 Sum up in your own words what Colossians 1:16–17 says about the relation
of the Son of God to creation.
4.17 Which two commandments did Christ describe as the greatest of all?
4.18 What is meant by saying that we are not robots? Is it true?
4.19 Most people consider themselves to be rational human beings. How then
would you account for the tragic mess that the world is in?
4.20 Do you think that everything in the universe is determined? Or would you
agree that it has a large degree of freedom and openness? Do you feel that
you are free to choose? If so, is that feeling true to the fact?
4.21 ‘Life is worth living.’ Discuss.
217
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
218
SCRIPTURE INDEX
Isaiah 3:16 91
5:35 137 n. 3
Ephesians
6 99 n. 49 1:13–14 139
8:9–20 63 n. 1 6:62 128
8:14 128
4:17–18 134
31:3 141
40:3–5 136 8:23 128 Philippians
45:5 49 8:26 128 3:21 140
45:12 49 14:9 137
45:18 49 14:10 137 n. 3 Colossians
14:17 139 1:16–17 142
Ezekiel 16:8–9 138 3:1–2 98
1–2 99 n. 49 16:14–15 138–9
16:28 128 1 Timothy
17:26 138 2:5 137
NEW TESTAMENT 20:28 132 6:16 141
220
GENERAL INDEX
222
GENERAL INDEX
223
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
224
GENERAL INDEX
225
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
226
GENERAL INDEX
S smriti 46
Sagan, Carl 28, 109, 117–18 sociology 4, 167
salvation 101–2, 121–2 Socrates 9, 11, 21, 64, 75–80, 81–2
Samkhya 47 and search for definitions 78–9
samsara 46, 48, 55. See also rebirth; and Ultimate Reality 79–80
reincarnation and virtue 77, 78
defined 48 and work 77–8
sat 54 sophists 82–3
Schaff, Adam 36–7 soul (human) 74–5, 83, 97–8
science 4, 15–16, 18–20, 26–9, 118–19, 147– transmigration of 102
79. See also scientific method Soul (World) 83, 92–3, 96, 97–8, 100–1,
defined 147–8 140
explanation 163–71 spirit (human) 75
and God as Creator 26–9 spiritism 63 n. 1
limitation of 19–20, 36–7, 150, 164, State, the 17
175, 178 stewardship 78, 140
presuppositions 171–9. See also Stoicism 59, 85, 92, 140. See also
presuppositions monism
scientific method 148–63 . See also concept of God 114–17
science Zeno of Citium 114
abduction 161–3 substance, primal 68–9
axioms 173–4 suffering, problem of 143
data collection 149–51, 156–9 summum bonum 21
deduction/inference 150, 154–6, 161–3 supernatural, the 109–10, 122, 164
experimentation 149, 150, 153, 178 Svetaketu 50
explanation 163–71 syllogism 155
falsifiability 159–60 syn (with) 131
hypotheses 149–51, 154–5, 156–9,
162–3 T
induction 150, 151–3, 154, 156 ‘tat tvam asi’ (‘thou art that’) 51, 52,
observation 149, 151–3, 154, 172, 178 140–1
paradigm shift 149, 177–9 telic view of things 87
repeatability 160–3 telos 164
trust 174 tension 69–70
Scotus Eriugena, John 105 Thales 63, 65–6, 68
Self (Hindu concept) 47–8, 49–52, 53–4, theios (divine) 132
59 n. 27, 98 . See also Brahman theism xiii, 13, 16, 24–9, 127–44,
self-consciousness 34 175–6 . See also atheism;
Seneca (Lucius Annaeus Seneca, dualism; monism; monotheism,
Seneca the Younger) 114 panentheism; pantheism;
sense (experience, perception) 29–30, polytheism
174 arguments against 143–4
SETI 28 divine revelation 132–6
Shankara 45, 47, 49–59, 60, 80, 94, 99, 139 God is knowable 127–39
Shiva 48, 59 n. 27 God is personal 136–9
shruti 46 humanity’s relation to God 139–43
significance, individual 35–6 worldview 178
Sikhism 45 theology 139, 167
sin 97, 101, 102, 129, 134, 135, 136, 138, negative 94, 103
140, 142–3 Theology of Aristotle 103–4
227
FINDING ULTIMATE REALITY
Theophrastus 32 Vedas 46
theory/theories 150–1, 154, 156, 172–3 Verification Principle 23, 159
theos (God) 65–6, 132 virgin birth 143
Thermodynamics, First Law of 111–12 virtue 77–8, 102
‘thou art that’ (‘tat tvam asi’) 51, 52, Vishnu 48, 59 n. 27
140–1 visions 98–9
touchstone 32–3 Vivekananda Swami 60
transmigration of souls 102 Vygotsky, Leo 167–8
Triad of major Hindu gods 48–9
Trinity, the 130, 132, 137–9 W
trust 174 Wallis, R. T. 97
truth 85 water 68, 70
Two Book view of revelation 26–7 Watson, James D. 147, 170
Whitehead, Sir Alfred North 27
U Wittgenstein, Ludwig 82 n. 21
Ultimate Reality xi, xii–xiii, 34–5, 49, work 48, 77–8
79–80 World Soul 83, 92–3, 96, 97–8, 100–1, 140
uniformity 175–6 worldview 3–9, 15–29
universe definition 8–9
fine-tuning of 70 theism 178
intelligibility of 175–6
origin of 120, 122, 160 X
rationality of 119 Xenophanes 65
Unmoved Mover, the 89–90, 112
Upanishads 46, 59 n. 27 Y
utopia 14–15, 23 Yoga 47
V Z
Vaisheskika 47 Zaehner, R. C. 54
Vedanta 47, 49–60 Zeno of Citium 114
228
ABOUT THE AUTHORS
�e �e�nition o� C��isti�nity
Who gets to determine what Christianity
means? Is it possible to understand its original
message aer centuries of tradition and
con�icting ideas? Gooding and Lennox throw
fresh light on these questions by tracing the
Book of Acts’ historical account of the message
that proved so effective in the time of Christ’s
apostles. Luke’s record of its confrontations
with competing philosophical and religious
systems reveals Christianity’s own original and
lasting de�nition.
Myrtlefield Encounters
These six volumes, totalling almost 2000 pages, were written by two
outstanding scholars who combine careers of research and teaching
at the highest levels. David Gooding and John Lennox cover well the
fields of Scripture, science, and philosophy, integrating them with
one voice. The result is a set of texts that work systematically through
a potpourri of major topics, like being human, discovering ultimate
reality, knowing truth, ethically evaluating life’s choices, answering
our deepest questions, plus the problems of pain and suffering. To get
all this wisdom together in this set was an enormous undertaking!
Highly recommended!
Gary R. Habermas, Distinguished Research Professor & Chair,
Dept. of Philosophy, Liberty University & Theological Seminary
David Gooding and John Lennox are exemplary guides to the deepest
questions of life in this comprehensive series. It will equip thinking
Christians with an intellectual roadmap to the fundamental conflict
between Christianity and secular humanism. For thinking seekers it
will be a provocation to consider which worldview makes best sense
of our deepest convictions about life.
Justin Brierley, host of the Unbelievable? radio show and podcast