Ziff (1951) Art and The Object of Art
Ziff (1951) Art and The Object of Art
Ziff (1951) Art and The Object of Art
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Mind.
http://www.jstor.org
BY PAUL ZIFF
PERHAPS the most persistentmy-th in presentday estheticsis
the notionthat whenwe discussa workofart we are nottalking
about a paintingb1utabout some " illusory" or " imaginary"
thing sometimescalled the " object of art" or the " esthetic
object ". I can best explain what this mythis by quotinga
statementof Samuel Alexander.
Morethan once I have pointedout how in the beautifulobject the
significanceis suppliedin partfromthe artist'smind; how it is he
whomakestheflatMadonnaseem,as Mr.Berensonputsit,a tangible
three-dimensional being,orwhogivesdivineplayfulness totheHermes,
or motionand dance to the motionless maidensin the pictureof the
Spring,or who findsthe perfect,the only fittingword,to express
a meaningthat springsfromhim, .. And I have contrasted
theobjectofartwiththemereperceptwherealso halfcomesfromthe
perceiver'smindand halffromwhat he directlysees: the coloured
movingshape is perceivedto be a man,thoughsightalone without
memorydoes not say so. The contrast. . . is this: the characters
we imputeto the object perceived,if we perceivecorrectly, really
do belongto the objectand maybe sensedthereon properoccasion;
the colouredshape is the visiblesurfaceof a man; but in the work
of art thereis alwaysillusion: the Hermesis not divineonly but
seemsso,andthegirlsintheSpringarenotinmotion.Atthesametime,
I haveadded,theartisticillusionis unlikeordinary perceptualillusion,
forthat-illusiondisappearsto betteracquaintance,is recognized to
be an illusion. Whereasthe illusionis ofthe essenceof the workof
art-ceases, therefore,to le illusionand makesthe objectsignificant.
Pieces,p. 259.
-Pilosoplical and Literary
Let me state the kind of thingAlexanderis talkingabout; for
even thoughhe expresseshimselfwith admirableclarity,it is
always usefulto statea pointin as simplea manneras is possible.
And let us take some particularexample,say, a Cezanne still-
life of some apples. When we describe Cezanne's painting
we may say 'the apples are solid, round full-volumes-like
tangible three-dimensionalthings. The painting has great
depth.' But a paintingis a thin stripof canvas coveredwith
tiny pellets of pigment. The canvas is flat,but the work of
art has great depth? Thus Alexanderarrivesat the viewthat
the workof art is distinctfromthe painting; forthe characters
we imputeto the paintingdo not reallybelongto it. We speak
of solid voluminousapples, but there are only thin pellets of
pigmenton the surfaceof the canvas. Thus thereis an illusion,
466
I
Firstofall we mustconsiderthe notionthatthereis an illusion
involved in observinga painting. This particular point is,
as we have alreadymentioned,somewhatpeculiarto Alexander.
For although other estheticiansclaim there is a discrepancy
between the characterswe impute to the painting and the
charactersit actually possesses,few are preparedto maintain
that thereis any illusionat workhere. Thus, even thoughwe
maysucceedin dispelling theillusionthatthereis illusioninvolved
in observinga painting,we shall not have dispelledthe more
significantand more momentousillusion that there is some
discrepancybetweenthe characterswe imputeto the painting
and the charactersthe paintingactuallypossesses. Nonetheless,
it is fruitfulto begin our discusssion
by pointingout that all
talk of illusionis whollymistaken. For althoughit does not
followfromthe fact that thereis no illusionat workhere,that
the characterswe impute to the paintingreally do belong to
look at it who didn't know what had been done, thenit would
look to him as thoughtherewas somethingon the otherside of
the painting. FFor all this is to say no morethan that if the
paintingdidn'tlook the way it does in factordinarily look,then
it mightlook as thoughtherewas somethingon the otherside of
the painting. And forall I know perhapswe could play such
trickswith paintings,but whetherit could be done or 'not is
totallyirrelevantto whatI am saying. For in sayingthat when
we look througha paintingit does not look as thoughthereis
somethingon the otherside of the painting,I am not talking
about what mightbe the case. I am talkingonly about what
is the case, and the factthat somethingelse mightbe the case
doesn'tin the least matter.
Thus, we may repeat,we have not as yet foundany evidence
whichwould warrantAlexander'sstatementthat " the illusion
is ofthe essenceofthe workofart ". Perhapsthisis due to the
fact that, as Alexanderstates, " the artisticillusionis unlike
ordinaryperceptualillusion". And we must admit that it is
unlikeordinaryperceptualillusion,verymuchunlikeit. Indeed,
so verymuchunlikeanythingwe ordinarily speak ofas an illusion
that, as yet, we haven't seen the slightestreason forspeaking
of it as an illusion. However,we need not labour this point.
It is clear that Alexanderdid thinksomethingdreadfullyqueer
was going on and he used the word 'illusion ' to describeit.
And one ofthethingsthathe,alongwithsomeotherestheticians,
finds dreadfullyqueer is the way we ordinarilytalk about
paintings. Here we have the real question.
II
The real question beforeus is, to use Alexander's terms,
whetherthe characterswe imputeto a paintingreallydo belong
to the painting or not. Alexander,along with some other
estheticians,claimsthat theydo not. Thus theyclaimthat we
oftensay thingsabout paintingswhichare not in facttrueofthe
paintings. Of course,theydo not claimthat none ofthe things
we say about paintingsare in facttrueofthe paintings,but only
that some of the.thingswe say about paintingsare not in fact
true. And what is more,it is the importarnt and interesting
thingswe say about paintingsthat are not in fact true. For
example,such statements- as 'The painting has great depth',
'The apples picturedare fullof solid volumes', etc.,are held to
to see one reason
be not in facttrue. Now it is not too difficult
why they are inclinedto say this. There are times when we