Unilog 2018 Handbook
Unilog 2018 Handbook
Unilog 2018 Handbook
UNILOG’2018
https://www.uni-log.org/vichy2018
Edited by
Jean-Yves Beziau, Arthur Buchsbaum and Christophe Rey,
with the assistance of Alvaro Altair and Yanis Ayari.
Editors:
Jean-Yves Beziau
Federal University of Rio de Janeiro
Rio de Janeiro, RJ
Brazil
Arthur Buchsbaum
Federal University of Santa Catarina
Florianópolis, SC
Brazil
Christophe Rey
Université Clermont Auvergne and LIMOS
Vichy and Clermont-Ferrand
France
ISBN: 978-2-9544948-1-4
Université Clermont Auvergne, Vichy, France, 2018
Contents
I Introduction 1
8 Tutorials 23
The Logic of Lying, by Franca D’Agostini . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
Topos theory and Caramello’s bridge technique, by Peter Arndt . . 26
Logic in the Brain, by Tal Dotan Ben-Soussan . . . . . . . . . . . . 28
The Adventures of the Turnstile ( ), by Jean-Yves Beziau . . . . 31
History of Medieval Logic, by Julie Brumberg-Chaumont . . . . . . 33
iii
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
iv
Contents
v
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
vi
Contents
14 Workshops 169
Logical Geometry and its Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169
Logical Oppositions in Avicenna’s Hypothetical Logic,
by Saloua Chatti . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171
On the Interaction of Tense and Aspect — Merging Kites,
by Dany Jaspers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172
Squares, Cubes and Circles. Sketches of Oppositional
Geometry between Geulincx and De Morgan,
by Jens Lemanski . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174
End of the square?, by Fabien Schang . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 176
Category Theory and Logical Geometry — Is a commutative
diagram an Aristotelian diagram?, by Daniel Wenz . . 177
Practices of Writing and Reading in Logic . . . . . . . . . . . 179
Logic as Subject and Method of a Logician’s Work,
by Moritz Cordes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180
Writing and Drawing in Logic — the Case of Aristotelian
Diagrams, by Lorenz Demey . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181
Teaching Begriffsschrift: Frege’s Notation and the Problems
of Pedagogy, by David Dunning . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 183
Practices of Writing and Reading in Logic: the 14th Century
case of Thomas Manlevelt, by Alfred van der Helm . . 184
Note on Paul Hertz and the Origins of the Sequent-Notation,
by Javier Legris . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186
vii
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
viii
Contents
ix
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
x
Contents
xi
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
xii
Contents
xiii
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
xiv
Contents
xv
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
15 Sessions 407
Universal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 407
Logics as models versus logics as proposals, by Pavel Arazim 407
Preservationist Consequence and Logical Pluralism,
by Bryson Brown . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 408
?
Universal Logic = Logic of the Universal, by Laurent Dubois . 410
Characterizing Context-Independent Logical Notions Among
the Context-Dependent Ones. The Case of
Quantifiers and Inferences, by Stanislaw Krajewski . . 411
Intensionality as a unifier: Logic, Language and Philosophy,
by Marı́a Manzano, Manuel A. Martins
& Manuel C. Moreno . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 413
Modular analysis of Hilbert calculi, by Sérgio Marcelino
& Carlos Caleiro . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 415
Semantics for combined Hilbert calculi, by Sérgio Marcelino
& Carlos Caleiro . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 416
On Dissent Pluralism and Paradigm-shifts from plural
perspectives, by Tony Marmo . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 417
Disjunctive and conjunctive multiple-conclusion consequence
relations, by Marek Nowak . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 418
S5 is a semi-bivalent logic, and so is classical logic,
by Fabien Schang . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 419
Internal Logic of the H-B topos and Universal Metalogic,
by Vladimir L. Vasyukov . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 421
Tarski: Logical Concepts as Invariants, by Jan Woleński . . . 422
Modal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 424
Polynomial Semantics for Normal Modal Logics,
by Juan C. Agudelo-Agudelo . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 424
Divided modality for Ockhamists, by Jacob Archambault . . . 425
Hypersequential Argumentation Frameworks:
An Instantiation in the Modal Logic S5,
by AnneMarie Borg and Ofer Arieli . . . . . . . . . . . 426
xvi
Contents
xvii
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
xviii
Contents
xix
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
xx
Contents
xxi
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
xxii
Contents
xxiii
Part I
Introduction
1
1 – Organizing, International Organizing
and Scientific Committees
Organizing Committee
Jean-Yves Beziau (Co-Chair), University of Brazil, Rio de Janeiro,
Brazil, and Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris, France
3
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı́ficas y Técnicas
4
Organizing, International Organizing and Scientific Committees
Scientific Committee
Arnon Avron, University of Tel-Aviv, Israel
5
2 – What is Universal Logic?
7
3 – Aim of the event
This is the 6th edition of a world event dedicated to universal logic called
“UNILOG”, standing for “World Congress and School on Universal Logic”.
Here is the list of previous UNILOGs:
9
4 – Call for papers
Scope of Validity
Domain of Applications of Fundamental Theorems
completeness
compactness
cut-elimination
deduction
interpolation
definability
incompleteness
decidability
Lindenbaum lemma
algebrization
Dugundji’s theorem
11
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
12
Part II
13
5 – Aim of the School
15
6 – ¿Why Study Logic?
*
Federal University of Rio de Janeiro
National Council for Scientific and Technological Development
17
7 – Speakers of the 6th World School
on Universal Logic
Jean-Yves Beziau
University of Brazil, Rio de Janeiro, Brazil
École Normale Supérieure, Paris, France
Julie Brumberg-Chaumont
CNRS* , Paris, France
European University Institute, Florence, Italy
Elena Ficara
Department of Philosophy, University of Paderborn, Germany
Jean-Baptiste Gourinat
Centre Leon Robin, Paris-Sorbonne University, France
*
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
Laboratoire d’Informatique, de Modélisation et d’Optimisation des Systèmes
19
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Alexei Muravitsky
Louisiana Scholars’ College, Northwestern State University,
Natchitoches, Louisiana, USA
Mykola Nikitchenko
Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv, Ukraine
20
Speakers of the 6th World School on Universal Logic
Jerzy Tomasik, LIMOS , CNRS§ , University for the Creative Arts, France
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique de Grenoble
Chief Technology Officer
Laboratoire d’Informatique, de Modélisation et d’Optimisation des Systèmes
§
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
21
8 – Tutorials
The recent literature about lying, deceiving, misleading and other forms
of deceit in philosophy of language is quite rich. The problem is also at the
centre of the public debate nowadays. (See the fortune of the concept of
“post-truth politics”, or the widespread worry concerning the circulation of
fake-news on the Internet.)
The tutorial aims at making the logic of deception clear, by stressing the
connection between the practice of deceptive processes and typically logical
issues related to the theme, such as the semantic behaviour of truth, the
inferential force of falsity and negation, and liar-like paradoxes.
23
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
1. L. Dobrez, J. Lyod Jones & P. Dobrez (editors), An ABC of Lying,
Australian Scholarly Publishing, Melbourne, 2004.
2. F. D’Agostini, Menzogna, Bollati Boringhieri, Turin, 2012, Spanish
translation: Mentira, Adriana Hidalgo Editora.
3. P. Eldridge-Smith, “The Cretan Liar Paradox”, in An ABC of Lying,
edited by L. Dobrez, J.L. Jones & P. Dobrez, Australian Scholarly Pub-
lishing, Melbourne, 2004, pp. 71–92.
4. P. Eldridge-Smith, “Pinocchio against the dialetheists”, Analysis,
vol. 71(2), 2011, pp. 306–308.
5. P. Eldridge-Smith, “Pinocchio beards the Barber”, Analysis, vol. 72(4),
2012, pp. 749–752.
6. V. Eldridge-Smith & P. Eldridge-Smith, “The Pinocchio paradox”, Anal-
ysis, vol. 70(2), 2010, pp. 212–215.
7. H. Field, Saving Truth from Paradox, Oxford University Press, 2008.
8. I. Kant, “Theorie-Werkausgabe”, in Werke in zwölf Bänden, Bd. VIII,
Frankfurt a.M., 1968.
9. J. Lackey, Learning From Words. Testimony as a Source of Knowledge,
Oxford University Press, 2008.
10. J. Lackey, “Lies and deception: an unhappy divorce”, Analysis,
vol. 73(2), 2013.
11. J.E. Mahon, “The Definition of Lying and Deception”, in The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E.N. Zalta, 2016, https://plato.
stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/lying-definition.
12. N. Marsili, “Lying as a Scalar Phenomenon: Insincerity along the Cer-
tainty-Uncertainty Continuum”, in Certainty-uncertainty — and the
Attitudinal Space in Between, edited by S. Cantarini, W. Abraham &
E. Leiss, John Benjamins Publishing, 2014.
13. G. Orwell, Nineteen Eighty-Four, Secker & Warburg, London, 1949.
14. J. Saul, “Did Clinton say something false?”, Analysis, vol. 60, 2000,
pp. 255–257.
24
Tutorials
15. J. Saul, Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, Oxford University Press,
2012.
16. J. Saul, “Just go ahead and lie”, Analysis, vol. 72(1), 2012.
17. R.A. Sorensen, “Permission to Cheat”, Analysis, vol. 67(295), 2007,
pp. 205–214.
18. R.A. Sorensen, “Bald-faced Lies! Lying without the intent to deceive”,
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 88(2), 2007, pp. 251–264.
19. R.A. Sorensen, “Knowledge-Lies”, Analysis, vol. 70(4), 2010,
pp. 608–615.
20. J. Webber, “Liar!”, Analysis, vol. 73(4), 2013.
21. B. Williams, Truth and Truthfulness. An Essay in Genealogy, Princeton
University Press, 2002.
25
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
26
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. O. Caramello, Theories, Sites, Toposes: Relating and studying math-
ematical theories through topos-theoretic ‘bridges’, Oxford University
Press, 2017.
2. O. Caramello, Grothendieck toposes as unifying ‘bridges’ in Mathemat-
ics, habilitation thesis, University of Paris 7, 2016.
3. S. MacLane & I. Moerdijk, Sheaves in Geometry and Logic, Springer,
1994.
4. M. Makkai & G. Reyes, First-Order Categorical Logic: Model-Theoretical
Methods in the Theory of Topoi and Related Categories, Lecture Notes
in Mathematics book series, vol. 611, Springer, 1977.
27
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
28
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. T.D. Ben-Soussan, J. Glicksohn & A. Berkovich-Ohana, “From cerebel-
lar activation and connectivity to cognition: a review of the Quadrato
Motor Training”, BioMed Research International, Article ID 954901,
2015, 11 pages.
29
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
30
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. J.-Y. Beziau, “Rules, derived rules, permissible rules and the various
types of systems of deduction”, in Proof, Types and Categories, edited
by E.H. Hauesler & L.C. Pereira, Pontifical Catholic University of Rio
de Janeiro, 1999, pp. 159–184.
2. J.-Y. Beziau, “From Consequence Operator to Universal Logic: A Sur-
vey of General Abstract Logic”, in Logica Universalis: Towards a Gen-
eral Theory of Logic, Birkhäuser, Basel, 2005, pp. 3–17.
3. J.-Y. Beziau, “La Puissance du Symbole”, in La Pointure du Symbole,
edited by J.-Y. Beziau, Petra, Paris, 2014, pp. 9–34.
4. C.J. Ducasse and H.B. Curry, “Early History of the Association for
Symbolic Logic”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 27(3), 1962,
pp. 255–258.
5. V.H. Dudman, “Frege’s Judgement-Stroke”, The Philosophical Quar-
terly, vol. 20(79), 1970, pp. 150–161.
6. D. Greimann, “The Judgement-Stroke as a Truth-Operator: A New
Interpretation of the Logical Form of Sentences in Frege’s Scientific
Language”, Erkenntnis, vol. 52(2), 2000, pp. 213–238.
7. S. Leśniewski “On some questions regarding the sense of the logistic the-
ses”, in Stanislaw Leśniewski: Collected Works, edited by S.J. Surma,
J.T.J. Srzednicki, J.D. Barnett & V.F. Rickey, 2 volumes, Springer,
1992, pp. 181–196.
8. F. Rombout, Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein on the Judgment Stroke,
MSc thesis, University of Amsterdam, 2011, https://goo.gl/k55sGg.
9. N.J.J. Smith, “Frege’s Judgement Stroke”, Australasian Journal of Phi-
losophy, vol. 78(2), 2000, pp. 153–175.
10. N.J.J. Smith, “Frege’s Judgement Stroke and the Conception of Logic as
the Study of Inference not Consequence”, Philosophy Compass,
vol. 4(4), 2009, pp. 639–665.
32
Tutorials
33
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
34
Tutorials
35
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
1. Boethius, De Differentiis Topicis, translation by E. Stump, Ithaca, Lon-
don, 1978.
2. John Buridan, Summulae de Dialectica, translation by G. Klima, New
Haven, London, 2001.
3. John Buridan, Treatise on Consequences, translation by S. Read, Ford-
ham University Press, 2014.
4. C. Duthil Novaes & S. Read (editors), The Cambridge Companion to
Medieval Logic, edited by C. Duthil-Novaes & S. Read, Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2016.
5. S. Ebbesen, Greek-Latin Philosophical Interaction, Routledge, 2008.
6. N.J. Green-Pedersen, The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages,
Philosophia, Munich and Vienna, 1984.
7. R. Kilwardby, Notule Libri Priorum, text and translation by P. Thom
& J. Scott, Oxford University Press, 2015.
8. G. Klima, John Buridan, Oxford University Press, 2009.
9. William of Ockham, Ockham’s Theory of Terms: Part I of the Summa
Logicae, translation by M.J. Loux, University of Notre Dame Press,
1974.
10. P.V. Spade (editor and translator), Five Texts on the Mediaeval Prob-
lem of Universals: Porphyry, Boethius, Abelard, Duns Scotus, Ockham,
Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, 1994.
Useful Links
Peter Abelard (SEP* )
Peter Abelard (IEP )
Buridan (SEP)
Ockham (SEP)
Ockham (IEP)
Consequence — Medieval (SEP)
Insolubles (SEP)
Medieval Terms (SEP)
Medieval Logic and Philosophy
Medieval Logic — Special Issue of Logica Universalis
*
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
36
Tutorials
Lindenbaum Method
Alex Citkin
Metropolitan Telecommunications, USA
[email protected]
Alexei Muravitsky
Louisiana Scholars’ College,
Northwestern State University, USA
[email protected]
During his brief life, the Polish mathematician and logician Adolf Lin-
denbaum (*1904–1941) contributed to mathematical logic, among other
things, by several significant achievements. Some results of Lindenbaum’s,
which bear his name, were published without proofs by other people from
the Lvov-Warsaw School and the proofs later were provided by some oth-
ers, though the authorship of Lindenbaum has never been challenged. Many
may have heard about Lindenbaum’s lemma, asserting the existence of Lin-
denbaum’s extension, and Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra; less known is Lin-
denbaum’s logical matrix. This tutorial is devoted to the two last concepts
rather than the first one. However, the latter can be understood in a purely
algebraic fashion, if one employs the notion of Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra.
In general, the notions of Lindenbaum matrix and Lindenbaum–Tarski al-
gebra have paved a way to further algebraization of logic, which had been
begun by George Boole in the 19th century, as well as to a new branch of
logic, model theory. For this reason, the present tutorial is also a gentle
introduction to algebraic logic.
A uniting idea of the aforementioned concepts is a special view on the for-
mal judgments of a formal language. It is this view we call the Lindenbaum
method. Although Lindenbaum expressed merely a starting viewpoint in
the tradition of Polish logic of the time, this viewpoint became a standard
ever since and its development goes on until this day, continuing to shape
the field of algebraic logic. Our main objective is to demonstrate how this
view gave rise to formulating the aforementioned concepts and how it opens
door to unexplored paths.
37
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
38
Tutorials
theorems (J. Kalicki for matrices, A. Citkin for bundles); whether any de-
ductive system formulated in a countable formal language can be determined
by a single denumerable matrix (A. Wrónski). Some of these problems and
related to them, as well as the finite model property of a system, will be
discussed in this part.
Bibliography
1. A. Citkin, “On an effective problem concerning mutual adequacy of
two finite truth-tables” (in Russian), in Proceedings of the Fourth Con-
ference on the Occasion of the 30th Anniversary of the Liberation of
Carpathians, Užgorod, USSR, 1975.
2. A. Citkin & A. Muravitsky, “Lindenbaum method (propositional lan-
guage)”, arXiv:1609.07379, Cornell University Library, 2016.
3. J. Czelakowski, Model-Theoretic Methods in Methodology of Proposi-
tional Calculi, Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, The Polish
Academy of Sciences, Warsaw, 1980.
4. J.-M. Font, Abstract Algebraic Logic, College Publications, London,
2016.
5. J. Kalicki, “A test for the equality of truth-tables”, The Journal of
Symbolic Logic, vol. 17(3), 1952, pp. 161–163.
6. J. Lo’s & R. Suszko, “Remarks on sentential logics”, Koninklijke Ne-
derlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings, Ser. A, vol. 61,
1958, pp. 177–183, also in Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 20, 1958,
pp. 177–183.
7. J.C.C. McKinsey & A. Tarski, “Some theorems about the sentential cal-
culi of Lewis and Heyting”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 13(1),
1948, pp. 1–15.
8. A. Muravitsky, “Beyond Rasiowan Systems: Unital Deductive Sys-
tems”, Logica Universalis, vol. 8(1), 2014, pp. 83–102.
9. W. Pogorzelski & P. Wojtylak, Completeness Theory for Propositional
Logics, Birkhäuser, 2000.
10. H. Rasiowa, An Algebraic Approach to Non-Classical Logics, North-
Holland, 1974.
11. A. Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Papers from 1923 to
1938, translated by J.H. Woodger, Clarendon Press, 1956.
12. R. Wójcicki, Theory of Logical Calculi: Basic Theory of Consequence
Operations, Springer, 1988.
13. A. Wrónski, “On cardinalities of matrices strongly adequate for the intu-
itionistic propositional logic”, Bulletin of the Section of Logic, vol. 3(1),
1974, pp. 67–72.
39
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Useful Links
Encyclopedia of Mathematics
— Lindenbaum method (propositional language)
— Abstract algebraic logic
— Decision problem
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
— Lindenbaum
— Logical consequence
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
— Algebraic propositional logic
— Lvov-Warsaw school
— Logical consequence
— Truth values
40
Tutorials
41
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
any sentence in its language, whether that sentence is provable from its ax-
ioms: the theory is undecidable. Presburger arithmetic is the well known
first-order theory of the natural numbers with addition and equality. The
axioms include the schema of induction. It is much weaker than Peano
arithmetic and has been proved to be decidable. However the algorithms
for decision require more than exponential run time. Stronger fragments
than Presburger arithmetic have been proved to be decidable, e.g. the ex-
istential theory of addition and divisibility. Decidable fragments of Peano
arithmetic are more and more involved in automatic reasoning.
II. Definability
Let us consider a set on words on a finite alphabet with k letters denoting
as digits {0, 1, 2, ..., k − 1}. There is a natural correspondence between such
words and natural numbers using base k representation. Let us now consider
the set of words recognizable by a finite automaton. It turns out that
the correspondent set of integers is definable by a formula of the language
(+, Vk ), where z = Vk (x) is the relation “z is the greatest power of k dividing
x”. The converse is true. This correspondence provides insight in the area
of complexity: a relation which is definable both in (+, Vk ) and (+, Vk′ ) for
m
which there is no n and m such that k n = k ′ is definable in Presburger
arithmetic.
Other correspondence are sources of problem or of solutions! The unary
relation “x is not prime nor 0 nor 1” is definable using the formula
∃u < x ∃v < x (x = u × v). More generally, the ∆0 -definability is essen-
tially definability with a formula in the language of arithmetic where the
quantified variables are bounded by terms. Most of the natural notions
have been proved to be ∆0 -definable, and classical diagonalization meth-
ods provide ad hoc non ∆0 -definable ones. A major open problem is to
find a “natural” arithmetical relation which is NOT ∆0 -definable. The
relation z = Card{i ≤ y ∣ i is a prime number} is not known to be ∆0 -
definable and is a candidate. An answer could provide the strict inclusion
LOGSPACE ⊊ LINSPACE.
III. Provability
Let E be a subset of Nn , for which there exists an algorithm that will
ultimately halt when a member of the set is provided as input, but may
continue indefinitely when the input is a non-member. There is a ∆0 -formula
ϕ such that E is defined by (∃y ∈ Nm ) (ϕ(x, y) = 0). This very last formula
is called a Σ1 −formula. The fundamental step of the answer to problem 1
42
Tutorials
43
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Dialectics. An Introduction
Elena Ficara
Department of Philosophy, University of Paderborn, Germany
[email protected]
44
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. T.W. Adorno, Negative Dialektik, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 1966.
2. T.W. Adorno, Einführung in die Dialektik, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 2010.
3. L. Apostel, “Logica e dialettica in Hegel”, in La formalizzazione della
dialettica, edited by D. Marconi, Rosenberg & Sellier, Turin, 1979,
pp. 85–113.
4. J. Barnes (editor), The Complete Works of Aristotle, Princeton Univer-
sity Press, 1984.
5. E. Berti, Contraddizione e dialettica negli antichi e nei moderni, Mor-
celliana, Brescia, Italy, 1987.
6. F. Berto, Che cosa é la dialettica Hegeliana? Un’interpretazione anali-
tica del metodo, Il Poligrafo, Padua, Italy, 2005.
45
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
46
Tutorials
47
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The aim of this tutorial is to present Stoic logic. Stoic logic is probably
the most important step in the history of logic between Aristotle and Frege.
Not only does it have an historical importance but it is also still worth read-
ing and studying for its fascinating insights, even if the fragmentary state
of the evidence does not allow to know all the refined details of their theory.
The tutorial will present the main sources and their alternative interpreta-
tions to give an idea as accurate as possible of the nature of Stoic logic.
Everybody interested in logic and ancient philosophy is welcome to join.
There is no specific prerequisites. The tutorial will be divided in the follow-
ing three sessions.
I. Stoic semantics
This part will be devoted to an overview of Stoic semantics: the Stoics
distinguished between the vocal sound, for instance ‘Dion’, the real object
of the world bearing the name, for instance the man called Dion, and an
intermediate incorporeal entity, which they called the ‘sayable’ (lekton) and
which they described as the signification of the vocal sound. An alternative
presentation distinguish between what is signified by a common or proper
name (‘man’, ‘horse’, ‘Dion’, ‘Socrates’), namely a quality (and not a sub-
stance as in Aristotle) and what is signified by a verb (‘walks’, ‘talks’),
namely, according to the Stoics, a predicate or ‘what happens’ to someone.
We will examine the logical and philosophical implications of these alterna-
tive presentations of Stoic semantic theory and the status of the ‘sayable’.
48
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. H. von Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, volume 2 of Chrysippi
fragmenta logica et physica, Teubner, Leipzig, 1905.
2. M. Frede, Die stoische Logik, Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, Göttingen,
Germany, 1974.
3. G. Gabriel, K. Huelser & S. Schlotter, “Zur Miete bei Frege: Rudolf
Hirzel und die Rezeption der stoischen Logik und Semantik in Jena”,
History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 30(4), 2009, pp. 369–388.
4. J.-B. Gourinat, La dialectique des stoiciens, Vrin, Paris, 2000.
5. K. Huelser, Die Fragmente zur Dialektik der Stoiker, 4 volumes,
Frommann-Holzboog, Stuttgart, Germany, 1987.
6. A.A. Long & D.N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers, Cambrige Uni-
versity Press, 1987.
7. Jan Lukasiewicz, “Zur Geschichte der Aussagenlogik”, Erkenntnis,
vol. 5(1), 1935, pp. 111–131.
8. B. Mates, Stoic Logic, California University Press, 1953.
49
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
This tutorial will bring together two subjects that are not normally dis-
cussed together, namely the inconsistency theory of truth and nominalistic
philosophies of mathematics.
Session 1
According to the inconsistency theory of truth, our conflicting intuitions
when it comes to determining the truth value(s) of the Liar Sentence and its
siblings are due to the fact that the linguistic rules for the truth predicate
are inconsistent. This was first argued by Chihara [2] and later by Eklund
[5] and Scharp [10]. I will explain this solution to the semantic paradoxes
and provide what I believe to be the best defence of it. Doing so involves
bringing in Lewis’ [8] theory of language conventions and Nagel’s [9] idea of
a view from nowhere.
Session 2
One conclusion from session 1 will be that we, as a language community,
have a high degree of freedom to decide by convention on what logic to use,
roughly in the sense of Carnap [1]. This puts the many formal theories of
truth that have been proposed in a new light: they can be evaluated on the
basis of how useful they would be as potential conventions, rather than on
the basis of whether they are correct. From this perspective, we will take
a closer look at Kripke’s theory of truth [7] and van Fraasen’s concept of
supervaluation [11]. Then we will tinker a little with the possible convention
they in effect describe until we get something that is useful for mathematics.
Session 3
The idea of a nominalistic mathematics is to give a philosophical account
of what mathematics is that does not inflate our ontology with ad-hoc ab-
stract objects. Chihara [3,4] proposed that we can do so by constructing
50
Tutorials
Prerequisites
I will assume a basic acquaintance with the Liar Paradox and philosophy
of mathematics. Session 3 in addition presupposes knowledge of Cantor’s
theorem about the cardinality of the set of the real numbers and of mathe-
matical analysis up to and including the Fundamental Theorem of Analysis.
Bibliography
1. R. Carnap, Logische Syntax der Sprache, Springer, 1934.
2. C. Chihara, “The semantic paradoxes: A diagnostic investigation”,
Philosophical Review, vol. 88(4), 1979, pp. 590–618.
3. C. Chihara, Constructibility and Mathematical Existence, Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1990.
4. C. Chihara, A Structural Account of Mathematics, Oxford University
Press, 2004.
5. M. Eklund, “Inconsistent languages”, Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, vol. 64(2), 2002, pp. 251–275.
6. H. Field, Science Without Numbers, Princeton University Press, 1980.
7. S. Kripke, “Outline of a theory of truth”, The Journal of Philosophy,
vol. 72(19), 1975, pp. 690–716.
8. D. Lewis, Conventions, Harvard University Press, 1969.
9. T. Nagel, The View from Nowhere, Oxford University Press, 1986.
10. K. Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford University Press, 2013.
11. B. van Fraassen, “Singular terms, truth-value gaps, and free logic”, The
Journal of Philosophy, vol. 63(17), 1966, 481–495.
51
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
These reactions show that Aristotle’s defence of PNC is, at worst, not
understood or, at best, not taken seriously. The aim of this tutorial will
be to answer this concern by accounting for Aristotle’s method. We shall
explain why PNC is defendable only as a true opinion, even though it is said
to be the most certain principle of all, and we shall conclude that Aristotle’s
weak defence of PNC is perfectly compatible with the postulate of PNC as
a strong axiom.
52
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. J. Barnes, “The Law of Contradiction”, Philosophical Quarterly,
vol. 19(77), 1969, pp. 302–309.
2. S.M. Cohen, “Aristotle on the Principle of Non-Contradiction”, Cana-
dian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 16(3), 1986, pp. 359–370.
53
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Useful Links
Aristotle on Non-Contradiction (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Wikipedia)
Library of Ancient Texts Online (Google)
54
Tutorials
55
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
van Fraasen and others. We finish the presentation with three different
theories developed on the ground of modal logic by Thomason and Garson,
Goldblatt, Fitting and Mendelsohn.
Bibliography
1. R. Carnap, Meaning and Necessity , University of Chicago Press, 1947.
2. M. Fitting & R.L. Mendelsohn, First-Order Modal Logic, Kluwer, 1998.
3. J.M. Garson, Modal Logic for Philosophers, Cambridge University Press,
2006.
4. R. Goldblatt, Quantifiers, Propositions and Identity, Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2011.
5. D. Kalish & R. Montague, “Remarks on Descriptions and Natural De-
duction”, Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung,
vol. 3, 1957, pp. 50–73.
6. K. Lambert, “Free Logic and Definite Descriptions”, in New Essays
in Free Logic — In Honour of Karel Lambert, edited by E. Morscher
& A. Hieke, Springer, 2001, pp. 37–47.
7. S. Negri & J. von Plato, Structural Proof Theory, Cambridge University
Press, 2001.
8. F.J. Pelletier & B. Linsky, “What is Frege Theory of Descriptions?”, in
On Denoting: 1905-2005, edited by B. Linsky & G. Imaguire, Philoso-
phia Verlag, 2005, pp. 195–250.
9. B. Russell, “On Denoting”, Mind, New Series, vol. 14(56), 1905,
pp. 479–493.
56
Tutorials
57
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Conceptual Engineering:
A Systematic Unified Framework
Manuel Gustavo Isaac
Swiss National Science Foundation
Department of Philosophy,
University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands
[email protected]
We use concepts all the time to make sense of reality. The quality of
our cognition thereby crucially depends on that of our conceptual schemes
and repertoires, so that: the better our concepts are, the better our cognitive
activities will be. Conceptual engineering is the fast-moving research field
[3,5,6] that means to provide a method to assess, criticize, and improve any
of our concepts working as such cognitive devices [4,5,10,13] [see also 18,20],
that is: to identify conceptual deficiencies, elaborate ameliorative strategies,
and prescribe normative guidelines as to whether and how to use a concept
(vs. to describe how it works as a matter of fact) [1,4,5,19,20]. The aim
of the SUFCE tutorial is to provide a systematic overview of conceptual
engineering, to be divided into three sessions:
S1: Research Program. The first session of the tutorial will intro-
duce the overall research program of conceptual engineering: its starting
point, its main goal and objectives, along with its most pressing chal-
lenges [6]. A typology of its main variants will be presented, [e.g. 3,5,17]
and the standard objections against them will be critically analyzed,
[e.g. 12] [cf. 18,20].
58
Tutorials
60
Tutorials
61
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Short Bibliography
1. P. Joray, “Teaching Leśniewski’s Protothetic with a Natural Deduc-
tion System”, in Fourth International Conference on Tools for Teaching
Logic, TTL 2015, Rennes, France, June 9–12, 2015.
2. P. Joray, “La définition dans les systèmes logiques de Lukasiewicz,
Leśniewski et Tarski”, in La Philosophie en Pologne: 1918–1939, edited
by R. Pouivet & M. Rebuschi, Vrin, Paris, 2006, pp. 203–222.
3. P. Joray, “Axiomatiques minimales et définitions. La thèse de Tarski sur
le calcul biconditionnel”, Travaux de Logique, vol. 20, 2011, pp. 57–83.
62
Tutorials
63
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Logic of Desires
Emiliano Lorini
IRIT* , CNRS , LILaC Team,
Université Paul Sabatier, Toulouse, France
[email protected]
The first session of the tutorial will devoted to discuss the logic of desires in
opposition to the logics of knowledge and belief (epistemic logic and doxastic
logic).
The second session of the tutorial will be devoted to the problems of pref-
erence generation and intention formation: (i) how preferences of agents are
determined both by her desires and by her moral values, and (ii) how beliefs and
preferences determine choices and are responsible for the formation of new in-
tentions about present actions (present-directed intentions) and future actions
(future- directed intentions).
The third session will be devoted to the dynamic aspects of desires including
desire expansion and desire revision as well as the connection between desire
and belief change, on the one hand, and preference change on the other hand.
*
Institut de Recherche en Informatique de Toulouse
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
Logic, Interaction, Language and Computation
64
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. D. Dubois, E. Lorini & H. Prade, “The Strength of Desires: a Logical
Approach”, Minds and Machines, forthcoming.
2. E. Lorini, “A logic for reasoning about moral agents”, Logique et Ana-
lyse , vol. 58(230), 2016, pp. 177–218.
3. E. Lorini & A. Herzig, “A logic of intention and attempt”, Synthese,
vol. 163(1), 2008, pp. 45–77.
65
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
66
Tutorials
67
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
algorithms but rather by very simple logical properties of the model, namely
that a type of quantifier can be relativised to a specific constant of the model.
We will discuss in particular the case of equality free positive first-order
logic (fragment ∃ ∀ ∧ ∨) a fragment for which one obtains a tetrachotomy
governed by the surjective hyper endormorphisms of the model.
Bibliography
1. T. Feder & M.Y. Vardi, Monotone monadic SNP and constraint satis-
faction, in Proceedings of the 25th annual ACM * Symposium on Theory
of Computing, STOC, 1993.
2. Th.J. Schaefer, “The Complexity of Satisfiability Problems”, Proceed-
ings of the 10th annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing,
STOC 1978.
3. F.R. Madelaine & B. Martin, “On the complexity of the model checking
problem”, arXiv:1210.6893, Cornell University Library, 2012.
4. F.R. Madelaine & B. Martin, “The complexity of positive first-order
logic without equality”, ACM Transactions on Computational Logic,
vol. 13(1), article no. 5, 2012, arXiv:1003.0802.
*
Association for Computing Machinery
Symposium on Theory of Computing
68
Tutorials
Related Surveys
1. H. Chen, “A rendezvous of logic, complexity, and algebra”, ACM Com-
puting Surveys, vol. 42(1), article no 2, 2009, arXiv:cs/0611018.
2. H. Chen, “Meditations on Quantified Constraint Satisfaction”, in Logic
and Program Semantics: Essays Dedicated to Dexter Kozen on the Oc-
casion of His 60th Birthday, edited by R.L. Constable & A. Silva, Pal-
grave Macmillan, 2012, pp. 35–49, arXiv:1201.6306.
3. B. Martin, “Quantified Constraints in Twenty Seventeen”, in The Con-
straint Satisfaction Problem: Complexity and Approximability, edited
by A. Krokhin & S. Zivny, Dagstuhl, Germany, 2017, pp. 327–346,
https://goo.gl/qj6sz1.
*
Association for Computing Machinery
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers
69
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
70
Tutorials
71
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Selected Bibliography
1. B. Martelli, An Introduction to Geometric Topology, University of Pisa,
Italy, 2016.
2. S. & R. Piergallini, “The Complex of Pant Decompositions of a Surface”,
Topology and its Applications, vol. 156(2), 2008, pp. 399–419.
3. R. Burch, A Peircean Reduction Thesis: The Foundations of Topological
Logic, Texas Tech University Press, Lubbock, Texas, 1991.
4. M. Dehn, Papers on Group Theory and Topology, translations and in-
troduction by J. Stillwell, Springer, 1987.
5. F. Harary, Graph Theory, Addison-Wesley, 1969.
6. A. Hatcher, Algebraic Topology, Cambridge University Press, 2001.
7. K.L. Ketner, “Peirce’s “Most Lucid and Interesting Paper”: An In-
troduction to Cenopythagoreanism”, International Philosophical Quar-
terly, vol. 26(4), 1986, pp. 375–392.
8. J.M. Lee, Introduction to Topological Manifolds, Springer, 2011.
9. Charles Sanders Peirce, The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce,
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 6 volumes, 1932.
10. Charles Sanders Peirce, The Logic of Interdisciplinarity: The Monist
Series, edited by H. van Elise Bisons, Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 2009.
11. Charles Sanders Peirce, Reasoning and the Logic of Things, edited by
K.L. Ketner, introduction by K.L. Ketner & H. Putnam, Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1992.
12. Charles Sanders Peirce, Semiotics and Significs: The Correspondence
between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby, edited by Ch.S.
Hardwick with assistance of J. Cook, The Press of Arisbe Associates,
Elsah, Illinois, USA, 2001.
13. D.D. Roberts, Existential Graphs of Charles S. Peirce, Mouton & Co.,
The Hague, The Netherlands, 1973.
14. J. Stillwell, Classical Topology and Combinatorial Group Theory,
Springer, 1980.
15. F. Zalamea, The Logic of Continuity, Docent Press, Boston, 2012.
72
Tutorials
Useful Links
Charles Peirce Society
Peirce.org
Centro de Sistemática Peirceana
Grupo de Estudios Peirceano
Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism
Helsinki Peirce Research Centre
Centro de Estudos de Pragmatismo, São Paulo, Brazil
Charles Sanders Peirce: Logic, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
73
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Wittgenstein’s Logic
Giovanni Mion
Department of Humanities and Social Sciences,
Istanbul Technical University, Turkey
[email protected]
Erik Thomsen
CTO* at Blender Logic, Cambridge, Mass, USA
[email protected]
I. Quantification
In the first section, we will explore Wittgenstein’s account of quantifi-
cation. See in particular sections 5.3, 5.501 and 5.52 of the Tractatus.
II. Decidability
In the second section, we will explore Wittgenstein’s philosophy of logic.
In particular, we will focus on Wittgenstein’s claim that “proof in logic is
merely a mechanical expedient to facilitate the recognition of tautologies in
complicated cases” (6.1262). See also section 6.1203.
74
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. E.B. Allaire, “Tractatus 6.3751”, Analysis, vol. 19(5), 1959,
pp. 100–105.
2. E. Anscombe, An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Hutchinson
University Library, 1959.
3. R. Fogelin, Wittgenstein, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976.
4. P. Frascolla, Understanding Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Routledge, 2006.
5. P.T. Geach, “Wittgenstein’s Operator N”, Analysis, vol. 41(4), 1981,
pp. 168–171.
6. P.T. Geach, “More on Wittgenstein’s Operator N”, Analysis, vol. 42(3),
1981, pp. 127–128.
7. P. Hacker, Insight and Illusion, Oxford University Press, 1972.
8. A. Kenny, Wittgenstein, Blackwell, 1973/2006.
9. F.P. Ramsey, “Critical Notice of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus”,
Mind, vol. 32(128), 1923, pp. 465-478.
10. S. Soames, “Generality, Truth Functions, and Expressive Capacity in
the Tractatus”, The Philosophical Review, vol. 92(4), 1983,
pp. 573–589.
11. F. Waismann, The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy, Macmillan, 1965.
75
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In the last decade, the increasing amounts of available data, which may
be large, complex, heterogeneous and/or incomplete, have deeply impacted
the field. How to better access data by incorporating knowledge, typically
expressed in ontologies, has become a crucial issue, at the crossroad of KR
and data management. On the KR side, the challenge was to tackle a new
reasoning task, namely querying data (whereas classical KR problems such
as consistency checking or classification can be recast as very specific query
answering problems), which required to find new languages and algorithmic
techniques offering various tradeoffs between expressivity and tractability
of reasoning. On the data management side, the challenge was rather to ex-
tend query answering techniques to take into account knowledge. The issue
of querying data while taking into account inferences enabled by an ontol-
ogy has received several names, it will be called ontology-mediated query
answering in this talk. It can also be seen as querying a knowledge base,
composed of an ontology and a (possibly virtual) fact base linked to data
sources.
76
Tutorials
Bibliography
1. J.-F. Baget, M. Leclère, M.-L. Mugnier & E. Salvat, “On rules with ex-
istential variables: Walking the decidability line”, Artificial Intelligence,
vol. 175(9-10), 2011, pp. 1620–1654.
2. M. Bienvenu & M. Ortiz, “Ontology-Mediated Query Answering with
Data-Tractable Description Logics”, in 11th International Summer
School, Berlin, Germany, July 31–August 4, 2015, Tutorial Lectures,
Reasoning Web. Web Logic Rules, Lecture Notes in Computer Science
book series, vol. 9203, Springer, pp. 218–307.
3. D. Calvanese, G. De Giacomo, D. Lembo, M. Lenzerini & R. Rosati,
“Tractable Reasoning and Efficient Query Answering in Description
Logics: The DL-Lite Family”, Journal of Automated Reasoning,
vol. 39(3), 2007, pp. 385–429.
4. Th. Lukasiewicz, A. Cali & G. Gottlob, “A General Datalog-Based
Framework for Tractable Query Answering over Ontologies”, Journal
of Web Semantics, vol. 14, 2012, pp. 57–83.
77
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
78
Tutorials
The aim of this tutorial is to acquaint attendees with the primary models
of program semantics; to present logics based on formal program models; to
study relationship between such logics; to discuss applicability of program
logics in program analysis and verification.
The main questions to be discussed during the first session are a short
review of program-oriented logics and main methods of description of formal
semantics of programs:
denotational semantics in style of Scott-Strachey;
operational semantics in style of Gordon D. Plotkin;
axiomatic semantics in style of Floyd-Hoare.
79
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
1. H.R. Nielson & F. Nielson, Semantics with Applications: A Formal
Introduction, John Wiley & Sons, 1992.
2. C.A.R. Hoare, “An axiomatic basis for computer programming”, Com-
munications of the ACM, vol. 12(1), 1969, pp. 576–580.
3. D. Sannella & A. Tarlecki, Foundations of Algebraic Specification and
Formal Software Development, Springer, 2012.
4. M. Nikitchenko & S. Shkilniak, Applied Logic (in Ukrainian), Publishing
House of Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv, Ukraine, 2013.
5. A. Kryvolap, M. Nikitchenko & W. Schreiner, “Extending Floyd-Hoare
Logic for Partial Pre- and Postconditions”, in International Conference
on Information and Communication Technologies in Education, Re-
search, and Industrial Applications, ICTERI 2013, Springer,
pp. 355–378.
80
Tutorials
Analogical Reasoning
Henri Prade
IRIT* , CNRS , Université Paul Sabatier, Toulouse, France
[email protected]
I. The first lecture singles out analogical proportion among logical pro-
portions. Logical proportions, a family of particular quaternary Boolean
operators built from similarity or dissimilarity indicators between pairs,
are first introduced. Then, different sub-families are identified accord-
ing to their definitional structure, or some characteristic properties.
Analogical proportion appears as one of the four symmetrical logi-
cal proportions that are code independent (which means that their
truth value does not change when 0 and 1 are exchanged). Analogical
*
Institut de Recherche en Informatique de Toulouse
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
81
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Couceiro, N. Hug, H. Prade & G. Richard, “Analogy-preserving
functions: a way to extend Boolean samples”, 26th International Joint
Conference on Artificial Intelligence, IJCAI’17, Melbourne, Australia,
August 19–25, 2017, pp. 1575–1581.
2. D. Dubois, H. Prade & G. Richard, “Multiple-valued extensions of
analogical proportions”, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 292(C), 2016,
pp. 193–202.
3. S. Klein, “Analogy and mysticism and the structure of culture [and
Comments and Reply]”, Current Anthropology, vol. 24(2), 1983,
pp. 151–180.
82
Tutorials
83
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Useful Link
MMT homepage
*
Laboratoire de Recherche en Informatique
Knowledge Adaptation and Reasoning for Content
84
Tutorials
In this tutorial, I will show that description logics provide a good model
for specifying ontologies over Web data (described in RDF), but that re-
strictions are necessary in order to obtain scalable algorithms for checking
data consistency and answering conjunctive queries. I will explain that the
DL-Lite family has good properties for combining ontological reasoning and
data management at large scale.
*
American Association for Artificial Intelligence
European Coordinating Committee for Artificial Intelligence
85
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
II. This part will be devoted to description logics, their use for specifying
ontologies and the associated inference algorithms for reasoning on
data in presence of ontologies.
III. In this last part, we will present a unifying rule-based logical framework
for reasoning on RDF ontologies and databases, based on Datalog and
its extensions.
Bibliography
S. Abiteboul, I. Manolescu, Ph. Rigaux, M.-Ch. Rousset & P. Senellart,
Web Data Management, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
Useful Link
Website of the book Web Data Management
86
Tutorials
Who was this French philosopher? History of logic almost completely ig-
nores him, because he didn’t contribute to the field. Nevertheless he played
an important role in the development of the discipline. He was among
the first who grasped the appeal of the new “algorithmic logic”, renewing
Leibniz’ dream of a characteristica universalis, and started very early to
integrate modern logic into the philosophy curriculum at the French uni-
versity. He wrote several introductory works on logic for the French public.
And he created a vast network of correspondents, extended from Argentina
to Russia, including among others Russell, Peano, Peirce, MacColl, Frege
and Schroeder. He devoted himself to mutually connect these scholars and
to make circulating their ideas through the scholarly world at a maximum
speed.
In this tutorial, we will try to grasp the work of Couturat in its entire
scope, ranging from his work on Leibniz to the philosophy of mathematics,
epistemology, and logic. Beyond his published work we will also consult
his correspondence and his unpublished manuscripts (e.g. on the history of
mathematical logic).
I. Louis Couturat
In the first session, I will provide an overview over the life and the
work of Louis Couturat. In particular, I will elaborate his philosophical
programme which eventually led him to study contemporary advances in
symbolic logic and to make considerable efforts for introducing symbolic
logic in France. I will also present and analyze his various activities as a
reviewer, editor, conference organizer, international “mail box”, partisan of
international auxiliary languages, and so on.
87
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
Selection of Couturat’s works:
1. De l’infini mathématique, Félix Alcan, Paris, 1896, https://goo.gl/
kNzFec.
2. La Logique de Leibniz, Félix Alcan, Paris, 1901, https://goo.gl/
KQ23n4, English version: The Logic of Leibniz, translated by Donald
Rutherford, https://goo.gl/TCNyXP.
3. with Ch. Ladd-Franklin: Symbolic Logic, in Dictionary of Philosophy
and Psychology, edited by J.M. Baldwin, 1902.
4. Les principes des mathématiques, avec un appendice sur la philoso-
phie mathématique de Kant, Félix Alcan, Paris, 1903, https://goo.gl/
WkgFEt.
5. L’algèbre de la logique, 1905, English version: The Algebra of Logic,
translated by L.G. Robinson, The Open Court Publishing Company,
1914, https://goo.gl/is1iA1.
6. Traité de logique algorithmique, posthumous, 2010.
On Couturat:
1. M. Fichant & S. Roux (editors), Louis Couturat (1868–1914). Ma-
thématiques, langage, philosophie, Classiques Garnier, Paris, 2017.
2. L’Œuvre de Louis Couturat — de Leibniz à Russell, Actes du Col-
loque International, L’École Normale Supérieure, Éditions Rue
d’Ulm, 1977, https://goo.gl/2uoCsP.
88
Tutorials
89
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Selected Bibliography
1. R.M. Adams, “The Logical Structure of Anselm’s Arguments”, The
Philosophical Review, vol. 80(1), 1971, pp. 28–54.
2. Anselm of Canterbury, Complete Philosophical and Theological Trea-
tises of Anselm of Canterbury, edited by J. Hopkins & H. Richardson,
translated by J. Hopkins, The Arthur J. Banning Press, Minneapolis,
USA, 2000.
3. J. Barnes, The Ontological Argument, Macmillan, London, 1972.
4. J.-Y. Beziau & R. Silvestre (editors), Logic and Religion, Special Issue
of Logica Universalis, vol. 11(1), 2017.
5. J.-Y. Beziau & R. Silvestre, “Logic and Religion”, Logica Universalis,
vol. 11(1), 2017, pp. 1–12.
6. J. Bowker (editor), The Oxford Dictionary of World Religions, Oxford
University Press, 1997.
7. P. Oppenheimer & E. Zalta, “On the Logic of the Ontological Argu-
ment”, in Philosophical Perspectives 5: The Philosophy of Religion,
edited by J. Tomblin, Ridgeview Press, Atascadero, USA, 1991.
8. M. Palmer (editor), World Religions, HarperCollins, London, 2002.
9. A. Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford University Press, 1974.
10. K. Rogers, Perfect Being Theology, Edinburgh University Press, 2000.
11. R. Silvestre, “On the Logical Formalization of Anselm’s Ontological
Argument”, Revista Brasileira de Filosofia da Religião, vol. 2(2), 2015,
pp. 142–161, http://abfr.org/revista/index.php/rbfr/article/view/
19/19.
90
Tutorials
12. R. Silvestre & J.-Y. Beziau (editors), Logic and Philosophy of Religion,
Special Issue of Sophia, vol. 56(2), 2017.
13. R. Silvestre & J.-Y. Beziau, “Logic and Philosophy of Religion”, Sophia,
vol. 56(2), 2017, pp. 139–145.
14. J. Sobel, Logic and Theism: Arguments for and against Beliefs in God,
Cambridge University Press, 2004.
15. C. Taliaferro, P. Draper & P. Quinn, The Blackwell Companion to the
Philosophy of Religion, Blackwell, Oxford, UK, 2010.
16. N. Trakakis, The God Beyond Belief: In Defense of William Rowe’s
Evidential Argument from Evil, Springer, 2007.
Useful Links
Anselm: Ontological Argument for God’s Existence, Internet Encyclo-
pedia of Philosophy
World Congresses on Logic and Religion
91
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Giovanni Mion
Department of Humanities and Social Sciences,
Istanbul Technical University, Turkey
[email protected]
Early computer science pioneers were well versed in the logic models
inspired by Boole, Frege and Russell (and later by Carnap, Church, Tarski
and Quine to name but a few) — what became classical first order logic
‘FOL’. As a result, semantic technologies such as Relational Databases,
Natural Language Processing and OWL (the predominant model for se-
mantic/knowledge representations) were all grounded in FOL.
However, the intellectual lineage that became FOL was not without its
opponents, almost from the beginning. The Cambridge of pre-war England
was also home to Ludwig Wittgenstein whose Tractatus provided, in sig-
nificant respects, an alternative approach to logic from that espoused by
Russell.
The divide between Russell and Wittgenstein still lives today. And it
is of supreme relevance to both theoretical and applied logicians because
it points to unanswered foundational issues in logic AND practical conse-
quences stemming from foundational problems. Moreover, semantic tech-
*
Chief Technology Officer
Web Ontology Language
92
Tutorials
II. In the second section, we make the link to show where Wittgenstein’s
ideas about logic are relevant for the design of semantic technolo-
gies. We will focus on knowledge representation and natural lan-
guage processing. For example, we will show that for Wittgenstein,
all semantic technologies must be grounded in abstract typing sys-
tems. And logical operators link experiential (sense) propositions to
molecular/composite representations.
93
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
On Wittgenstein’s Logic in the Tractatus
1. E. Anscombe, An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Hutchin-
son University Library, 1959.
2. R.J. Fogelin, Wittgenstein, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976.
3. P. Frascolla, Understanding Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Routledge,
2006.
4. S. Shanker, Wittgenstein and the Turning Point in the Philosophy of
Mathematics, Croom Helm Publishers, London & State University
of New York Press, New York, 1987.
5. S. Toulmin & A. Janik, Wittgenstein’s Vienna, Simon and Schuster,
New York, 1973.
6. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge,
1930–1932: From the Notes of John King and Desmond Lee,
Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Maryland, USA, 1980.
On semantic technologies
1. D.B. Lenat & R.V. Guha, Building Large Knowledge-Based Systems:
Representation and Inference in the Cyc Project, Addison-Wesley,
1990.
2. S. Nirenburg & V. Raskin, Ontological Semantics, MIT* Press, 2004.
3. J. Sowa, Knowledge Representation: Logical, Philosophical and Com-
putational Foundations, Brooks-Cole Publishing, Pacific Grove, Cal-
ifornia, USA, 2000.
4. E. Thomsen, OLAP Solutions: Building Multidimensional Informa-
tion Systems, 2nd edition, John Wiley & Sons, Hoboken, New Jersey,
USA, 2002.
*
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
94
Tutorials
The aim of the tutorial is to give an overview of a few chosen models and
information synthesis formalisms. We introduce three models of the fusion
operator on theories/specifications. See e.g. [2] for other fusion models. No
previous knowledge of information fusion is assumed, but we will do assume
basic knowledge of propositional and first-order logic.
I. Fusion by Products
We start with a quick historical overview of the fusion problem and
we present the first fusion formalization under the generalized products of
relational structures. Fraissé-Hintika-Galvin Autonomous Systems are the
main tool for the decision synthesis of models of first-order theories under
products of models [4,7,8].
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique, de Modélisation et d’Optimisation des Systèmes
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
95
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
International Society for Optical Engineering
96
Tutorials
(2) Equality. The concepts “equal”, “less”, “greater”, to which today are
ascribed a purely quantitative meaning, in Euclid seems to be also asso-
ciated with the geometric notion of relative position, but also applied to
multitudes when Euclid compares two sets of numbers-arithmoi.
97
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
ii. The infinite descent principle: the process of anthyphairesis will termi-
nate in a finite number of steps, that is the chain A > B > B1 > B2 >
. . . > Bk > . . . is finite.
98
Tutorials
(7) The finitary principle and the use of effective procedures. Euclidean
arithmetic is constructed from below, beginning from the unit. Further,
a number of arithmetical concepts are introduced in the Definitions of Book
VII. From these, the concepts of part, multiple, parts, proportionality, and
prime numbers are not defined effectively. However, they become effective
in virtue of Propositions 1, 2, and 3 that provide an effective procedure for
any numbers to find their common measure. In this way, the proofs of the
Propositions 4–19 should be considered as effective either. The introduc-
tion of more complex objects is realised through the comparison of these
objects and the establishment of an equality-type relation between them.
Euclid always provides an effective procedure for finding the least pair of
the objects found in equality-type relation.
(9) Underlying logic. The approach adopted by Euclid does not need any
special predicate logic. Euclid’s arithmetic can be characterised as a finitary
fragment of classical arithmetic; hence, it does not necessarily presuppose
the full force of first-order predicate logic.
99
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
100
Tutorials
Plato puts the following solution into Parmenides’ mouth. The eidos is
defined as a paradigm, which expresses the form of instances of the eidos,
considered as a singular thing ‘found’ in nature. Further, participation in
an eidos is identified with instantiation of the eidos. Further, the eidos is
compared with a fixed instance of it and the following question is posed:
can we conclude that an eidos is similar to an instance of it on the basis
that the latter is an instantiation of the eidos?
101
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bibliography
1. I.G. Bashmakova, “The Arithmetic Books of Euclid’s Elements” (in
Russian), Istoriko-matematičeskie issledovaniya, vol. I, 1948, p. 321.
2. J. Corcoran (editor), Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretations,
D. Reidel, 1974.
3. G. Fine, On Ideas. Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Theory of Forms,
Clarendon Press, 1993.
4. H. Freudenttall, “Zur Geschichte der vollständigen Induktion”, Archive
Internationale d’Histoire des Sciences, vol. 6, 1953, pp. 17–37.
5. J.-L. Gardies, Le raisonnement par l’absurde, Presses Universitaires de
France, 1991.
6. A.F. Losev, History of Ancient Aesthetics (in Russian), 7 volumes,
Isskustvo, Moscow, 1963–1988.
7. I. Mueller, Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Eu-
clid’s “Elements”, MIT* Press, 1981.
8. F.J. Pelletier & E.N. Zalta, “How to Say Goodbye to the Third Man”,
Nous, vol. 34(2), 2000, pp. 165–202, https://mally.stanford.edu/
plato.pdf.
9. I. Vandoulakis, “Was Euclid’s Approach to Arithmetic Axiomatic?”,
Oriens-Occidens, Cahiers du Centre d’Histoire des Sciences et des Phi-
losophies Arabes et Médiévales, vol. 2, 1998, pp. 141–181.
10. I. Vandoulakis, “Styles of Greek arithmetic reasoning”, Study of the
History of Mathematics, RIMS Kôkyûroku, no. 1625, 2009, pp. 12–22,
https://goo.gl/dc7Fuu.
11. I. Vandoulakis, “Plato’s Third Man Paradox: its Logic and History”,
Archives Internationale d’Histoire des Sciences, vol. 59(162), 2009,
pp. 3–53.
12. I. Vandoulakis, “A Generic Interpretation of Neo-Pythagorean Arith-
metic”, Oriens-Occidens, Cahiers du Centre d’Histoire des Sciences et
des Philosophies Arabes et Médiévales, vol. 7, 2010, pp. 113–154.
13. G. Vlastos, “The Third Man Argument in the Parmenides”, Philosoph-
ical Review, vol. 63, 1954, pp. 319–349.
Useful Link
Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Edward N. Zalta, “How to Say Goodbye to
the Third Man”: https://mally.stanford.edu/plato.pdf.
*
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
102
Tutorials
As John Woods [19, p. 15] put it: “Formal logic is a theory of logical
forms; and informal logic is all the rest”. Informal logicians [e.g. 11,1] as
well as proponents of the Pragma-dialectical school of argumentation [4,3]
tend to view “all the rest” as shouldering the real work in the analysis and
evaluation of natural language argumentation.
103
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Please note: The three tutorial sessions build on each other. Rather than
pick one or two sessions, participants would do well to attend all three.
We provide learning materials in class as online resources; there is no prior
reading assignment. A background in formal logic or probability theory is
neither required nor harmful to profit from the tutorial. The main learning
outcome is the improved ability to orient oneself within the field of argu-
mentation studies, and correctly apply p-logic to such crucial notions as
argument cogency, fallacy, or argument strength, among others.
References
1. J.A. Blair, “Relevance, Acceptability and Sufficiency Today”, in Ground-
work in the Theory of Argumentation, edited by C.W. Tindale, Springer,
2012, pp. 87–100.
2. A. Corner & U. Hahn, “Normative theories of argumentation: Are some
norms better than others?”, Synthese, vol. 190(16), 2013,
pp. 3579–3610.
3. F.H. van Eemeren, Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse.
Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation, John Ben-
jamins, Amsterdam, 2010.
4. F.H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst, A systematic theory of argumen-
tation: the pragma-dialectical approach, Cambridge University Press,
2004.
5. D. Godden & F. Zenker, “Denying antecedents and affirming conse-
quents: The state of the art”, Informal Logic, vol. 35(1), 2015,
pp. 88–134.
6. D. Godden & F. Zenker, “A probabilistic analysis of argument cogency”,
Synthese, vol. 195(4), 2018, pp. 1715–1740.
104
Tutorials
Session 1
— Material implication vs. mutually inverse implication
— Composition operators vs. connection operators
— Formations of terms and propositions
— Truth tables for composition operators
— Inductive compositions vs. decompositions
— Truth tables of connection operators
— Mutually inverse diagrams for connection operators
— The principle of meaningfulness and meaninglessness duality for distin-
guished propositions
Session 2
— First-level single quasi-predicate calculus
— Second-level single quasi-predicate calculus
Session 3
— Unified logics unify more than a dozen logics.
Bibliography
1. Xunwei Zhou, Mutually-Inversistic Logic, Mathematics, and Their Ap-
plications, Central Compilation & Translation Press, Beijing, China,
2013.
106
9 – Poster Session for Students
107
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Supported by Coordination of Improvement of Higher Level Personnel (CAPES), Brazil.
108
Poster Session for Students
109
10 – ¿Why, what, when, where
and how to publish?
*
Institut des Hautes Études Scientifiques
Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et en Automatique
111
Part III
113
11 – Opening Ceremony of the
6th World Congress
on Universal Logic
It will take place on June 21, 2018, 11–12h, at Vichy University Campus.
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique, de Modélisation et d’Optimisation des Systèmes
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
115
12 – Secret Speaker
The talk of the secret speaker will be at a secret time in a secret place.
Keep your eyes open!
The happy winner will be the first to send the right answer. All partic-
ipants of UNILOG are welcome to play, except the secret speaker.
Hint: “What I tell you three times is true.” (The Hunting of the Snark,
Lewis Carroll)
117
13 – Talks of Keynote Speakers
Argument-based logics
Leila Amgoud*
Institut de Recherche en Informatique de Toulouse, France
[email protected]
References
1. P. Dung, “On the Acceptability of Arguments and its Fundamental
Role in Non-Monotonic Reasoning, Logic Programming and n-Person
Games”, Artificial Intelligence, vol. 88, 1995, pp. 321–357.
2. L. Amgoud & J. Ben-Naim, “Axiomatic foundations of acceptability
semantics”, in Proceedings of the International Conference on Principles
of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 2016, pp. 2–11.
*
Keynote speaker at the session “Argumentation” (page 460).
119
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Reference
1. F. Berto “How to rule out things with words: strong paraconsistency
and the algebra of exclusion”, in New waves in philosophical logic, edited
by G. Restall & G.K. Russell, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 169–189, 2012.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Reflections on Paraconsistency” (page 295).
120
Talks of Keynote Speakers
Since the work of the early pioneers in the 1970s, it’s known that any
topos supports an internal language, which allows to speak and reason about
its objects and morphisms in a naive element-based language: From the
internal perspective, objects of the topos look like sets, morphisms look like
maps between sets, epimorphisms look like surjective maps, group objects
look like plain groups and so on; and any theorem which has an intuitionistic
proof also holds in the internal universe of a topos.
With recent discoveries of new applications of the internal language in
algebra, geometry, homotopy theory, mathematical physics and measure
theory, the study of the internal language of toposes is currently experienc-
ing a resurgence. Our goal is give an introduction to this topic and illustrate
the usefulness of the internal language with two specific examples.
Firstly, the internal language of the “little Zariski topos” allows us to
assume without loss of generality that any reduced ring is Noetherian and in
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic, Law and Legal Reasoning” (page 381).
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Categories and Logic” (page 368).
121
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
122
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. K.-O. Apel, Charles Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism,
Prometheus Books, New York, 1995.
2. S. Brier, Cybersemiotics: why information is not enough, Toronto
University Press, 2008/13.
3. S. Brier, “Can Biosemiotics be a “Science” if its Purpose is to be a
Bridge between the Natural, Social and Human Sciences?”, Progress in
Biophysics and Molecular Biology, vol. 119(3), 2015, pp. 576–587.
4. S. Brier, “How to Produce a Transdisciplinary Information Concept for
a Universal Theory of Information?”, in Information Studies and the
Quest for Transdisciplinarity: Unity through Diversity, vol. 9, edited
by M. Burgin & W. Hofkirchner, World Scientific Series in Informa-
tion Studies, World Scientific Publishing, Singapore, 2017, pp. 11–58,
doi:10.1142/9789813109001 0002.
5. V. Romanini & E. Fernandez (editors), Peirce and Biosemiotics:
A Guess at the Riddle of Life, Biosemiotics series, vol. 1, Springer,
2014.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Categories and Logic” (page 368).
123
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. B. Coecke & A. Kissinger, Picturing Quantum Processes: A First Course
in Quantum Theory and Diagrammatic Reasoning, Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 2017.
2. B. Coecke, “Quantum picturalism”, Contemporary Physics, vol. 51(1),
2010, pp. 59–83.
3. B. Coecke & S. Gogioso, “Quantum theory in Pictures”, Top Secret.
4. B. Coecke & S. Gogioso, “Quantum theory in Hilbert space”, a bit less
top Secret.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic for Children” (page 361).
124
Talks of Keynote Speakers
*
Keynote speaker at the session “Non-Classical Logics” (page 439).
Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et en Automatique
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
125
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. D. Dubois, J. Lang & H. Prade, “Possibilistic logic”, in Handbook of
Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming, vol. 3, edited
by D.M. Gabbay, C.J. Hogger, J.A. Robinson & D. Nute, Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1994, pp. 439–513.
2. D. Ciucci & D. Dubois, “A modal theorem-preserving translation of
a class of three-valued logics of incomplete information”, Journal of
Applied Non-Classical Logics, vol. 23(4), 2013, pp. 321–352.
3. M. Banerjee & D. Dubois, “A simple logic for reasoning about in-
complete knowledge”, International Journal of Approximate Reasoning,
vol. 55, 2014, pp. 639–653.
4. D. Ciucci & D. Dubois, “A Two-Tiered Propositional Framework for
Handling Multisource Inconsistent Information”, in European Confer-
ence on Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning and Un-
certainty, Lugano, Switzerland, 2017, pp. 398–408.
5. D. Dubois, H. Prade & S. Schockaert, “Generalized possibilistic logic:
Foundations and applications to qualitative reasoning about uncertainty”,
Artificial Intelligence, vol. 252, 2017, pp. 139–174.
In order to follow the objective of the title, let us list some quotations by
Alonzo Church. These quotations are well enough to give a good account
of the ideas we shall be venturing in. Our attempt in this presentation
would be to bring to the fore the usual practice of the logical systems,
where some of the following requirements are lacking. The theory of graded
consequence (GCT) [2], in contrast, would be presented as a formal set-up
where the following prescriptions are preserved.
126
Talks of Keynote Speakers
127
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
These issues are also addressed in some other works [1,4,5,6,7]. Our aim
is to briefly touch on others’ perspectives, keeping the focus on the treat-
ment offered by GCT.
References
1. A. Bacon, “Non-classical Metatheory for Non-classical Logics”, Journal
of Philosophical Logic, vol. 42, 2012, pp. 335–355.
2. M.K. Chakraborty, “Graded consequence: further studies”, Journal of
Applied Non-Classical Logics, vol. 5, 1995, pp. 227–237.
3. A. Church, “Introduction to Mathematical Logic”, vol. 1, Princeton
University Press, 1956.
4. G. Malinowski, “Inferential many-valuedness”, Philosophical Logic in
Poland, edited by J. Woleński, Kluwer, Amsterdam, 1994, pp. 75–84.
5. R. Parikh, “The Problem of Vague Predicates”, in Language, Logic, and
Method, edited by R.S. Cohen & M.W. Wartofsky, D. Ridel Publishing
Company, 1983, pp. 241–261.
6. C. Pelta, “Wide sets, deep many-valuedness and sorites arguments”,
Mathware & Soft Computing, vol. 11, 2004, pp. 5–11.
7. T. Vetterlein, F. Esteva & L. Godo, “Logics for Approximate Entail-
ment in ordered universes of discourse”, International Journal of Ap-
proximate Reasoning, vol. 71, 2016, pp. 50–63.
128
Talks of Keynote Speakers
129
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
hereditarily finite lists was constructed in [3], and the computability the-
ory was developed in terms of Σ-definability in this superstructure. From
the standpoint of constructing a programming language, such an approach
seems more natural for accompanying logical programs since for a specific
implementation of a language of logical type on sets, we must externally
define the sequence of an efficient exhaustion of their elements. In choosing
a list of elements, the order is already contained in the model, and we have
a definition in the model of operations that explicitly defines the work with
the list items. However, from the viewpoint of the construction of programs,
taking into account the complexity of their implementation, it is preferable
to consider their constructions based on the ∆0 -construction while retaining
sufficiently broad logical means of definitions, and on the other hand, ensur-
ing more imperative constructions in the required estimates of performance
complexity.
In this talk, we consider the questions of definability on the basis of
the ∆0 -formulas whose verification of truth has bounded complexity with
respect to the basic terms and relations in the basic model, as well as the
implementation of the list operations in the superstructure. From the stand-
point of specific applications of this logical programming system, the two
types of problems we solve can be distinguished: (1) the local problems
of constructing specific computations with data from the domain under in-
vestigation and searching for fast ways of computing these characteristics
from making operative decisions in real time; (2) the strategic multipurpose
problems that use large data for solving them and require search and defi-
nition already in a language allowing unrestricted existence quantifiers. To
solve problems of the first type, we propose to extend the class of terms
of our language by conditional terms which can be determined using only
∆0 -formulas and by recursive terms which can be determined using only
∆-formulas.
References
1. S.S. Goncharov & D.I. Sviridenko, “Σ-Programming”, American Math-
ematical Society Translations: Series 2, vol. 142, 1989, pp. 101–121.
2. S.S. Goncharov & D.I. Sviridenko, “Theoretical aspects of Σ-program-
ming”, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 215, 1986, pp. 169–179.
3. Yu.L. Ershov, S.S. Goncharov & D.I. Sviridenko, “Semantic program-
ming”, in Information Processing 86: Proceedings of the IFIP 10th
World Computer Congress, IFIP* Congress Series, vol. 10, Elsevier Sci-
ence, Dublin, 1986, pp. 1093–1100.
*
International Federation for Information Processing
130
Talks of Keynote Speakers
131
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
132
Talks of Keynote Speakers
When analyzing, in Tool and object [1], the historical development of cat-
egory theory and the early debate on its foundations, I was led to discuss
some general philosophical aspects of the formation of new mathematical
concepts (in learners and in a community as a whole) and of mathematical
research programmes; motivating examples were discussed under the head-
ings of “intended models” and “technical common sense”. It turned out to
be crucial to focus on the respective background of the people involved in
these processes, in particular, the attitude of “people without expertise in
a certain area” was shown to play a role.
This observation lends itself to discussion within the perspective of the
workshop (which speaks about such groups of people as “children in a wider
sense of the term”); therefore, the talk will review this issue to some extent.
A special focus will be laid on the role of diagrams in the debates on category
theory. On the one hand, I intend to compare the role of diagrams played
in proofs of category theory with the role of diagrams played in proofs of
classical Euclidean geometry (as analyzed by Manders [2], among others).
In both cases, one should focus on the ways in which a diagram is used to
prove a proposition, on the one hand, or to display a proposition, on the
other. And there is a tension playing an eminent role, in my opinion, in
the foundational debate, namely the tension between diagrams as display-
ing propositions about finite sets of objects of a category on the one hand
and the consideration of a category as an infinite diagram (or graph) on the
other.
References
1. R. Krömer, Tool and object. A history and philosophy of category theory,
Birkhäuser, 2007.
2. K. Manders, “Diagram-Based Geometric Practice” and “The Euclidean
Diagram” (1995), in The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, edited
by P. Mancosu, Oxford University Press, 2008, chapters 3 and 4, pp. 65–
79, pp. 80–133.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic for Children” (page 361).
133
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
134
Talks of Keynote Speakers
135
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. P.M. Dung, ‘On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role
in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming, and n-person games’,
Artificial Intelligence, vol. 77, 1995, pp. 321–357.
2. H. Prakken & G. Vreeswijk, ‘Logic for Defeasible Argumentation’, in
Handbook of Philosophical Logic, edited by D. Gabbay and F. Guenth-
ner, vol. 4, 2nd edition, Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, 2002, pp. 218–
319.
3. E. Lisanyuk, “Argumentation, R. Pavilionis’s Meaning Continuum and
the Kitchen Debate”, Problemos, vol. 88, Faculty of Philosophy, Vilnius
University, 2015, pp. 218–319, http://www.journals.vu.lt/problemos/
article/view/8481.
4. M. Caminada & L. Amgoud, ‘On the evaluation of argumentative for-
malisms’, Artificial Intelligence, vol. 171(5–6), 2007, pp. 286–310.
5. V. Finn, ‘On a logic of argumentation’, Research and technology infor-
mation, series 2: Information processes and systems, vols. 5–6, 1996,
pp. 3–19 (in Russian).
6. D. Bochvar, “On a three-valued calculus and its application to the para-
doxes of the extended classical functional calculus”, Mathematical Col-
lection, vol. 4(2), 1938 (in Russian).
136
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. G. Frege, “Conceptual Notation: A Formula Language of Pure Thought
Modeled upon the Formula Language of Arithmetic”, in Begriffsschrift,
first published in 1879, English version: Conceptual Notation and Re-
lated Articles, translated by T. Bynum, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1972.
2. G. Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, first published in 1884, En-
glish version: Foundations of Arithmetic, translated by J. Austin, North-
western University Press, Evanston, 1980.
3. C. Peirce, “The Logic of Mathematics in Relation to Education”, first
published in 1898, in Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Writings,
edited by M. Moore, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 2010.
4. C. Peirce, “The Simplest Mathematics”, written in 1902, in Philoso-
phy of Mathematics: Selected Writings, edited by M. Moore, Indiana
University Press, Bloomington, 2010.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Around Peirce” (page 257).
137
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Over the years, relevance logics have been generated in many ways.
Among them may be mentioned syntactic generation by Hilbertian axiom
systems, natural deduction rules, and Gentzen consecution calculi; and se-
mantic production via Meyer-Routley relational structures and semi-lattice
semantics. Each approach has brought valuable insights and techniques,
but it seems fair to say that none has been really satisfying. That, perhaps,
is the main reason for the gradual decline of interest in the subject since
the turn of the century. In this talk, we will discuss a fresh perspective that
has recently been developed. It suitably adapts the procedure of semantic
decomposition trees, well-known for their usefulness in classical and modal
contexts, to give a ‘syntactically monitored semantics’ for relevance logic.
The semantics is perfectly classical, the syntactic monitoring is not.
The roots of many-valued logics can be traced back to 4th century BC.
In Chapter IX of De Interpretatione Aristotle considers the timely honoured
sentence “There will be a sea-battle tomorrow”. Since the battle-sentence
refers to not actually determined events, it is a future contingent. Accord-
ingly, the Philosopher from Stagira suggests the existence of the “third”
logical status of propositions.
In 1920 Lukasiewicz and Post successfully formulated many-valued sys-
tems. Their constructions were possible in the result of an adaptation of
the truth-table method used to the classical logic by Frege and Peirce (in
1879 and 1885, respectively). Incidentally, the priority lies on the side of the
Polish scholar, who presented his three-valued logic already in his official
university lecture in 1918.
*
Keynote speaker at the session “Non-Classical Logics” (page 439).
Keynote speaker at the workshop “The Lvov-Warsaw School: Past, Present and Future”
(page 270).
138
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. J. Lukasiewicz, “O logice trójwartościowej”, Ruch Filozoficzny, vol. 5,
1920, pp. 170–171, English version: “On three-valued logic”, in [2],
pp. 87–88.
2. J. Lukasiewicz, Selected Works, edited by L. Borkowski, North-Holland,
Amsterdam and PWN, Warsaw, 1970.
3. G. Malinowski, “Many–valued logic and its philosophy”, in Handbook
of the History of Logic, vol. 8: The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic
Turn in Logic, edited by D.M. Gabbay & J. Woods, North-Holland,
Amsterdam and Oxford, 2007, pp. 13–94.
A prevalent view during the last decades in the logic and the philosophy
of science submits the thesis that — contrary to what the traditional view
might suggest [1,2] — inconsistent theories do not always have to be rejected,
as history of science has shown that inconsistencies are often present and
tolerated in scientific practice [3,4,5,6]. But, while the coherence of this
view has nowadays been widely defended, there is still no consensus on how
this toleration takes place, and more precisely, on why are inconsistencies
tolerable to begin with. My aim here is to address two important questions
concerning this view, namely: how do we usually characterize ‘inconsistency
toleration’ in empirical sciences? and how should we characterize it?
The first question has already been answered by the defenders of two
different approaches to inconsistency toleration, namely, (a) the ‘handling
inconsistency’ projects [7,8,9,5] and (b) and the ‘avoiding triviality’ projects
[10,11,12,13,14]. Projects of the first type often assume that inconsistencies
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Reflections on Paraconsistency” (page 295).
139
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
are falsities that, while most of the time are problematic for the scientific
endeavor, almost never, are an actual risk for scientific reasoning. In con-
trast, the defenders of the ‘avoiding triviality’ approaches assume that when
faced with a case of inconsistent science, one needs to explain how Explosion
is avoided in that very case, as Explosion has always been thought of as a
danger when talking about contradictions in science. With that in mind,
the ‘avoiding triviality’ approach has characterized inconsistency toleration
as the avoidance of triviality when facing a contradiction.
To finally provide an answer to the second question, I will claim that
the second approach is unsuccessful for the following reasons. First, while
cases of inconsistent and trivial formal theories are well documented in the
literature, the same does not happen with inconsistent and trivial empirical
theories. This has prevented philosophers and logicians of science from
grasping how triviality looks like in the context of empirical sciences. In
contrast, in the latest decades, much understanding has been gained on how
to handle contradictions in science; different strategies have been proposed,
explained and extended, and, as a matter of fact, many of the handling
inconsistencies maneuvers have been explicative of the cases of inconsistency
toleration in empirical sciences.
Furthermore, I will conclude that in order to provide a better under-
standing of inconsistency toleration in empirical sciences, we should modify
the way in which contradictions are often understood (as a risk of explo-
sion), the way in which triviality is often characterized and, of course the
way in which inconsistency toleration is often defined. All these modi-
fications should be done in such a way that these concepts are sensibly
explanatory for the actual scientific activity when facing contradictions
in empirical sciences.
References
1. K.R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Routledge, 1959.
2. C. Hempel, Selected Philosophical Essays, Cambridge University Press,
2000.
3. I. Lakatos, “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research
Programmes”, in Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the
Philosophy of Science: Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, vol. 4,
edited by I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave, Cambridge University Press, 1970,
pp. 91–196.
4. L. Laudan, Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific
growth, University of California Press, 1977.
5. J. Smith, “Inconsistencies and scientific reasoning”, Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science, vol. 4(19), 1988, pp. 429–445.
140
Talks of Keynote Speakers
141
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
142
Talks of Keynote Speakers
Of particular interest, in addition to the pair ⟨c, a⟩, are the pair ⟨a′ , c′ ⟩
(where the prime represents negation) and the pair ⟨c, a △ c⟩ (where the
triangle represents exclusive disjunction or symmetric difference). Since c
is deducible from a if and only if a′ is deducible from c′ , and also if and
only if c is deducible from a △ c, the three functions c(c ∣ a) = p(c ∣ a)
(usually called credence), q(c ∣ a) = p(a′ ∣ c′ ) (called deductive dependence in
[2]), and n(c ∣ a) = p(c ∣ a △ c) (which may be called nearness) all take the
value 1 when c is deducible from a. They generalize deducibility in diverse
ways: provided that c is not deducible from a, c(c ∣ a) = 0 when a and c
are contraries, q(c ∣ a) = 0 when a and c are subcontraries, and n(c ∣ a) = 0
when a is deducible from c (and conversely too if p is regular).
c(c ∣ a) is almost universally understood to measure the degree of belief of
the hypothesis c given the evidence a (or the appropriate betting quotient).
q(c ∣ a) measures the extent to which the content of c is included within the
content of a, the deductive dependence of c on a. It is often a good substitute
for c(c ∣ a), for example as a measure of degree of confirmation. In [1] it
is shown how the replacement of c (or p) by q resolves some outstanding
problems besetting the interpretation of indicative conditionals.
The present paper will consider whether there is any illuminating inter-
pretation of the function n. It will also seek to demystify the surprising fact
that the three functions c, q, n, though demonstrably distinct functions, can
be transformed into one another by means of simple linguistic translations.
References
1. D.W. Miller, “Reconditioning the Conditional”, in Conceptual Clarifica-
tions. Tributes to Patrick Suppes (1922–2014), edited by J.-Y. Beziau,
D. Krause & J.R.B. Arenhart, College Publications, London, 2015,
pp. 205–215, reprinted in Princı́pios, vol. 23(40), Natal, Brazil, 2016,
pp. 9–27.
2. D.W. Miller & K.R. Popper, “Deductive Dependence”, in Actes IV
Congrés Català de Lògica, Barcelona, Universitat Politècnica de Cata-
lunya and Universitat de Barcelona, 1986, pp. 21–29.
144
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. A. Moktefi, “Beyond syllogisms: Carroll’s (marked) quadriliteral dia-
gram”, in Visual Reasoning with Diagrams, Birkhäuser, Basel, 2013,
pp. 55–71.
2. L. Carroll, Lewis Carroll’s Symbolic Logic, edited by W.W. Bartley III,
Clarkson N. Potter, New York, 1986.
3. F. Abeles, The Logic Pamphlets of Charles Lutwidge Dodgson and Re-
lated Pieces, Lewis Carroll Society of North America, New York, 2010.
4. A. Moretti, “Was Lewis Carroll an amazing oppositional geometer?”,
History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 35, 2014, pp. 383–409.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logical Geometry and its Applications” (page 169).
145
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Rudolph Carnap in his famous book The Logical Structure of the World
instances musical chords in order to illustrate his concept of quasi analysis.
And he sets the bar high, when he characterizes chords as “uniform totali-
ties, which are not composed of constituents”. On the basis of similarity cir-
cles Carnap suggests the possibility of regaining tones as quasi-constituents
of chords. So it is interesting to ask: what are the contributions of present
day working music theorists to the identification of chord-constituents (or
quasi-constituents)?
The prevalent study of musical chords as subsets X ⊆ Z12 of the chro-
matic 12-tone system provides a quite restricted and abstract level of de-
scription. Nevertheless it plays a quite productive role for the generation of
new ideas and for the reconsideration of old ones. It provides insights into
aspects of musical actuality and constitutes a manageable playground for
theoretical explorations. Therefore it serves as a good starting point for the
lecture.
Linchpin and point of departure in two directions of study is the con-
version of a chord X ⊆ Z12 into a characteristic function χX ∶ Z12 → {0, 1}:
2. The study of the subsets X ⊂ Z12 through their affine stabilizisers, i.e
affine endomorphisms f ∶ Z12 → Z12 , satisfying f (X) ⊆ X leads to an
intuitionistic interpretation of elementhood, where a refined character-
istic function χX ∶ Z12 → Ω takes values in the subobject classifier (truth
value object) Ω of a topos SetM of monoid actions. The special case of
the 8-element triadic monoid M and a 6-element truth value object Ω
is music-theoretically illuminating and moreover it provides a nice vade
mecum into topos theory and Lawvere-Tierney topologies.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic and Music” (page 204).
146
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. E. Amiot, Music Through Fourier Space: Discrete Fourier Transform
in Music Theory, Springer, 2016.
2. R. Carnap, Der Logische Aufbau der Welt, Felix Meiner Verlag, Leipzig,
1928, English version: The Logical Structure of the World. Pseudoprob-
lems in Philosophy, translated by R.A. George, University of California
Press, 1967.
3. T. Noll, “The Topos of Triads”, Colloquium on Mathematical Music
Theory, Grazer Mathematische Berichte, vol. 347, University of Graz,
2005, pp. 1–26.
Formalizing Umwelts
Rohit Parikh*
City University of New York, USA
[email protected]
147
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
148
Talks of Keynote Speakers
Capturing Consequence
Alexander Paseau*
Philosophy Faculty, University of Oxford, UK
[email protected]
149
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. D. Hilbert, “Grundlagen der Geometrie”, in Festschrift zur Feier der
Enthüllung des Gauss-Weber-Denkmals in Göttingen, edited by the Fest-
Comitee, Teubner, Leipzig, 1899.
2. D. Hilbert, Logische Principien des mathematischen Denkens, lecture
summer semester, 1905, notes by E. Hellinger, Library of the Mathe-
matical Seminar, University of Göttingen.
3. D. Hilbert & W. Ackermann, Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik, Julius
Springer, Berlin, 1928.
150
Talks of Keynote Speakers
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic and Physics” (page 398).
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
Laboratoire Lorrain de Recherche en Informatique et ses Applications
§
Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et en Automatique
¶
Research Team on Proofs and Verification
151
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Hintikka’s Logical Thought” (page 355).
152
Talks of Keynote Speakers
The concept of grounding has a long and venerable history that starts
with Aristotle and continue through philosophers such as Ockham or Bolzano.
Quite recently we assist to an impressively flourishing and increasing inter-
est for the notion of grounding, which is studied and analyzed from many
different angles. Amongst them, scholars have been trying to capture the
structural and formal properties of the concept in question by proposing
several logics of grounding [e.g. see 1,2,3,4]. In these logics grounding is for-
malized either as an operator or as a predicate. The main aim of this talk is
to present a different approach to the logic of grounding, where grounding
is formalized as a meta-linguistic relation, just like the notion of derivability
or that of logical consequence. Let me call such an approach LG. The central
characteristics of LG can be resumed in the following list:
— LG allows a rigorous account of ground-theoretic equivalence.
— In LG grounding rules are unique; in particular it is possible to formulate
an unique grounding rule for negation.
— In LG it is also possible to formulate grounding rules for implication
which are quite different from everything that has been proposed so far
and that seem to better reflect our intuitions on the issue.
— Finally LG allows to prove important results such as the soundness and
completeness theorems, but also the deduction theorem.
The main aim of this talk is to present a different approach to the logic
of grounding, where grounding is formalized as a meta-linguistic relation,
just like the notion of derivability or that of logical consequence [see 4,5].
References
1. F. Correia,“Logical Grounds”, Review of Symbolic Logic, vol. 7, 2014,
pp. 31–59.
2. K. Fine,“The pure logic of ground”, Review of Symbolic Logic, vol. 25,
2012, pp. 1–25.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Proof Theory” (page 192).
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
École Normale Supérieure
§
Institut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques
153
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Model Theory” (page 226).
154
Talks of Keynote Speakers
Homomorphism:
Definition. A map f from M to N , such that if the atomic formula ϕ(a) is
true in M , then ϕ(f.a) is true in N .
Observation. If ϕ(a) is positive and true in M , then ϕ(f.a) is true in N .
N is a continuation of M ⇔ there is an homomorphism from M to N .
Therefore: ¬ϕ(a) is forced in M ⇔ for no homomorphism f from M into
another L-structure N , ϕ(f.a) is forced in N .
Coherence of forcing:
Preservation Lemma. If ϕ(a) is forced in M , it is forced in any continuation
of M .
Definition. M is generic if truth in M coincides with forcing in M .
Lemma. M is generic iff one of the following holds, for every ϕ(a), a ∈ M :
(i) If ϕ(a) is true in M , then it is forced in M .
(ii) ϕ(a) is forced or ¬ϕ(a) is forced.
(iii) If ϕ(a) is forced in some continuation of M , then it is forced in M .
Existence Lemma. Every model of T can be continued into a generic one.
Observation. A model M of T is generic iff every homomorphism from M
into a generic model of T is an elementary embedding. Because of the JCP,
all the generic models satisfy the same sentences.
Conclusion (weak forcing). M forces ¬¬ϕ(a) iff ϕ(f.a) is true in every
generic continuation of M .
Types:
Definition. A type in n variables x = (x1 , ...xn ) is a maximal set of positive
formulae ϕi (x) which is consistent with T .
155
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Model theory:
Tarski: we consider the class of models of a (complete) theory, and elemen-
tary embeddings between them.
Robinson: we consider the class of existentially closed models of an induc-
tive theory (with the Joint Embedding Property), and embeddings between
them.
Ben-Yaacov: we consider the class of positively closed models of an h-
inductive theory (with the Joint Continuation Property), and homomor-
phisms between them.
Morleyisation interprets Tarski in Robinson and Robinson in Ben-Yaacov.
The universal domains, that is, the ω-saturated models, are more general in
Ben-Yaacov setting than in Robinson setting, and more general in Robinson
setting than in Tarski setting.
Ben-Yaacov observed that Positive Logic gives the most general Model
Theory if we want to preserve Compacity, and that the classical manipu-
lations that were done in Tarski’s setting can be extended to the positive
(and Robinson’s!) frame provided that Hausdorff separation is assumed.
156
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. F. Boas, The Mind of Primitive Man, Macmillan, New York, 1911.
2. I. Kant, Logic, translated by R.S. Hartman & W. Schwarz, Dover, New
York, 1974, 1988.
3. C. Lévi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, The University of Chicago Press,
1966.
4. L. Lévy-Bruhl, How Natives Think, translated by L.A. Clare, A.A.
Knopf, New York, 1925.
5. H.L. Morgan, Ancient Society, Henry Holt, New York, 1877.
6. J. Royce, “The Principles of Logic”, in Royce’s Logical Essays: Collected
Logical Essays of Josiah Royce, edited by D.S. Robinson, William C.
Brown, Dubuque, Iowa.
7. B. Whorf, “Science and Linguistics”, Technology Review, vol. 44, 1940,
pp. 229–231, pp. 247–248.
157
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Dialetheism is the view that some contradictions are true. One might
naturally ask for examples. This paper offers a new one. There is a well
known psychological phenomenon (noted, for example, by Plato in The
Republic) in which something is so repulsive that one is compelled to look
at it. One is attracted and repelled. Prima facie, that is a contradiction,
and, given the context, a true one. I argue that is exactly what it is. A
brief discussion of dialetheism frames the topic.
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Reflections on Paraconsistency” (page 295).
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Practices of Writing and Reading in Logic” (page 179).
158
Talks of Keynote Speakers
References
1. C. Babbage, “Observations on the notation employed in the calculus of
functions”, Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, vol. I,
1821, pp. 63–76.
2. C. Babbage, “On the influence of signs in mathematical reasoning”,
Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, vol. II, 1827,
pp. 325–377.
3. C. Babbage, “On notations”, in Edinburgh Encyclopedia, vol. 15, 1830,
pp. 394–399.
4. H. MacColl, “The calculus of equivalent statements II”, in Proceedings
of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 9, 1878, pp. 177–186.
5. H. MacColl, “On the diagrammatic and mechanical representation of
propositions and reasoning”, The London, Edinburgh and Dublin Philo-
sophical Magazine and Journal of Science, vol. 10, 1880, pp. 168–171,
reprinted in [6], pp. 276–279.
6. S. Rahman & J. Redmond (editors), Hugh MacColl: An overview of his
logical work with anthology, College Publications, 2007.
Louis Couturat is known for having made known and defended the works
of logic which were contemporary to him, especially those of Russell and the
Italian school. It is a well-deserved reputation, the work of conceptual anal-
ysis and which, different, of putting in relation the mathematicians of his
time are exceptional. But if you take a closer look at it along its work,
you realize that the place and value of logic are not simple problems for
Couturat. The logic is no longer the one taught in Greek studies, and yet it
has no place in mathematics, unlike the algebra of logic to which Couturat
always returns. On the other hand, he discovers the logic of Russell as a
novelty and invention, to which he gives, in agreement with Lalande and
Itelson, the old name of Logistics. But later, in his unpublished Manuel de
Logistique (1905), he will present it as an ancient science to which symbols
have been added, yet we know he does not like the use of symbols as Peano
instituted. Couturat is therefore in a complex relationship with the logic of
his time, and we will try, in this presentation, to unfold the causes.
*
Keynote speaker at the session “History” (page 521).
159
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. Louis Couturat, references given by Oliver Schlaudt (page 87).
2. M. Fichant & S. Roux (editors), Louis Couturat (1868–1914). Mathé-
matiques, langage, philosophie, Classiques Garnier, Paris, 2017.
3. Bertrand Russell, Correspondance avec Louis Couturat sur la Philoso-
phie, la Logique et la Politique (1897–1913), Edition and notes by Anne-
Françoise Schmid, Kimé, 2001, 735 pages.
4. A.-F. Schmid, “La Controverse entre Bertrand Russell et Henri
Poincaré”, in Dimensions of Logical Concepts, Coleção CLE book se-
ries, vol. 54, edited by J.-Y. Béziau & A. Costa-Leite, State University
of Campinas, Brazil, 2009.
5. A.-F. Schmid, “Méditation sur la clause finale”, in Construction: Fest-
schrift for Gerhard Heinzmann, edited by L. Rollet, P.-E. Bour
& Ph. Nabonnand, Archives Henri-Poincaré series, Presses de l’Université
de Nancy, 2010, pp. 75–84.
6. A.-F. Schmid, “Couturat’s Reception of Leibniz”, in New Essays on
Leibniz Reception in Science and Philosophy of Science 1800–2000,
edited by R. Krömer & Y. Chin-Drian, Birkhäuser, 2011, pp. 65–84.
7. A.-F. Schmid, “La notion de critique chez Couturat et ses effets dans
sa philosophie des mathématiques”, in [2], pp. 65–85.
8. A.-F. Schmid & O. Schlaudt, “Annexe II — Sur le projet d’édition de
la correspondance de Couturat”, in [2], pp. 335–339.
Ill-Defined Attitudes
Roy Sorensen*
Department of Philosophy,
Washington University, St. Louis, USA
[email protected]
160
Talks of Keynote Speakers
When the topic changes ‘God exists’, Ayer ([1], pp. 115–116) and Geach
[2] reverse roles. Now, it is Geach who must make sense of Ayer’s attribution
of nonsense. He will receive little help from standard models of belief.
Nevertheless, Geach poses the deeper enigma because he is a non-cognitivist
about a simple logical tautology. In “The Deviant Logician’s Dilemma”,
W.V. Quine ([3], pp. 80–83) says that any attempt to deny a logical law
just changes the subject. But Geach only denies that ‘(x)(x = x)’ is well-
defined.
References
1. A.J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic, Dover, New York, 1946.
2. P. Geach, Logic Matters, Blackwell, Oxford, 1972.
3. W.V. Quine, Philosophy of Logic, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1970.
161
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Here the common conflation of 1) and 2), as well as the almost universal
reduction of 2) to 4), will be given special attention at the hand of writings
of Frege and Tarski.
References
1. G. Frege, “Gefankengefüge” (Compound Thoughts), Beiträge zur Philoso-
phie des deutschen Idealismus, vol. 3(1), 1923, pp. 36–51.
2. P. Schroeder-Heister, “Validity Concepts in Proof-theoretic Semantics”,
Synthese, vol. 148(3), 2006, pp. 525–571.
3. G. Sundholm, ““Inference versus consequence” revisited: Inference,
consequence, conditional, implication”, Synthese, vol. 187(3), 2012,
pp. 943–956.
4. G. Sundholm, “The Neglect of Epistemic Considerations in Logic.
The Case of Epistemic Assumptions”, forthcoming in TOPOI, 2017,
http://goo.gl/YKJMpe.
5. A. Tarski, “On the Concept of Following Logically”, History and Phi-
losophy of Logic, vol. 23(3), 2002, pp. 155–196.
162
Talks of Keynote Speakers
lesser known side of Sobociński — that is, his philosophical formation fol-
lowing in the footsteps of his two great teachers. Sobociński combined the
philosophical acumen and ‘mathematical’ preciseness of Lukasiewicz with
Leśniewski’s deep philosophical interests expressed in his general and sys-
tematic framework. His early philosophical interests are known because of
his collaboration with the Cracow Circle — the Catholic ‘branch’ of the
Lvov-Warsaw School. Sobociński did not publish any papers concerning
the topics researched by the school, having a merely ‘advisory’ role on the
subject of logic. However, as evidenced by his unpublished correspondence
with Father Bocheński, Sobociński had his own, original philosophical views
on the topics addressed by the Circle. In his letters he discussed the issue
of the existence of universals and developed his original metaconceptualistic
point of view; he considered the possibility to formalise the concept of the
Universe on mereological grounds, and outlined the applications of mereo-
logical concepts to theological issues. This lecture will survey his views in to
the original manuscripts and suggest an modern formulation of their main
tenets.
Ryuta Arisaka
University of Perugia, Italy
a [email protected]
Ken Satoh
National Institute of Informatics, Tokyo, Japan
[email protected]
163
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
164
Talks of Keynote Speakers
165
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Keynote speaker at the workshop “Logic, Law and Legal Reasoning” (page 381).
166
Talks of Keynote Speakers
The first part of this talk will be concerned with theory of paraconsistent
logics. Namely, a new upcoming book titled ‘Effective Propositional Para-
consistent Logics’ (joint work with Arnon Avron and Ofer Arieli) will be
introduced and discussed. The purpose of this book is to provide a compre-
hensive methodological presentation of the rich mathematical theory that
exists by now concerning what is the heart of paraconsistent reasoning:
paraconsistent propositional logics. Among those logics it mainly concen-
trates on those which are effective (in the sense that they are decidable, have
a concrete semantics, and can be equipped with implementable analytic
proof systems). We will start by defining basic notions related to paracon-
sistency, considering some important approaches to paraconsistency, such
as multi-valued logics (both truth functional and non-deterministic); logics
of formal inconsistency; paraconsistent logics which are based on modal log-
ics. Each logic in the book is studied from both a semantical and a proof
theoretical points of view.
The second part of this talk will focus on practical aspects of paracon-
sistency in the context of requirement engineering, one of the fundamental
stages of software development. The problem of inconsistency in require-
ments specifications has been in the spotlight of the software engineering
community for many years. While in the previous decades, it was perceived
as a problem that needs to be eliminated on sight, recently, it has been more
widely recognized that maintaining consistency at all times is not only in-
feasible but even counterproductive. Over the last decades, a more tolerant
approach toward inconsistency has emerged [1], along with tools supporting
inconsistency management (e.g., [2,3]). However, their adoption in practice
has remained quite modest. I will describe an empirical study (joint work
with Irit Hadar and Daniel Berry [4,5,6]), which investigated practition-
ers’ perceptions and attitudes towards inconsistency management, aiming
to better understand the practical barriers of the adoption of inconsistency
management tools in practice.
*
Keynote speaker at the session “Non-Classical Logics” (page 439).
167
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. B. Nuseibeh, S. Easterbrook & A. Russo, “Making Inconsistency Re-
spectable in Software Development”, Journal of Systems and Software,
vol. 58(2), 2001, pp. 171–180.
2. N. Ernst, A. Borgida, J. Mylopoulos & I. Jureta, “Agile Requirements
Evolution via Paraconsistent Reasoning”, in Proceedings of the 24th
International CAiSE* , 2012, pp. 382–397.
3. A. Finkelstein, D. Gabbay, A. Hunter, J. Kramer & B. Nuseibeh, “In-
consistency Handling in Multiperspective Specifications”, in IEEE Trans-
actions on Software Engineering, vol. 20(8), 1994, pp. 569–578.
4. I. Hadar & A. Zamansky, “When a Paradigm is Inconsistent with In-
tuition: The Case of Inconsistency Management”, in Proceedings of 3rd
International Workshop on COGNISE , Lecture Notes in Business In-
formation Processing, vol. 215, 2015, pp. 107–113.
5. I. Hadar & A. Zamansky, “Cognitive Factors in Inconsistency Manage-
ment”, in Proceedings of 23rd IEEE§ International Requirements Engi-
neering Conference, 2015, pp. 226–229.
6. A. Zamansky, I. Hadar & D. Berry, “Reasoning about Inconsistency in
RE¶ : Separating the Wheat from the Chaff”, in Proceedings of the 11th
International Conference on ENASE , 2016, pp. 377–382.
*
Conference on Advanced Information Systems Engineering
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers
Cognitive Aspects of Information Systems Engineering
§
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers
¶
Requirements Engineering
Evaluation of Novel Software Approaches to Software Engineering
168
14 – Workshops
Lorenz Demey
Center for Logic and Analytic Philosophy,
KU Leuven, Belgium
[email protected]
Hans Smessaert
Department of Linguistics, KU Leuven, Belgium
[email protected]
169
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
170
Workshops
171
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. Avicenna, al-Shifā“, al-Mant.iq 4: al-Qiyās, edited by S. Zayed, revision
and introduction by I. Madkour, Cairo, 1964.
2. E.A. Hacker, “The octagon of opposition”, Notre Dame Journal of For-
mal Logic, vol. 16(3), 1975, pp. 352–353.
In our talk, we shall first review the evidence that these two choices
form an asymmetric ordered pair ⟨±R, ±P ⟩, with the past oriented binary
choice ±R linearly before and vertically higher in the syntactic structure
than the future oriented binary choice ±P . This state of affairs parallels the
asymmetrical earlier to later iconicity that characterizes path expressions
such as spatial from Brussels to Paris or temporal from 2 to 5, where the
172
Workshops
And here too, what is involved is an ordered pair: ⟨±perf, ±prog⟩. Though
the two aspectual choices involve finite time-segments rather than jumps to
tense reference points, they are characterised by the same source-goal or
before-after-asymmetry as ⟨±R, ±P ⟩, witness the only possible order of the
perfective and progressive auxiliaries in the tense forms below.
173
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
tense vertices in the kite-representation provided in [1, p. 135, fig. 12], more
specifically the A- and Y-corners of each of the two connected kites.
Reference
1. D. Jaspers, “The English Tenses, Blanché and the Logical Kite”, in The
Road to Universal Logic: Festschrift for 50th Birthday of Jean-Yves
Béziau, Volume II, edited by A. Koslow & A. Buchsbaum, Birkhäuser,
2015, pp. 319–337.
174
Workshops
References
1. A. Moretti, “Arrow Hexagons”, in The Road to Universal Logic: Festschrift
for 50th Birthday of Jean-Yves Béziau, Volume II, edited by A. Koslow
& A. Buchsbaum, Birkhäuser, 2015, pp. 417–489.
2. H. Schepers, “Logisches Quadrat”, in Historisches Wörterbuch der Philoso-
phie, volume 7, edited by H.J. Ritter, K. Gründer et al., Schwabe, Basel,
Switzerland, 1971ff, pp. 1733–1736.
3. U. O’Meadhra, “Medieval Logic Diagrams in Bro Church, Gotland, Swe-
den”, Acta Archaeologica, vol. 83(1), 2012, pp. 287–316.
4. A. Moretti, The Geometry of Logical Opposition, PhD thesis, University
of Neuchâtel, Switzerland, 2009.
5. A. Geulincx, “De Cubo Logico”, in Methodus inveniendi argumenta,
quae solertia quibusdam dicitur, Lugdunum Batavorum, 1675.
6. A. De Morgan, “Logical Bibliography”, Notes and Queries, vol. 3(6),
1864, pp. 101–104.
175
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
176
Workshops
References
1. A. Costa-Leite, “Opposition in a line segment”, arXiv:1604.03054,
Cornell University Library, 2016.
2. F. Schang, “An Arithmetization of Logical Oppositions”, in The Square
of Opposition: A Cornerstone of Thought, edited by J.-Y. Béziau
& G. Basti, Birkhäuser, 2017, pp. 215–237.
3. H. Smessaert & L. Demey, “Logical Geometries and Information in the
Square of Oppositions”, Journal of Logic, Language and Information,
vol. 23(4), 2014, pp. 527–565.
177
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
this to simple examples of classical Aristotelian diagrams and the way they
are utilized. In this comparison the focus will be on the function of the
geometrical property of symmetry.
178
Workshops
Anna-Sophie Heinemann
University of Paderborn, Germany
[email protected]
Amirouche Moktefi
Tallinn University of Technology, Estonia
[email protected]
A great deal of the working logician’s job is to write and read. This
holds in at least two senses:
First, in order to tackle a task in logic, it is necessary to apply the rules
for transformation or deduction as stated relative to a given logical system.
In order to apply these rules correctly, you may produce certain inscriptions
and watch a sequence of transformations of an initially given formula, i.e.,
you may write down the consecutive steps and eventually read off the result.
But secondly, there is a broader sense in which writing and reading
are relevant to logic. Communicating logical problems (and solutions) in-
evitably requires activities of writing for an audience, and most commonly
at least some bits of prose. Then, participating in the ‘logical community’
will typically require to disseminate your outcomes. But participating in
the ‘logical community’ also requires to work through others’ contributions.
Hence activities of reading are necessary to assess received input — which
may then again be commented on, corrected or disproved. Moreover, the
range of available input may depend on individual or collective activities of
selecting and systematizing items of logical work which is deemed as rele-
vant. Hence what there is for you to read may to great extent depend not
only on what has been written, but also on what has been read by others.
The presently announced workshop aims at an account of logic as con-
strued from logicians’ practices of writing and reading in both respects.
Further interests are activities of commenting or reviewing, and of publish-
ing and collecting. In order to take an interdisciplinary stance, the workshop
will allow for a variety of approaches.
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Dirk Schlimm (page 158) and
Volker Peckhaus (page 149).
179
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
180
Workshops
References
1. P. Hinst, “Pragmatische Regeln des logischen Argumentierens”, in Logik
und Pragmatik. Zum Rechtfertigungsproblem logischer Sprachregeln,
edited by C.F. Gethmann, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 1982, pp. 199–215.
2. F. Reinmuth, Logische Rekonstruktion. Ein hermeneutischer Traktat,
Dissertation, Institute of Philosophy, University of Greifswald, 2014,
http://ub-ed.ub.uni-greifswald.de/opus/volltexte/2014/1996.
3. F. Reinmuth & M. Cordes, “Commentary and Illocutionary Expressions
in Linear Calculi of Natural Deduction”, Logic and Logical Philosophy,
vol. 26(2), 2017, pp. 163–196, doi.org:10.12775/LLP.2017.002.
When communicating their research, logicians not only write words and
formulas, but they also draw various kinds of diagrams. The use of diagrams
has a very long history in logic, including diagrams such as the Porphyrian
tree and the pons asinorum in medieval logic, and Euler diagrams, Venn
diagrams and Peirce graphs in more recent times [2]. In this contribution,
however, I will focus on yet another broad category of diagrams used in logic,
viz. Aristotelian diagrams. These diagrams visually represent the elements
of some logical, lexical or conceptual field, and the logical relations hold-
ing between them (in particular, the relations of contradiction, contrariety,
subcontrariety and subalternation). Without a doubt, the oldest and most
well-known example is the ‘square of opposition’ for the categorical state-
ments from syllogistics; however, throughout history, several larger, more
181
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
182
Workshops
References
1. C. Dutilh Novaes, “Toward a Practice-Based Philosophy of Logic:
Formal Languages as a Case Study”, Philosophia Scientiae,
vol. 16(1), 2012, pp. 71–102, https://journals.openedition.org/
philosophiascientiae/719.
2. A. Moktefi & S.-J. Shin, “A History of Logic Diagrams”, in Handbook
of the History of Logic, volume 11: Logic: A History of its Central
Concepts, edited by D.M. Gabbay, F.J. Pelletier & J. Woods, Elsevier,
2012, pp. 611–682.
3. H. Smessaert & L. Demey, “Logical Geometries and Information in the
Square of Oppositions”, Journal of Logic, Language and Information,
vol. 23(4), 2014, pp. 527–565.
183
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
so with the hope that a community of researchers will actually use it; in
this sense notation is a social project. Frege had little success on the social
side of notation-building, but he understood its importance. His sustained
efforts to teach students in Jena to use Begriffsschrift spanned decades. As
Frege drew and explicated his sprawling symbolism on the blackboard, how-
ever, he did not invite students into any sort of dialogue. I argue that by
conducting his lectures without interaction, Frege performed in practice his
theoretical position that logic was already there to be observed, not sub-
ject to human intervention or manipulation. Just as Frege promoted his
notation as an observational technology for arraying logic on the page, so
was attending his lectures a passive, observational experience. By explor-
ing Frege’s concept of notation as he enacted it in the classroom, I aim to
reveal the enmeshed social and theoretical layers of the ultimately practical
question of how people write logic down.
References
1. G. Frege, Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formel-
sprache des reinen Denkens, L. Nebert, Halle, Germany, 1879.
2. G. Landini, Frege’s Notations: What They Are and How They Mean,
Palgrave, New York, 2012.
3. D. Macbeth, Frege’s Logic, Harvard University Press, 2005.
4. D. Schlimm, “Frege’s Begriffsschrift Notation for Propositional Logic:
Design Principles and Trade-Offs”, History and Philosophy of Logic,
vol. 39(1): History and Philosophy of Logical Notation, 2018,
pp. 53–79, doi:10.1080/01445340.2017.1317429.
184
Workshops
185
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
186
Workshops
References
1. G. Gentzen, “Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen”, Mathema-
tische Zeitschrift, vol. 39, 1935, pp. 176–210 and pp. 405–431.
2. G. Gentzen, “Über die Existenz unabhängiger Axiomensystem zu un-
endlichen Satzsystemen”, Mathematische Annalen, vol. 107, 1933,
pp. 329–350.
3. P. Hertz, “Über Axiomensysteme für beliebige Satzsysteme. I Teil.
Sätze ersten Grades”, Mathematische Annalen, vol. 87, 1923, pp. 246–
269.
4. P. Hertz, “Über das Wesen der Logik und der logischen Urteilsfor-
men”, Abhandlungen der Fries’schen Schule. Neue Folge, vol. 6, 1935,
pp. 227–272.
187
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
tolerance and logical pluralism. Compared with this, Hahn’s role as a pio-
neer of logical pluralism has not been sufficiently acknowledged yet, partly
due to the informal style of his few philosophical writings, which were di-
rected towards a broad public. It is only transcripts of Hahn’s courses at
the University of Vienna which document his use of truth-tables. Along
with hitherto barely discussed remarks in the meetings of the Vienna Cir-
cle, Hahn’s more technical lectures to students and experts corroborate the
claim that he indeed systematically adopted logical pluralism prior to Car-
nap and Menger.
As a consequence of the more nuanced reading proposed in this paper,
Hahn’s logicist and nominalist philosophy of mathematics is not subject to
the otherwise fatal critique brought forward by Gödel [7].
References
1. W. Goldfarb, “The Philosophy of Mathematics in Early Positivism”, in
Origins of Logical Empiricism, edited by R.N. Giere et al., volume 16
of Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science series, University of
Minnesota Press, 1996, pp. 213–230.
2. W. Goldfarb, “On Gödel’s Way in: The Influence of Rudolf Carnap”,
The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 11(2), 2005, pp. 185–193.
3. W. Goldfarb & T. Ricketts, “Carnap and the Philosophy of Mathemat-
ics”, in Wissenschaft und Subjektivität — Der Wiener Kreis und die
Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, edited by D. Bell & R. Vossenkuhl,
Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1992, pp. 61–78.
4. T. Ricketts, “Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance, Empiricism, and Conven-
tionalism”, in Reading Putnam, edited by P. Clark & B. Hale, Blackwell,
Oxford, 1992, pp. 176–200.
5. T. Uebel, “Learning Logical Tolerance: Hans Hahn on the Foundations
of Mathematics”, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 26(3), 2007,
pp. 175–209.
6. T. Uebel, “Carnap’s Logical Syntax in the Context of the Vienna Cir-
cle”, in Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language, edited by P. Wagner,
Palgrave-Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2009, pp. 53–78.
7. K. Gödel (1953), “Is mathematics syntax of language?”, in Collected
Works: Volume III: Unpublished essays and lectures, edited by S. Fe-
ferman et al., Oxford University Press, 1995, pp. 334–363.
188
Workshops
This talk will be about the notational choices made by American philoso-
pher Fred Sommers in the design of his system of formal logic, called Tra-
ditional Formal Logic (TFL). Starting in the 1960s, Sommers objected to
the mainstream practice in formal logic, rooted in the work of Frege: in
particular, Sommers criticized the quantifier-variable rendering of general
statements, because this practice produces formal sentences which are of-
ten syntactically distant from their natural language equivalents. Sommers
instead proposed that a logic like Aristotle’s, that takes sentences of the
form “[Some/All] X [are/are not] Y” to be primitive, could be formalized to
achieve the same inferential power as the mainstream Fregean logic, while
maintaining the ease for users and learners that comes with syntactic close-
ness to natural language. Thus, in developing TFL, Sommers paid close
attention to how his logic would be used, an important aspect of which
is its notational design: Sommers revised TFL’s notation many times over
three decades, as he invented new notational devices and his design princi-
ples changed.
At the beginning, Sommers’ desiderata for his notation were ease of use
and extendibility to sentences of arbitrarily high complexity, but over time
these evolved to include psychological realism, i.e., the belief that a logical
notation can and should mirror the actual cognitive processes of reasoning.
These desiderata sometimes came into conflict, and in later versions of TFL
concerns with psychological realism seem to take precedence over ease of
use. Ease of use, moreover, is difficult to characterize, in part because it
depends on the examples on which the logic is employed — in particular,
the frequent choice of Lewis Carroll’s logic puzzles as in-text examples by
Sommers and his followers shows the ease of using TFL for those puzzles,
but that easiness may not extend to more “everyday” situations of infer-
ence. Sommers’ notational choices can also be fruitfully compared to those
of historical designers of formal logical systems. For instance, like Boole,
Sommers chose to exploit analogies of logic to arithmetic and algebra in
his notational design, despite important and potentially confusing disanalo-
gies. Also, contra Frege, Sommers uses mathematical symbols in his logical
notation, reflecting his vision of TFL as a tool for philosophers, to aid in
natural-language reasoning, rather than as a tool for mathematicians, to
organize proofs.
189
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. F. Sommers, “The Calculus of Terms”, Mind, New Series, vol. 79(313),
1970, pp. 1–39.
2. F. Sommers, The Logic of Natural Language, Clarendon Press, 1982.
190
Workshops
References
1. M. Black, A Companion to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, Cornell University
Press, 1964.
2. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, translated by
C.K. Ogden, Routledge, 2005.
191
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Proof Theory
This workshop is organized by
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Francesca Poggiolesi (page 153)
and Alexander Leitsch (page 134).
192
Workshops
Reference
1. R. Goré, “Substructural logics on display”, Logic Journal of the IGPL * ,
vol. 6(3), 1998, pp. 451–504.
*
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
193
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Topic of our talk is the notion of pure proofs from a proof theoretical
point of view. In a first step, we explain how to deal with this informal
philosophical notion in a formal way. We identify formal counterparts to the
relevant philosophical concepts and notions and provide a formal definition
of pure proofs, this means a definition of pure derivations (in the calculus
of Natural Deduction).
The main goal of our talk is to show that every derivation can be trans-
formed into a pure derivation, namely into a derivation satisfying the follow-
ing condition: every non-logical symbol (the counterparts of mathematical
notions) occurring in the derivation already occur in an essential assumption
or in the conclusion of this derivation.
Partial results are easily obtained via well-known results: it is a technical
lemma that we may replace unnecessary constant symbols by variables.
Pureness with respect to relation symbols is a consequence of the existence
of the Prawitz normal form and of the subformula property. The crucial
aspect is the treatment of function symbols: to prove the existence of a pure
derivation, we have to replace some (only the unnecessary) occurrences of
terms in a derivation by variables, and to show that the resulting derivation
satisfies our demands.
In the course of our argumentation, we overcome some technical difficul-
ties: we introduce a formal notion of occurrences of terms in a derivation.
We identify congruent occurrences of terms in a derivation, namely those
occurrences which have to be of the same shape due to the inference rules
according to which the derivation under discussion is generated. Finally, we
show under which conditions such congruent occurrences can be replaced
by variables (or other suitable terms). Applying this substitution theorem
to derivations in Prawitz normal form, we obtain pure derivations.
Our result also sheds light on the problem of the identity of proofs, an-
other philosophically relevant problem of proof theory. When transforming
a derivation into its pure version, we do not change its normal form, but
an essential property of this derivation. This seems to be a good reason to
reconsider, whether we should identify derivations having the same normal
form.
194
Workshops
195
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. R.B. Brandom, Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Dis-
cursive Commitment, Harvard University Press, 1994.
2. R.B. Brandom, Articulating reasons: an introduction to inferentialism,
Harvard University Press, 2000.
3. R.B. Brandom, Between saying and doing: towards an analytic prag-
matism, Oxford University Press, 2008.
4. W. de Campos Sanz & T. Piecha, “Inversion by definitional reflec-
tion and the admissibility of logical rules”, Review of Symbolic Logic,
vol. 2(3), 2009, pp. 550–569.
5. M.N. Lance & P. Kremer, “The logical structure of linguistic commit-
ment 1: Four systems of non-relevant commitment entailment”, Journal
of Philosophical Logic, vol. 23(4), 1994, pp. 369–400.
6. B. Nickel, “Dynamics, Brandom-style”, Philosophical Studies,
vol. 162(2), 2013, pp. 333–354.
7. J. Peregrin, Inferentialism: why rules matter, Palgrave Macmillan, 2014.
8. T. Piecha & P. Schroeder-Heister, “Atomic systems in proof-theoretic
semantics: Two approaches”, in Epistemology, Knowledge and the Im-
pact of Interaction, edited by J. Redmond, O.P. Martins & Á.N. Fer-
nández, Springer, 2016, pp. 47–62.
9. P. Piwek, “Towards a computational account of inferentialist meaning”,
in Proceedings of the 50th Anniversary Convention of the AISB * , 2014,
https://goo.gl/zyrMJR.
10. T. Sandqvist, “Base-extension semantics for intuitionistic sentential
logic”, Logic Journal of the IGPL , vol. 23(5), 2015, pp. 719–731.
11. T. Sandqvist, Hypothesis-Discharging Rules in Atomic Bases, Springer,
2015.
12. P. Schroeder-Heister, “Generalized definitional reflection and the inver-
sion principle”, Logica Universalis, vol. 1(2), 2007, pp. 355–376.
13. P. Schroeder-Heister, “Definitional reflection and basic logic”, Annals
of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 164(4), 2013, pp. 491–501.
*
Society for the Study of Artificial Intelligence and the Simulation of Behaviour
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
196
Workshops
197
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In the last section V of his thesis, after the proof of the Hauptsatz,
Gentzen proved the equivalence between the main three types of formal-
ization of the logical inference: the Hilbert-Ackermann system (H.A.), the
Natural Deduction Calculus (N.D.), and the Sequent Calculus (S.C.). In this
proof we can see, so to say, the birth of the same formalism of S.C., which is
maybe the most important formalization of logical deduction ever provided.
Also the handwritten version of the thesis, let’s say Ms.ULS, contains a sim-
ilar proof of equivalence, as we have learnt from the important researches
made by Jan von Plato on the newly found Gentzen’s texts. Admittedly, the
last section of the thesis is normally rated “less important” than the other
sections, but nonetheless it casts some important light on the emergence of
the S.C., and more generally on some structural features of Gentzen’s work.
In the Thesis the equivalence proof proceeds through the following sequence
of steps: i) a proof that every derivation within the H.A.-axiomatization can
be transformed in an equivalent derivation of N.D.-calculus; ii) a proof that
every N.D.-derivation can be transformed into an equivalent S.C.-derivation;
iii) a proof that every S.C.-derivation can be transformed into an equivalent
H.A.-derivation. The proof is conducted first for Intuitionistic logic and
afterward for Classical logic. In this way, of course, the goal to prove the
equivalence of all three calculi is accomplished. However, the main single
component showing the origin of S.C. is the translation of derivations built
198
Workshops
199
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
S = {Γi ϕi ∣ i ∈ I} ⊆ EXP
F ○ (G ⊔ H) = (F ○ G) ⊔ (F ○ H)
of the first axiom does not hold, and neither do the variants
I ⊔ F* ○ F ⊑ F*
and
if F ○ G ⊑ F then F ○ G* ⊑ F
*
F G iff G ⊑ ( ⊔ (σ ⋅ F)) ,
σ∈SUB
where SUB denotes the set of all substitutions and where σ ⋅ F is defined by
With the proper establishment of notions and results for the combi-
nation of set-valued functions with substitutions, we can scale up to the
investigation of proof systems for algebraic theories and propositional log-
ics, involving sequents. The next step to first-order logic requires another
extension to deal with variable binders (like quantifiers). All in all, it is my
goal to substantiate the claim that set-valued functions are a core ingredient
for the proper mathematical analysis of derivability.
References
1. G.R. Renardel de Lavalette, “Interpolation in propositional Horn logic”,
Journal of Logic and Computation, doi:10.1093/logcom/exx042.
2. B. Möller, “Kleene getting lazy”, Science of Computer Programming,
vol. 65(2), 2007, pp. 195–214.
201
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
202
Workshops
References
1. D.J.D. Hughes, “Proofs without Syntax”, Annals of Mathematics,
vol. 164(3), 2006, pp. 1065–1076.
2. D.J.D. Hughes, “Towards Hilbert’s 24th problem: Combinatorial Proof
Invariants: (preliminary version)”, Electronic Notes in Theoretical Com-
puter Science, vol. 165, 2006, pp. 37–63.
3. L. Straßburger, Combinatorial Flows and Proof Compression, Research
Report RR-9048, Inria Saclay, 2017, https://hal.inria.fr/hal-
01498468.
4. L. Straßburger, “Combinatorial Flows and Their Normalisation”, in
Conference on Formal Structures for Computation and Deduction,
LIPIcs * book series, vol. 84, edited by D.W. Miller, 2017, also published
in Schloss Dagstuhl, vol. 31, Leibniz-Zentrum fuer Informatik, 2017,
pp. 1–31.
*
Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics
203
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Ingolf Max
University of Leipzig, Germany
[email protected]
204
Workshops
205
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. W.E. Johnson, Logic: Part 1, Dover, New York, 1921.
2. M. Matthen, Seeing, Doing and Knowing. A Philosophical Theory of
Sense Perception, Oxford University Press, 2005.
3. W. Sellars, “The Structure of Knowledge* ”, in Action, Knowledge and
Reality: Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, edited by H.-N. Castañeda,
Bobbs Merrill, Indianapolis, USA, 1975, pp. 295–347.
*
Lecture I: Perception; Lecture II: Minds; Lecture III: Epistemic Principles.
206
Workshops
207
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. D. Huron, Sweet Anticipation: Music and the Psychology of Expectation,
MIT* Press, 2006.
2. P.N. Juslin & J.A. Sloboda (editors), Handbook of Music and Emotion,
Oxford University Press, 2010.
3. V. Kolman, “Emotions and Understanding in Music”, Idealistic Studies,
vol. 44(1), 2014, pp. 83–100.
4. V. Kolman, “Normative Pragmatism and the Language Game of Mu-
sic”, Contemporary Pragmatism, vol. 11(2), 2014, pp. 147–163.
5. V. Kolman, “Hegel’s ‘Bad Infinity’ as a Logical Problem”, Hegel Bul-
letin, vol. 37(2), 2016, pp. 258–280.
6. L. Meyer, Emotion and Meaning in Music, University of Chicago Press,
1956.
208
Workshops
selves towards those present around us. We synchronize all of our move-
ments. When we slow down a video of people, they seem to be dancing.
Other great apes may lack this joint synchronicity.
Musical activity could have fostered such joint synchronicity. It may
have started with identical twins. Rhythmic unison — singing, drumming
and dancing together — may have attracted mates, and engendered a vir-
tuous cycle of rapid evolutionary change. This would have fostered that
“sixth sense” but also improved vocal chord control. For the group, musical
activity could have heightened the sense of “we” before and after a shared
activity, such as a hunt. Work songs fostered a sense of shared work. As
the repertoire of songs grew, they could influence language.
In linguistics, Jackendoff has noted that syntax must have arisen after a
protolanguage with a linear grammar which was quite robust. Such a linear
grammar is used by sailors speaking pidgin; second language users who
never develop fluency; people with certain brain injuries; deaf children who
develop their own gestures; but also the great apes. It consists of strings
of words for which there are no rules. Word order is simply determined
pragmatically in context.
Joint musical activity demands a perfection of all and at all times. It
thus legislates rules. Sounds or words must be annunciated exactly. Rituals
develop. Words and concepts become categorized, as Levi-Strauss observed.
People develop a sense of right or wrong, in-tune or out-of-tune, grammatical
or ungrammatical. Rules must be followed in creating new words. Syntax
arises as rules which may not be broken, and is distinct from pragmatic
constraints.
Language arises from pragmatic activity. Nonlinear grammar arises with
the division of labor such that we can perform a task that we do not com-
pletely understand, as when using a new word, or playing our own part in a
greater musical whole. This fosters our ability to hear what others are say-
ing as well as what we ourselves are thinking. Whereas perhaps other apes
can only think one perspective at a time. Thus they can answer questions
but they never ask them. Musical activity teaches us to be “I” and “you”
and “they” and “we”, in parallel.
209
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J. Harrington, Time: A Philosophical Introduction, Bloomsbury, Lon-
don, 2015.
2. J.E. McTaggart, “The unreality of time”, Mind, vol. 17(68), 1908,
pp. 457–474.
210
Workshops
211
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
using chord operators. Internal harmony is nothing else than the relation
between two or more chords based solely on the inner structure of these
chords. In this sense “chord” as well as “harmony” are formal concepts.
Euphony is not necessary. E.g., we have of course chords and harmony
in twelve-tone music (dodecaphony) and free jazz in a chromatic space.
A unary chord operator takes a chord as its input and yields a chord as
its output. There are operators permuting the lengths of basic intervals.
Examples are complete inversions of basic interval lengths relative to tone-
related or interval-related fixed points (among them a kind of non-classical
negation of chords) and cyclic permutation operators. There are tone-related
operators like barré operators (outputs with identical matrices of interval
lengths. An n-ary chord operator (n ≤ 2) takes an n-tuple of chords as input
and yields a chord as its output. If it comes to more complex harmonic
constructions like sequences consisting of tonic, subdominant and dominant
(cadences) it can be useful to have at least binary operators to create them.
4. Inference relations: Characterization of types of tone-related inference re-
lations as well as inference relations with respect to interval lengths: Tonal-
ity can be understood as rule-governed restrictions on the inner structure
of chords as well as restrictions on the sequences of chords (e.g., creating
cadences) accompanied by special inference properties.
If total this means that we will show that there is a partial positive
answer to our initial question but the jury is still out.
Michael Heather
University of Cambridge, UK
[email protected]
212
Workshops
References
1. A. Popoff, M. Andreatta & A. Ehresmann, “A Categorical Generaliza-
tion of Klumpenhouwer Networks”, in Mathematics and Computation
in Music: 5th International Conference, 2015, pp. 303–314.
2. N. Rossiter, M. Heather & M. Brockway, “Monadic Design for Universal
Systems”, ANPA * Proceedings 37 & 38, edited by A.L. Vrba, 2018,
pp. 369–399, https://goo.gl/YXxy43.
*
Alternative Natural Philosophy Association
213
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Raffaela Giovagnoli
Faculty of Philosophy,
Pontifical Lateran University, Vatican City
[email protected]
Robert Lowe
Division of Cognition and Communication,
Department of Applied Information Technology,
University of Gothenburg, Sweden
[email protected]
214
Workshops
215
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
distributive principles of social and economical justice, such as, for instance,
the famous J. Rawl’s maxmin principle, which gives priority to the interests
of worst-off persons. This transforms SCF Theory into a normative theory
of social choices. On this regard, Sen demonstrated that an effective math-
ematical modeling of ethical constraints in economy cannot be based on
abstract and not-computable optimal choices defined on the complete (to-
tal) ordering of social/economical states in a society, but on concrete criteria
of maximal choices relative to the different contexts, and then defined on
partial orderings, not necessarily satisfying a transitive relation among the
different social aggregates (sets) of persons so defined, and between groups
and the whole society. All this means that the physical paradigm under-
lying Sen’s mathematical theory of economy and society is no longer the
gas thermodynamics stable at equilibrium of the liberalism mathematical
models, but the fluid thermodynamics of condensed matter systems, stable
in far from equilibrium conditions, characterizing a “liquid society” such
as ours. The real-time information exchange among communication agents
determines the fast aggregation/dissolution of interest groups in a world-
wide environment — think, for instance, at the stock-exchange market and
at the infinite flow of data streams it produces. Unfortunately, this con-
dition makes unrealistic a SCF/SWF Theory based on finite [5], and then
Turing-computable sets, because, on infinite sets, Sen’s maximal partial or-
ders correspond to as many ultrafilters requiring higher order functions to
be calculated [6]. We propose in this contribution an original solution of
this problem in the formal framework of the Category Theory, based on the
categorical dual equivalence (anti-isomorphism) between co-algebras (en-
vironment) and algebras (system), originally applied to the mathematical
modelling of condensed matter thermodynamic systems, stable in far from
equilibrium conditions, in the context of quantum field theory of dissipa-
tive systems, human brains included [7,8,9]. The same categorical duality
co-algebras/algebras is used also in theoretical computer science, for for-
malizing the effectiveness of dynamic computations on infinite data streams
with always changing inner correlations — i.e., on infinite data sets just
it is the case of Sen’s SCFs. This approach is inside the paradigm of the
Algebraic/Co-algebraic Universality in computations [10,11], which is wider
than the classic Turing Universality, “probabilistic”, “quantum” Turing Ma-
chines included.
References
1. A. Bergson, “A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics”,
The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 52(2), 1938, pp. 310–334.
2. P.A. Samuelson, Foundations of Economic Analysis, Harvard University
Press, 1947.
216
Workshops
3. K.J. Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, Wiley, New York,
1951.
4. A. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare, expanded edition, Penguin
Random House, London, 2017.
5. A. Sen, “The informational basis of social choices”, in Arrow Impos-
sibility Theorem, edited by E. Maskin & A. Sen, Columbia University
Press, 2014, pp. 67–100.
6. H.R. Mihara, “Arrow’s theory and Turing computability”, Economic
Theory, vol. 10(2), 1997, pp. 257–266.
7. M. Blasone, P. Jizba & G. Vitiello, Quantum field theory and its macro-
scopic manifestations. Boson condensation, ordered patterns and topo-
logical defects, Imperial College Press, London, 2011.
8. W.J. Freeman & G. Vitiello, “Dissipation and spontaneous symmetry
breaking in brain dynamics”, Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and
Theoretical, vol. 41(30), 2008, p. 304042.
9. G. Basti, A. Capolupo & G. Vitiello, “Quantum field theory and coal-
gebraic logic in theoretical computer science”, Progress in Biophysics
and Molecular Biology, vol. 130, 2017, pp. 39–52.
10. J.J.M. Rutten, “Universal coalgebra: a theory of systems”, Theoretical
Computer Science, vol. 249(1), 2000, pp. 3–80.
11. Y. Venema, “Algebras and co-algebras”, in Handbook of Modal Logic,
edited by P. Blackburn, F.J.F. van Benthem & F. Wolter, Elsevier,
Amsterdam, 2007, pp. 331–426.
Our aim is to try to isolate a process that is common to habits and rituals
and this process is related to a reduction of complexity (in the Aristotelian
sense it entails habitus and consuetudo), that characterizes individual and
social ordinary life. But, to share habits in a larger environment where
ritual can become public, with specific rules of behavior, that make it rec-
ognizable from people inside and out side the community, we need a third
level of behavior, i.e. the process of institutionalization of them. The set of
acts which characterizes human habits can be institutionalized to form the
cultural rituals that belong to human life-forms. What we must clarify here
is how this institutionalization is possible and actually works. In this sense
what can seem merely shared habits become “social” in a strong sense, and
reinforce their function in establishing solidarity and social identity.
We can observe that human beings (but also other species) have the
capacity to impose a function to an object so that the object acquires a
function dependent on the peculiar scope of the agent. The continuity be-
tween individual habits and rituals (social habits) is thus showed by the fact
that humans create these “agentive functions” (in Searle’s terminology) in
a wide variety of situations. Also non human animals have their form of
creating functions for objects but there is a fundamental difference in the
concept of “function” in the human case.
References
1. R. Giovagnoli, “Life-world, Language and Religion. Habermas’ Per-
spective”, Aquinas, vol. 58(1–2), 2015, pp. 253–260.
2. R. Giovagnoli, “Communicative Life-world and Religion”, Asian Re-
search Journal of Arts and Social Sciences, vol. 1(3), 2016, pp. 1–7.
3. R. Giovagnoli, “Habits and Rituals”, in Proceedings of the IS4SI * ,
Gothenburg, Sweden, 2017.
4. R. Giovagnoli, “Lifeworld, We-Intentionality and Rituals”, in Mind,
Collective Agency, Norms. Essays on Social Ontology, edited by P. Salis
& G. Seddone, Shaker Verlag, Aachen, Germany, 2017, pp. 22–32.
5. R. Giovagnoli, “The Function of Language for the problem of Represen-
tation”, in Representation and Reality. Humans, Other Living Beings
and Intelligent Machines, edited by G. Dodig-Crnkovic & R. Giovagnoli,
Springer, Cham, Switzerland, 2017, pp. 235–246.
6. A. Graybiel, “Habits, Rituals and the Evaluative Brain”, Annual Review
of Neuroscience, vol. 31, 2008, pp. 359–387.
7. J. Habermas, Nachmetaphysisches Denken II: Aufsätze und Repliken,
Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt, 2012.
*
International Society for the Study of Information
218
Workshops
8. J.A. Lombo & J.M. Gimenez-Amaya, “The unity and stability of hu-
man behavior. An interdisciplinary approach to habits between philoso-
phy and neuroscience”, Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, vol. 8, 2014,
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4127468.
9. K. Schilbrak, Thinking through Rituals: Philosophical Perspectives, Rout-
ledge, London, 2004.
10. J. Searle, Making the Social World, Oxford University Press, 2010.
11. M. Tomasello, Why We Cooperate, MIT* Press, 2009.
219
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
the everyday practice of teachers and police officers where two options pre-
sented above turn out to conflict with each other. In the second part of our
presentation we will provide a critical analysis of the Aristotelian concept
of “phronesis”, that is traditionally discussed within the framework of indi-
vidual agents and judgement [5], and discuss it in relation to the question
of the possibility of collective judgment. In a third part we discuss in what
way a professional judgement or action could be understood as an expres-
sion of “collective phronesis”.
References
1. Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Harvard University Press, 1975.
2. H. Collins, Tacit and Explicit Knowledge, University of Chicago Press,
2012.
3. A. Goldman, “Experts. Which ones should you trust?”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, vol. 63(1), 2011, pp. 85–110.
4. E.A. Kinsella & A. Pitman (editors), Phronesis as Professional Knowl-
edge: Practical Wisdom in the Professions, Sense Publishers, 2012.
5. M. van Manen, Phenomenology of Practice: Meaning-Giving Methods
in Phenomenological Research and Writing, Routledge, 2014.
The link between, on the one hand, habits and goal-directed learning
within a dual-process structure, and, on the other hand, the learning of
cognitive capacities has a tradition within animal (and human) learning
paradigms. Neural network models of animal learning have been used to
learn associative relations between stimuli or/and processes and provide new
hypotheses as to the nature of learning and relationships between learn-
ing systems. However, more biologically realistic models that account for
the continuous (spatiotemporal) dynamics of the learning/decision making
problems that such theorized animal learning processes are tested on may
suffer from the challenge of finding an appropriate and cognitively intuitive
parameterization. As a consequence, the modelled processes in learning
220
Workshops
may not be easily tuned to each other. Following recent interest in integrat-
ing principles of logic into neural computational modelling, in this article,
by way of an example concerning the Associative Two-Process theory, we
suggest a neural-dynamic logic approach to understanding the nature of the
interaction between the two (habitual and goal-directed) learning processes.
We attempt to describe how the cognitive phenomena of categorization by
common outcomes, and transitive inference, can be grounded in the learning
and interactions of habits with goal-directed systems.
References
1. J. Woods, Errors of Reasoning. Naturalizing the Logic of Inference,
College Publications, London, 2013.
2. S. Arfini & L. Magnani, “An eco-cognitive model of ignorance immu-
nization”, in Philosophy and Cognitive Science II. Western & Eastern
Studies, edited by L. Magnani, P. Li & W. Park, Springer, 2015.
3. L. Magnani, Understanding Violence. The Intertwining of Morality,
Religion and Violence: A Philosophical Stance, Springer, 2011.
I will research John Searle’s [1] idea of social causation as collective inten-
tionality and (according to my understanding) the more important notion of
background. I will compare Searle’s notions of collective intentionality and
background of the social to Maurizio Ferraris’s [2] notions of text as replace-
ment of collective intentionality. The problems that Ferraris addresses are
understood here in terms of practises. In this article I will look into more
contemporary debates in social ontology and in practise approach Theodore
Schatzki [3] is a kind of pioneer in this approach. My viewpoint to Searle
comes from two ordinary language philosophers: John Austin and Ludwig
Wittgenstein. I will interpret Searle as an analytic version of the practise
approach. By this I mean that Searle has analytically distinguished social
practise to have three components, which are performative, background,
and collective intentionality. These notions, combined with the Practice
approach of Schatzki, will help me to formulate a constructive critique of
Searle’s theory. mostly in terms of Practise Approach of Schatzki, even
though many theories are used. I will concentrate. The main focus will be
in the understanding of background as the collective intentionality of being
part of the practise in general.
222
Workshops
References
1. J.R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality, Penguin Books, 1995.
2. M. Ferraris, Documentality: Why it is Necessary to Leave Traces,
Fordham University Press, 2013.
3. T.R. Schatzki Social Practices: A Wittgensteinian Approach to Human
Activity and the Social, Cambridge University Press, 1996.
223
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Del Vicario, A. Bessi, F. Zollo et al., “The spreading of misinforma-
tion online”, in PNAS * , vol. 113(3), 2016, pp. 554–559.
2. F. Zollo, P.K. Novak, M. Del Vicario et al., “Emotional dynamics in
the age of misinformation”, PLoS ONE, vol. 10(9), 2015, doi:10.1371/
journal.pone.0138740.
3. F. Zollo, A. Bessi, M. Del Vicario et al., “Debunking in a world of
tribes”, PLoS ONE, vol. 12(7), 2017, doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0181821.
4. M. Del Vicario, F. Zollo, G. Caldarelli et al., “Mapping social dynam-
ics on Facebook: The Brexit debate”, Social Newtorks, vol. 50, 2017,
pp. 6–16, doi:10.1016/j.socnet.2017.02.002.
5. A.L. Schmidt, F. Zollo, M. Del Vicario et al., “Anatomy of news con-
sumption on Facebook”, in PNAS, vol. 114(12), 2017, pp. 3035–3039,
doi:10.1073/pnas.1617052114.
224
Workshops
war & peace, war & ∼peace, ∼war & ∼peace, ∼war & peace.
225
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Model Theory
This workshop is organized by
Petros Stefaneas
National Technical University of Athens, Greece
[email protected]
Sergey Sudoplatov
Sobolev Institute of Mathematics,
Novosibirsk State Technical University,
Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk, Russia
Institute of Mathematics and Mathematical Modeling,
Almaty, Kazakhstan
[email protected]
Model theory is the branch of mathematical logic dealing with the con-
nection between a formal language and its interpretations, or models, i.e.,
it represents links between syntactic and semantic objects. These objects
can be used to classify each others producing structural classifications of
theories and their models. Solving classification questions valuable char-
acteristics arise (dimensions, ranks, complexities, spectra etc.) for various
classes of structures and their theories.
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Bruno Poizat (page 154) and
Sergey Goncharov (page 129).
226
Workshops
227
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The logic LITK, which language LLITK containing 2U is called the lin-
ear multi-agent logic based on non-transitive time with universal modality
(ULITK for short).
References
1. S. Ghilardi, “Unification Through Projectivity”, Journal of Logic and
Computation, vol. 7(6), 1997, pp. 733–752.
2. R. Iemhoff, “On the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic”,
The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 66(1), 2001, pp. 281–294.
3. W. Dzik, “Remarks on projective unifiers”, Bulletin of the Section of
Logic, vol. 40(1), 2011, pp. 37–45.
4. S.I. Bashmakov, “Unification in linear modal logic on non-transitive
time with the universal modality”, Journal of Siberian Federal Univer-
sity. Mathematics & Physics, vol. 11(1), 2018, forthcoming.
5. V.V. Rybakov, “Nontransitive temporal multiagent logic, information
and knowledge, deciding algorithms”, Siberian Mathematical Journal,
vol. 58(5), 2017, pp. 875–886.
228
Workshops
References
1. S.S. Goncharov & V.D. Dzgoev, “Autostability of models”, Algebra and
Logic, vol. 19(1), 1980, pp. 28–37.
2. B. Khoussainov & T. Kowalski, “Computable isomorphisms of Boolean
algebras with operators”, Studia Logica, vol. 100(3), 2012, pp. 481–496.
3. D.R. Hirschfeldt, B. Khoussainov, R.A. Shore & A.M. Slinko, “Degree
spectra and computable dimensions in algebraic structures”, Annals of
Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 115(1–3), 2002, pp. 71–113.
229
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Nicola Angius
Department of History, Human Sciences and Education,
University of Sassari, Italy
[email protected]
This paper focuses on the logic relations holding between syntactic and
semantic presentations of empirical theories. Two problems advanced in [2]
are extensively examined here: first, the problem of defining a notion of
equivalence such that the theoretical equivalence of two syntactic theories
implies the model-theoretic equivalence of the two corresponding semantic
theories. Secondly, the problem of establishing whether language transla-
tions of a syntactic theory are in a many-to-one or many-to-many relation
with the corresponding semantic theory(ies). This paper introduces the
theory of institutions [1] to show the logical duality holding between syntac-
tic and semantic presentations of a given theory in a language-independent
context and for any-order and multi-sorted logics.
First, syntactic and semantic presentations of scientific theories are for-
malized in the theory of institutions framework. The notions of theoretic
and model-theoretic equivalence are then defined as isomorphisms in the
categories Th and Vth of, respectively, syntactic and semantic theories. Sec-
ondly, it is proven that given an institution I, two syntactic theories over
I are equivalent if and only if the corresponding semantic theories over I
are equivalent. Finally, the many-to-many logic relations holding between
language translations of a syntactic theory and the corresponding semantic
theories are shown in terms of functors mapping syntactic theory morphisms
in Th to semantic theory morphisms in Vth.
230
Workshops
References
1. J.A. Goguen & R.M. Burstall, “Institutions: Abstract model theory
for specification and programming”, Journal of the ACM * , vol. 39(1),
pp. 95–146.
2. H. Halvorson, “What Scientific Theories Could Not Be”, Philosophy of
Science, vol. 79(2), pp. 183–206.
231
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. S.V. Sudoplatov, Classification of Countable Models of Complete The-
ories, Novosibirsk State Technical University, 2014.
2. S.V. Sudoplatov, Group Polygonometries, Novosibirsk State Technical
University, 2013.
3. D.Yu. Emelyanov & S.V. Sudoplatov, “On Deterministic and Absorb-
ing Algebras of Binary Formulas of Polygonometrical Theories”, Re-
ports of Irkutsk State University, Series “Mathematics”, vol. 20, 2017,
pp. 32–44.
We have deal with some J-ω-stable theory [1] and its semantic model.
This thesis introduced and discussed the concepts of minimal Jonsson sub-
sets and respectively strongly minimal Jonsson subsets of this semantic
model.
We want to each Jonsson subset X of the semantic model assign ordinal
number (or, perhaps, −1 or ∞) and it is the rank Morley of this set, denoted
by MR(X).
Let T is a fragment of some Jonsson set and it is a perfect Jonsson
theory, C will be its semantic model. X is a definable subset of C.
232
Workshops
References
1. A.R. Yeshkeev & M.T. Kassymetova, Jonsson theory and its classes of
models, monograph, E.A. Buketov Karaganda State University, 2016.
2. B. Zilber, Zariski geometries: geometry from the logician’s point of view,
Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Petros Stefaneas
National Technical University of Athens, Greece
[email protected]
Sergey Sudoplatov
Sobolev Institute of Mathematics,
Novosibirsk State Technical University,
Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk, Russia
Institute of Mathematics and Mathematical Modeling,
Almaty, Kazakhstan
[email protected]
In this talk we will present our joint work on definable sets and generic
structures [1]. First of all we will present an analysis of the diagrams which
forming generative classes to describe definable sets and their links in generic
structures as well as cardinality bounds for these definable sets, finite or
infinite.
233
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
234
Workshops
Petros Stefaneas
National Technical University of Athens, Greece
[email protected]
Sergey Sudoplatov
Sobolev Institute of Mathematics,
Novosibirsk State Technical University,
Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk, Russia
Institute of Mathematics and Mathematical Modeling,
Almaty, Kazakhstan
[email protected]
Theorem 1. For any self-sufficient class (D0 , ⩽) and a (D0 , ⩽)-generic struc-
ture M, the structure ⟨L(M, D0 , ⩽), ∧, ∨⟩ is a lattice which can be non-
distributive.
Theorem 2. For any self-sufficient class (D0 , ⩽) and a (D0 , ⩽)-generic struc-
ture M, the lattice L = ⟨L(M, D0 , ⩽), ∧, ∨⟩ has the following characteristics:
(1) 1 < h(L) ≤ ∣M ∣ + 1 if M is finite, and h(L) = ω if M is infinite;
(2) 1 ≤ w(L) ≤ ∣M ∣ if M is at most countable, and h(L) = ∣M ∣ if M is
uncountable.
235
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. S.V. Sudoplatov, “Syntactic approach to constructions of generic mod-
els”, Algebra and Logic, vol. 46, 2007, pp. 134–146.
2. S.V. Sudoplatov, Classification of Countable Models of Complete The-
ories, Novosibirsk State Technical University, 2018.
3. S.V. Sudoplatov, “Generative classes generated by sets of diagrams”,
Algebra and Model Theory, vol. 10, Novosibirsk State Technical Uni-
versity, 2015, pp. 163–174.
4. S.V. Sudoplatov, “Classes of structures and their generic limits”, Loba-
chevskii Journal of Mathematics, vol. 36, 2015, pp. 426–433.
5. Y. Kiouvrekis, P. Stefaneas & S.V. Sudoplatov, “Definable sets in generic
structures and their cardinalities”, Siberian Advances in Mathematics,
vol. 28, 2018, pp. 39–52.
236
Workshops
237
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
239
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
240
Workshops
Corollary. Let G be the group. Then all connected G-acts are subdirectly
irreducible if and only if the set of all subgroups of the group G is linearly
ordered.
References
1. V. Gould, “Axiomatisability problems for S-systems”, Journal of the
London Mathematical Society, vol. s2-35(2), 1987, pp. 193–201.
2. A.A. Stepanova, “Axiomatizability and completeness of some classes of
s-polygons”, Algebra and Logic, vol. 30(5), 1991, pp. 379–388.
3. A.A. Stepanova, “Axiomatizability and model completeness of classes
of regular polygons”, Siberian Mathematical Journal, vol. 35(1), 1994,
pp. 181–193.
4. S. Bulman-Fleming & V. Gould, “Axiomatisability of weakly flat, flat
and projective acts”, Communications in Algebra, vol. 30(11), 2002,
pp. 5575–5593.
241
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Theorem.
(1) For any λ ∈ ω ∪ {ω, 2ω } there is an E-combination T of theories of
finite Abelian groups (in A ∩ F and with least generating set) such that
e-Sp(T ) = λ.
(2) There are 2ω families in ClE (A)D whose E-closures do not have least
generating sets and whose E-combinations T satisfy e-Sp(T ) = 2ω .
(3) For any λ ∈ ω ∪ {ω, 2ω } there is an E-combination T of theories in BE
(respectively, ΓE, AΓE, BΓE) and with least generating set such that
e-Sp(T ) = λ.
(4) There are 2ω families ClE (BE)D (respectively, ClE (ΓE)D , ClE (AΓE)D ,
ClE (BΓE)D ) whose E-closures do not have least generating sets and
whose E-combinations T satisfy e-Sp(T ) = 2ω .
Reference
1. In.I. Pavlyuk & S.V. Sudoplatov, “On families of theories of Abelian
groups and their closures”, in 11th Panhellenic Logic Symposium, Del-
phi, Greece, 2017, pp. 45–49.
242
Workshops
θi (x, y 0 ), y1 , . . . , ymi , 1 ≤ i ≤ k;
243
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. S.S. Goncharov, Isomorphisms and Definable Relations on Computable
Models, in 2005 Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic,
Logic Colloquium ’05, The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 12(2), 2006),
pp. 310–361.
2. A.H. Mekler, “Stability of Nilpotent Groups of Class 2 and Prime Ex-
ponent”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 46(4), 1981, pp. 781–788.
3. D.R. Hirschfeldt, B. Khoussainov, R.A. Shore & A.M. Slinko, “Degree
spectra and computable dimensions in algebraic structures”, Annals of
Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 115(1–3), 2002, pp. 71–113.
4. D.A. Tussupov, “Isomorphisms and Algorithmic Properties of Struc-
tures with Two Equivalences”, Algebra and Logic, vol. 55(1), 2016,
pp. 50–57.
5. J. Johnson, J.F. Knight, V. Ocasio, J. Tussupov & S. VanDenDriessche,
“Preserving Categoricity and Complexity of Relations”, Algebra and
Logic, vol. 54(2), 2015, pp. 140–154.
6. E. Fokina, A. Frolov & I. Kalimullin, “Categoricity Spectra for Rigid
Structures”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 57(1), 2016,
pp. 45–57.
244
Workshops
With the help of the nonforking notion we will give the notion of in-
dependence for Jonsson sets. Let M ∃-saturated existentially closed model
power k (k enough big cardinal) of Jonsson theory T . Let A be the class
of all Jonsson subsets of M and P is the class of all ∃-types (not necessar-
ily complete), let JNF (Jonsson nonforking) ⊆ P × A be a binary relation.
There is the list of the axioms 1–7 which defined Jonsson nonforking notion
JNF and we have result for fragment Fr(X) of the Jonsson set X.
(in the classical meaning of S. Shelah [1]), where Fr(X)* is the center of
the fragment Fr(X).
This notion of independence for above mentioned Jonsson sets has many
desirable properties: monotonicity, transitivity, finite basis, symmetry, etc.
All concepts that are not defined in this thesis can be extracted from [2].
References
1. S. Shelah, Classification Theory and the Number of Non-Isomorphic
Models , North-Holland, 1990.
2. A.R. Yeshkeev & M.T. Kassymetova, Jonsson theory and its classes of
models, monograph, E.A. Buketov Karaganda State University, 2016.
245
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Definition 2. A theory T is called convex (C) if, for any model A and
any family {Bi ∣ i ∈ I} of its substructures, which are models of the theory
T , the intersection ⋂i∈I Bi is a model theory T . It is assumed that this
intersection is not empty. If this intersection is never empty, then the theory
is called strongly convex (SC). An inductive theory is called an existentially
prime strongly convex theory (EPSC) if it satisfies the above definitions
simultaneously.
All concepts that are not defined in this thesis can be extracted from [2].
246
Workshops
References
1. T.G. Mustafin, “On similarities of complete theories”, Logic Colloquium
’90: Proceedings of the Annual European Summer Meeting of the Asso-
ciation for Symbolic Logic, Finland, 1990, pp. 259–265.
2. A.R. Yeshkeev & M.T. Kassymetova, Jonsson theory and its classes
of models, monograph, E.A. Buketov Karaganda State University, 2016.
Theorem. For every finite set Rul of axiom schemes and rules of inference,
it is possible to efficiently calculate the slice number of calculi obtained by
adding Rul as new axioms and rules to Gl.
References
1. L. Maksimova & V. Yun, “Slices over minimal logic”, Algebra i Logica,
vol. 55(4), 2016, pp. 449–464.
2. T. Hosoi, “On intermediate logics I”, Journal of the Faculty of Science,
University of Tokyo, Section Ia, vol. 14, 1967, pp. 293–312.
3. L. Maksimova & V. Yun, “Strong decidability and strong recognizabil-
ity”, Algebra i Logica, vol. 56(5), 2017.
248
Workshops
Logical Correctness
This workshop is organized by
Fabien Schang
Federal University of Goiás, Brazil
[email protected]
James Trafford
University of Creative Arts, Surrey, UK
[email protected]
249
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
250
Workshops
References
1. C. Benzmüller & L. Paulson, “Quantified multimodal logics in simple
type theory”, Logica Universalis, vol. 7(1), 2013, pp. 7–20.
2. C. Benzmüller, L. Weber & B. Woltzenlogel Paleo, “Computer-assisted
analysis of the Anderson-Hájek controversy”, Logica Universalis,
vol. 11(1), 2017, pp. 139–151.
3. C. Benzmüller & B. Woltzenlogel Paleo, “The inconsistency in Gödel’s
ontological argument: a success story for AI in metaphysics”, in
IJCAI’16, Proceedings of the Twenty-Fifth International Joint Con-
ference on Artificial Intelligence, edited by S. Kambhampati, 2016,
pp. 936–942.
4. D. Davidson, “Radical interpretation”, in Inquiries into Truth and In-
terpretation, Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 125.
5. D. Fuenmayor & C. Benzmüller, “Automating emendations of the onto-
logical argument in intensional higher-order modal logic”, in KI * 2017:
Advances in Artificial Intelligence, Lecture Notes in Computer Science,
vol. 10505, edited by G. Kern-Isberner, J. Fúrnkranz & M. Thimm,
Springer, 2017, pp. 114–127.
*
‘KI’ is the shorthand for ‘Künstliche Intelligenz’ (Artificial Intelligence). KI is the Ger-
man Conference on Artificial Intelligence.
251
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. T. Kouri Kissel, “Logical Pluralism from a Pragmatic Perspective”,
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, forthcoming.
2. M. Moortgat, “Multimodal Linguistic Inference”, Journal of Logic, Lan-
guage and Information, vol. 5(3–4), 1996, pp. 349–385.
3. M. Moortgat, “Symmetric Categorial Grammar”, Journal of Philosoph-
ical Logic, vol. 38(6), 2009, pp. 681–710.
252
Workshops
References
1. M. Fitting, “Possible world semantics for first order LP”, Annals of Pure
and Applied Logic, vol. 165, 2014, pp. 225–240.
2. K. Gödel, Collected Works: Volume III: Unpublished essays and lec-
tures, edited by S. Feferman et al., Oxford University Press, 2001.
3. K. Gödel, “On undecidable propositions of formal mathematical sys-
tems” (1934–1964), in Collected Works: Volume I: Publications 1929–
1936, edited by S. Feferman et al., Oxford University Press, 2001.
4. K. Gödel, “Vortrag bei Zilsel” (1938), in [2].
5. K. Gödel, “The modern development of the foundations of mathematics
in the light of philosophy” (1961), in [2].
6. S. Kovač, “Causal interpretation of Gödel’s ontological proof”, in Gödel’s
ontological argument, edited by K. Świetorzecka,
, Semper, Warsaw, 2015.
253
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
254
Workshops
This talk argues that we can look to logical practice for help in both pro-
viding support for logical anti-exceptionalism and pinpointing the types of
data logical theories must explain. While using the practice of researchers
has proven a useful method to study how knowledge is acquired in the
natural sciences [1] and mathematics [3], the same method has yet to be ex-
tensively used in the study of logic. Yet, just as philosophers of science have
used historical scientific experiments and disputes as their data to infer how
we come to know empirical claims, so we can use a practice based method
in studying logical knowledge. By taking logical arguments as our data, we
can infer from these arguments the methodological principles that logicians
rely upon, and the data their theories attempt to explain. The rationale
for using practice to inform an epistemology of logic is the presumption
that generally, as with scientists, logicians provide suitable reasons for their
claims even if, ultimately, they are not wholly satisfactory. Thus, we should
expect logicians’ arguments to provide insight into how we can come to
know logical truths, and the data logical theories must accommodate.
To show the fruitfulness of this practice-based approach, the talk con-
siders as a case study arguments from one of the most significant debates in
the modern logic, the dispute between classical logic and dialetheism over
the truth of inconsistent theories. Concentrating particularly on Priest’s [4]
initial arguments for dialetheism from the liar and Russell-set paradoxes,
and classical replies to the arguments, it’s proposed that both Priest and
his classical opponents rely upon at least three methodological principles:
Firstly, that linguistic and mathematical puzzles, such as the liar sentence
and Russell set, can form part of a logical theory’s explanandum; secondly,
that linguistic norms form part of logical evidence, for example in admit-
ting the need to take the meaningfulness of the liar sentences seriously;
and thirdly, that mathematical concepts and findings form part of logical
evidence, for example by suggesting that only classical logic can underpin
mathematical results.
The talk concludes that these initial results from the practice-based ap-
proach provide both support for logical antiexceptionalism, and details on
the types of evidence a logical theory should accommodate. To offer support
for their logical views, rather than attempting to settle disputes on purely
definitional or intuitional grounds, logicians appeal to their logic’s ability
to explain certain relevant phenomena, including linguistic norms and find-
ings from mathematics. We suggest that with yet further consideration of
important logical disputes, we can hope to build an even fuller picture of
logical epistemology and evidence.
255
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. R.M. Burian, “The Dilemma of Case Studies Resolved: The Virtues of
Using Case Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science”, Perspec-
tives on Science, vol. 9(4), 2001, pp. 383–404.
2. O.T. Hjortland, “Anti-Exceptionalism about Logic”, Philosophical Stud-
ies, vol. 174(3), 2017, pp. 631–658.
3. P. Mancosu, The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2008.
4. G. Priest, In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, 2nd edi-
tion, Clarendon Press, 2006.
5. G. Priest, “Revising logic”, in The Metaphysics of Logic, edited by P.
Rush, Cambridge University Press, 2014, pp. 211–223.
6. T. Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Blackwell, 2007.
7. T. Williamson, “Logic, Metalogic and Neutrality”, Erkenntnis, vol. 79,
supplement 2, 2014, pp. 211–231.
256
Workshops
Around Peirce
This workshop is organized by
257
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
258
Workshops
Peirce’s works, the aim of this paper is to answer the question: is the ob-
server’s response contentful just insofar as it occupies a node in a web of
inferential relations? In addition, what is the right kind of content for a
basic observation?
References
1. R. Baillargeon, “Object permanence in 3 21 - and 4 12 - months-old in-
fants”, in Developmental Psychology, vol. 23(5), 1987, pp. 655–664,
doi:10.1037/
0012-1649.23.5.655.
2. K.L. Ketner (editor), Reasoning and the Logic of Things: The Cam-
bridge Conferences Lectures of 1898, Introduction by H. Putnam, Har-
vard University Press, 1992.
3. J.M. Mandler, The Foundations of Mind: Origins of Conceptual
Thought, Oxford University Press, 2006.
4. C.S. Peirce, “Training in Reasoning” (1898), in Reasoning and the Logic
of Things: The Cambridge Conferences Lectures of 1898, edited by K.L.
Ketner, Harvard University Press, 1992.
“E. (a + b) × c = (a × c) + (b × c) (a × b) + c = (a + c) × (b + c).
These are cases of the distributive principle. They are easily proved
by [4] and [2], but the proof is too tedious to give”,
where [2] and [4] state that × and + behave as the usual infimum and
supremum in a lattice. So, Peirce seems to be saying that every lattice is
distributive!
Now, it is very well known that there are non-distributive lattices. The
usual examples are the pentagon and the diamond. So, how can we explain
Peirce’s statement?
In 1890, regarding Peirce’s statement that every lattice is distributive,
Schröder observed that he could prove that the following hold in any lattice
[see 4, p. 280]:
Theorem 25× ) ab + ac ≤ a(b + c) and Theorem 25+ ) a + bc ≤ (a + b)(a + c).
259
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
However, he stated that the given inequalities did not hold the other
way round. So, it seems that Schröder has proved Peirce to be wrong.
However, he gave an example with 990 equalities! He also stated a restricted
version of distributivity for lattices with bottom (Prinzip III) and used it,
together with some form of negation, in order to prove usual distributivity
[see 4, p. 310].
Many years afterwards, Huntington presented a proof of distributiv-
ity for “lattices” “borrowed, almost verbatim, from a letter of Mr. C.S.
Peirce, dated December 24, 1903”. The given proof was very indirect (see
[1, pp. 300–302] proving 22a).
In our talk we give many details concerning the question at issue. In
particular, we give a very direct proof of 22a, we state an open question re-
garding arguments by Schröder, and comment on Korselt’s counterexample
for distributivity presented in [2].
References
1. E. Huntington, “Sets of Independent Postulates for the Algebra of
Logic”, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 5(3),
1904, pp. 288–309.
2. A. Korselt, “Bemerkung zur Algebra der Logik”, Mathematische An-
nalen, vol. 44, 1894, pp. 156–157.
3. C.S. Peirce, “On the algebra of logic”, American Journal of Mathemat-
ics, vol. 3(1), 1880, pp. 15–57.
4. E. Schröder, Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik, volume 1, Teubner,
Leipzig, Germany, 1890.
In [1] (1904), Peirce claims that ‘the purpose of every sign is to express
“fact”, and by being joined with other signs, to approach as nearly as pos-
sible to determining an interpretant which would be the perfect Truth, the
absolute Truth, and as such (at least, we may use this language) would be
the very Universe’ [2, vol. 2, p. 304]. He adds that this “entelechy’ or ‘ideal
sign’ would be ‘quite perfect, and so identical — in such identity as a sign
may have — with the very matter denoted united with the very form sig-
nified by it’ [2, vol. 2, p. 304]. In this paper, I articulate the account of the
identity of truth and reality that Peirce defends in this text.
260
Workshops
References
1. The New Elements of Mathematics, 4 volumes, edited by C. Eisele,
Mouton, The Hague, 1976.
2. C.S. Peirce, The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, 2
volumes, 1st volume edited by N. Houser & C. Kloesel, 2nd volume
edited by The Peirce Edition Project, Indiana University Press, 1992
and 1998.
261
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. F. Bellucci & A-V. Pietarinen, “Assertion and Denial: A Contribution
from Logical Notation”, Journal of Applied Logic, 2017, to appear.
2. C.S. Peirce, Manuscripts in the Houghton Library of Harvard Uni-
versity, identified by R. Robin, Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of
Charles S. Peirce, University of Massachusetts Press, 1967, “The Peirce
Papers: A supplementary catalogue”, Transactions of the Charles S.
Peirce Society, 1971, vol. 7, pp. 37–57.
3. M. Carrara, D. Chiffi & C. De Florio, “Assertions and Hypotheses: A
Logical Framework for their Opposition Relations”, Logic Journal of
the IGPL * , vol. 25(2), 2017, pp. 131–144.
Gianluca Caterina
Department of Mathematics, Endicott College, USA
[email protected]
263
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
264
Workshops
Charles Sanders Peirce was the first philosophical logician to develop the
mathematics for a comprehensive logic of relations; that is, a logic for the
modelling, combining, and manipulating relations of any adicity (valency)
whatsoever. The corazon de corazon of his logic of relations is a thesis which
he characterized as a “remarkable theorem”, specifically, the claim that a
relationally complete logic requires, but only requires monadic, dyadic, and
triadic relations. One of the immediate consequences of this theorem is that
there are genuine triadic relations, relations of three relata which cannot be
analyzed into combinations of either monadic or dyadic relations. All other
n-adic relations can be composed out of combinations of the three elemen-
tary species of relations by two elementary logical operations of relative
and auto-relative multiplication. Peirce also recognized that binary mathe-
matical operations are special cases of triadic relations; that is, any binary
operation X ○ Y = Z is equivalent to some triadic relation t○ (X, Y, Z). He
argued that such operations cannot be analyzed into operations of arity less
than two. This realization provides additional grounds for his contention
that there are genuine triadic relations.
Peirce’s insights are the seeds for a logic of operations as a branch of his
logic of relations — seeds he never nurtured to fruition. This essay presents
the rudiments of that field of inquiry consonant with his logic of relations.
Binary operations in simple algebras such as magmas, semigroups, loops,
and groups will be represented by Peirce-inspired directed wye diagrams.
These can be grafted together by (auto-)relative multiplication to generate
both acyclic (tree) and cyclic graphs to model n-ary operations. This ap-
proach can be further applied to rings, fields, bi-algebras, categories, partial
orders, lattices and other algebraical systems. This work, when married to
Waclaw Sierpinski’s theorem that every n-ary operation (n > 2) can be ana-
lyzed into a compound operation consisting exclusively of binary operations,
provides a Peircean framework for Universal Algebra.
265
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Francesco Bellucci
Department of Philosophy and Communication Studies,
University of Bologna, Italy
[email protected]
266
Workshops
By 1882, on the other side of the ocean, Peirce had made the same
discovery as Frege. But unlike Frege, Peirce spent the rest of his logical life
to experiment with different and alternative notations for the representation
of quantification theory. The first, complete version of the theory is what
Peirce would later call the General Algebra of Logic. In the General Algebra,
the above multiply quantified sentence would be represented as “Πi Σj li,j ”,
of which the contemporary “∀x ∃y Lxy” is a mere notational variant. But
in parallel to the General Algebra, in 1882 Peirce created a system of logical
graphs in which the sentence in question would be represented thus:
where the crossed line at the left of the predicate term “l” is the sign of
the universal quantifier, the plain line at the right of it the sign of the
existential quantifier. But since the sheet on which these graphs are scribed
is symmetric and thus unordered, not only the system can only express
symmetric predicates, but also, the relations of dependence of the signs of
generality cannot be represented, as in the General Algebra, by exploiting
the linear ordering. The first solution that Peirce found for this problem
was to add to the vocabulary: numerical indices are attached to the lines
to indicate the order of selection.
The graph on the left would thus represent “Πi Σj li,j ” (“everybody loves
somebody”), while that on the right would represent “Σj Πi li,j ” (“somebody
is loved by everybody”).
This must have been highly unsatisfactory to Peirce. In 1896 he invented
two systems of graphs, later termed Entitative and Existential Graphs, re-
spectively. The 1896 graphs adopt the 1882 substructure of spots and lines
of identity but add to that substructure the “oval”. By means of the ovals,
the compositional (“endoporeutic”) structure of the formulas is immediately
represented, and thus also the relations of dependence of the quantifiers.
In the Existential graphs on the left, the first line is less enclosed than
the second, and thus its corresponding quantifier has logical precedence; in
267
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The presentation will show how C.S. Peirce developed his symbolic logic
from the works of G. Boole and A. De Morgan. Boole devised a calculus
for what he called the algebra of logic to overcome syllogistic. Interpreting
categorical propositions as algebraic equations, Boole showed an isomor-
phism between the calculus of classes and of propositions, being indeed the
first to mathematize logic. With a different purport, De Morgan tried to
improve on syllogistic, taking it as object of study. With a very unusual
system of symbols of his own, De Morgan develops the study of logical re-
lations that are defined by the very operation of signs. Although his logic
is not a Boolean algebra of logic, De Morgan defined the central notion of
a universe of discourse. Peirce takes a critical and decisive step forward.
First, claiming Boole had exaggeratedly submitted logic to mathematics,
thus mistaking the nature and the purpose of each discipline to the point of
erasing their characteristic differences to the impairment of the first, Peirce
emphasizes the normative purport of logic. Second, identifying De Morgan’s
limitations as a rigid restraint of logic to the study of relations, thus hin-
dering compositions of relations with classes, Peirce develops his own logic
of relative terms. Peirce’s originalities to be highlighted in the presentation
are:
(a) a theory of multiple quantification,
(b) the development of the logic of relatives from it (and not vice-versa),
(c) the calculus for multi-saturated expressions (arity superior to 2),
(d) the contrast between mathematics and logic by their distinct ends and
degrees of generality.
In the end, brief considerations on Peirce’s relation to Tarski’s interpre-
tation of the logic of relatives will be hinted at.
268
Workshops
References
1. George Boole, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on which are
founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities, Walton
and Maberly (London) & Macmillan and Co. (Cambridge), 1854.
2. Augustus De Morgan, Formal Logic: Or, the Calculus of Inference,
Necessary and Probable, Taylor and Walton, London, 1847.
3. Charles Sanders Peirce, Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological
Edition, 7 volumes, Indiana University Press, 1982–2006.
4. Alfred Tarski, Conferências na Unicamp em 1975 — Lectures at Uni-
camp in 1975, CLE * & Editora Unicamp , Campinas, SP, Brazil, 2016 .
*
Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science
State University of Campinas
In 1975, Alfred Tarski, invited by Ayda Arruda and Newton da Costa, visited the Insti-
tute of Mathematics, Statistics and Scientific Computing at Unicamp. In this bilingual
text, it is presented an inedited transcription of the two lectures delivered by him on re-
lation algebras, preceded by a brief introduction, with an update on some open problems
mentioned by Tarski.
269
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Angel Garrido
Faculty of Sciences, Department of Fundamental Mathematics,
National Distance Education University, Madrid, Spain
[email protected]
Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska
Cardinal Stefan Wyszyński University, Warsaw, Poland
[email protected]
Grzegorz Malinowski
Department of Logic, University of Lódź, Poland
[email protected]
270
Workshops
271
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
272
Workshops
273
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Although strong arguments speak for ontological reism, its original ver-
sion formulated by Kotarbiński encounters serious problems related to the
ontology of the domain of mathematics and its set-theoretical foundations.
Still worse, the positive thesis of reism is endangered by triviality, and its
negative theses with contradiction. It is argued that the problems of the
first kind may be overcome by combining reism not with classical nomi-
nalism, but with the so-called theory of the respectus. Unfortunately, the
latter is not expressible in any extensive logic, in particular, in Leśniewski’s
Ontology, chosen by Kotarbiński as the logical background for reism.
Next, in order to avoid triviality of the positive thesis of reism, one must
express it not in the reistic language, but rather in some multicategorial
language. However, in the framework of Leśniewski’s Ontology, this implies
commitment to the existence of individuals of categories other than the
category of things. This, in turn, would make negative theses of reism
contradictory.
A remedy for the problems of the first kind is choosing as the logical
background for reism, instead of Leśniewski’s Ontology, a weaker calculus
that may be called Weak Ontology, obtained from it by disabling the rule
of extensionality and appropriate weakening of its axiom. A further weak-
ening of the calculus by modifying the quantifier rules in the spirit of free
logics results in what may be called Free Ontology, which enables avoiding
both kinds of problems. Thus, Free Ontology is preferable to Leśniewski’s
Ontology as the logical background for reism.
*
Scientific Society of John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin
274
Workshops
275
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Searching for the origins could lead too far and eventually disperse,
which, as we know is not very convenient for a job pretending to be research.
So we will refer to these first signs that appear in the East (China, India,. . . ),
and then we may analyze the problem of “future contingents”, treated by
Aristotle in Peri Hermeneias.
About Future Contingent Propositions, we must remember that they are
statements about states of affairs in the future that are neither necessarily
true nor necessarily false. Suppose that a sea-battle will not be fought
tomorrow. Then it was also true yesterday (and the week before, and last
year) that it will not be fought, since any true statement about the case
that will be was also true in the past. But all past truths are now necessary
truths; therefore it is now necessarily true that the battle will not be fought,
and thus the statement that it will be fought is necessarily false. Therefore
it is not possible that the battle will be fought. In general, if something will
not be the case, it is not possible for it to be the case.
As we know, although the starting point of Leibniz’s “calculus univer-
salis” were Stagirite’s theories, Leibniz ends to be dependent from the ideas
of Aristotle, to finally develop its own axiomatic system, a more general
type, based on applying the Combinatorial Instrument to syllogistic. That
issue (Future Contingent’s problem, with variations) would be then crucial
in medieval times, as during the Scholasticism, with William of Ockham,
and Duns Scotus, looked at from different point of views, for its relationships
with Determinism and ‘Divine Foreknowledge’. Then, this issue is taken up
by Spanish Jesuit F. Luis de Molina (and the famous controversy ‘De Aux-
iliis’ maintained with the Dominican Fray Domingo Báñez), or Francisco
Suarez, and even the great polymath G.W. Leibniz dedicated his time.
At first, Lukasiewicz introduced the three-valued logic and then general-
ized to the infinite-valued. That possibility modulation can be expressed by
a membership function, which is to come all the unit interval [0,1], instead
of being reduced to the dichotomy of classical logic: True vs. False, 0 vs. 1,
White vs. Black, etc., allowing the treatment of uncertainty and vagueness,
important not only from the theoretical point of view, but also for applica-
tions. The deep and far connection from Leibniz to Lukasiewicz, and then to
Zadeh, crossing through Bernhard Bolzano, Franz Brentano and Kazimierz
Twardowski has its progressive justification by Jan Woleński, Roman Mu-
rawski, Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska and Roger Pouivet, among others.
References
1. Aristotle, Tratados de Lógica I y II (Organon), Biblioteca Clásica,
Editorial Gredos, Madrid, 2000.
2. J. Lukasiewicz, Selected Works, edited by L. Borkowski, North-Holland,
Amsterdam, 1970.
276
Workshops
278
Workshops
279
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Taneli Huuskonen
Independent Scholar
[email protected]
280
Workshops
References
1. A. Grzegorczyk, “Filozofia logiki i formalna logika niesymplifikacyjna”
(Philosophy of Logic and Perceptive Equivalence), Zagadnienia Nauko-
znawstwa, vol. 4(190), 2011, pp. 445–450.
2. J. Golińska-Pilarek & T. Huuskonen, “Logic of descriptions. A new
approach to the foundations of mathematics and science”, Studies in
Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, vol. 27(40), 2012, pp. 63–94.
3. J. Golińska-Pilarek & T. Huuskonen, “Grzegorczyk’s non-Fregean logics
and their formal properties”, in Applications of Formal Philosophy. The
Road Less Traveled, edited by R. Urbaniak & G. Payette, series Logic,
Argumentation and Reasoning, vol. 14, 2017, pp. 243–263.
281
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J. Lukasiewicz, Elementy logiki matematycznej, Państwowe Wydawn,
Warsaw, 1929.
2. E. Marczewski, “A general scheme of the notions of independence in
mathematics”, Bulletin de l’Académie Polonaise des Sciences. Série
des Sciences Mathématiques, Astronomiques et Physiques, vol. 6, 1958,
pp. 731–736.
3. A. Tarski, “Fundamentale Begriffe der Methodologie der deductiven
Wissenshaften I”, Montshefte für Mathematik und Physik, vol. 37, 1930,
pp. 361–404.
In the history of natural deduction (ND) one may distinguish two prob-
lems: when the method was invented and when it started to be practically
applied in textbooks as a tool for teaching logic. Stanislaw Jaśkowski was
one of the founders of ND although his work is not as well recognized as the
work of Gerhard Gentzen. However, in the talk we are not going to focus
on his role as the inventor of ND but rather on his priority in the field of
the application of this new approach to logic.
Quine in “Methods of Logic” claims that the first textbook applying
ND is Cooley’s “A Primer of Logic” printed in 1942, then reprinted in 1946.
In fact, Cooley applies a variety of inference rules, however it is doubtful
if there is ND system in his book. Conditional proofs are only briefly de-
282
Workshops
scribed on few pages but not widely used in the text. Moreover, Cooley did
not apply any devices for separating subproofs and his rule for elimination
of existential quantifier is stated without sufficient restrictions. In Quine’s
“Methods of Logic” from 1950, ND system is correctly defined but also intro-
duced only in three sections as an illustration rather, not as the main proof
system. Quine mentioned also some earlier mimeographed notes of himself
and of Rosser which applied ND but I had no possibility to check them and
in the light of known textbooks of these logicians it is also doubtful. For
example, a well known Rosser”s textbook “Logic for Mathematicians” from
1953 is using axiomatic system and introduces additional ND-like rules only
as a metalogical devices for simplification of axiomatic proofs. Undoubtedly,
the first widely known textbook which consequently applies ND as the way
of doing logic is “Symbolic Logic” of Fitch published in 1952.
However, in 1947, Jaśkowski published in mimeographed form his lec-
ture notes “Elements of Mathematical Logic and Methodology of Deductive
Sciences” in Polish. The book consists of 105 pages and is of great impor-
tance since it is perhaps the first logic textbook where natural deduction is
uniformly used as a method for presentation of logic. It is used from the
beginning for proving theorems of logic without any reference to axiomatic
systems. Moreover, it is applied also in proofs of metalogical results and
even truth-functional semantics is introduced via analysis of ND proofs of
selected theses. In the talk I will briefly characterize the main features of
ND introduced in this textbook and make a comparison with his original
version from the paper published in 1934.
284
Workshops
References
1. K. Ajdukiewicz, “O intencji pytania”(in Polish), Ruch Filozoficzny,
vol. 8, 1923, pp. 152–153.
2. K. Ajdukiewicz, “Zdanie pytajne” (in Polish), Jezyk
, i poznanie, vol. 1,
*
PWN , Warsaw, 1960, pp. 278–286.
3. A. Brożek, Theory of Questions: Erotetics Through the Prism of Its
Philosophical Background and Practical Applications, Rodopi, 2012.
4. T. Kubiński, Wstep, do logicznej teorii pytań, PWN, Warsaw, 1971.
5. T. Kubiński, An Outline of the Logical Theory of Questions, Akademie-
Verlag, Berlin, 1980.
6. D. Leszczyńska-Jasion, From Questions to Proofs. Beyond Logic of
Questions and Proof Theory, in preparation.
7. P. Lupkowski, Logic of Questions in the Wild. Inferential Erotetic Logic
in Information Seeking Dialogue Modelling, College Publications, Lon-
don, 2016.
8. A. Wiśniewski, The Posing of Questions: Logical Foundations of Erotetic
Inferences, Kluwer, 1995.
9. A. Wiśniewski, Questions, Inferences, Scenarios, College Publications,
London, 2013.
285
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
directly to the School but whose views are interesting) will be presented.
The problem whether those philosophical views did influence the technical
investigations and results will be discussed.
References
1. K. Lewin, Der Begriff der Genese in Physik, Biologie und Entwicklungs-
geschichte, Springer, Berlin, 1992.
2. D.W. Zimmerman, “Persistence and Presentism”, Philosophical Papers,
vol. 25(2), 1996, pp. 115–126, doi:10.1080/05568649609506542.
286
Workshops
287
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
288
Workshops
briefly landed and yielded a cultivar that was to supplant and overtake the
Western world. From 1908 until 1916, articles supporting AC or exploring
some of its consequences were scant and scarcely concerted. The situation
changed dramatically in 1916 when Waclaw Sierpiński, a young professor at
the Lwów University published a series of articles on AC and revived the
dormant debate surrounding AC — albeit on completely different grounds.
Eschewing theoretical concerns about the nature and methodology of math-
ematical practice, he paid little attention to the dominant question as to
whether Zermelo’s existence postulate could be accepted as a mathematical
construction.
Instead, he recentred the discussion towards practical matters (viz.,
its consequences, its interrelations and degree of necessity within various
proofs, as well as its role in obtaining various basically trivial mathemat-
ical theorems). Starting in 1918, Sierpiński also rallied the newly formed
Polish schools of mathematics around a common programme of research
which was to include an in-depth exploration of AC’s role in a few select
branches of mathematics. Originally adopting an objective stance vis-à-
vis AC, his programme was to eventually completely supplant the previous
philosophical and methodological debates — and Sierpiński was to become
AC’s biggest champion since Zermelo. The posterity of AC as we know it
would be unimaginable without Sierpiński’s efforts: “Since the labours of
Mr. Sierpiński and of the Polish School, a revolution has been produced. A
certain number of mathematicians have fruitfully used the axiom of choice;
things are no longer in the same place” (Lebesgue 1941, p. 109).
References
1. K. Ajdukiewicz, Jezyk, i poznanie, PWN* , Warsaw, 1960.
2. M. Lechniak, “Logika epistemiczna Jerzego Losia a teoria racjonalnego
zachowania”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, vol. 36(1), 1988, pp. 77–89.
3. M. Lechniak, “Wielowartościowość a pojecia, epistemiczne”, Roczniki
Filozoficzne, vol. 54(2), 2006, pp. 375–390.
4. J. Loś, “Logiki wielowartościowe a formalizacja funkcji intensjonalnych”,
Kwartalnik Filozoficzny, vol. 17(1–2), 1948, pp. 59–78.
5. J. Loś, “Podstawy analizy metodologicznej kanonów Milla”, Annates
Universitatis Mariae Curie-Shlodowska, Section F, vol. 2(5), 1948,
pp. 269–301.
6. N. Rescher, Topics in Philosophical Logic, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1968.
7. N. Rescher & A. Urquhart, Temporal Logic, Springer, 1971.
8. M. Tkaczyk, “Logika temporalna”, in Metodologiczne i teoretyczne prob-
lemy kognitywistyki, edited by J. Woleński & A. Dabrowski,
, Copernicus
Center Press, Cracow, 2014.
9. M. Tkaczyk, Futura Contingentia, Wydawnictwo KUL , Lublin, 2015.
10. M. Tkaczyk & T. Jarmużek, Normalne logiki pozycyjne, Wydawnictwo
KUL, Lublin, 2015.
11. K. Twardowski, “O tak zwanych prawdach wzglednych”, , in Wybrane
pisma filozoficzne, PWN, Warsaw, 1956.
This paper starts with an explanation of how the logicist research pro-
gram can be approached within the framework of Leśniewski’s systems. One
nice feature of the system is that Hume’s Principle is derivable in it from
an explicit definition of natural numbers. I generalize this result to show
that all predicative abstraction principles corresponding to second-level rela-
tions, which are provably equivalence relations, are provable. However, the
*
Polish Scientific Publishers, formerly Polskie Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
KUL Publisher. KUL is a shorthand for John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin.
290
Workshops
system fails, despite being much neater than the construction of Principia
Mathematica (PM). One of the key reasons is that, just as in the case of the
system of PM, without the assumption that infinitely many objects exist,
(renderings of) most of the standard axioms of Peano Arithmetic are not
derivable in the system. I prove that introducing modal quantifiers meant
to capture the intuitions behind potential infinity results in the (renderings
of) axioms of Peano Arithmetic (PA) being valid in all relational models
(i.e. Kripke-style models, to be defined later on) of the extended language.
The second, historical part of the paper contains a user-friendly description
of Leśniewski’s own arithmetic and a brief investigation into its properties.
291
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The Rasiowa-Pawlak School (formed during the 70s and 80s of the 20th
century in Warsaw) may be considered as the contemporary branch of
the Lvov-Warsaw School (established by Kazimierz Twardowski in Lvov
in 1895), which extends this old methodological tradition on Polish modern
computer science.
The most important step towards the Rasiowa-Pawlak school was made
in the middle 1980s. In this time Helena Rasiowa started her work in cooper-
ation with Victor Marek and Andrzej Skowron on logics related to rough set
theory — the mathematical method of data analysis founded by Zdzislaw
Pawlak. In the same time, Cecylia Rauszer (the student of Helena Ra-
siowa) cooperated with Zdzislaw Pawlak, Victor Marek, Andrzej Skowron,
and Andrzej Jankowski. Intensive investigations conducted by this group
led to important research results and to merging two conceptual frameworks
and scientific circles created around Helena Rasiowa and Zdzislaw Pawlak
into a school: the Rasiowa-Pawlak school.
In the talk I would like to return to the theoretical results of Cecylia
Rauszer obtained in the 1970s about semi-boolean algebras [1,2], and discuss
them against the background of rough set theory and formal concept analy-
sis. Although formal concept analysis can be traced back to almost the same
time as rough set theory (in the 1980s Zdzislaw Pawlak even met Rudolf
292
Workshops
References
1. C. Rauszer, “Representation theorem for semi-Boolean algebras I”,
Bulletin de l’Académie Polonaise des Scienses, vol. 19(10), 1971,
pp. 881–887.
2. C. Rauszer, “Semi-Boolean algebras and their applications to intuition-
istic logic with dual operations”, Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 83,
1974, pp. 81–87.
In his seminal work [1], J.M. Bocheński warned that some currents of
thought that support opposing ontologies could nevertheless embrace simi-
lar logical postulates. And he gave as an example the doctrines developed by
the Nyāya and Buddhist schools, both originally from ancient India. This
being so, we nonetheless find certain aspects of Buddhist ontology that gen-
erate important differences in the field of logic; we refer to the absence of
paradoxes and antinomies, alluded to by the Megaric sages and that the
Nyāya philosophers also knew how to detect. The purpose of this paper is
to analyze why these paradoxes did not appear in the Buddhist ontology
and if the Alfred Tarski hypotheses carried out in [2] can explain this sin-
gularity in some way.
References
1. J.M. Bocheński, “Logic and Ontology”, Philosophy East and West,
vol. 24(3), 1974, pp. 21–55.
293
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Reflections on Paraconsistency
This workshop is organized by
Franca D’Agostini
Department of Political and Social Sciences,
University of Milan, Italy
[email protected]
Elena Ficara
Department of Philosophy, University of Paderborn, Germany
[email protected]
295
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
2. In epistemological perspective:
— Do we really believe the unbelievable?
— What kinds of epistemic gluts are rationally acceptable?
3. In ethical and generally practical perspective:
— Disagreements and dilemmas are typical contexts in which the occur-
ring of contradictions has political and practical consequences: can
the theories of paraconsistent logicians be used to deal with these
occurrences?
4. In meta-theoretical perspective:
— Why do we study contradictions?
— What can we learn from the history of paraconsistency?
— Is ‘philosophy’ as such the enterprise that aims at solving or inter-
preting contradictions, as many authors in the tradition held (see
Hegel or Wittgenstein)?
296
Workshops
(De)motivating Gluts
Jonas R. Becker Arenhart
Department of Philosophy,
Federal University of Santa Catarina, Brazil
[email protected]
Ederson Safra Melo
Department of Philosophy,
Federal University of Maranhão, Brazil
[email protected]
Semantic paradoxes, like the Liar Paradox, are one of the best-known
motivations for the dialetheists’ claim that there are true contradictions
(dialetheias). Liar-like arguments arise in natural language and dialetheists
argue that the Liar sentence is true and false, i.e., a glut. In order to advo-
cate this approach to the paradoxes, some dialetheists, like Graham Priest,
advance a dilemma: a semantic theory of English is either inconsistent
(glutty) or else incomplete (with respect to its expressive power). Usually,
dialetheists choose expressive completeness and urge that glut theory is the
only approach able to achieve this ideal without triviality. However, recently
in [1] JC Beall argued that, by parallel reasoning, one should also be led
from expressive completeness to triviality by validity paradoxes (Curry-style
paradoxes involving not a conditional, but the notion of validity). The re-
sulting dilemma produced by Beall is: a semantic theory of English is either
trivial or else incomplete. So, according to Beall, the demand for complete
expressive power leads directly to triviality. Validity paradoxes are not dealt
with by the adoption of gluts, but rather by other means typically associate
with approaches to Curry-style paradoxes, which are not paradoxes directly
involving negation and contradiction. In face of these difficulties, Beall have
suggested, that “the glutty treatment arises from aesthetic considerations:
such target liars simply look like gluts” [1, p. 583]. We shall argue that
not even that may be available. Priest in [2] answers Beall’s challenge with
one typical move against Curry paradoxes: we avoid triviality by avoiding
one of the rules involved in the derivation of triviality, which is the rule of
absorption. Now, while that move may help one to block Beall’s argument
from expressive power to triviality, it also seems to pose troubles for the
motivation for gluts: some approaches to the semantic paradoxes also bar
the derivation of the liar with such restrictions on absorption. As a result, in
order to avoid triviality, one may end up having also no gluts. In this talk,
we present this dilemma for dialetheists and discuss the resulting trouble
for dialetheism and for the adoption of gluts.
297
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J.C. Beall, “Trivializing sentences and the promise of semantic com-
pleteness”, Analysis, vol. 75(4), pp. 573–584, 2015.
2. G. Priest, “Old wine in (somewhat leaky) new bottles. Some com-
ments on Beall”, The Australasian Journal of Logic, vol. 13(5), 2016,
doi:10.26686/ajl.v13i5.3934.
298
Workshops
References
1. H. Barseghyan, The Laws of Scientific Change, Springer, New York,
2015.
2. M.R. Martı́nez-Ordaz, “Holism, Inconsistency Toleration and Inconsis-
tencies between Theory and Observation”, Humana.Mente Journal of
Philosophical Studies, vol. 32, 2017, pp. 117–147.
3. Z. Sebastien, “The Status of Normative Propositions in the Theory of
Scientific Change”, Scientonomy, vol. 1, 2017, pp. 1–9.
Chisholm’s paradox, Ross’s paradox and Sartre’s dilemma are good ex-
amples of problems that are still “alive and kicking” [1] inside most of deon-
tic logic systems. Despite many good proposals that claimed to have solved
one or another of those problems, the fact is that most of them seemed just
299
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
too shy to save the deontic logic from that high dose of pessimism towards
any use in philosophical debate. How can the logician of normative concepts
get around this is the real challenge.
Considering Newton da Costa’s example in [2], it was interesting to see
that, despite the logic presented being very strong, the attempt to represent
incomplete actions, like a failed murder, led immediately to a contradiction.
In our proposal, a very simple procedure of switching the classical basis
for a paraconsistent one showed to be a successful tool to fix the inconsis-
tency. Important to note, however, that providing a paraconsistent view of
da Costa’s deontic system not only represented a way to get rid of trivial-
ity, but almost a mandatory adaptation to extend the language towards a
more intuitive and reliable representation of any moral philosophy or legal
code. It is shown that non-classical reasoning should be the starting point
of any discussion about deontic logic, not just a backup plan when things
don’t work in the classical field. This particular approach, once accepted,
should lead the deontic logic community to change completely the analysis
of paradoxes, dilemmas and gluts inside deontic logic.
References
1. J. Hansen, “The Paradoxes of Deontic Logic: Alive and Kicking”,
Theoria, vol. 72(3), 2006, pp. 221–232.
2. N.C.A. da Costa, “New Systems of Predicate Deontic Logic”, The Jour-
nal of Non-Classical Logic, vol. 5(2), 1988, pp. 75–80, https://www.cle.
unicamp.br/eprints/index.php/jancl/article/view/1088/902.
Paraconsistent logics that have arisen during the 20th century claim that
the law of contradiction is not applicable to certain circumstances. The most
radical paraconsistent logic is the dialetheic logic, which argues that some
contradictions arising within the limits of thought are true and even real.
Dialetheic logic — as Graham Priest and Richard Routley developed —
proves to be academically efficient by its metaphysical implications within
both at the level of logic and at the level of metaphysics. Priest, claims
that some contradictions which are realized in the states of change, motion
and time are real. These real contradictions are the subject of metaphysical
300
Workshops
investigation.
This paper aims to examine the possibility of doing metaphysics based
on dialetheic logic. Firstly, after sharing Priest’s view on metaphysics of
change, motion and time, I will demonstrate that dialetheic logic embodies
some important potentials — especially on metaphysics of time, but it does
not yet realize these potentials. In the final part, I will argue that the shift
from dialethic logic to metaphysics is not sufficiently prepared by Priest and
dialetheic metaphysics requires a transcendental point of view.
Paradoxes are a kind of conundrum with more than one good answer [7],
but I distinguish among such conundrums: paradoxes, hypodoxes and hy-
podoxical paradoxes. Paradoxes, like the Liar, are overdetermined, whereas
hypodoxes, like the Truth-teller, are underdetermined [2,4]. Being under-
determined explains the Truth-teller phenomenon, which Mackie [6] char-
acterised as consistent but undecidable. Notice that being consistent but
undecidable does not explain being underdetermined. The concept of hy-
podox is a more general concept than Mackie’s conception of a Truth-teller
counterpart, as I will demonstrate in this paper. While not all paradoxes
have hypodoxes, hypodoxes are almost as common. There are hypodoxes of
naı̈ve truth, set theory, and time travel to give but a few examples. Only a
few types of the ungrounded and ill-founded paradoxes do not have closely
associated hypodoxes. With respect to the converse relation, I conjecture
that all hypodoxes can be paired with paradoxes by a kind of duality, and
demonstrate this for ungrounded or ill-founded hypodoxes [2,3]. Surpris-
ingly, the concepts of paradox and hypodox are not exclusive; I analyse
antinomies such as Bertrand’s chord paradox and the Ship of Theseus as
hypodoxical paradoxes. This explains why it is natural to think of these as
paradoxical dilemmas, as Clark [1] does. Hypodoxes are proto-paradoxes
in that adding certain principles to a hypodox will generate a paradox [4].
Moreover, many hypodoxes, such as the Truth-teller and the set of all self-
membered sets do not use the principles characteristic of their related para-
*
International Marketing Institute of Australia
301
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
doxes, in particular the T-schema and Set Abstraction [4,5]. Finally, I argue
that an intermediate resolution of the Liar paradox may reduce it from an
apparent dialetheia to a kind of hypodox, a kind that is still distinct from
a Truth-teller.
References
1. M. Clark, Paradoxes from A to Z, 3rd edition, Routledge, 2012.
2. P. Eldridge-Smith, “Paradoxes and Hypodoxes of Time Travel”, in Art
and Time, edited by J.L. Jones, P. Campbell & P. Wylie, Australian
Scholarly Publishing, 2007, pp. 172–189.
3. P. Eldridge-Smith, The Liar Paradox and its Relatives, PhD Thesis,
Australian National University, 2008.
4. P. Eldridge-Smith, “A Hypodox! A Hypodox! A Disingenuous Hypo-
dox!”, The Reasoner, vol. 6(7), 2012, pp. 118–119.
5. P. Eldridge-Smith, “Two Paradoxes of Satisfaction”, Mind, vol. 124(493),
2015, pp. 85–119.
6. J.L. Mackie, Truth, Probability and Paradox: Studies in Philosophical
Logic, Oxford University Press, 1973.
7. R. Sorensen, A Brief History of the Paradox: Philosophy and the Labyrinths
of the Mind, Oxford University Press, 2003.
What is a Contradiction?
Ben Martin
Department of Philosophy,
Queen’s University, Kingston, Canada
[email protected]
302
Workshops
303
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
isn’t true, and that this divergence between the definitions demonstrations
the structured account’s superiority. Firstly, we show that there are many
explosion contradictions that are neither truth-conditional nor structured
contradictions. Particularly important are those explosive sets of propo-
sitions, such as those of the form {B, A → ¬B, A}, which the explosion
account contains as contradictions. Including these explosive sets as con-
tradictions must count against the definition’s plausibility, as they ensure
the explosion account cannot effectively distinguish between sets containing
contradictions, sets containing contradictory pairs, and sets of propositions
that entail contradictions, which are particularly important distinctions to
make when discussing theories and beliefs.
Secondly, we show that there are truth-conditional contradictions, such
as propositions of the form ¬(A → A), which though logically false in clas-
sical logic, are not structured contradictions. Again, we argue that this di-
vergence from the structured account counts against the truth-conditional
account’s plausibility, as propositions of the form ¬(A → A) fail to have two
important properties we expect of contradictions: i) While contradictions
are formed of contradictories, such propositions have no clear constituents
identifiable as contradictories; ii) We are able to derive the negation of an
assumption from a contradiction when constructing a formal reductio. How-
ever, we are not able within our formal systems to complete a reductio from
propositions of the form ¬(A → A). Thus, to admit propositions of this form
as contradictions would be to admit our formal systems fail to recognise cer-
tain contradictions as such. The talk, therefore, concludes that not only are
three prominent semantic definitions of ‘contradiction’ non-equivalent, but
that in future discussions of paraconsistency and dialetheism, it is the struc-
tured account of contradiction we should use.
References
1. R.T. Cook, A Dictionary of Philosophical Logic, Edinburgh University
Press, 2009.
2. M. Detlefsen, D.C. McCarty & J.B. Bacon (editors) (1999), Logic from
A to Z, Routledge, London, 1999.
3. H. Field, “Is the Liar Sentence Both True and False?”, in Deflationism
and Paradox, edited by Jc Beall & B. Armour-Garb, Clarendon Press,
2005, pp. 23–40.
4. S. Haack, Philosophy of Logics, Cambridge University Press, 1978.
5. H. Price, “Why ‘Not’ ?”, Mind, vol. 99(394), 1990, pp. 221–238.
6. H. Slater, “Paraconsistent Logics?”, Journal of Philosophical Logic,
vol. 24(4), 1995, pp. 451–454.
304
Workshops
305
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Generally speaking, paraconsistent logics are used for the formal treat-
ment of the inconsistent theories outside the classical approach. The defin-
ing feature of all paraconsistent logics is that the so-called explosion law,
which holds true in classical logic, is rejected. Arising from the critique of
how classical formal logic deals with contradictions, paraconsistent logics
form a wide array of systems with these paraconsistent logics that retain as
many classical laws as possible being of special interest to the researchers.
The maximal paraconsistent logics, as they are known, can also be ad-
equately described in terms of what they reject from classical logic, rather
than what they retain. There are many ways, in which such maximality
can be defined. We focus on two ways of doing so: maximality of theory
and maximality of consequence and consider logics that have both maximal
theory and consequence relation. This shift in focus from what is valid to
*
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
306
Workshops
what is not, allows one to use the methods from the so-called refutation
calculus in order to analyse such systems. Traditionally, refutation dealt
with designing anti-axiom systems with rules preserving non-validity (this
has been initiated in the context of Aristotle’s syllogistic by Lukasiewicz in
his seminal [1]).
However, we view refutation in a somehow broader way: it is not the
task of designing such systems as such but the change in approaching logical
systems that is important here. We describe a specific method used in the
past in this context to show maximality of certain (mostly) three-valued
paraconsistent logics. Here, logics are described using matrix semantics
and certain refutation-related conditions are defined that ensure maximality.
The conditions, first described in [2] mean that the problem of maximality
is reduced to finding specific substitutions. Our main contribution is to
show how this method generalises, allowing one to prove maximality of a
number of such logics in one fell swoop, thus providing a simple and unifying
account. We also present parts of the work in progress on extending this
method even further to cover classes of n-valued paraconsistent logics for
n > 3, and the results of an initial computational analysis confirming the
theoretical results in case n = 3.
Surely, maximality of paraconsistent logics has been the topic of research
from the very beginning. However, early results were related to showing
maximality of specific systems, using a variety of methods. More recently,
there were attempts at a more general approach [3], mostly limited to the
case of three-valued logics. The approach we propose has the benefit of
being arguably the simplest one and thus having a potential to be further
generalised to values greater than three (which we attempt to do). And
this, according to our knowledge, has not been accomplished yet.
References
1. J. Lukasiewicz, Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern
Formal Logic, Oxford University Press, 1957.
2. T. Skura & R. Tuziak, “Three-valued Maximal Paraconsistent Logics”,
Logika, vol. 23, Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Wroclawskiego, Wroclaw,
Poland, 2005.
3. O. Arieli, A. Avron & A. Zamansky, “Maximally Paraconsistent Three-
Valued Logics”, Twelfth International Conference on the Principles of
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, Toronto, AAAI* Publica-
tions, 2010.
*
Association for the Advancement of Artificial Intelligence
307
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
H, F H ∧ F.
References
1. S. Jaśkowski, “A propositional Calculus for Inconsistent Deductive Sys-
tems” (in Polish), Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis, Sectio A,
vol. 1(5), 1948, pp. 57–77, English version: “Propositional calculus
for contradictory deductive systems”, Studia Logica, vol. 24(1), 1969,
pp. 143–157, other English version: “A propositional Calculus for incon-
sistent deductive systems”, Logic and Logical Philosophy, vol. 7, 1999,
pp. 35–56.
2. M. Urchs, “Just Complexity”, in New Directions in the Philosophy of
Science, edited by M.C. Galavotti et al., Springer, 2014, pp. 203–219.
*
European Business School
308
Workshops
309
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
310
Workshops
Walter Carnielli
Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science,
Department of Philosophy,
State University of Campinas, Brazil
[email protected]
Juliana Bueno-Soler
School of Technology,
State University of Campinas, Limeira, Brazil
[email protected]
311
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Interpretations of probability
Philosophy of probability
Probabilistic argumentation and inference, and their generalizations
Questions on foundations of probability, including conditional probabil-
ities
Abstracts (one page) should be sent by November 15, 2017 via email
to [email protected].
In a 2013 interview for the Royal Statistical Society [2], D.V. Lindley
pointed out that, in his 2000 article [1], none of the reviewers of his pa-
per made any kind of comment about the presented axioms of subjective
probability. Lindley’s axioms of subjective probability are equivalent to the
relative probability functions for LI presented in [7] — which are equivalent
to the axiomatic system of Miller and Popper [4,5]. Lindley viewed statistics
as the study of uncertainty, combined with the rules of the probability calcu-
lus. There seems to be little disagreement, thus, between subjectivists and
others concerning the nature of the probabilistic reasoning. Bayes Theorem
is true, Popper admits, although warning that such a ’triviality’ cannot be
claimed to support inductive generalization, or predictions about the fu-
ture. Using a minimum of propositional logic and the elementary calculus
of probability, Popper [6] revisits Miller and Popper [3], a short paper in
which they proved that probabilistic support in the sense of the calculus of
probability can never be inductive support. Miller and Popper’s paper [3]
has received a wide audience, with more than hundred other papers directly
referring to it, many of them with harsh criticisms. Good part of such crit-
icisms is directed towards the logic contents of [3]. It is interesting to note,
however, that Miller and Popper dispose of a powerful autonomous axiom
system for relative probability which assumes neither the propositional cal-
culus nor Boolean algebra (albeit allows their derivation). An interesting
question would be to know whether the main argument of [3] can be made
entirely autonomous, independent of propositional calculus and Boolean al-
gebra. If so, the argument would be much stronger than it seems. If not,
312
Workshops
References
1. D.V. Lindley, “The Philosophy of Statistics”, Journal of the Royal Sta-
tistical Society. Series D (The Statistician), vol. 49(3), 2000,
pp. 293–337, doi:10.1111/1467-9884.00238.
2. D.V. Lindley, interview by Tony O’Hagan, in Bayes 250 Conference * ,
Royal Statistical Society, 2013, https://youtu.be/cgclGi8yEu4.
3. D.W. Miller & K.R. Popper, “A proof of the impossibility of inductive
probability”, Nature, vol. 302, 1983, pp. 687–688, doi:10.1038/302687a0.
4. D.W. Miller & K.R. Popper, “Deductive Dependence”, in Actes IV
Congrès Català de Lógica, Universitat Politécnica de Catalunya & Uni-
versitat de Barcelona, 1986, pp. 21–29.
5. D.W. Miller & K.R. Popper, “Deductive Dependence”, digitally re-
mastered version from [4] and later versions of 1989 and 2011, done by
D.W. Miller, Klagenfurt University Library, 2015.
6. K.R. Popper, “The Non-existence of Probabilistic Inductive Support”,
in Foundations of Logic and Linguistics, edited by G. Dorn
& P. Weingartner, Springer, 1985, pp. 303–318.
7. P. Roeper & H. Leblanc, Probability Theory and Probability Logic, Uni-
versity of Toronto Press, 1999.
313
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
the propensity interpretation, and to elicit its significance both for quan-
tum theory and for a new metaphysics of nature. In [3] the autonomous
probability functions play a central role in the development of the Popper’s
theory, since they are independent of semantic notions. There are two ways
to define autonomous probability functions: in absolute (given by unary
functions) and in relative (given by binary functions) sense.
In this approach the connection between logic and probability is guar-
anteed by the result that shows that absolute probability theory is a gener-
alization (in some sense) of two-valued propositional logic.
In this paper we intend to extend Popper’s Probability Theory by en-
larging the scope of the theory so as to include a class of paraconsistent
logics based upon the Logics of Formal Inconsistency introduced in [1]. Our
strategy is to generalize the autonomous probability functions (in absolute
and relative sense) to a class of paraconsistent autonomous probability func-
tions and show some technical results which ensure that these functions are
indeed autonomous and satisfy the paraconsistent requirements.
References
1. W.A. Carnielli, M.E. Coniglio & J. Marcos, “Logics of Formal Inconsis-
tency”, in Handbook of Philosophical Logic, edited by D. Gabbay and
F. Guenthner, 2nd edition, Springer, 2007.
2. D.W. Miller, “Popper’s contributions to the theory of probability and
its interpretation”, in The Cambridge Companion to Popper, edited
by J.F.G. Shearmur & G. Stokes, Cambridge University Press, 2016,
pp. 230–268.
3. K.R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson & Co., Lon-
don, 1959.
314
Workshops
References
1. J. Bueno-Soler & W.A. Carnielli, “Paraconsistent Probabilities: Consis-
tency, Contradictions and Bayes’ Theorem”, Entropy, vol. 18(9), 2016,
http://www.mdpi.com/1099-4300/18/9/325/htm.
2. W.A. Carnielli & M.E. Coniglio, Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency,
Contradiction and Negation, volume 40 of Logic, Epistemology, and the
Unity of Science book series, Springer, 2016.
3. K.R. Popper, “A Note on Probability”, Mind, N.S. 47, pp. 275–279,
1938, also in The Logic of Scientific Discovery, by K.R. Popper, Basic
Books, New York, 1959, Appendix ii, pp. 318–322.
4. K.R. Popper & D.W. Miller, “Contributions to the Formal Theory
of Probability”, in Patrick Suppes: Scientific Philosopher, volume 1,
edited by P.W. Humphreys, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994,
pp. 3–23.
315
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Probability Valuations*
Joachim Mueller-Theys
Independent Scholar, Heidelberg, Germany
[email protected]
*
Acknowledgments to Walter Carnielli, Juliana Bueno-Soler, Luis Estrada-González,
Tamar Lando, Hanti Lin, Schafag Kerimova, Arthur Buchsbaum, Andreas Haltenhoff.
316
Workshops
Walter Carnielli
Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science,
Department of Philosophy,
State University of Campinas, Brazil
[email protected]
318
Workshops
In previous work the authors have explored logical conditions for con-
sistent and coherent statistical test of hypothesis, using these conditions to
derive the GFBST — Generalized Full Bayesian Significance Test. [1,3,6]
explore in detail the mathematical statistics and logical properties of the
GFBST. The GFBST generalizes the previously defined non-agnostic ver-
sion of the test, see [2,4,5]. However, these articles do not provide specific
methodologies and concrete examples on how to construct an extended non-
sharp version of a sharp hypothesis, a necessary step to apply the GFBST
theory in some real statistical modelling situations.
319
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. R. Blanché, Structures Intellectuelles. Essai sur l’Organisation Systé-
matique des Concepts, J. Vrin, Paris, 1966.
2. W. Borges & J.M. Stern, “The Rules of Logic Composition for the
Bayesian Epistemic e-values”, Logic Journal of the IGPL * ,
vol. 15(5–6), 2007, pp. 401–420.
3. L.G. Esteves, R. Izbicki, J.M. Stern & R.B. Stern, The Logical Con-
sistency of Simultaneous Agnostic Hypothesis Tests, Entropy Journal,
vol. 18(7), 2016, doi:10.3390/e18070256.
4. R. Izbicki & L.G. Esteves, “Logical Consistency in Simultaneous Sta-
tistical Test Procedures”, Logic Journal of IGPL, vol. 23(5), 2015,
pp. 732–758.
5. C.A.B. Pereira & J.M. Stern, “Evidence and Credibility: Full Bayesian
Signicance Test for Precise Hypotheses”, Entropy Journal, vol. 1(4),
1999, pp. 99–110, doi:10.3390/e1040099.
6. J.M. Stern, R. Izbicki, L.G. Esteves & R.B. Stern (2017), “Logically-
Consistent Hypothesis Testing and the Hexagon of Oppositions”, Logic
Journal of IGPL, vol. 25(5), 2017, pp. 741–757.
7. J.M. Stern, “Paraconsistent Sensitivity Analysis for Bayesian Signifi-
cance Tests”, in Brazilian Symposium on Artificial Intelligence, SBIA
2004, Lecture Notes in Computer Science book series, vol. 3171, 2004,
pp. 134–143.
*
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
320
Workshops
Erik Thomsen
CTO* at Blender Logic, Cambridge, USA
[email protected]
Over the past fifty years, the fabric of our society has been radically
transformed by successful logic-based applications. In today’s world, logic
chips (i.e., CPUs) and the logic-grounded software that controls them sup-
port nearly all socio-economic infrastructure, from banking to defense.
Semantic Information Systems (SIS) are software that process infor-
mation based on some formal (i.e., logical) understanding of the meaning
of that information. SIS typically provide interpretation, representation
and/or reasoning capabilities. They include:
1. Data-knowledge bases (or languages) that represent and support query-
ing and calculations over an internal canonical form. For example: Ora-
cle (2016), Teradata (2016), DB2 (2016), CYC (2016), OWL (2016) and
RDF (2014).
2. Natural Language Processing (NLP) that converts text into an internal
canonical form that expresses facts, rules and definitions. For example:
OpenNLP (2016), Stanford parser (2016) and Berkley parser (2016).
Overwhelmingly, SIS are grounded in some (possibly restricted variant
of) First Order Logic (FOL). For example, Relational (or, more properly,
SQL) databases, which are still the predominant form of data management
for organizations around the world, are varyingly faithful implementations
of Codd’s Relational Model [3,13,11], which itself was explicitly grounded
in FOL. NLP also uses FOL as its predominant target representation [5,10].
In this sense, logic provides the abstract material technology from which
SIS are engineered. SIS where the semantics are pre-defined and the do-
main knowledge is static within any particular transaction (e.g., banking
and e-commerce applications), form the information backbone of our global
economy. They are incredibly reliable. FOL has proven to be an extremely
successful abstract material technology for these sorts of software applica-
tions.
*
Chief Technology Officer
321
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
However, for other SIS where the semantics are hard to predefine, or
where domain knowledge may need to change within a transaction, what we
call “Dynamic Real-World Information Domains”, FOL-based SIS’s exhibit
real world problems. Sometimes the problem is that the software generates
incorrect inferences based on the information entered into the system. This
happens, for example, when the assertions made represent only some of the
domain that needs to be reasoned over and bivalency, tout court, is insuf-
ficient [14]. Sometimes the problem is that the software cannot compose
a formal representation to interpret what a normal adult can speak or un-
derstand [18]. Sometimes the problem is that the software assumes certain
attributes of the objects it is representing, and performs analysis based on
those assumptions even though there was information ingested about the
objects that a human would have understood as signaling that background
assumptions about the domain were false [1].
The goal of this workshop is to explore:
Where and how real-world SIS problems (e.g., those that occur in the
analytical information systems of large corporations and governments)
can be traced to specific characteristics of the logic (e.g., FOL) upon
which they are constructed.
Modifications to FOL (e.g., the alternative views espoused by Wittgen-
stein in the Tractatus or by Peirce) that would enable the construction
of SIS that can operate more successfully in dynamic information do-
mains.
The keynote speaker at this workshop is David McGoveran (page 142).
References, Links and Suggested Readings
1. S. Al-Fedaghi, “Context-aware software systems: Toward a diagram-
matic modeling foundation”, Journal of Theoretical and Applied Infor-
mation Technology, vol. 95(4), 2017, pp. 936–947.
2. J. Barwise & J. Etchemendy, Language, Proof and Logic, Seven Bridges
Press, New York, 1999.
3. E.F. Codd, “A relational model of data for large shared data banks”,
Communications of the ACM * , vol. 13(6), 1970, pp. 377–387.
4. E.F. Codd, The Relational Model for Database Management: Version
2, Addison-Wesley, 1990.
5. M. Collins, Head-driven Statistical Models for Natural Language Pars-
ing, PhD Thesis, University of Pennsylvania, 1999.
6. W. Croft, Syntactic Categories and Grammatical Relations: The Cog-
nitive Organization of Information, The University of Chicago Press,
1991.
*
Association for Computing Machinery
322
Workshops
Semantic softwares
Berkley Parser (2016)
CYC (2016)
Db2 (2016)
OpenNLP (2016)
Oracle (2016)
OWL (2016)
RDF (2014)
Semeval (2015)
Stanford Parser (2016)
Style Syntax (2012)
TAC (2015)
Teradata (2016)
Real world information system problems that can be traced to the logic
upon which the information system is built:
○ Missing data
○ Non-applicable data
○ Nulls
○ Inaccessible data
○ Word sense disambiguation
○ Semi-autonomous representational layers
○ Autonomous systems
○ Application contexts
○ Data-driven schema updates
○ Multi-agent planning systems with imperfect information
324
Workshops
○ Sub-structural logics
○ Tractarian logics
○ Peircean logics
*
Basic Formal Ontology
325
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Web services now play an important role in our lives. Both our per-
sonal and enterprise related data can now be found in some remote data
centers accessible only through third party application programming inter-
faces (API). This shift from self-controlled database systems to third-party
managed database systems has brought forward many research challenges,
one of which is the ability to integrate such multiple heterogeneous and au-
tonomous web service API in a transparent manner. Mediation-based data
integration approach when extended to web service API on one hand helped
to achieve a declarative approach to the problem of extracting desired in-
formation from the web services, but on the other hand led to several new
open challenges.
Data providing operations of web service API can be considered as rela-
tion with access patterns [1], i.e., a relation that takes as input one or more
values and returns associated tuple of values. Several currently available
web service documentations are only human readable. Hence, one major
goal is to reduce the human programming effort of the process of extract-
ing information from web services. Datalog program, including conjunctive
queries help to describe API operations as well as query them using query
rewriting algorithms like inverse-rules algorithm. However, there are sev-
eral practical challenges [2] especially considering the strict certain answer
semantics of such algorithms that fail to address the problem of incomplete
information as well as a large number of spurious calls that need to be made
for API operations involving more than one input arguments. These two
cases were studied by us while building DaWeS [1], a data warehouse fed
with web services.
References
1. J. Samuel & C. Rey, “DaWeS: Data Warehouse fed with Web Services”,
in Actes du XXXIIème Congrès INFORSID , 2014, pp. 329–344.
*
École Supérieure de Chimie, Physique, Életronique de Lyon
Laboratoire d’Informatique, de Modélisation et d’Optimisation des Systèmes
INFormatique des ORganisations et Systèmes d’Information et de Décision
326
Workshops
References
1. A. Cussins, “Subjectivity, Objectivity and Frames of References in
Evan’s Theory of Thought”, Electronic Journal for Analytic Philoso-
phy, 1999, https://mind.ucsd.edu/misc/ejap/ejap 6 5 cussins.html.
327
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
328
Workshops
*
Chief Technology Officer
329
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Cyril Pshenichny
Geognosis Project, ITMO University* , Russia
[email protected]
330
Workshops
References
1. C. Pshenichny, “Qualitative and quantitative calculi in the theory of
multitudes”, in Dynamic Knowledge Representation in Scientific Do-
mains, IGI Global* , 2018, in preparation.
2. C.A. Pshenichny, S.I. Nikolenko, R. Carniel, P.A. Vaganov,
Z.V. Khrabrykh, V.P. Moukhachov, V.L. Akimova-Shterkhun & A.A.
Rezyapkin, “The event bush as a semantic-based numerical approach
to natural hazard assessment (exemplified by volcanology)”, Computers
and Geosciences, vol. 35(5), 2009, pp. 1017–1034.
3. C.A. Pshenichny & O.M. Kanzheleva, “Theoretical foundations of the
event bush method”, GSA Special Papers, vol. 482, 2011, pp. 139–164,
doi:10.1130/2011.2482(12).
4. U. Wolter, “Scenarios in event bushes — a formal proposal”, in Dynamic
Knowledge Representation in Scientific Domains, IGI Global, 2018, in
preparation.
5. P. Diviacco, C. Pshenichny, R. Carniel, Z. Khrabrykh, V. Shterkhun,
D. Mouromtsev, S. Guzmán & P. Pascolo, “Organization of a geophysi-
cal information space by using an event-bush-based collaborative tool”,
Earth Science Informatics, vol. 8(3), 2015, pp. 677–695.
*
IGI Global (formerly Idea Group Publishing) is an international academic publishing
company, specialized in research publications covering the fields of computer science and
IT management.
Geological Society of America
331
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Naming Logics II
This workshop is organized by
Jean-Yves Beziau
University of Brazil, Rio de Janeiro, Brazil
[email protected]
332
Workshops
333
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In this talk I will discuss these issues, on the basis of a semiotical anayl-
sis and a critical study of notations in logic from Boole to Tarski, via Frege
and Peirce.
References
1. C.J. Ducasse & H.B. Curry, “Early History of the Association for Sym-
bolic Logic”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 27(3), 1962,
pp. 255–258.
2. J.-Y. Beziau (editor), The arbitrariness of the sign in question, College
Publication, London, 2018.
3. P. Halmos, “How to write mathematics”, L’enseignement mathématique,
vol. 16(2), 1970, pp. 123–152.
4. J. Venn, Symbolic Logic, MacMillan, London, 1881.
5. A. Tarski, “Contributions to the theory of models. I, II, III”, Indiga-
tiones Mathematicae, vol. 16, 1954, pp. 572–581, pp. 582–588, vol. 17,
1955, pp. 56–64.
In spite of the fact that Informal Logic, as a discipline, has been founded
in 1978, its roots go back to the Ancient Philosophy. The primal aim of this
paper is to try to identify the place of informal logic in the history of logic
while taking the concept of reasoning into consideration. Our second aim
is to discuss the relation between informal logic and formal logic through
the concepts of form and deductivism. Based especially on their names,
a relation of opposition is established between formal and informal logic.
We, however, aimed to show the aforementioned relation can be established
through unity rather than opposition, intending the concept of reasoning to
be the common denominator of that relation.
References
1. M.E. Barth & E.C. Krabbe, From Axiom to Dialogue: A Philosophical
Study of Logics and Argumentation, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 1982.
2. J.A. Blair, “The ’Logic’ of Informal Logic”, in Groundwork in The The-
ory of Argumentation: Selected Papers of J. Anthony Blair, Springer,
2012.
3. A. Dumitriu, History of Logic, 3 volumes, Abacus Press, Kent, UK,
1977.
334
Workshops
335
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
338
Workshops
Dialetheic Validity
Graham Priest
Graduate Center, City University of New York, USA
[email protected]
I assume for the purposes of this talk that a dialetheic solution to para-
doxes of self-reference, such as the liar paradox and Russell’s paradox, is
correct. In particular, given a language, one should reject the move of el-
evating its metatheoretic notions to a distinct “metalanguage”. This does
not mean that one should eschew reasoning about such notions. It means
that one should reason about such notions in the language to which those
notions apply. And given that the logic of such a language must be a para-
consistent one, this means that we must reason about metatheoretic notions
paraconsistently.
A prime metatheoretic notion is truth (simpliciter). Much thought has
been put into paraconsistent theories for languages which contain their own
truth predicate. How to produce inconsistent but non-trivial theories which
contain the T-Schema for sentences of the language of the theory is well
known.
339
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
340
Workshops
341
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Claude Rosental
CEMS* , IMM , CNRS , EHESS§ ,
PSL¶ Research University, France
[email protected]
Julie Brumberg-Chaumont
LEM , CNRS, PSL Research University, France
[email protected]
342
Workshops
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Scott L. Pratt (page 156)
and Christopher Goodey (page 131).
343
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Studies in Early Modern Philosophy take now for granted that the Age
of Reason is also the Age of Passions. But the full consequences of that idea
are not yet explored for Logic seen as the highest manifestation of Human
Rationality.
This link between Reason and Passions is particulary striking in philoso-
phies considering the overthrow of values since the original sin. I aim at
analyzing conceptions of Logic within this kind of rationalism and its con-
sequences to understand Boundaries of Humanity. For that purpose, Nicolas
Malebranche is a relevant Case Study.
My main finding is a typology of three Pathologies of Rationality:
(i) The fool who is immediately and truly identified as such by every
fallen man. This one pronounces incoherent discourses; or discourses
obviously contradictory or inadequate to reality;
(ii) The fool who is falsely regarded as the highest expression of rationality
by every fallen man. The Stoic Sage, for instance, coherently considers
himself and is considered by others, as a God within Men. But this
true expression of Monstrousness truly lies on the passions of Glory
and Self Esteem;
(iii) The fool who is falsely regarded as fool by every fallen man. Yet this
rare Man truly tries to reach the highest Rationality by seing in God’s
Rationality itself.
In Conclusion, the logical criteria of Coherence in Early Modern Phi-
losophy can’t be understood without Anthropological criteria (i.e. a theory
of passions) and concrete Reality (i.e. the logical coherence could be mere
imagination).
344
Workshops
345
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
of this paper. One promising way to begin explicating the central features of
this naturalized social conception of logic is by drawing a contrast between
his position and two of the most appealing, traditional views of this dis-
cipline mentioned above, Platonism and Formalism. Neither is naturalist,
and neither has any place for the social element, but both are still dom-
inant today. The key thought is threefold. Logic is (i) a special type of
social practice, which (ii) is inextricably embedded into the human form of
life, and thus is natural, immanent, not an historical accident. It is (iii)
a way of regulating social interaction, as opposed to a solitary manipula-
tion of abstractions taking place in the heads of individuals. Moreover, if
Wittgenstein is right, and the symbols have meaning only in use, then the
conception of mathematics as a mere formalism, a conventional manipula-
tion of signs on paper, is extremely problematic too. What accounts for the
necessity, certainty and generality of logical propositions is a key — social
component, encapsulated within the idea that social interaction is not pos-
sible among those who doubt (the universal applicability of) logical truths.
Necessity is social, and derived from the commonness of our natural, prim-
itive reactions. Certainty is public, not private. The generality of logic is
intrinsic, not conventional.
References
1. I. Hacking, Why is There Philosophy of Mathematics at All, Cambridge
University Press, 2014.
2. L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, edited by G.E.M.
Anscombe & R. Rhees, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, Blackwell,
Oxford, 1953.
3. L. Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, edited
by G. von Wright, R. Rhees & GEM Anscombe, translated by G.E.M.
Anscombe, Blackwell, Oxford, 1956.
4. L. Wittgenstein, Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cam-
bridge, 1939, edited by C. Diamond, University of Chicago Press, 1976.
346
Workshops
The second half of the 13th century witnessed two phenomena I would
like to bring together: the definition of a strong anthropological ideal, the
“philosopher” as the sole “complete human being”, where logic is seen as
an anthropological norm according to which a “logical scale” of humanity
is defined and a (large) group of “logically disable people” is discriminated,
and the rise of logic as a social norm for the scholarly worlds, within the
newly-born universities as well as outside of them. Logic became then, for
the first time, part of the basic European education system for young peo-
ple, together with grammar. The social history of the practices and theories
of concept of logic as a “discipline”, in every senses of the term, means that
a ‘strong’ and a ‘weak’ program for the sociology of philosophical knowledge
can be fruitfully combined, and the debates between internalist and exter-
nalist approaches to the history of philosophy can be happily overcome. The
method followed could be termed a non-normative historical study of the
normativity of logic as embedded in practices and theories.
In three recent papers [2,4,5], Cora Diamond has criticized Peter Winch’s
1964 paper [10], in which Winch attacked E.E. Evans-Pritchard’s classic
book [8] for European ethnocentrism. Diamond, in turn, attack’s Winch’s
arguments for, in effect, trying to (use the later Wittgenstein to [11]) lay
down what she calls “supergrammatical” laws for what can and can’t be
done with language, in particular with reference to criticisms of social sys-
tems of thought and practice in which one is not a participant. Diamond
argues that this kind of argument is not necessarily to be found in the later
Wittgenstein’s work [11] and, moreover, that it is wrong. While I basically
*
Laboratoire d’Études sur les Monothéismes
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
Paris Sciences & Lettres
347
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In several passages of his works, Hegel claims that logic is natural and
that the forms of thought are the natural element in which human beings
live, act and interact. My paper has two parts. In the first I present Hegel’s
view on the naturalness of logic. I explore his use of the concept of “logic”,
focusing on the meaning of the expression das Logische, coined by Hegel
himself, and on Hegel’s distinction between das Logische, natürliche Logik
and die Logik. In the second I show that Hegel’s views on logic’s naturalness
could profitably join current debates about the sociology and anthropology
of logic.
References
1. G.W.F. Hegel, Werke in zwanzig Bänden. Theorie Werkausgabe, new
edition on basis of the works of 1832–1845, edited by E. Moldenhauer
& K.M. Michel, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, Germany, 1969ff * .
2. G.W.F. Hegel, Hegel’s Science of Logic, English translation by A. Miller,
Humanity Books, New York, USA, 1969.
3. G.W.F. Hegel, The Encyclopaedia Logic, Part I of Encyclopaedia of
Philosophical Sciences with Additions, English translation by
T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting & H.S. Harris, Hackett Publishing Com-
pany, Indianapolis, USA, 1991.
4. G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen über Logik und Metaphysik (Heidelberg,
1817), edited by K. Gloy, Meiner, Hamburg, Germany, 1992.
*
“ff”, in this context, is a shorthand for “and following years”.
349
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
350
Workshops
References
1. I.M. Blanco, The Unconscious as Infinite Sets: An Essay in Bi-logic,
Karnac, London, 1980, first published in 1975.
2. C. Ginzburg, Ecstasies: Deciphering the Witches’ Sabbath, The Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1990, first published in 1989, second Italian
edition in 2017.
3. Francesco Orlando, L’intimità e la storia: lettura del “Gattopardo”,
Einaudi, Turin, Italy, 1998.
Hakob Barseghyan
Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science
and Technology, University of Toronto, Canada
[email protected]
352
Workshops
353
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
354
Workshops
Saloua Chatti
University of Tunis, Tunisia
[email protected]
355
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In their virulent criticism against Kripke [7], Hintikka and Sandu [6]
show that the necessity of identity between proper names is question-begging,
even if they are rigidly interpreted. Indeed, in the context of world lines se-
mantics, this would amount to assume that world lines never split or merge,
i.e. to assume the necessity of identity itself. By contrast, rigidity would
restore the validity of existential generalization, which is invalidated it we
do not presuppose uniqueness of reference of proper names. This thesis had
been initially advocated by Hintikka [4], and deepened in a more system-
atic study on epistemic logic by Hintikka [5]. In this presentation, I argue
that endorsing the validity of existential generalization commits to another
paradoxical Kripkean thesis, namely the thesis of the contingent a priori.
Therefore, in world lines semantics, if we reject the contingent a priori,
we must also reject the presuppositions of uniqueness of reference. After
a critical discussion of the contingent a priori, I propose a modal formula-
tion of the paradox. I conclude with further considerations in relation to
Tulenheimo’s innovative approach to world lines semantics.
One of Kripke’s [7, p. 56] well-known examples is the following: the
length referred to by “one metre” is fixed by stipulating its identity with
the length of a particular stick (S) at a determinate instant (t), namely the
standard metre rod. Since we are fixing that length by stipulation, we know
a priori (automatically) that “the standard metre rod is one metre long” is
true. Once the length of “one metre” has been fixed, “one metre” rigidly
refers to that length. The length of S might change, not the length of one
metre. Therefore, that S is one metre long at time t is a contingent fact.
Even though we know a priori that “the standard metre rod is one metre”
is true, this statement expresses a contingent truth.
According to Dummett [3, p. 124], this thesis is the sign that something
goes wrong with rigidity. By following Donnellan’s [1] distinction between
attributive and referential uses of definite description, it can be explained
that when we know the contingent fact expressed by “the standard metre
rod is one metre”, we do not know the same that when we know a priori
that “the standard metre rod is one metre”. Indeed, the attributive use
consists of introducing “one metre” as a name for the length of S at time
t, whatever this length is. By stipulation, we thus know a priori that “the
356
Workshops
Now, if “one metre” was a rigid designator for that length, the latter
knowledge attribution would follow the former, by existential generalization.
Therefore, if a priori contingent truths are rejected, existential generaliza-
tion, and thus rigidity, must be rejected too. For the sake of comparison,
Donnellan [2, p. 18] suggests distinguishing between “knowing that a certain
sentence expresses a truth and knowing the truth of what is expressed by
the sentence”, but without emphasizing the role of existential generalization
and without rejecting rigidity.
We will conclude by discussing some new insights provided by the dis-
tinction of physical and intentional modes of predications put forward by
Tulenheimo [8] in the context of world lines semantics. What is the impact
of such a distinction with respect to the different kinds of knowledge attri-
butions we have previously referred to? What consequences can be drawn
with respect to our analysis of the paradoxical thesis of the contingent a
priori?
References
1. K.S. Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions”, The Philosoph-
ical Review, vol. 75(3), 1966, pp. 281–304.
2. K.S. Donnellan, “The contingent a priori and rigid designators”, Mid-
west Studies in Philosophy, vol. 2(1), 1977, pp. 12–27.
3. M. Dummet, Frege: Philosophy of Language, Gerald Duckworth, Lon-
don, 1973.
4. J. Hintikka, “Modality as Referential Multiplicity”, Ajatus, vol. 20,
1957, pp. 49–64.
357
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
In his 1997 reply to Woods and Hansen, “What was Aristotle Doing in
His Early Logic, Anyway?”, Jaakko Hintikka clears some misunderstandings
concerning his reconstruction, by means of an interrogative model, of Aris-
totle’s logic. He thus explicitly challenges some of the deep-rooted assump-
tions of Aristotelian scholars and modern logicians: Aristotle’s Analytics,
asserts Hintikka, are not radically separated from his Topics and De So-
phisticis Elenchis, but are rather the pursuit of the same goal at a different
level, that of strategies, as opposed to down-to-earth — or “down-to-agora”
as he says — dialectical bouts between individual, concrete opponents.
Hintikka justifies the absence of an explicit question-and-answer frame-
work in the Prior and Posterior Analytics by the strategic principle of antic-
ipation of the answers to one’s questions: since the best strategic course of
action in a game of questions and answers is to ask only those questions of
which you can anticipate the answers, and for which the anticipated answers
go your way, then, in a strategic perspective, one can actually do without
an answerer. This would thus yield both the presentation of Aristotle’s
syllogistic framework and Hintikka’s interrogative model of it.
Two essential elements of Hintikka’s interpretation can thus be outlined:
that Aristotle was first and foremost interested in question-and-answer in-
quiries and in this regard thought like a dialectician; and that this question-
and-answer mold for reasoning could be made implicit through a strategic
perspective.
The purpose of this talk will be to uphold Hintikka’s perspective on
Aristotelian logic, which is still not universally accepted among scholars,
and further his insights by proposing a new logical framework in which
the rules themselves are defined through questions and answers, or, as we
*
Unité Mixte de Recherche 8163: Savoirs, Textes, Langage
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
359
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
call them, through challenges and defenses. The dialogical structure of the
syllogisms should thus become apparent in the logical framework, with the
added benefit that such a framework rests on a rule, the Socratic rule, that
directly yields Hintikka’s distinction between a justification ad hominem,
concerning only the dialectical bouts at the agora level, and a justification
ad argumentum, which also concerns the strategy level.
The path which will be tread in order to defend and illustrate Hintikka’s
two tenets on Aristotelian logic will not be Hintikka’s own path consisting
in making the interlocutor implicit, but will rather be the path consisting
in making everything more explicit, enabling us to emphasize, in the logical
framework itself, the structural link between syllogistics (Analytics) and
dialectics (Topics), and to provide a logical rendering of the distinction
between ad hominem and ad argumentum conclusions through the Socratic
rule.
References
1. J. Hintikka , “What was Aristotle Doing in His Early Logic, Anyway?
A Reply to Woods and Hansen”, Synthese, vol. 113(2), 1997, pp. 241–
249.
2. Aristotle, Prior Analytics, translated by R. Smith, Hackett Publishing
Company, Indianapolis, Indiana, 1989.
Eduardo Ochs
Department of Natural Sciences,
Fluminense Federal University, Rio das Ostras, Brazil
[email protected]
361
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
vation for the general definition, are also treated as somewhat second-class
— and this inspires a possible meaning for what can call “Category The-
ory for Children”: to start from the diagrams for particular cases, and then
“lift” them to the general case. Note that this can be done outside Category
Theory too; [1] is a good example.
Our third aim is to discuss models. A standard example is that every
topological space is a Heyting Algebra, and so a model for Intuitionistic
Predicate Logic, and this lets us explain visually some features of IPL.
Something similar can be done for some modal and paraconsistent logics;
we believe that the figures for that should be considered more important,
and be more well-known.
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Bob Coecke (page 124) and
Ralf Krömer (page 133).
References
1. M. Jamnik, Mathematical Reasoning with Diagrams: From Intuition to
Automation, Center for the Study of Language and Information, 2002.
2. R. Krömer, Tool and Object: A History and Philosophy of Category
Theory, Birkhäuser, 2007.
362
Workshops
365
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J. Bénabou, “Introduction to Bicategories”, in Reports of the Midwest
Category Seminar, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 47, Springer,
1967, pp. 1–77, doi:10.1007/BFb0074299.
2. G.M. Kelly & R.H. Street, “Review of the elements of 2-categories”, in
Category Seminar, Lectures Notes in Mathematics, vol. 420, edited by
G.M. Kelly, Springer, 1974, pp. 75–103, doi:10.1007/BFb0063101.
3. F.L. Nunes, “Freely generated n-categories, coinserters and presenta-
tions of low dimensional categories”, arXiv:1704.04474, Cornell Univer-
sity Library, 2017.
4. A.J. Power, “A 2-categorical pasting theorem”, Journal of Algebra,
vol. 129(2), 1990, pp. 439–445.
366
Workshops
References
1. D. Blackwell, Basic Statistics, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1969.
2. M.H. DeGroot, Optimal Statistical Decisions, John Wiley and Sons,
2004.
3. D.V. Lindley, Making Decisions, 2nd edition, John Wiley and Sons,
1985.
4. J. Pearl, Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of
Plausible Inference, Morgan Kaufmann, 1988.
367
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Peter Arndt
University of Düsseldorf, Germany
[email protected]
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Pierre Cartier (page 123)
and Ingo Blechschmidt (page 121).
368
Workshops
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique de l’École Polytechnique
Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et en Automatique
369
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Acclavio, “Proof diagrams for multiplicative linear logic: Syntax and
semantics”, arXiv:1702.00268, Cornell University Library, 2017.
2. J.C. Baez & A. Lauda, “A prehistory of n-categorical physics”, arXiv:
0908.2469, Cornell University Library, 2009.
3. A. Burroni, “Higher-dimensional word problems with applications to
equational logic”, Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 115(1), 1993,
pp. 43–62.
4. G. Gentzen, “Investigations into Logical Deduction”, in The collected
papers of Gerhard Gentzen, edited by M.E. Szabo, North-Holland, 1969.
5. P. Selinger, “A Survey of Graphical Languages for Monoidal Cate-
gories”, in New Structures for Physics, edited by B. Coecke, Springer,
2010, pp. 289–355.
370
Workshops
The notion of filter pair was introduced in [1], for creating and analyz-
ing general finitary propositional logics and their translation morphisms,
expanding the work initiated in [4], that is restricted to the setting of alge-
braizable logics [2].
Considering the special case of filter pairs ⟨G, i⟩ where the functor
G = CoK is given by congruences relative to a class of algebra K, we give
criteria when the associated logic is protoalgebraic, equivalential, algebraiz-
able, truth-equational, self-extentional or Lindenbaum algebraizable, just
analyzing the relation between Leibniz operator, Suszko operator and Frege
operator with the adjoint of i, improving our previous results.
We adjust the notion of filter pair in such a way that we can treat κ-
compact logics, for each regular cardinal κ: The corresponding new notion
is called κ-filter pair. We show that any κ-filter pair gives rise to a κ-
logic and that every κ-logic comes from a κ-filter pair. Taking adequate
notions of morphisms, we show that the category of κ-logics and translation
morphisms is (isomorphic to) a full reflective subcategory of the category
of κ-filter pairs. We use the notion of κ-filter pair to show that logics
always admit natural extensions, providing an(other) answer to a question
of Cintula and Noguera [3]. We further point out how κ-filter pairs allow to
extend standard notions from finitary logics to arbitrary logics, e.g. those of
being algebraizable, protoalgebraizable, equivalential or truth-equational.
References
1. P. Arndt, R. Jansana, H.L. Mariano & D.C. Pinto, “Filter functors in
logic and applications to categorial analysis of meta-logic properties”,
to be published, 2016.
2. W.J. Blok & D. Pigozzi, Algebraizable Logics, Memoirs of the American
Mathematical Society, vol. 77(396), 1989, doi:10.1090/memo/0396.
371
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
372
Workshops
References
1. A. Brunner, H.L. Mariano & S.G. da Silva, “Categorial forms of the ax-
iom of choice”, Logic Journal of the IGPL * , vol. 25(4), 2017,
pp. 408–430, doi:10.1093/jigpal/jzx020.
2. M. Kashiwara & P. Schapira, Categories and Sheaves, Springer, 2006.
Reference
1. R. Diaz, “Quantum Boolean Algebras”, arXiv:1011.5215, Cornell Uni-
versity Library, 2015.
*
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
373
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
H
Key: A logical rule C is indeed a fraction, but its numerator is C and its
denominator is H.
References
1. C. Domı́nguez & D. Duval, “Diagrammatic logic applied to a parameter-
isation process”, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science,
vol. 20(4), 2010, pp. 639–654.
2. C. Domı́nguez & D. Duval, “A parameterization process: from a func-
torial point of view”, International Journal of Foundations of Computer
Science, vol. 23(1), 2012, pp. 225–242.
3. D. Duval, “Diagrammatic Specifications”, Mathematical Structures in
Computer Science, vol. 13(6), 2003, pp. 857–890, doi:10.1017/
S0960129503003979.
4. D. Duval, “Diagrammatic inference”, arXiv:0710.1208, Cornell Univer-
sity Library, 2007.
5. P. Gabriel & M. Zisman, Calculus of Fractions and Homotopy Theory,
Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete book series, vol. 35,
Springer, 1967.
374
Workshops
375
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. P. Johnstone, “Fibrations and partial products in a 2-category”, Applied
Categorical Structures, vol. 1(2), 1993, pp. 141–179.
2. R. Street, “Fibrations and Yoneda’s lemma in a 2-category”, in Pro-
ceedings of Sydney Category Theory Seminar, 1972–1973, edited by
G.M. Kelly, Lectures Notes in Mathematics book series, vol. 420, 1974,
pp. 104–133.
3. S. Vickers, “Sketches for arithmetic universes”, arXiv:1608.01559,
Cornell University Library, 2016.
376
Workshops
References
1. W.J. Blok & D. Pigozzi, Algebraizable Logics, Memoirs of the American
Mathematical Society book series, vol. 77(396), American Mathemati-
cal Society, Providence, USA, 1989, doi:10.1090/memo/0396.
2. H.L. Mariano & C.A. Mendes, “Towards a good notion of categories of
logics”, arXiv:1404.3780, Cornell University Library, 2014.
3. D.C. Pinto & H.L. Mariano, “Algebraizable logics and a functorial en-
coding of its morphisms”, Logic Journal of the IGPL * , vol. 25(4), 2017,
pp. 524–561.
4. G. Voutsadakis, “On the Categorical Algebras of First-Order Logic”,
Scientiae Mathematicae Japonicae Online, vol. 10, 2004, pp. 47–54,
http://www.jams.or.jp/scm/contents/Vol-10-1/10-7.pdf.
377
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
colimits. The existence of these provides natural mechanisms for the fac-
torization and combination of logics. One natural way to obtain from these
categories new ones with better properties is to consider the quotient cat-
egory induced by the interdemonstrability relation, as done in [4]. In this
case the existence of finite limits and colimits is only guaranteed when the
objects involved are congruential logics.
Following the aforementioned works, we consider the category whose
objects are Tarskian logics and whose morphisms are flexible translations
that preserve the interchangeability relation between metaformulas. We
say that two metaformulas with the same metavariables α(ξ1 , . . . , ξn ) and
β(ξ1 , . . . , ξn ) are interchangeable if, for any metaformula φ(ξ1 ) and formulas
α1 , . . . , αn , we have φ[α(α1 , . . . , αn )] and φ[β(α1 , . . . , αn )] are interdemon-
strable. This relation induces a congruence on the class of morphisms of
this category.
In this communication, we study the quotient category induced by in-
terchangeability and some of its categorical properties. For example, the
existence of finite products and coproducts, without needing to be restricted
to congruential logics. This is of interest since there are relevant examples,
such as some logics of formal inconsistency studied in [3] that are not con-
gruential.
References
1. P. Arndt, “Homotopical categories of logics”, in The Road to Universal
Logic: Festschrift for 50th Birthday of Jean-Yves Béziau, vol. 1, edited
by A. Koslow & A. Buchsbaum, Birkhäuser, 2015, pp. 13–58.
2. C. Caleiro & R. Gonçalves, “Equipollent logical systems”, in Logica
Universalis: Towards a General Theory of Logic, edited by J.-Y. Beziau,
Birkhäuser, 2007, pp. 97–109, doi:10.1007/978-3-7643-8354-1 6.
3. W. Carnielli, M. Coniglio, D.M. Gabbay, P. Gouveia & C. Sernadas,
Analysis and Synthesis of Logics: How to Cut and Paste Reasoning
Systems, Springer, 2008.
4. C. Mendes & H.L. Mariano, “Towards a good notion of categories of
logics”, arXiv:1404.3780, Cornell University Library, 2016.
378
Workshops
Observe that (DP) is in some sense the most general condition guaran-
teeing that central elements have all the information about direct product
decompositions in the variety. In [1] it is proved that (DP) is equivalent to
each one of the following conditions:
*
Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı́ficas y Técnicas
379
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
(FD) There is a first order formula Ψ(x, y, z⃗) such that, for every A, B ∈ V,
A×B ⃗ ⃗1])
Ψ((a, b), (a′ , b′ ), [0, iff b = b′ .
(BFC) V has Boolean factor congruences, i.e., the set of factor congruences
of any algebra in V is a Boolean sublattice of its congruence lattice.
Let V a variety with BFC. If the formula Ψ of (FD) is existential we
will say that V is a variety with exBFC. The aim of this talk is to exhibit a
representation theorem for some varieties with exBFC in terms of internal
connected models in toposes of sheaves over bounded Boolean algebras. The
present work is motivated by the Pierce representation theorem for integral
rigs [2] and Lawvere’s strategic ideas about the topos-theoretic analysis of
coextensive algebraic categories [3].
References
1. P.S. Terraf & D.J. Vaggione, “Varieties with definable factor congru-
ences”, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society,
vol. 361(10), 2009, pp. 5061–5088.
2. W. Zuluaga, Representación por haces de riRigs, PhD Thesis, Uni-
versidad Nacional de La Plata, 2016, http://sedici.unlp.edu.ar/handle/
10915/54115.
3. F.W. Lawvere, “Core varieties, extensivity, and rig geometry”, Theory
and Applications of Categories, vol. 20(14), 2008, pp. 497–503.
380
Workshops
The workshop will discuss new insights in the interaction between logic
and law, and more precisely the study of different answers to the question:
What role does logic play in legal reasoning?
It will present both current challenges and historical perspectives in the
relation between logic and law. The perspectives to be discussed involve the
interface of the following studies:
Foundational studies:
Logical Principles and Frameworks
Meaning
Reasoning in Deontic Contexts
Applications:
Legal practice and Computer-Based Modelisations
Argumentation Theory
Historical perspectives:
Legal reasoning in Ancient Roman, Arabic, Jewish and Far-East con-
texts
Others contexts
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Walter Edward Young
(page 166) and Matthias Armgardt (page 121).
381
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
382
Workshops
Myriam Quatrini
CNRS, Institut de Mathématiques de Marseille,
Université d’Aix-Marseille, France
[email protected]
References
1. C. Fouqueré & M. Quatrini, “Un cadre formel issu de de la théorie de
la démonstration pour la théorie de l’argumentation”, Mathématiques
et Sciences Humaines, vol. 198(2), 2012, pp. 49–83.
2. J.-Y. Girard, “Locus solum: From the rules of logic to the logic of
rules”, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, vol. 11(3), 2001,
pp. 301–506.
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris-Nord
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
383
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
384
Workshops
In this paper, two main objectives will be pursued. First, I wish to inves-
tigate different answers to the Sorites paradox as they have been developed
with modern logical tool. Three schools of thought will be presented: many-
valued logic, including a few of its variants [1,6,9,14]; supervaluationism and
subvaluationism, as the two sides to the same coin [7,11,14]; and contextu-
alism [5,8,12,14].
Secondly, after having examined these possible answers to the Sorites
paradox, I will draw parallels between these purely logical solutions and
their possible applications to the philosophical problem of vagueness in the
law. Philosophical vagueness raises special problems in legal philosophy.
Lawmakers often use vague, abstract terms. Some legal scholars have ar-
gued that this vagueness is a necessary feature of law [3,4], which cannot
be erased or bypassed. They think we should embrace vagueness and use
its tools — after all, it does seem to offer some benefits [10]. Others believe
that vagueness has no function in law [13], because the philosophical prob-
lems it raises are not at issue in practice. This answer highlights a crucial
aspect of legal adjudication: unlike a philosopher thinking about hay stacks,
a judge cannot simply remain befuddled. She must make a decision that
will have direct consequences on the life of other people. The main legal
issue concerning vagueness is thus that of pragmatic application.
References
1. P. Cintula, C.G. Fermüller & C. Noguera, “Fuzzy Logic”, in The Stan-
ford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E.N. Zalta, 2016, https://
plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-fuzzy.
2. D. Edgington, “The Philosophical Problem of Vagueness”, Legal The-
ory, vol. 7(4), 2001, pp. 371–378.
3. T. Endicott, “Law is Necessarily Vague”, Legal Theory, vol. 7(4), 2001,
pp. 379–385.
4. T. Endicott, “The Value of Vagueness”, in Philosophical Foundations
of Language in the Law, edited by A. Marmor & S. Soames, Oxford
University Press, 2011, pp. 14–30.
5. D. Graff, “Shifting sands: an interest-relative theory of vagueness”,
Philosophical Topics, vol. 28(1), 2000, pp. 45–81.
6. S. Halldén, The Logic of Nonsense, Uppsala Universitets Årsskrift* ,
Uppsala, Sweden, 1949.
7. D. Hyde, “Sorites Paradox”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by E.N. Zalta, 2011, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sorites-
paradox.
*
Uppsala University’s Annual Report
388
Workshops
389
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
for res ipsa loquitur that the defendant exerted exclusive control over the
injurious ‘thing’ or instrumentality; (2) whether there must be an entire
‘absence of explanation’ for the maxim to apply; (3) whether res ipsa lo-
quitur is a species of circumstantial evidence; and (4) whether it authorizes
a burden-shifting presumption of negligence or only a permissive evidentiary
inference. I argue that the controversy and jurisdictional disagreement over
these issues is due, in no small part, to the maxim’s little understood logical
foundation in abduction. By recognizing that foundation, these issues that
mar res ipsa loquitur’s consistent application largely fall away.
390
Workshops
Bolzano [1] was the first to propose explicitly that a probability function
p(c ∣ a) may be used to measure the degree to which a conclusion c is
classically deducible from an assumption (or premise) a. It is central to the
logical interpretation of probability that the value of p(c ∣ a) is 1 when c is
deducible from a, and sinks to 0 when c′ is deducible from a; that is, when
c contradicts a.
Cohen’s The Probable and the Provable [2] argues that the other popular
interpretations of probability, which are all tied to variants of the axioms
of Kolmogorov [4], may also be understood as measures of deducibility, but
of deducibility in deductive systems of diverse kinds. It seems to have been
the first work to state explicitly that what he labels mathematical or Pas-
calian probability is not the only respectable way of grading the deducibility
or provability (in a loose sense) of a conclusion c from the evidence (or
assumption) a, and to contest the idea that the lowest grade of deducibility
must reflect the inconsistency of c with a. According to Cohen, reasoning
392
Workshops
References
1. B.P.J.N. Bolzano, Wissenschaftslehre, Seidel’sche Buchhandlung, Sulz-
bach-Rosenberg, 1837, English translation: Theory of Science, Oxford
University Press, 2014.
2. L.J. Cohen, The Probable and the Provable, Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1977.
3. A.P. Dawid, “The Difficulty About Conjunction”, Journal of the Royal
Statistical Society, Series D (The Statistician), vol. 36(2–3), 1987,
pp. 91–97, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2348501.
4. A.N. Kolmogorov, Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung,
Springer, Berlin, 1933, English translation: Foundations of the Theory
of Probability, Chelsea Publishing Company, New York, 1950.
5. D.A. Schum, “A Review of a Case against Blaise Pascal and His Heirs”,
Michigan Law Review, vol. 77(3), 1979, pp. 446–483.
393
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Imagine two cars have a head-on collision in a desert and a police officer
arrives on the scene. She has to decide about the liability of a driver but
she has no reason to accuse one and acquit the other driver. Sometimes,
in such dilemmas, a moral principle [1] or a legal preference [2] helps the
judge to adjudicate the case as some scholars have proposed. However, it is
hard to see why a principle or a preference might work for one driver and
against the other one. Thus, the question is that: How the judge decides in
such cases? Sometimes evidence for and against a verdict is equally strong
and based on objective criteria; the judge does not know how to decide. In
modern contemporary legal systems, these cases simply ask for a subjective
judgement pictured by Roy Sorensen [3, p. 300] and a judge would decide
based on her personal interests even if she might not be aware of that. This
way of decision-making might cause a great injustice by imposing racial, sex-
based or ethnic discriminations, reflected in personal unconscious interests
of judges.
I argue that in cases in which there is not enough evidence, it is better to
leave the case to a chancy process of judgement instead of deciding it based
on personal interests since a random process removes the adverse impact of
psychological or political biases on legal decisions. In the next step, firstly,
I show that an automatic decision procedure that includes randomness is
practically more efficient than a manual procedure like flipping a coin. Sec-
ondly, I show that an automatic decision procedure could be achieved by
using electric devices such as robot referees.
References
1. R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, Harvard University Press, 1977.
2. S. Soames, “Interpreting Legal Texts: What Is, and What Is Not, Spe-
cial about the Law”, in Philosophical Essays, volume 1, by S. Soames,
Princeton University Press, 2009.
3. R. Sorensen, “How Vagueness Makes Judges Lie”, in Vagueness in the
Law: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives, edited by G. Keil
& R. Poscher, Oxford University Press, 2016, pp. 297-316.
394
Workshops
3. L.J. Cohen, The Probable and the Provable, Oxford University Press,
1977.
4. L.J. Cohen, “Subjective probability and the paradox of the gatecrasher”,
Arizona State Law Journal, vol. 2(2), 1981, pp. 627–634.
5. A.P. Dawid, “The Difficulty About Conjunction”, The Statistician,
vol. 36(2–3), Special Issue: Practical Bayesian Statistics, 1987,
pp. 91–97.
6. J. Earman, Bayes or Bust?: A Critical Examination of Bayesian Con-
firmation Theory, Bradford Books, 1992.
7. S. Haack, Evidence Matters: Science, Proof, and Truth in the Law,
Cambridge University Press, 2014.
8. S. Haack, “Legal Probabilism: An Epistemological Dissent”, in [7],
2014, pp. 47–77.
9. C.R. Nesson, “Reasonable doubt and permissive inferences: The value
of complexity”, Harvard Law Review, vol. 92(6), 1979, pp. 1187–1225.
10. L.H. Tribe, “The Continuing Debate over Mathematics in the Law of
Evidence: A Further Critique of Mathematical Proof”, Harvard Law
Review, vol. 84(8), 1971, pp. 1810–1820.
11. L.H. Tribe, “Trial by mathematics: Precision and ritual in the legal
process”, Harvard Law Review, vol. 84(6), 1971, pp. 1329–1393.
12. B.D. Underwood, “The thumb on the scale of justice: Burdens of
persuasion in criminal cases”, Yale Law Journal, vol. 86(7), 1977,
pp. 1299–1348.
13. R. Urbaniak, “Narration in judiciary fact-finding: a probabilistic expli-
cation”, submitted to Artificial Intelligence and Law, 2017.
14. R. Urbaniak, “Reconciling Bayesian epistemology and narration-based
approaches to judiciary fact-finding”, Proceedings of Sixteenth Con-
ference on Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, Liver-
pool, UK, 2017, Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Sci-
ence, vol. 251, edited by J. Lang, Open Publishing Association, 2017,
pp. 504–514.
396
Workshops
H ∧ ¬H F,
H, ¬H F.
In order to differentiate between one and the other, one has to block the
rule of adjunction:
H, F H ∧ F.
To that aim the Polish logician Stanislaw Jaśkowski designed his system
D2 [1]. This non-adjunctive calculus, the first inconsistency-tolerant one in
history, is correlated with Lewis’ modal logic S4. We demonstrate how D2
(and alternative systems) provide a promising methodological basis for legal
reasoning.
References
1. S. Jaśkowski, “A Propositional Calculus for Inconsistent Deductive Sys-
tems”, Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis, Sectio A, vol. 1(5),
1948, pp. 57–77, reprinted in Logic and Logical Philosophy, vol. 7, 1999,
pp. 35–56.
2. J. Lukasiewicz, On Aristotle’s principle of contradiction (in Polish),
PWN , Warsaw, Poland, 1987.
*
European Business School
Polish Scientific Publishers, formerly Polskie Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
397
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Bob Coecke
Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford, UK
[email protected]
The keynote speakers at this workshop are Sander Uijlen (relativity talk,
page 164) and Simon Perdrix (quantum talk, page 151).
References
1. B. Coecke & A. Kissinger, Picturing Quantum Processes. A first course
on quantum theory and diagrammatic reasoning, Cambridge University
Press, 2017.
2. B. Coecke, M. Sadrzadeh & S. Clark, “Mathematical Foundations for a
Compositional Distributional Model of Meaning”, in A Festschrift for
Jim Lambek, edited by J. van Benthem, M. Moortgat & W. Buszkowski,
Linguistic Analysis, vol. 36, 2010, pp. 345–384, arXiv:1003.4394.
3. J. Bolt, B. Coecke, F. Genovese, M. Lewis, D. Marsden & R. Piedeleu,
“Interacting Conceptual Spaces I : Grammatical Composition of Con-
cepts”, arXiv:1703.08314, Cornell University Library, 2017.
399
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
400
Workshops
Eigenlogic
Zeno Toffano
CentraleSupélec, L2S* , CNRS , Université Paris-Saclay,
Gif-sur-Yvette, France
[email protected]
This work presents an operational and geometric approach to logic. It
starts from the multilinear elective decomposition of binary logical functions
in the original form introduced by George Boole [1]. A justification on
historical grounds is presented bridging Boole’s theory and the use of his
arithmetical logical functions with the axioms of Boolean algebra using sets
and quantum logic.
It is shown that the algebraic polynomial formulation can be naturally
extended to operators in vector spaces. In this way propositional logic can
be formalized in linear algebra by using combinations of tensored elemen-
tary operators. The original and principal motivation of this work is for
applications in the new field of quantum information, differences are out-
lined with more traditional quantum logic approaches. This formulation is
named Eigenlogic [3].
The interesting feature is that the eigenvalues of these operators are
the truth values of the corresponding logical connective and the associated
eigenvectors correspond to one of the fixed combinations of the inputs (in-
terpretations). The outcome of a “measurement” or “observation” on a
logical observable will give the truth value of the associated logical proposi-
tion, and becomes “interpretable” when applied to its eigenspace leading to
a natural analogy with the measurement postulate in quantum mechanics.
The following diagram summarizes this point of view:
eigenvalues Ð→ truth values ; eigenvectors Ð→ interpretations ;
logical operators Ð→ connectives.
One can generalize to eigenvalues different from the Boolean binary val-
ues {0, 1} for example with {+1, −1} associated to self-inverse unitary op-
erators [2]. In general one can associate a binary logical operator with
whatever couple of distinct eigenvalues {λ1 , λ2 } the corresponding family
of logical operators can be found by Lagrange-Cayley-Hamilton matrix in-
terpolation methods. The extension from binary to many-valued logic is
then considered by defining specific operators using multivariate interpola-
tion. The interesting property is that a unique seed operator generates the
complete logical family of operators for a given m-valued n-arity system.
*
Laboratoire des Signaux et Systèmes
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
401
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
402
Workshops
403
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Our proof works from these axioms to show that the ‘pure’ processes in
our theory possess phased coproducts, a categorical feature we introduce to
describe superpositions in general process theories. In fact, we show that any
theory possessing these contains a copy of QuantS for some semi-ring S. This
provides a general and highly promising recipe for further reconstructions,
beyond our special axioms. In the future, we hope to use this to remove our
less operationally motivated axiom of dagger-compactness, to provide even
simpler and more intuitive categorical axioms for quantum theory.
References
1. S. Abramsky & B. Coecke, “A categorical semantics of quantum pro-
tocols”, in Proceedings of the 19th Annual IEEE * Symposium on Logic
in Computer Science, LICS ’04, 2004, pp. 415–425.
2. G. Chiribella, G.M. D’Ariano & P. Perinotti, “Informational derivation
of quantum theory”, Physical Review A, vol. 84(1), 2011.
3. B. Coecke & R. Lal, “Categorical quantum mechanics meets the pavia
principles: towards a representation theorem for cqm constructions”, in
Quantum Physics and Logic, hold in October 27–29, 2011, Nijmegen,
The Netherlands, p. 67, 2011.
4. B. Coecke & É.O. Paquette, “Categories for the Practising Physicist”,
in New Structures for Physics, edited by B. Coecke, Lecture Notes in
Physics, vol. 813, Springer, 2010, pp. 173–286.
5. L. Hardy, “Quantum Theory From Five Reasonable Axioms”, arXiv:
quant-ph/0101012, Cornell University Library, 2001.
6. L. Hardy, “Reformulating and Reconstructing Quantum Theory”, arXiv:
1104.2066, Cornell University Library, 2011.
7. C. Heunen & B. Jacobs, “Quantum logic in dagger kernel categories”,
‘Order, vol. 27(2), 2010, pp. 177–212.
8. M.P. Solèr, “Characterization of Hilbert spaces by orthomodular spaces”,
Communications in Algebra, vol. 23(1), 1995, pp. 219–243.
9. J. von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics,
Princeton University Press, 1955.
10. A. Wilce, “A Royal Road to Quantum Theory (or Thereabouts)”,
extended abstract, in Proceedings of 13th International Conference
on Quantum Physics and Logic, QPL 2016, University of Strathclyde,
UK, June 6–10, 2016, arXiv:1701.00664.
*
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers
Logic in Computer Science
404
Workshops
405
15 – Sessions
Universal
The keynote speaker at this session is Alexander Paseau (page 149).
407
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J.C. Beall & G. Restall, Logical Pluralism, Oxford University Press,
2006.
2. R.B. Brandom, Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Dis-
cursive Commitment, Harvard University Press, 1994.
3. J. Peregrin, Inferentialism: Why Rules Matter, Palgrave Macmillan,
2014.
408
Sessions
?
Universal Logic = Logic of the Universal
Laurent Dubois
Free University of Brussels, Belgium
[email protected]
410
Sessions
References
1. J. Barwise, “Axioms for abstract model theory”, Annals of Logic, vol. 7,
1974, pp. 221–265.
2. J.-Y. Beziau (editor), Logica Universalis: Towards a General Theory of
Logic, 2nd edition, Springer, 2007.
3. J.-Y. Beziau (editor), Universal Logic: An Anthology — From Paul
Hertz to Dov Gabbay, Springer, 2012.
4. A. Koslow and A. Buchsbaum (editors), The Road to Universal Logic:
Festschrift for 50th Birthday of Jean-Yves Béziau, Volume I, Birkhäuser,
2015.
5. R. Brady, Universal Logic, CSLI* Publications, 2006.
6. L. Dubois, “Lambda Theory: introduction of a constant for “nothing”
into set theory, a model of consistency and most noticeable conclusions”,
Logique et Analyse, vol. 56(222), 2013, pp. 165–181.
411
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. R.L. Epstein, Critical Thinking, Wadsworth Publishing, 1st edition,
1998.
2. R.L. Epstein, Five Ways of Saying “Therefore”: Arguments, Proofs,
Conditionals, Cause and Effect, Explanations, 2nd edition, Wadsworth
Publishing, 2001.
3. S. Krajewski, “Wnioskowania prawomocne i mocne: jednolite podejście
do wnioskowań niezawodnych i uprawdopodobniajacych”,
, in Identy-
cznosc znaku czy znak identycznosci, edited by J. Golinska-Pilarek &
A. Wojtowicz, Wydawnictwa UW, Warsaw, 2012, pp. 247–254.
412
Sessions
413
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Most of the issues treated in intensional logic have their roots in phi-
losophy. A look to the history reveals that modal notions (like necessity or
possibility) as well as the distinctions between de re and de dicto readings
of sentences are present all over.
The treatment of the identity concept and its distinction from the also
binary relation of equal denotation between terms of the formal language
can also be analyzed from a philosophical perspective.
In particular, we were surprised by the philosophical concept of nomi-
nalism. The models we have created in our completeness proofs need only
terms of the language and maximal consistent sets of sentences with partic-
ular extra properties. We wonder if, following ideas of Leon Henkin, we can
dispense with sets and relations in the definition of models by using sets of
formulas instead, and limit the existing objects to individuals. When modal,
hybrid and intensional logics are taken into account this view gains force as
it is in consonance with Carnap’s view of worlds as maximal consistent sets
of sentences.
References
1. C. Areces, P. Blackburn, A. Huertas & M. Manzano, “Completeness
in Hybrid Type Theory”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 43(2–3),
2014, pp. 209–238.
2. M. Manzano, M.A. Martins & A. Huertas, “Completeness in Equational
Hybrid Propositional Type Theory”, forthcoming.
3. M.C. Moreno, Intensions, Types and Existence, PhD thesis, University
of Salamanca, Spain, 2017.
414
Sessions
References
1. S. Marcelino & C. Caleiro, “Disjoint fibring of non-deterministic matri-
ces”, in Logic, Language, Information, and Computation: 24th Inter-
national Workshop, 2017, edited by J. Kennedy & R. Queiroz, Lecture
Notes in Computer Science, vol. 10388, 2017, pp. 242–255.
*
Research Workshop of the Israel Science Foundation
This work was done under the scope of R&D Unit 50008, financed by the applicable
financial framework (FCT/MEC through national funds and when applicable co-funded
by FEDER/PT2020).
Security and Quantum Information Group
416
Sessions
*
Research Workshop of the Israel Science Foundation
417
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
418
Sessions
References
1. M. Nowak, “A syntactic approach to closure operation”, Bulletin of the
Section of Logic, vol. 46(3–4), 2017, pp. 219–232.
2. D.J. Shoesmith & T.J. Smiley, Multiple-conclusion Logic, Cambridge
University Press, 1978.
3. J. Zygmunt, An Essay in Matrix Semantics for Consequence Relations,
Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Wroclawskiego, Wroclaw, Poland, 1984.
419
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
operators [n]. We want to defend two main theses about modal logic S5
and classical logic CL, considered as closed sets of theorems:
(1) S5 can be characterized by a semi-bivalent affirmative operator
[viii]ϕ = ([ii] ⊗ [iii])ϕ obeying (PBV2 ) and (PBV3 ), together with a
Morganian and non-Boolean negation obeying none of (NEG1 )–(NEG4 ).
(2) CL can be characterized by a semi-bivalent affirmative operator
[x]ϕ = ([i] ⊗ [iv])ϕ obeying (PBV1 ) and (PBV4 ), together with a
Morganian and Boolean negation obeying all of (NEG1 )–(NEG4 ).
References
1. F. Berto, “A Modality Called ‘Negation’ ”, Mind, vol. 124(495), 2015,
pp. 761–793.
2. J.-Y. Béziau, “Bivalence, excluded middle and non contradiction”, in
The Logica Yearbook 2003, edited by L. Behounek, Academy of Sciences,
Prague, 2003, pp. 73–84.
3. J.-Y. Béziau, “Classical negation can be expressed by one of its halves”,
Logic Journal of the IGPL * , vol. 7(2), 1999, pp. 145–151.
4. J.-Y. Béziau, “S5 is a paraconsistent logic and so is first-order classical
logic”, Logical Investigations, vol. 9, 2002, pp. 301–309.
5. J.-Y. Béziau, “A new four-valued approach to modal logic”, Logique et
Analyse, vol. 54(213), 2011, pp. 109–121.
6. J. Dugundji, “Note on a property of matrices for Lewis and Langford’s
calculi of propositions”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 5(4), 1940,
pp. 150–151.
7. J.M. Font & P. Hajek, “On Lukasiewicz’s four-valued logic”, Studia
Logica, vol. 70, 2002, pp. 157–182.
8. J. Lukasiewicz, “A system of modal logic”, Journal of Computing Sys-
tems, vol. 1(3), 1953, pp. 111–149.
9. R. Purtill, “Four-valued tables and modal logic”, Notre Dame Journal
of Formal Logic, vol. 11, 1970, pp. 505–511.
10. F. Schang & A. Costa-Leite, “Une sémantique générale des croyances
justifiées”, CLE e-Prints, vol. 16(3), 2016, pp. 1–24.
*
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science
420
Sessions
For each topos one can define a language which would be employed as a
convenient mean for yielding statements on objects and arrows of the topos
in question or even for proving theorems about them. Brief description of
the language and zero-order topos logic, formulated in this language, could
be found, for example, in [1].
Chris Mortensen, in his book “Inconsistent Mathematics” [2], introduced
the notion of complement topos where internal logic is dual to the usual logic
of standard topos. A principal peculiarity of complemented topos lies in a
presence of complement classifier in the latter. At the same time Mortensen
shown that a complement classifier in a topos Set is indistinguishable (via
categorical methods) from a standard subobject classifier, that they are
isomorphic. Thus, in Set we always have paraconsistency because of the
presence of both types of subobject classifiers. And complement toposes
support paraconsistency logic via Brouwerian algebra in a way exactly par-
allel to the way toposes support intuitionistic logic via Heyting algebras.
Since toposes support intuitionistic logics due to reflecting the Heyting
algebra structure by subobject classifier then in a complement topos comple-
ment classifier reflects the Brouwerian algebra structure respectively. Hence,
to describe an internal logic of complement topos we have to proceed in a
dual way. Taking that into account L. Estrada-Gonzáles in [3] presented a
sequent calculus for the zero-order complement topos logic.
But it seems that this ‘abstract’ categorical structure of toposes is prin-
cipally twofold by its nature. Actually, Heyting logic and Brouwer logic
always appear as Siamese twins — if one is given then the second might
be reconstructed. So, maybe in this case we should discuss not the stan-
dard topos alone and not the complement topos alone but another type of
category which, in a sense, contains them both.
The respective an H-B topos would be defined as a topos for which an
algebra of subobjects of any object is a semi-Boolean algebra [4]. It might
be regarded as the join of Heyting and Brouwerian algebras. For an H-B
topos one can also define an internal typed language and internal logic which
would be employed as a convenient mean for yielding statements on objects
and arrows of such topos in question.
*
This research is supported by RFH grant 16-03-00364.
421
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. C. McLarty, Elementary Categories, Elementary Toposes, Clarendon
Press, 1992.
2. C. Mortensen, Inconsistent Mathematics, Springer, 1995.
3. L. Estrada-González, “From (Paraconsistent) Topos Logic to Universal
(Topos) Logic”, in The Road to Universal Logic: Festschrift for 50th
Birthday of Jean-Yves Béziau, Volume II, edited by A. Koslow & A.
Buchsbaum, Birkhäuser, 2015, pp. 263–296.
4. C. Rauszer, An algebraic and Kripke-style approach to a certain ex-
tension of intuitionistic logic, Dissertationes Mathematicae, vol. 167,
PWN* , Warsaw, Poland, 61 pages, 1980.
5. V.L. Vasyukov, “Structuring the Universe of Universal Logic”, Logica
Universalis, vol. 1(2), 2007, pp. 277–294.
422
Sessions
1960s and 1970s, Tarski delivered at least three lectures on the nature of
logical concepts, but his related work was posthumously published in 1986
(in History and Philosophy of Logic). According to Tarski, a concept is
just logical provided that “it is invariant under all possible one-one trans-
formations of the world onto itself”. The adequacy of this characterization
depends whether we work in the type theory (the answer is “yes”) or ax-
iomatic set theory (the answer is negative). Thus, logicism can be defended
in the former scheme, but not in the latter. The problem is how to relate
invariance of logical notions to the universality of logic.
423
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Modal
Polynomial Semantics for Normal Modal Logics
Juan C. Agudelo-Agudelo
Institute of Mathematics,
University of Antioquia, Medellin, Colombia
[email protected]
References
1. J.C. Agudelo-Agudelo & W. Carnielli, “Polynomial ring calculus for
modal logics: a new semantics and proof method for modalities”, The
Review of Symbolic Logic, vol. 4(1), 2011, pp. 150–170.
2. J.C. Agudelo-Agudelo & W. Carnielli, “Polynomial ring calculus for
modalities”, Journal of Logic and Computation, vol. 27(6), 2017,
pp. 1853–1870, doi:10.1093/logcom/exv069.
3. J.C. Agudelo-Agudelo, C.A. Agudelo-González & O.E. Garcı́a-Quintero,
“On polynomial semantics for propositional logics”, Journal of Applied
Non-Classical Logics, vol. 26(2), 2016, pp. 103–125.
424
Sessions
*
Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science
425
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
*
The first author is supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation and the Ger-
man Ministry for Education and Research.
Both authors are supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant 817/15).
426
Sessions
References
1. O. Arieli and C. Straßer, “Sequent-based logical argumentation”, Argu-
ment and Computation, vol. 6(1), 2015, pp. 73–99.
2. A. Avron, “A constructive analysis of RM”, Symbolic Logic, vol. 52(4),
1987, pp. 939–951.
3. P. Besnard & A. Hunter, “A logic-based theory of deductive arguments”,
Artificial Intelligence, vol. 128(1-2), 2001, pp. 203–235.
4. M. Caminada and L. Amgoud, “On the evaluation of argumentation
formalisms”, Artificial Intelligence, vol. 171(5), 2007, pp. 286–310.
5. G. Gentzen, “Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen I, II”, Ma-
thematische Zeitschrift, vol. 39, 1934, pp. 176–210, pp. 405–431.
427
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
428
Sessions
References
1. F. Arntzenius, “Gunk, topology and measure”, in Oxford Studies in
Metaphysics, volume 4, edited by D. Zimmerman, Oxford University
Press, 2008, pp. 225–247.
2. Ph. Balbiani, T. Tinchev & D. Vakarelov, “Modal Logics for Region-
based Theories of Space”, Fundamenta Informaticae, vol. 81(1–3),
2007, pp. 29–82.
3. D. Vakarelov, “Region-Based Theory of Space: Algebras of Regions,
Representation Theory, and Logics”, in Mathematical Problems from
Applied Logic II: Logics for the XXIst Century, edited by D.M. Gabbay,
M. Zakharyaschev & S.S. Goncharov, Springer, 2007, pp. 267–348.
429
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
430
Sessions
If Eα, then the two rules of derivation are not valid. But, if Eα, then in
Ξ there is a possibility of the non-normal modal system called Falsum one.
Thus Ξ unites the normal and non-normal modal logics in one conceptual
scheme modeled by the square-and-hexagon [1].
Reference
1. V. Lobovikov, “An Axiomatization of Philosophical Epistemology”,
Tomsk State University Journal, Series: Philosophy, Sociology, Polit-
ical Studies, vol. 36(4), 2016, pp. 69–78.
References
1. K. Świetorzecka,
, Classical Conceptions of the Changeability of Situa-
tions and Things Represented in Formalized Languages, Cardinal Stefan
Wyszyński University, Warsaw, Poland, 2008.
2. K. Świetorzecka
, & J. Czermak, “A Logic of Change with Modalities”,
Logique et Analyse, vol. 52(253), 2011, pp. 511–527.
431
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Paola Glavan
Faculty of Mechanical Engineering and Naval Architecture,
University of Zagreb, Croatia
[email protected]
Using our logic, we can prove the correctness of the maintenance of the
ring topology of the Chord protocol [2] with the respect of the fact that
nodes are not allowed to departure the system after they join it.
References
1. R. Fagin, J.Y. Halpern, Y. Moses & M.Y. Vardi, Reasoning About
Knowledge, MIT* Press, 1995.
2. I. Stoica, R. Morris, D. Liben-Nowell, D. Karger, M. Kaashoek, F.
Dabek & H. Balakrishnan, “Chord: A Scalable Peer-to-peer Lookup
Service for Internet Applications”, IEEE /ACM Transactions on Net-
working, vol. 11(1), 2003, pp. 17–32.
D2 ∶= { A ∈ Ford ∶ ⌜3A● ⌝ ∈ S5 },
{ A ∈ Ford ∶ ⌜3A●n ⌝ ∈ S5 } .
The formulation of S5D2 depends on the normal modal logic S5. Al-
though, it is known [e.g. 5] that the very same logic D2 can be obtained
by means of different modal logics, it is possible to indicate modal logics
that give other than D2 discussive-like logics. Similarly, by appropriately
varying the accessibility relation, i.e. the relation that connects participants
of a given discussion, we can obtain other than S5D2 modal discussive logics.
The change of the accessibility relation leads to change of the philosophical
interpretation of functors in terms of Jaśkowski’s model of discussion.
References
1. S. Jaśkowski, “Rachunek zdań dla systemów dedukcyjnych sprzecznych”,
Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis, Sectio A, vol. 1(5), 1948,
pp. 57–77, English version: “Propositional calculus for contradictory
deductive systems”, Studia Logica, vol. 24(1), 1969, pp. 143–157, other
English version: “A propositional Calculus for inconsistent deductive
systems”, Logic and Logical Philosophy, vol. 7, 1999, pp. 35–56.
2. S. Jaśkowski, “O koniunkcji dyskusyjnej w rachunku zdań dla systemów
dedukcyjnych sprzecznych”, Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis,
Sectio A, vol. 1(8), 1949, pp. 171–172, English version: “On the discus-
sive conjunction in the propositional calculus for inconsistent deductive
systems”, Logic and Logical Philosophy, vol. 7, 1999, pp. 57–59.
3. J. Kotas, “The axiomatization of S. Jaśkowski’s discussive system”,
Studia Logica, vol. 33(2), 1974, pp. 195–200.
4. K. Mruczek-Nasieniewska, M. Nasieniewski & A. Pietruszczak, “A modal
logic over Jaśkowski’s discussive logic D2 , in preparation.
5. M. Nasieniewski & A. Pietruszczak, “A method of generating modal log-
ics defining Jaśkowski’s discussive logic D2 ”, Studia Logica, vol. 97(1),
2011, pp. 161–182.
434
Sessions
Many different modal logics have been developed about different modali-
ties (ontic, deontic, temporal, topological, epistemic. . . ). Syntactically, they
all share modal operators that affect propositional contents. Semantically,
from a Kripkean standpoint, they all can be represented as systems that
establish relations between possible worlds or between the actual world and
possible worlds. Each modal system has some axioms that define the specific
relations that it establishes between these worlds. This way, the specificity
of a modal system resides in the presence or the absence of axioms of seri-
ality, reflexivity, density, transitivity, symmetry, asymmetry, euclidianity. . .
Our talk aims at producing a general metamodal framework for modal
logics that can classify existing modal logics within it and that can generate
new modal logics from that framework. In such a framework, there are
two basic modalities, the strong one (the one true in all possible worlds,
like “necessary”) and the weak one (true in at least one possible world, like
“possible”).
The second goal of our talk is to develop hypotheses about the concep-
tions of different modalities that spontaneous reasoners might apply when
they reason with modalities. This way, many modal fallacies can be repre-
sented and explained as simplifications of the information occurring in the
premises. For example, many spontaneous reasoners consider “not neces-
sary p” (∼2p) as equivalent to “possible p” (3p). On the other hand, some
ways of reasoning can be different from what the modal system allows, with-
out being a fallacy, but being rather a distinctive philosophical conception
of the modality, like avoiding the asymmetry of time (FHp ⊃ p and PGp ⊃ p)
in temporal modalities, when holding, for example, a circular conception of
time. Of course, some logicians have made relevant contributions on such
philosophical conceptions of modalities [see e.g. 1,2], our aim is to suggest
a general framework for such contributions.
So, our metamodal framework for modalities allows 1) the generation of
new modal systems, 2) the modeling of what can be considered as modal
fallacies and 3) the modeling of different philosophical conceptions about
the different types (ontic, deontic, temporal. . . ) of modalities.
435
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. R. Girle, Modal Logics and Philosophy, McGill-Queen’s University Press,
2nd edition, 2009.
2. J.-L. Gardies, Essai sur la logique des modalités, Presses Universitaires
de France, 1979.
and
436
Sessions
the frame. The completeness theorem from [1] says that (1) the formulas
valid in all contact algebras are exactly the formulas valid in all Kripke
frames F with reflexive and symmetric accessibility relation R. Moreover,
if the contact algebras correspond to the connected topological spaces, then
the valid formulas are exactly the valid formulas in the class of Kripke
frames with reflexive, symmetric and connected (in the graph theory sense)
accessibility relation.
In this talk we will demonstrate undecidability of the modal definability
of the first-order sentences over the class of all (1) reflexive and symmetric
frames and (2) reflexive, symmetric and connected frames.
References
1. P. Balbiani, T. Tinchev & D. Vakarelov, “Modal Logics for Region-
based Theories of Space”, Fundamenta Informaticae, vol. 81(1–3),
2008, pp. 29–82.
2. I. Düntsch & D. Vakarelov, “Region-Based Theory of Discrete Spaces:
A Proximity Approach”, in Proceedings of Fourth International Con-
ference Journées de l’Informatique Messine, Metz, France, 2003, edited
by M. Nadif, A. Napoli, E. SanJuan & A. Sigayret, pp. 123–129, journal
version: Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence,
vol. 49(1–4), 2007, pp. 5–14.
Philippe Balbiani
CNRS* , IRIT , University of Toulouse, France
[email protected]
437
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Theorem.
(i) Any modal formula is first-order definable in CS4.3 .
(ii) First-order CS4.3 -definability is decidable.
References
1. Ph. Balbiani, D. Georgiev & T. Tinchev, “Modal correspondence theory
in the class of all Euclidean frames”, Journal of Logic and Computation,
to appear.
2. Ph. Balbiani & T. Tinchev, “Decidability and complexity of definability
within the class of all partitions”, in 5th Panhellenic Logic Symposium,
Athens, Greece, pp. 26–33, 2005.
3. A. Chagrov & L. Chagrova, “The Truth About Algorithmic Problems in
Correspondence Theory”, in Advances in Modal Logic, volume 6, edited
by G. Governatori, I. Hodkinson & Y. Venema, CSLI* Publications,
2006, pp. 121–138.
4. D. Georgiev, “Definability in the class of all KD45-frames computability
and complexity”, Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, to appear.
*
Center for the Study of Language and Information
438
Sessions
Non-Classical Logics
The keynote speakers at this session are Didier Dubois (page 125), Anna
Zamansky (page 167) & David Makinson (page 138).
The aim of this paper is to analyze the kind of inference that we use to
reconstruct Proto-Languages [7,4,6]. The importance of hypotheses for the
process and the whole structure of reasoning make us think that we are in
front of a certain kind of reasoning called abduction [5,3,1,8]. We analyze
the nature of this concrete abductive reasoning and we specify its nuances
and particularities. In fact, what is new in this work is that we center our
point in the importance of context. We pay attention to a form of abduc-
tion that goes beyond the context, where the scientific work is developed by
using other sciences as a contextual frame. So, an inter-contextual chain of
inferences can be part of an abductive process, being the resulting hypothe-
sis still provisional. To explain the ways for reconstructing Proto-Languages
— where several disciplines play a cognitive role, as archeology, history and
linguistic — we need several contexts, not just one.
We use the case of Proto-Semitic language reconstruction from the un-
expected fact of the discoveries of Ugarit and Ebla languages. Pointing
at Proto-Semitic, we need to presuppose the existence of a proto-Semitic
society, just like the most plausible hypothesis. The problem we have is
*
V Plan Propio de Investigación
439
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. A. Aliseda, Abductive Reasoning: Logical Investigations into Discovery
and Explanation, Springer, 2006.
2. P. Bonzon, M. Cavalcanti & R. Nossum (editors), Formal Aspects of
Context, Springer, 2000.
3. D.M. Gabbay & J. Woods (editors), The Reach of Abduction: Insight
and Trial, volume 2 of A Practical Logic of Cognitive Systems, Elsevier,
2005.
4. G. Garbini & O. Durand, Introduzione alle lingue semitiche, Paideia
Editrice, 1994.
5. J. Hintikka, Inquiry as Inquiry: A Logic of Scientific Discovery, Springer,
1999.
6. E. Lipinski, Semitic Languages Outline of a Comparative Grammar,
Orientalia Lovaniensia Analecta book series, vol. 80, 2nd edition, Peeters,
2000.
7. S. Moscati, A. Spitaler, E. Ullendorff & W. von Soden, An Introduction
to the Comparative Grammar of the Semitic Languages: Phonology and
Morphology, Porta Linguarum Orientalium book series, vol. 6, Otto
Harrassowitz, Wiesbaden, German, 1969.
440
Sessions
441
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
442
Sessions
Yanquan Zhou
Beijing University of Posts and Telecommunications,
Beijing, China
[email protected]
443
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
5. Differing from flexible logic, rigid logic does not have transition values
between 0 and 1. Consequently, it is workable as soon as it satisfies
reliability and completeness, without any abnormal results. However,
flexible logic does have transition values between 0 and 1. We cannot
use them directly, because abnormal results may appear. To solve this
problem, we put forward the condition to the integrity of flexible logic.
The basic principles for ensuring logical integrity are:
(1) The truth of two propositions may be the same, but h is not neces-
sarily 1, and the truth of the same proposition must be the same,
and h must be 1.
(2) As long as k is the same, integrity must be guaranteed.
444
Sessions
Γ⇒A Γ ⇒ ∼B Γ ⇒ ∼A[t∣x]
R∼⊃, R∼∀,
Γ ⇒ ∼(A ⊃ B) Γ ⇒ ∼∀xA
and so on.
The notion of partial conditional probability function is introduced. It
is any partial function Pr∶ WFF × 2WFF → [0, 1] satisfying 20 postulates
which express constraints. For example, POS.4: If A ∈ Γ, then Pr(A, Γ) = 1,
POS.8: Pr(A ⊃ B, Γ) = Pr(B, Γ ∪ {A}), and so on. POS.8 is critical: it
says that the probability of the conditional in SCISN is the conditional
probability (in fact, Lewis’ triviality result does not hold in SCISN nor in
intuitionistic logic). See [1] and [2].
The definition of probabilistic validity is given: the sequent Γ ⇒ A is
valid iff for any Pr and ∆, Pr(A, Γ ∪ ∆) = 1. See [3].
All the rules of SCISN are proved to be sound, i.e. if Pr satisfies all the
POS.n, then when the antecedent(s) is (are) valid, the succedent is valid.
446
Sessions
447
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
logic is not adequate for reasoning with indefinite and inconsistent informa-
tion. Moreover, the paradoxes of material implication of classical logic are
counterintuitive.
Rough set theory is concerned with the lower and the upper approxi-
mation of object sets. This approximation divides sets into three regions,
namely, the positive, negative, and boundary regions. Thus, Pawlak rough
sets have often been studied in a three-valued logic framework because the
third value is thought to correspond to the boundary region of rough sets
[2,3].
In this study, we show the relationship between decision logic and three-
valued semantics based on partial semantics and propose extended decision
logics based on three-valued logics. The formalization of many-valued logic
is carried out using a consequence relation based on partial semantics [4].
The basic logic for decision logic is assumed to be many-valued, in particular,
three-valued and some of its alternatives [5]. The decision logic will be ax-
iomatized using Gentzen sequent calculi and three-valued semantic relation
as basic theory. To apply three-valued logics to decision logic, consequence
relations based on partial interpretation are investigated, and sequent cal-
culi of three-valued logics are constructed. Subsequently, three-valued logics
with different structures are considered for the deduction system of decision
logic. These logics can serve as foundations for reasoning about rough and
vague information and we propose some extended decision logics.
References
1. Z. Pawlak, Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Data, Kluwer Aca-
demic Publishers, 1991.
2. A. Avron and B. Konikowska, “Rough Sets and 3-Valued Logics”, Studia
Logica, vol. 90, 2008, pp. 69–92.
3. Y. Nakayama, S. Akama & T. Murai, “Deduction System for Decision
Logic based on Partial Semantics”, The Eleventh International Confer-
ence on Advances in Semantic Processing, 2017, to appear.
4. J. van Benthem, “Partiality and Nonmonotonicity in Classical Logic”,
Logique et Analyse, vol. 29, 1986, pp. 225–247.
5. A. Urquhart, “Basic Many-Valued Logic”, in Handbook of Philosophical
Logic, volume 2, 2001, pp. 249–295.
449
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
450
Sessions
451
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The conclusion is that fuzzy logic and fuzzy semantics does not go the
whole way towards solving the communication problem in the presence of
words with inexact meanings and inexact domains of application, thus the
success of [2] and [5] is only partial.
This will be a small problem in a purely decision theoretic context. If
I am an Indian citizen and think that Sonia Gandhi is only 0.53 Indian,
I might then decide to vote for someone else. But many of our practices
are game theoretic or communication theoretic. We often need to work
with others who may use a different (fuzzy) semantics. See [4] for a partial
solution.
Can we develop a semantics where disagreements about the meaning
and application of words are minimized or eliminated? If two people have
similar values, but one likes feminism and the other opposes feminism, it
could be that they understand the same term “feminism” differently. Can
we reconcile them somehow? This is a burning question for modern times,
where AI has brought us closer and closer to social issues and not just
scientific issues or engineering issues.
References
1. R.E. Bellman & L.A. Zadeh, “Decision-Making in a Fuzzy Environ-
ment”, Management Science, vol. 17(4), 1970, pp. B141–B164.
2. M.K. Chakraborty & S. Dutta, “Graded consequence revisited”, Fuzzy
Sets and Systems, vol. 161(14), 2010, pp. 1885–1905.
3. R. Parikh, “A test for fuzzy logic”, ACM * SIGACT News, vol. 22(3),
1991, pp. 49–50.
4. R. Parikh, “Vagueness and utility: The semantics of common nouns”,
Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 17(6), 1994, pp. 521–535.
5. L.A. Zadeh, “The concept of a linguistic variable and its application
to approximate reasoning—I”, Information Sciences, vol. 8(3), 1975,
pp. 199–249, doi:10.1016/0020-0255(75)90036-5.
*
Association for Computing Machinery
Special Interest Group on Algorithms and Computation Theory
452
Sessions
453
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
454
Sessions
3. R.K. Meyer & R. Routley, “Classical relevant logics II”, Studia Logica,
vol. 33(2), 1974, pp. 183–194.
4. G. Robles & J.M. Méndez, Routley-Meyer ternary relational semantics
for intuitionistic-type negations, Elsevier, forthcoming in 2018.
5. R. Routley, R.K. Meyer, V. Plumwood & R.T. Brady, Relevant Logics
and their Rivals, volume 1, Ridgeview Publishing Co., Atascadero, CA,
USA, 1982.
456
Sessions
457
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Ivana Kuzmanović
Department of Mathematics,
Josip Juraj Strossmayer University, Osijek, Croatia
[email protected]
This paper based on M -theory [1] wants to show the correlation of Carte-
sian product of elements of ordered set with a basic, multi-value logic. Us-
ing simple algorithms discovered by M. Šare in the natural laws of electrical
networks [3], it is possible to construct logical tables, i.e. grids, for all logic
functions of n variables.
458
Sessions
Each element of the ordered set has its ‘semantic domain’ in the partition
of the total logical space (dashed in the table), e.g. for n = 2 domains are
‘ba, bb’ (for element ‘b’) and ‘aa, ab’ (for element ‘a’). Unlike fuzzy logic,
domains have (hierarchical) structure. By increasing the dimension n, there
is a shift of the value (weight) of the logic variable, as already noted in [2].
The paper is accompanied with an interactive M -theory online program
written in Python.
References
1. M. Essert, I. Kuzmanović, I. Vazler & T. Žilić, “Theory of M-system”,
Logic Journal of the IGPL * , vol. 25(5), 2017, pp. 836–858.
2. Y. Shramko & H. Wansing, “Some Useful 16-Valued Logics: How a
Computer Network Should Think”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 34(2),
2005, pp. 121–153.
3. M. Šare, Jorbologija, Element, Zagreb, Croatia, 2000.
*
Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics
459
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Argumentation
The keynote speakers at this session are Leila Amgoud (page 119), Leon
van der Torre (page 163) and Elena Lisanyuk (page 135).
460
Sessions
abduction might take place. In this respect, we focus on the notion of con-
cession that plays a central role in deductive dialogues. Indeed, abductive
dialogues are triggered by a concession-problem. That is, some participants
in a dialogue might want to continue an argumentative interaction despite
a blockage provoked by a lack of concessions. In that context, the dia-
logue becomes non-deductive and the proponent is allowed to introduce an
abductive conjecture by means of a conditional move. According to our ap-
proach, abductive dialogues are unconceded-preserving dialogues, that is,
what has been introduced by the proponent without previous concessions
of the opponent remains unconceded when the conjecture is used.
References
1. D.M. Gabbay & J. Woods, The Reach of Abduction: Insight and Trial,
Practical Logic of Cognitive Systems: volume 2, Elsevier, 2005.
2. C.S. Peirce, Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, edited
by C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A.W. Burks, 8 volumes, Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1931–1958.
of steps the procedure yields either the satisfiability or not of the formula
or formulas. In our case, we want a method to decide if sentences like
‘argument a is in’ or ‘argument a is out’ are satisfiable, combining ideas
from proof-theoretic and semantic approaches to argumentation. Starting
with an original sentence about the acceptation status of an argument, a
tree is build upon the different attack lines. Arguments along them are
marked in or out. In the end, some of the branches remain “open” (i.e.
without contradiction) and tracking back we can state whether the original
formula is satisfiable or not.
We define notions of satisfiability and validity, based on this tableaux
method, for argumentation frameworks. Furthermore, we show how to apply
it to capture skeptic/credulous acceptance criteria for Dung’s preferred and
credulous semantics.
References
1. E. Beth, Semantic Entailment and Formal Derivability, Mededelingen
van de Knifelike Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afdeling
Letterkunde, vol. 18(13), 1955, pp. 309–342, reprinted in The Philos-
ophy of Mathematics, edited by J. Hintikka, Oxford University Press,
1969.
2. M. Caminada, “On the Issue of Reinstatement in Argumentation”,
in Logics in Artificial Intelligence: 10th European Conference, Lecture
Notes in Computer Science, vol. 4160, 2006, pp. 111–123.
3. C. Cayrol, S. Doutre & J. Mengin, “Dialectical Proof Theories for the
Credulous Preferred Semantics of Argumentation Frameworks”, in Sym-
bolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning with Uncertainty: 6th
European Conference, Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol. 2143,
pp. 668–679, 2001.
4. C.I. Chesñevar & G.R. Simari, “An Abstract Model for Computing
Warrant in Skeptical Argumentation Frameworks”, in Proceedings of
the 11th Workshop on Nonmonotonic Reasoning, edited by J. Dix & A.
Hunter, IfI Technical Report Series, Clausthal University of Technology,
UK, 2006, pp. 409–417.
5. C.I. Chesñevar & G.R. Simari, “A Lattice-based Approach to Com-
puting Warranted Belief in Skeptical Argumentation Frameworks”, in
Proceedings of the 20th International Joint Conference on Artificial In-
telligence, 2007, pp. 280–285.
6. P.M. Dung, “On the Acceptability of Arguments and its Fundamental
Role in Non-Monotonic Reasoning, Logic Programming and n-Person
Games”, Artificial Intelligence, vol. 77(2), 1995, pp. 321–357, doi:10.
1016/0004-3702(94)00041-X.
462
Sessions
463
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. S. Kearns & D. Star, “Reasons as evidence”, in Oxford Studies
in Metaethics, edited by R. Shafer-Landau, volume 4, Oxford University
Press, 2009, pp. 215–242.
2. D. Godden & F. Zenker, “A probabilistic analysis of argument cogency”,
Synthese, vol. 195(4), 2018, pp. 1715–1740, doi:10.1007/s11229-016-
1299-2.
3. W. Spohn, The Laws of Belief, Oxford University Press, 2012.
4. F. Zenker, Review of [3], Philosophical Quaterly, vol. 65(259), 2014,
pp. 310–313.
5. F. Zenker, “Denying the Antecedent Probabilized: a Dialectical View”,
in Proceedings of the 8th International Conference of the International
Society for the Study of Argumentation, edited by F.H. van Eemeren,
B. Garssen, D. Godden & G. Mitchell, Rozenberg, Amsterdam, 2014,
pp. 1–14.
464
Sessions
465
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. J.-P. Desclés, G. Guibert & B. Sauzay, Logique Combinatoire et λ-
Calcul: des logiques d’opérateurs, Cépaduès Éditions, 2016.
2. J.R. Hindley & J.P. Seldin, Lambda-Calculus and Combinators: An
Introduction, Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition, 2008.
3. J.-P. Desclés, G. Guibert & B. Sauzay, Calculs de significations par une
logique d’opérateurs, Cépaduès Éditions, 2016.
4. J. Van Bethem, “The Lambek Calculus”, in Categorial Grammars and
Natural Language Structures, edited by R.T. Oehrle, E. Bach & D.
Wheeler, Springer, 1988, pp. 35–68.
466
Sessions
References
1. F. de Saussure, Cours de Linguistique Générale, Critical Edition, edited
by T. De Mauro, Payot, Paris, 1983.
2. R. Jakobson, Essais de Linguistique Générale 1, Minuit, Paris, 1963.
3. Cl. Lévi-Strauss, Les structures élémentaires de la parenté, Presses Uni-
versitaires de France, Paris, 1967.
467
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
468
Sessions
In [1], Marı́a Manzano and Enrique Alonso claimed that talking about
semantics before the 1920s is ‘a misconception’. For this reason, they pro-
pose the word ‘proto-semantics’ to speak about the collection of algorithmic
proceedings which were employed by Post [2], Bernays [3] or Wittgenstein
[4] to classify formulas of propositional logic. But contrary to them, we
argue that a conscientious analysis of the earliest consistency proofs for the
theory of propositional logic reveals that, while Post’s procedure of truth
tables can be fairly named ‘proto-semantics’, Bernays was able to identify
valid and provable formulas by providing an interpretation to his axioms.
What is more, Bernays compared the set of valid formulas with the set of
provable formulas, so that he proved soundness and completeness for propo-
sitional logic. We conclude our contribution wondering why Hilbert’s own
469
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Manzano & E. Alonso, “Completeness: from Gödel to Henkin”, in
History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 35(1), 2013, pp. 50–75, doi:10.1080
/01445340.2013.816555.
2. E. Post, “Introduction to a general theory of elementary propositions”,
1921, in [5] pp. 264–283.
3. P. Bernays, “Beiträge zur axiomatischen Behandlung des Logik-Kalküls”,
1918, in [6], pp. 231–271.
4. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Routledge, 1922.
5. J. van Heijenoort (editor), From Frege to Gödel: a Source Book in
Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Harvard University Press, 1967.
6. W. Ewald & W. Sieg (editors), David Hilbert’s lectures on the Founda-
tions of Arithmetic and Logic, 1917–1933, Springer, 2013.
The purpose of this paper is to start from the basis of formal logic and
mathematical logic, to establish the generalized bilingual logic based on the
scientific method system. The method is as follows: Step 1, use formal logic
with any language or symbol system; Step 2, use mathematical logic with
logical matrices and tableaux; Step 3, use logic of sequence and position
with the completeness of a single set or a series of finite set from hierarchi-
cal sets, and the relative completeness of attribute sets. It is characterized in
that the linkage function relation between two series of symbolic systems by
using the double list or matrix of both digital and textual, which is based
on human-computer interaction system, in both of interaction and batch
processing, based on the scientific method system. The result is that the
470
Sessions
471
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
472
Sessions
References
1. J.-Y. Girard, Interprétation fonctionnelle et élimination des coupures
de l’arithmétique d’ordre supérieur, Ph.D. Thesis, Université Paris 7,
1972.
2. J.C. Reynolds, “Towards a theory of type structure”, in Programming
Symposium, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 19, Springer, 1974,
pp. 408–425.
473
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Yanquan Zhou
Beijing University of Posts and Telecommunications,
Beijing, China
[email protected]
474
Sessions
Jerzy Loś is the Polish logician who happens to be one of the pioneers in
the field of philosophical logic. Precisely, his works [3,4] covering epistemic
and temporal logic, are the very first publications offering systems which
formalize topics such as propositional attitudes and time. However, the
pathfinder’s glory has somehow passed him by. One could point out many
causes for such exclusion, but, more than anything, unfortunate times are
there to blame. Nonetheless, despite the Iron Curtain, Loś’ ideas became
accessible to the western world due to reviews of Henryk Hiż [1] and Roman
Suszko [7]. In this respect, Polish thinker’s ideas are appreciated in Prior
[5] and Rescher [6]. Soon after that, his name is rarely mentioned.
The year 2018 marks the 70th anniversary of publishing [3], which makes
a great occasion to bring back some of the Loś’ work. We present general
treatment of logics with R-operator logics, as in [2]. Then we give it an epis-
temic interpretation by selecting certain systems. We construct a tableau-
style proof systems for those logics based on the more general theory [8].
References
1. H. Hiż, Review of [4], The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 16, 1951,
pp. 58–59.
2. T. Jarmużek & M. Tkaczyk, Normalne logiki pozycyjne (Normal posi-
tional logics), Towarzystwo naukowe KUL* , Lublin, 2015.
3. J. Loś, “Logiki wielowartościowe a formalizacja funkcji intensjonalnych”
(Multivalued logics vs. intensional functions formalization), Kwartalnik
Filozoficzny, vol. 17(1–2), 1948, pp. 59–78.
4. J. Loś, “Podstawy analizy metodologicznej kanonów Milla” (Basics of
methodological analysis of Mill’s canons), Annales Universitatis Mariae
Curie-Sklodowska, Sectio F, vol. 2, 1948, pp. 269–301.
5. A. Prior, Formal Logic, Oxford University Press, 1955.
6. N. Rescher & A. Urquhart, Temporal Logic, Springer, 1971.
7. R. Suszko, Review of “Many-Valued Logics and the Formalization of In-
tensional Functions”, by J. Loś, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 14(1),
1949, pp. 64–65.
*
Scientific Society of the Catholic University of Lublin
476
Sessions
Gergely Székely
Alfréd Rényi Institute of Mathematics, Budapest, Hungary
[email protected]
477
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell, Principia Mathematica, volume 1, Cam-
bridge University Press, 1910.
2. M. Fitting, Types, Tableaus, and Gödel’s God, Kluwer Academic Pub-
lishers, 2002.
References
1. M. Gardner, Logic Machines and Diagrams, 2nd edition, The University
of Chicago Press, 1982.
2. D.D. Roberts, The Existential Graphs of Charles S. Pierce, Mouton,
The Hague, 1973.
479
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Jean-Pierre Desclés
Université Paris-Sorbonne, France
[email protected]
Ismaı̈l Biskri
Université de Québec, Trois Rivières, Canada
[email protected]
References
1. J.-P. Desclés, “Schèmes et topologie (de Kant à la sémantique cog-
nitive)”, in Colloque Histoire des mathématiques et sciences sociales,
École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales, November 15–17, Lyon,
France, 2009.
2. J.-P. Desclés & A.C. Pascu, “Logique de la Détermination des Objets
(LDO): structuration topologique et quasi-topologique des extensions”,
in Logique en Question — Logic in Question, Association des Sciences
du Langage, Université Paris-Sorbonne, 2016.
480
Sessions
482
Sessions
C(C1 /x)
[C1 ≅C2 ]
(SI)
2
[Sub 0 C2 0 C1 0 C(C1 /x) ]
484
Sessions
485
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Mereology is the theory of the relation “being a part of”. The formal
language of mereology contains only one binary predicate “P”, whose in-
tended meaning is “being a part of”. Two additional binary predicates
“PP” and “O”, whose intended meanings are respectively “being a proper
part of” and “overlapping”, can be defined as follows. PPxy = Pxy ∧ ¬Pyx
and Oxy = ∃z (Pzx ∧ Pzy). The following axiom which can be found in
the literature [1] is called by the present writer “global complementation”
(GC):
∀x (¬∀y Pyx → ∃z ∀w (Pwz ↔ ¬Owx)).
Such an axiom says that anything which is not the greatest member
has a complement. There is another axiom called “local complementation”
(LC), which is formulated by the present writer [2] as follows:
It says that, for anything which is not the greatest member, any of its
proper part must have a complement in respect to that thing. It has been
shown that (GC) and (LC) have a lot to do with whether a first-order
axiomatizable mereological theory is decidable or not.
However, there can be some kind of complementation located in between,
for example, the complement of a member in respect to a definable class of
members. Let α(x) be a formula in which x is a free variable (where other
486
Sessions
Other kinds of complementation are still possible and this talk will look
into them in a more systematical way but will be confined to those which
can be first-order defined. In addition, some metalogical issues, such as
completeness or decidability, will also be touched.
References
1. R. Casati & A.C. Varzi, Parts and Places, MIT* Press, 1999.
2. H.-c. Tsai, “Notes on Models of First-Order Mereological Theories”,
Logic and Logical Philosophy, vol. 24(4), 2015, pp. 469–482, doi:10.
12775/LLP.2015.009.
*
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
487
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Philosophy
The keynote speaker at this session is Hartry Field (page 128).
Patrizio Paoletti
Patrizio Paoletti Foundation for Development
and Communication
[email protected]
488
Sessions
489
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
490
Sessions
491
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
492
Sessions
493
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
494
Sessions
References
1. M.V. Kritz, “Boundaries, interactions and environmental systems”,
Mecánica Computacional, vol. 29(26), 2010, pp. 2673–2687.
2. G.J. Klir, Facets of Systems Science, 2nd edition, Plenum Press, New
York, 2001.
3. M.V. Kritz & J.-Y. Beziau, “Théorie et modèle II”, Cadernos UFS de
Filosofia, vol. 10, 2011, pp. 7–16.
4. M.V. Kritz, “From systems to organisations”, Systems, vol. 5(1), 2017,
article no. 23, http://www.mdpi.com/2079-8954/5/1/23.
The distinction between the analytic and the synthetic as well as the
problem of the a priori synthetic judgment is an important point in mod-
ern history of philosophy and logic. In Kant’s Critique [3], the analytic is
associated with the a priori and the synthetic with the a posteriori, and the
distinction between the two is linked to the criteria of necessity and uni-
versality. The a priori synthetic judgment makes it possible to account for
the nature of judgments in logic and mathematics, but it appears to many
philosophers as a kind of monstrous hybrid. The critics of the analytic / syn-
thetic distinction and of the hybrids it allows for are diverse: some of them
assume it, but reject the a priori synthetic judgment [2], while some others
does accept it (Husserl); some reject the analytic/synthetic distinction [6]
while some others dispute the association between the analytic, a priori and
necessity and between the synthetic, a posteriori and contingency [4]. Il
would like to suggest that the debate on the analytic / synthetic distinction
can be thought over in a new way and framed as a problem of heterological
synthesis. It is a fact that the problem of synthesis has hitherto been posited
in terms of homology, for instance, when one makes an epistemic synthesis
of some theoretical and empirical statements. The outcome of this kind of
homological synthesis is well illustrated by an epistemic statement such as
P : ‘It is possible to clone a human being’. It is quite different if the problem
of synthesis is posed in terms of heterology, for instance, when one makes an
*
Institut Catholique d’Arts et Métiers
Groupe de Sociologie Pragmatique et Réflexive
496
Sessions
References
1. A.J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic, Penguin, 2001.
2. G. Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetics: A Logico-Mathematical En-
quiry into the Concept of Number, Northwestern University Press, 1980.
3. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Cambridge University Press, 1999.
4. S.A. Kripke, Naming and necessity, Wiley-Blackwell, 1999.
5. H. Putnam, “The Analytic and the Synthetic”, in Mind, Language
and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Cambridge University Press, 1975,
pp. 33–69.
6. W.V.O. Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, The Philosophical Re-
view, vol. 60(1), 1951, pp. 20–43.
7. G. Schurz, “The Is-Ought Problem: An Investigation in Philosophical
Logic”, Studia Logica, vol. 65(3), 2000, pp. 432–434.
8. S. Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the 20th Century, 2 volumes, Prince-
ton University Press, 2005.
497
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. P. Lukowski, “An approach to the liar paradox”, in New Aspects in Non-
Classical Logics and Their Kripke Semantics, RIMS, Kyoto University,
1997, pp. 68–80.
2. P. Lukowski, Paradoxes, Springer, 2011.
3. A.N. Prior, “On a family of paradoxes”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic, vol. 2(1), 1961, pp. 16–32.
4. S. Rahman, T. Tulenheimo & E. Genot (editors), Unity, Truth and the
Liar: The Modern Relevance of Medieval Solutions to the Liar Paradox,
Springer, 2008.
*
This research is supported by the National Science Center of Poland — grant no.
2015/17/B/HS1/02332.
498
Sessions
Stereology
Nikolay Milkov
Paderborn University, Germany
[email protected]
The tasks put forward by the recent developments in information sys-
tems research, especially those connected with the problems of knowledge
representation, made the parallel task of advancing a formal ontology for
the common sense world — for the world of everyday human experience
— of first rate importance. This is, above all, a task of representing the
denizens of the naive physics, of the mesoscopic objects and of the quan-
titative reasoning in space and time in general. By way of addressing this
problem, many authors placed great hopes on a variety of new approaches
of increasing complexity:
(a) Set Theory. To this purpose the resources of the naive set theory are
widely used. Unfortunately, set theories — of any kind — fail to do
justice to the difference between natural totalities, such as dog, and ad
hoc totalities, such as Brezhnev, the sun, the sea.
(b) Mereology. This is the discipline investigating the relation between
parts and whole. Unfortunately, as it was noted in the literature, in ca-
pacity of formal ontology of the mesocosmic objects, traditional mere-
ology has many deficiencies. For example, it neglects the problems of
continua and boundaries which are sine qua non when the objective is
to represent integral objects of the mesocosmos.
(c) Mereotopology. This motivated attempts — made in the recent years
mainly by Roberto Casati, Achille Varzi and Barry Smith — to supple-
ment mereology with topology to a mereotopology. Central concepts of
mereotopology are boundary, inside/outside, abutting and surrounding.
It is based on a simple mereo-topological primitive of connected part-
hood. Regrettably, mereotopology fails to present the objects in their
full integrity as well. This brings some proponents of mereotopology to
the idea to supplement it with at least two other disciplines: (1) mor-
phology: theory of qualitative discontinuants, and (2) kinematics and
dynamics which explain the behavior of its parts. They must help to
represent the shape and behavior of objects, as well as the interaction
between them.
(d) Theory of Granular Partitions. This new discipline tries to come
to terms with the task to represent the results of sorting, classification,
dividing into units, counting, parceling out, mapping, listing, pigeon-
holing, and cataloguing. Its models apply different types of partitions
— that are appropriate for different situations — in which the objects
under scrutiny can be put in. Partitions themselves are not objects.
499
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The time has come to take a long hard look at the teaching of intro-
ductory logic. The very first lesson of the very first logic course contains
highly contested material that only those with an interest in the philoso-
phy of logic will ever again re-visit. Teachers say things which are vital to
an understanding of logic, right at the point when those things are most
likely to be accepted without critical examination, and then never return
and re-examine those points. As Stephen Read says, “Teaching in philoso-
phy departments across the world exhibits this schizophrenia, in which the
dogmatic approach to the philosophy of logic sits uncomfortably side by side
with the ceaseless critical examination which is encourages and demanded
in philosophy” [1, p. 2]. This alone is bad enough, but the current state of
the teaching of philosophy of logic is worse.
The teaching of logic starts in the right place, with a discussion of the
nature of the subject matter at hand, which as it happens is also introduc-
tory philosophy of logic. Courses typically open with a discussion of what
logic is about and a definition of validity, and as Stephen Read says, “The
central topic in the philosophy of logic is inference, that is, logical conse-
quence, or what follows correctly from what” [1, p. 1]. So, forcibly excising
the teaching of the philosophy of logic from introductory logic course would
be the wrong approach because another way to see that very first lesson is
not as a lesson at all but merely the sort of sensible introduction to what
the student will learn during the course.
There are hard questions in the philosophy of logic, questions that stu-
dents probably can’t engage with immediately, so the introduction should
walk a fine line — setting the stage for a conversation that a student will not
500
Sessions
be prepared to join until later. But in the very first lesson of the very first
logic course students are introduced to the central topic in the philosophy
of logic in a manner which is unforgivably contradictory and inexcusably
dogmatic. This bad pedagogy is bad enough, but the potential ramifica-
tions for the discipline are worse. In what has become a pivotal piece in the
discussion of the nature of validity MacFarlane says that for addressing the
hard questions in the philosophy of logic “The dominant methodology for
addressing them involves frequent appeals to our “intuitions” about logical
validity. I do not think it should surprise us that this methodology leads dif-
ferent investigators in different directions. For our intuitions about logical
validity, such as they are, are largely the products of our logical educations”
[2, p. 2]. It is a disservice to philosophical colleges who will not specialise
in logic to teach bad philosophy of logic, but it shows a reckless disregard
for the advancement of the discipline to introduce a central topic in a way
that impairs future investigators.
In this paper, I will present a combination of the results of a text analysis
of introductory logic texts along with some exemplars of the ideas that these
texts communicate on the subject matter of logic. I break the examples of
problematic teaching down into three categories: the pseudo psychological,
the normative nonsense, and the over-concentration on argument as if that
gets you out of it. I discuss the aspects of the current debate in philosophy
of logic that make these teachings problematic.
I finish with a discussion of the connections between logic, psychology,
norms, and argument and explain that I am not arguing that these ideas
do not belong to the discipline of logic, but their impact on the notion of
validity is significant enough that presentation in introductory texts should
be conducted with care.
References
1. S. Read, Thinking about Logic: An Introduction to the Philosophy of
Logic, Oxford University Press, 1995.
2. J. Macfarlane, “In What Sense (If Any) Is Logic Normative for
Thought?”, in Central Division * Meeting, Symposium on the Normativ-
ity of Logic, American Philosophical Association, 2004, https://
johnmacfarlane.net/normativity of logic.pdf.
*
The Central Division is one of three divisions of the American Philosophical Association,
along with the Eastern and Pacific Divisions.
501
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
502
Sessions
(i) some conceptual support may be provided for Token Preservation, which
doesn’t rely on a causal misreading of the turnstile, and that (ii) the appeal
to non feasible ways of doing feasible things is not a good way to argue for
Preservation of Local Feasibility.
I shall then assess the merits and limits of radical antirealism and the
logic of feasible proofs, whether the radical antirealist merely stipulates what
human feasibility amounts to, or dispenses with structural rules by arguing
in favour of a curb on the epistemic idealizations they unwarrantedly embed.
It will be noted here that there is a great difference, conceptually speak-
ing, between the rejection of classical logic via the curbing of the epistemic
idealizations embedded in structural rules, and the rejection of classical logic
via the criticism of introduction and elimination rules which fix the meaning
of the classical constants. E.g., the rejection of Weakening and Contraction
by way of Token Preservation and Preservation of Local Feasibility doesn’t
have to rely on arguments in favour of the surveyability of the implemen-
tation of decision procedures, or to any particular conception of how one
may go from one proof to another by way of deductive rules. The reasons
why we should want to narrow the scope of idealization are quite different
in each case. One telling case of study in this respect is that of the rela-
tion between structural rules and logical rules in the intuitionistic context.
The kind of logical revisionism envisaged by intuitionists from Heyting on
is in many respects stronger than the one envisaged by advocates of linear
logic, should such revisionists ground their arguments on an endorsement of
strict antirealism. A clearer philosophical conception is needed of how the
rules for the logical connectives in the intuitionistic calculus depend on the
structural rules which the radical antirealist wishes to reject.
References
1. D. Bonnay & M. Cozic, “Which Logic for the Radical Antirealist?”, in
The Realism-Antirealism Debate in the Age of Alternative Logics, edited
by S. Rahman, G. Primiero & M. Marion, Springer, 2012, pp. 47–67.
2. J. Dubucs & M. Marion, “Strict Antirealism and Substructural Log-
ics”, in Philosophical Dimensions of Logic and Science, edited by J.
Cachro, G. Kurezewski & A. Rojsczak, Kluwer Academic Publishers,
2004, pp. 235–249.
3. M. Dummett, “The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionistic Logic” (1973),
in Truth and Other Enigmas, Harvard University Press, 1st edition,
1978, pp. 215–247.
4. C. Wright, “Strict Finitism” (1982), in Realism, Meaning and Truth,
Wiley-Blackwell, 2nd edition, 1993, pp. 107–175.
503
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
504
Sessions
References
1. W. Künne, “Are Questions Propositions?”, Revue Internationale de
Philosophie, vol. 224, 2003, pp. 45–56, https://www.cairn.info/revue-
internationale-de-philosophie-2003-2-page-45.htm.
2. J. Groenendijk & M. Stokhof, “Questions”, in The Handbook of Logic
and Language, edited by J. van Benthem and A. Ter Meulen, North
Holland, 1997, pp. 1055–1124.
3. L. Åqvist, “Revised foundations for imperative-epistemic and interrog-
ative logic”, Theoria, vol. 37(1), 1971, pp. 33–73.
Combinations of Interpretations
in Universal Logical Hermeneutics
Elena Shulga
Institute of Philosophy,
Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow, Russia
[email protected]
505
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. B. Wolniewicz, Logic and Metaphysics, Znak-Jȩzyk-Rzeczywistość, War-
saw, Poland, 1999.
2. V.L. Vasyukov, “Structuring the Universe of Universal Logic”, Logica
Universalis, vol. 1(2), 2007, pp. 277–294.
506
Sessions
507
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
the proposed theory: Scott’s and Aczel’s semantics. The first one yields a
problematic result, that there are no models for the considered theory, con-
taining a non-empty collection of all substantially funded attributes - the
so called adherences. We show that Aczel’s semantics does not contain this
difficulty. There are described Aczel’s models with a non-empty set of all
adherences. The self-referentiality of such a collection becomes irrelevant
here. Finally, we show that there are Aczel’s structures verifying the for-
mula on reloading abstracts and we exclude them from the class of models
intended for our theory.
508
Sessions
References
1. L. Wittgenstein, Carnets (1914–1916), translated by G.-G. Granger,
Gallimard, Paris, 1971.
2. N.A. Vasiliev, “Logic and Metalogic” (1912–1913), translated by V.L.
Vasyukov, Axiomathes, vol. 4(3), 1993, pp. 329–351.
509
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Computation
Is Classical Mathematics Appropriate
for Theory of Computation?
Farzad Didehvar
School of Mathematics and Computer Science,
Amir Kabir University, Tehran, Iran
[email protected]
In this talk, we try to show how and why our mathematical framework
seems inappropriate to solve some problems in Theory of Computation.
More exactly, the concept of turning back in time in paradoxes causes incon-
sistency in modeling of the concept of “Time” in some semantic situations.
As we see in the first chapter, by introducing a version of “Unexpected
Hanging Paradox”, first we attempt to open a new explanation for some
paradoxes. In the second step, by applying this paradox, it is demonstrated
that any formalized system for the Theory of Computation based on Clas-
sical Logic and Turing Model of Computation leads us to a contradiction.
We conclude that our mathematical frame work is inappropriate for Theory
of Computation. Furthermore, the result provides us a reason that many
problems in Complexity Theory resist to be solved.
References
1. F. Didehvar, “A Semantic Situation without Syntax (Non axiomatiz-
ability of Theories)”, in Handbook of the 5th World Congress and School
on Universal Logic, İstanbul University, Turkey, 2015, pp. 307–311.
2. F. Didehvar, “Is Classical Mathematics Appropriate for Theory of Com-
putation?”, viXra.org, 2017, viXra:1705.0226.
3. F. Didehvar, “When the proof doesn’t show the truth”, World Philos-
ophy Day, 2010, pp. 153–161.
4. R. Lipton, The P = NP Question and Gödel’s Lost Letter, Springer,
2010.
510
Sessions
Mykola Nikitchenko
Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv, Ukraine
[email protected]
Program logics are main formalisms that are used to prove properties of
software systems. Different types of such systems (sequential, distributed,
real-time, reactive, embedded, etc.) lead to different types of program logics.
Obtained diversity of logics complicates their investigation and usage. In
this situation, methodological principles can provide the theoretical under-
pinning for understanding of program logics construction and investigation.
In this paper we continue our research on developing methodological
basis for logic construction [1,2] concentrating on program logics. The main
attention is paid to the principle of development from abstract to concrete
and to the principle of integrity of intensional and extensional aspects.
These principles are applied to the main semantic notions of programs:
data, function and composition. Data are specified as intensionalized data
that represent integrity of data intension and extension [1]. We identify
three types of such data: abstract data, nominative sets and hierarchical
nominative data. A such classification leads to three types of intension-
alized functions: abstract function, quasiary functions and hierarchic-ary
functions. Finally, we define three classes of compositions over above men-
tioned classes of functions. This permits to construct various classes of
algebras which form the semantic base for predicate logics [3] and program
logics of Floyd-Hoare type [4].
Obtained program logics better represent such program properties as
partiality, nondeterminism and semistructuring of data. Such logics gen-
eralize conventional program logics and demonstrate usefulness of method-
ological principles for their construction.
References
1. M. Nikitchenko & A. Chentsov, “Basics of Intensionalized Data: Pre-
sets, Sets, and Nominats”, Computer Science Journal of Moldova,
vol. 20, no. 3(60), 2012, pp. 334–365.
2. V. Gavryluk & M. Nikitchenko, “Philosophical Aspects of Program-
ming Theory Development”, in Handbook of the 5th World Congress
and School on Universal Logic, İstanbul, Turkey, 2015, pp. 210–211.
511
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
512
Sessions
References
1. J. Peregrin & V. Svoboda, Reflective Equilibrium and the Principles of
Logical Analysis, Routledge, 2017.
2. A. Turing, “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Ent-
scheidungsproblem”, Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society,
vol. 2(42), 1936, pp. 230–65.
513
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Nikitchenko & V. Tymofieiev, “Satisfiability in Composition-Nomina-
tive Logics”, Central European Journal of Computer Science, vol. 2(3),
2012, pp. 194–213.
2. M. Nikitchenko & S. Shkilniak, “Algebras and logics of partial quasiary
predicates”, Algebra and Discrete Mathematics, vol. 23(2), 2017,
pp. 263–278.
Application Areas
Defining a category for languages allows us to define lifts, for example,
from context. The linguistics abstraction techniques proposed allows us to
lift from context. With signature tree languages we can carry on partitions
on models for a formal language that factor generic models. Let L1 , . . . , Ln
be language fragments n ∈ ω. Σ1 , . . . , Σn are the fragment natural grammar
signatures. TΣ1 , . . . , TΣn are the free trees on the grammar signatures. Each
fragment language signature tree TΣ ⊂ i ∈ ω can be assigned a fragment
semantics whereby to each t ∈ TΣi the free well-formed syntax trees ti and
tj are congruent, which is denoted ti ≡ tj , iff there is a context free parse
normal form common to both. Let us denote that congruence with ≡ ⊂ CT F
fragment. L1 , L2 , . . . , Ln are fragments n < ω, i.e. natural numbers.
Proposition 2. ≡ ⊂ CT F is a Σ-congruence.
References
1. J.A. Goguen, J.W. Thatcher, E.G. Wagner & J.B. Wright, A Junction
Between Computer Science and Category Theory (parts I and II), IBM
Thomas J. Watson Research Center, Yorktown Heights, USA, 1973.
2. C.F. Nourani, “Slalom tree computing — a tree computing theory for
artificial intelligence”, AI Communications, vol. 9(4), 1996,
pp. 207–213.
515
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
516
Sessions
References
1. C. Cohen, Th. Coquand, S. Huber & A. Mörtberg, “Cubical Type The-
ory: a constructive interpretation of the univalence axiom”, arXiv:1611.
02108, Cornell University Library, 2016.
2. Univalent Foundations Program* , Homotopy Type Theory: Univalent
Foundations of Mathematics, Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton,
New Jersey, USA, 2013.
3. P. Suppes, Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures, CSLI
Publications, 2002.
517
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Makkai, “Generalized sketches as a framework for completeness the-
orems. Part I”, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra, vol. 115(1), 1997,
pp. 49–79, doi:10.1016/S0022-4049(96)00007-2.
2. M. Makkai, “Generalized sketches as a framework for completeness the-
orems. Part II”, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra, vol. 115(2),
1997, pp. 179–212, doi:10.1016/S0022-4049(96)00008-4.
3. M. Makkai, “Generalized sketches as a framework for completeness the-
orems. Part III”, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra, vol. 115(3),
1997, pp. 241–274, doi:10.1016/S0022-4049(96)00009-6.
4. Z. Diskin & U. Wolter, “A Diagrammatic Logic for Object-Oriented
Visual Modeling”, Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science,
vol. 203(6), 2008, pp. 19–41.
519
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
520
Sessions
History
The keynote speaker at this session is Anne-Françoise Schmid (page 159).
521
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. Abu Nasr Al-Farabi, Ihsa’ al-’ulum (Enumeration of the Sciences), in-
vestigated by O. Amin, Anglo Library, Cairo, Egypt, 1968.
2. Abu Nasr Al-Farabi, Al-Farabi’s Commentary and Short Treatise on
Aristotle’s De Interpretation, Investigation by P.W. Zimmerman, Ox-
ford University Press, 1981.
3. Abu Nasr Al-Farabi, Book in Logic Al-Burhan (Analytica Posteriore),
investigated by M.G. Salem & D. Alktub, Book of House, Egypt, 1976.
4. J. Allwood, L.-G. Andersson & O. Dahl, Logic in Linguistics, Cam-
bridge University Press, 1979.
5. O. Bakar, Classification of Knowledge in Islam: A Study in Islamic
Philosophies of Science, The Islamic Texts Society, Cambridge, UK,
1998.
6. J. van Ess, “The Logical Structure of Islamic Theology”, chapter in
Logic in Classical Islamic Culture, edited by G.E. von Grunebaum, Otto
Harrassowitz, Germany, 1970.
Since Aristotle’s works of logic edited under the title of Organon [1],
many logicians prepared and evaluated methods of demonstrating the va-
lidity and invalidity of Aristotle’s syllogisms that we encounter mainly in
the Prior Analytics of Organon. This paper is not a historical evaluation
of various such methods and attempts of demonstrations. Instead, I intend
to put forward a new and simple method of checking the validity of syl-
logisms for which I will claim that it has several advantages over some of
the previous influential and popular methods. Some of the methods that
I am going to evaluate in this paper are either algebraic, geometrical or in
modern symbolic fashion. By means of this, I will evaluate Leibniz’s linear
diagrams, Boole’s [2] algebraic treatment of syllogisms, Venn’s diagrams
and Lucasiewicz [3], Simely and Corcoran [4] types of proofs by natural
deduction and compare them with the method I am proposing here.
This paper have two main parts. In the first part I will introduce a
new method of demonstration which I will call the hierarchical method of
demonstration for the ontological logic of Aristotle. The core reason of
522
Sessions
References
1. Aristotle, Organon, in The Works of Aristotle, edited and translated by
W.D. Ross, Clarendon Press, 1951.
2. G. Boole, An Investigation of the Law of Thought (1854), on line source:
http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/15114.
3. J. Lukasiewicz, Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern
Formal Logic, 2nd edition, Oxford University Press, 1957.
4. J. Corcoran, “Aristotle’s demonstrative logic”, in History and Philoso-
phy of Logic, volume 30, 2009, pp. 1–20.
523
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
524
Sessions
References
1. Aristotle, Analytica Priora et Posteriora, edited by W.D. Ross, Claren-
don Press, 1964.
2. J. Etchemendy, “Tarski on Truth and Logical Consequence”, The Jour-
nal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 53(1), 1988, pp. 51–79.
3. J. Etchemendy, The Concept of Logical Consequence, Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1990.
4. J. Etchemendy, “Reflections on Consequence”, in New Essays on Tarski
and Philosophy, edited by D. Patterson, Oxford University Press, 2008,
pp. 263-299.
5. P. Mancosu, “Tarski on Models and Logical Consequence”, in The
Architecture of Modern Mathematics. Essays in History and Philos-
ophy, edited by J. Ferreiros & J. Gray, Oxford University Press, 2006,
pp. 209–237.
6. P. Mancosu, “Fixed- versus Variable-domain Interpretations of Tarski’s
Account of Logical Consequence”, Philosophy Compass vol. 5(9), 2010,
pp. 745–759.
7. A. Tarski, “Über den Begriff der logischen Folgerung”, Actes du Congrès
International de Philosophie Scientifique, VII Logique, Actualités Scien-
tifiques et Industrielles, vol. 394, Hermann et Cie, Paris, 1936, pp. 1–11.
8. T. Williamson, “Logics as Scientific Theories”, unpublished paper pre-
sented on October 26, 2011 at the Munich Center of Mathematical
Philosophy, Ludwig Maximilians University of Munich, Germany, 2011.
9. T. Williamson, “Logics as Scientific Theories”, unpublished paper pre-
sented on October 30, 2011 in the Parliament Hall of St. Andrews, Arché
Workshop: The Epistemology of Logic, 2011.
10. T. Williamson, “Logics as Scientific Theories”, unpublished talk given
on June 5, 2012 at the University of Lisbon, Petrus Hispanus Lectures,
2012.
525
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. P.M. Healey, “Understandings of Logic Sublated by the Dialectic”, Phi-
losophy Study, vol. 4(1), 2014, pp. 41–54, doi:10.17265/2159-5313/2014.
01.006.
2. P.M. Healey, “Squaring the Dialectic of Inference and Chance”, Phi-
losophy Study, 2015, vol. 5(5), 2015, pp. 257–271, doi:10.17265/2159-
5313/2015.05.004.
3. K. de Boer, “Hegel’s Account of Contradiction in the Science of Logic
Reconsidered”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, vol. 48(3), 2010,
pp. 345–373.
4. D.K. Lewis, “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance”, in Philos-
ophy of Probability: Contemporary Readings, edited by R.C. Jeffrey,
University of California Press, 1980, pp. 83–132.
5. D.K. Lewis, “Humean Supervenience Debugged”, Mind, vol. 103(412),
1994, pp. 473–490.
526
Sessions
References
1. Aristotle, Prior Analytics, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, Book
II, Chapter 4, edited by J. Barnes, Princeton University Press, 1984.
2. M. Storrs, “A History of Connexivity”, in Logic: A History of its Central
Concepts, edited by D.M. Gabbay, F.J. Pelletier & J. Woods, volume
11 of Handbook of The History of Logic, North-Holland, 2012.
3. R.B. Angell, “Three Logics of Subjunctive Conditionals”, presented
at Colloquium on Logic and Foundations of Mathematics, Hannover,
Germany, 1966, online resource: http://www.rbangell.com/papers
AndArticles.asp, abstract published in The Journal of Symbolic Logic,
vol. 32(4), 1967, pp. 556–557.
4. G. Priest, “The logic of paradox”, Journal of Philosophical Logic,
vol. 8(1), 1979, pp. 219–241, doi:10.1007/BF00258428.
527
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Reference
1. I. Kant, Lectures on Metaphysics, edited and translated by K. Ameriks
& S. Naragon, Cambridge University Press, 1997.
528
Sessions
529
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The objectives of the paper are threefold. First, it will aim at giving a
thorough description of eristic based on the ancient sources that remain. It
will also address the controversial question of the identity of eristics. Sec-
ondly, it will analyse the different arguments used by eristics and highlight
their originality and philosophical implications. Finally, it will discuss the
influence of eristic on the developments of logic and demonstrate its impor-
tance.
JianMing Zhou
Independent Scholar, YueYang, China
zhou [email protected]
One of the most basic and difficult problems in Computer Science and
Artificial Intelligence is about human judgment and machine decision as
well as their relationship, which concerns nondeterminism.
In computability theory, determinism is expressed in terms of com-
putability. A deterministic problem (P) is decidable and solvable by an exact
algorithm. The work of Turing [1] shows that the computability means that
the capacity of algorithm can match the growth of problem size. Moreover,
in computational complexity theory, determinism is precisely defined by the
concept of polynomial time complexity. The polynomial time complexity is
related to linear, while the exponential time complexity related to nonlinear,
which corresponds to nondeterministic problem (NP).
On the one hand, the power of computer gives people a conceptual
illusion: NP may be solved ultimately by exact algorithms as P; on the other
hand, people still keep a cognitive intuition that P is essentially different
from NP. This situation is expressed as famous P vs NP problem, designated
as one of seven Millennium Problems by the Clay Mathematics Institute [2].
Although P is defined by computability, but NP cannot be defined by
computability, which is logically unjudgeable, thus undecidable. P vs NP
expresses the inherent difficulty in formal logic due to self-winding, the
difficult relationship between the pure formal thought and the subjectivity
of human cognition.
*
Laboratoire de Modélisation, Information & Systèmes
530
Sessions
The difference and relation between nature languages and formal lan-
guages has become an important research direction in the modern philoso-
phy. In Chinese language, Chinese traditional logic focus on human judg-
ment, and has a natural rationality that is consistent with the content of
reasoning, so the difficulty of self-winding in formal logic can be naturally
avoided.
Chinese traditional logic is not separated from natural language to form
a special logic system, but combined with Chinese thought, which is inte-
grated into history and classics. It remains a few representative figures and
case studies, such as the famous Chinese paradox white horse is not horse,
proposed by a great Chinese logician Gongsun Long (*325–250 BC) [3].
From a modern point of view, Chinese traditional logic is based on the
idea of logical hierarchy. Although Chinese traditional logic has a particular
style and has not been sufficiently developed, it can bring insight into the
most difficult problems involved in modern mathematical logic.
References
1. A. Turing, “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Ent-
scheidungsproblem”, Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society,
1937, doi:10.1112/plms/s2-42.1.230.
2. S. Cook, “The P versus NP Problem”, Clay Mathematics Institute,
2000, https://www.claymath.org/sites/default/files/pvsnp.pdf.
3. Q. Sun, Gongsun Long Zi, English version, ZheJiang Gongshang Uni-
versity Press, 2014.
531
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. F. Beiser, Hegel, Routledge, 2005.
2. J.M. Dunn, “A truth value semantics for modal logic”, Studies in Logic
and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 68, 1973, pp. 87–100.
3. N.P. Eisnor, Hegelian and Syllogistic Logic Compared, Boston Univer-
sity Libraries, 1947, https://open.bu.edu/handle/2144/14797.
4. G.W.F. Hegel (1812–1816), The Science of Logic, Introduction and
translation by G. Di Giovanni, Cambridge University Press, 2010.
5. G.W.F. Hegel (1830), Hegel’s Logic: Part One of the Encyclopedia of
the Philosophical Sciences, translated by W. Wallace, Foreword by J.N.
Findlay, 3rd edition, Clarendon Press, 1975.
6. P. Redding, “The Role of Logic ‘Commonly So Called’ in Hegel’s Science
of Logic”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, vol. 22(2),
2014, pp. 281–301.
532
Sessions
Alsteed’s Encyclopedy
Ruxandra Irina Vulcan
University Paris-Sorbonne, France
[email protected]
533
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
And the arguments seem instances of the plural cousin of the standard,
singular form of Barbara:
Plural Barbara: Any things that are-P are-Q. Any things that are-Q
are-R. ∴ Any things that are-P are-R.
One can get (2) from (1) by replacing ‘are one horse’ with ‘are two
horses’. While (1) is a valid argument, however, (2) is not. Although its
premisses are true, its conclusion is false — two horses have eight feet (with
four each), not four.
Some scholars of Chinese philosophy (e.g., [1] suggest that argument
(2) shows that Plural Barbara (or its Chinese counterpart) is not a valid
form. Like Barbara, however, Plural Barbara is a valid form. The paper
argues that (2) is not a genuine instance of the form because it involves
equivocal uses of the predicate ‘have four feet’. This predicate has the
distributive/non-distributive ambiguity (and so does its Chinese counter-
part). This shows the importance of the distributive/non-distributive dis-
tinction in studies of logic and semantics of constructions that go beyond
the confines of singular constructions.
534
Sessions
References
1. A.C. Graham, Later Mohist Logic, Ethics, and Science, Chinese Uni-
versity Press, Hong Kong, 1978.
2. D. Mo, The Mozi: A Complete Translation, translated by I. Johnston,
Columbia University Press, 2010.
535
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. Acclavio, “A Constructive Proof of Coherence for Symmetric Mon-
oidal Categories Using Rewriting”, arXiv:1606.01722, Cornell Univer-
sity Library, 2016.
2. A. Burroni, “Higher-dimensional word problems with applications to
equational logic”, Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 115(1), 1993,
pp. 43–62.
3. Y. Guiraud & Ph. Malbos, “Coherence in monoidal track categories”,
Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, vol. 22(6), 2012,
pp. 931–969.
*
Laboratoire d’Informatique de l’École Polytechnique
Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et en Automatique
536
Sessions
Ramon Jansana
University of Barcelona, Spain
[email protected]
In this work we introduce the notion of filter pair as a tool for creat-
ing and analyzing logics. A filter pair over a signature Σ is a structured
collection of lattice homomorphisms LA → ℘(A), where A runs over all Σ-
structures, LA is some algebraic lattice and ℘(−) the power set. Taking A
to be the formula algebra, the image of this homomorphism can then be
taken as the lattice of theories of a logic. Thus a filter pair can be seen as
a presentation of a logic, different from the usual style of presentation by
axioms and derivation rules.
The case of interest for this work is LA = CoK (A), the lattice of congru-
ences whose quotient lies in some quasivariety K.
537
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
One can show that the class of logics arising in this way is the class of
logics having an algebraic semantics in the technical sense of [2], a huge
class containing all algebraizable logics, but also logics that are neither
protoalgebraic nor truth-equational.
538
Sessions
framework for dealing with several logics of formal inconsistency (or LFIs)
which cannot be semantically characterized by a single finite matrix. In par-
ticular, these LFIs are not algebraizable by the standard tools of abstract
algebraic logic. The swap structure semantics generalize the characteriza-
tion results of LFIs by means of finite Nmatrices due to Avron [see, e.g., 1].
Moreover, this semantics allows soundness and completeness theorems by
means of a very natural generalization of the well-known Lindenbaum-Tarski
process.
In this talk some advances towards a theory of non-deterministic al-
gebraization of logics by swap structures will be described, following the
results recently obtained in [4]. It will be developed a formal study of swap
structures for LFIs, by adapting concepts of universal algebra to multial-
gebras in a suitable way. A decomposition theorem similar to Birkhoff’s
representation theorem will be described for each class of swap structures.
It will be shown that, when applied to the 3-valued algebraizable logic J3,
the usual class of algebraic models is recovered by means of this technique,
and so the swap structures semantics became twist-structures semantics (as
introduced by Fidel [6] and Vakarelov [7]). The twist-structures semantics
produces semisimple Nelson algebras, which are polynomially equivalent to
the variety of MV-algebras of order 3 [see 5]. From this, our representation
theorem coincides with the original Birkhoff’s representation theorem in the
case of the algebraizable 3-valued logic J3. This fact, together with the ex-
istence of a functor from the category of Boolean algebras to the category
of swap structures for each LFI, which is closely connected with Kalman’s
functor, strongly suggests that swap structures can be considered as non-
deterministic twist structures.
References
1. A. Avron, “Non-deterministic matrices and modular semantics of rules”,
in Logica Universalis, edited by J.-Y. Béziau, Birkhäuser, 2005,
pp. 155–173.
2. W.A. Carnielli, M.E. Coniglio & J. Marcos, “Logics of Formal Incon-
sistency”, in Handbook of Philosophical Logic, edited by D.M. Gabbay
& F. Guenthner, vol. 14, 2nd edition, Springer, 2007, pp. 1–93.
3. W.A. Carnielli & M.E. Coniglio, Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency,
Contradiction and Negation, volume 40 of Logic, Epistemology, and the
Unity of Science, Springer, 2016.
4. M.E. Coniglio, A. Figallo-Orellano & A.C. Golzio, “Non-deterministic
algebraization of logics by swap structures”, arXiv:1708.08499, Cornell
University Library, 2017.
539
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. Aristotle, Catégories, Éditions du Seuil, Paris, 2002.
2. E. Benveniste, “Catégories de pensée et catégories de langue”, in Pro-
blèmes de Linguistique Générale, by E. Benveniste, vol. 1, Gallimard,
1966, pp. 63–74.
3. O. Caramello & L. Lafforgue, Sur la dualité des topos et de leurs pré-
sentations et applications: une introduction, Institut des Hautes Études
Scientifiques, IHES/M/16/26, 2016.
4. J.-P. Desclés, G. Guibert & B. Sauzay, Calculs de signification par une
logique d’opérateurs, Cépaduès, 2016.
541
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
or modalities. What we can then observe is that most of these logical oper-
ators come through dual pairs (conjunction ∧ and disjunction ∨, quantifiers
∀ and ∃, modalities 2 and 3).
When looking at the algebraic properties of mathematical morphology
[4] on the one hand, and of all these dual operators on the other hand,
several similarities can be shown, and suggest that links between institu-
tions and mathematical morphology are worth to be investigated. This has
already been done in the restricted framework of modal propositional logic
[3]. It was shown that modalities 2 and 3 can be defined as morphological
erosion and dilation. The interest is, based on properties of morphological
operators, that this leads to a set of axioms and inference rules which are
de facto sound. In this communication, we propose to extend this work by
defining, at the abstract level of institutions, a pair of abstract operators
as morphological erosion and dilation. We will then show how to obtain
standard quantifiers and modalities from these two abstract operators.
In mathematical morphology, erosion and dilation are operations that
work on lattices, for instance on sets. Thus, they can be applied to formulas
by identifying formulas with sets. We have two ways of doing this, either
given a model M identifying a formula ϕ by the set of states η that satisfy ϕ
and classically noted M η ϕ, or identifying ϕ by the set of models that sat-
isfy it. As usual in logic, our abstract dual operators based on morphological
erosion and dilation will be studied both on sets of states and sets of models.
The problem is that institutions do not explicit, given a model M , its set of
states. This is why we will define our abstract logical dual operators based
on erosion and dilation in an extension of institutions, the stratified institu-
tions [1]. Stratified institutions have been defined in [1] as an extension of
institutions to take into account the notion of open sentences, the satisfac-
tion of which is parameterized by sets of states. For instance, in first-order
logic, the satisfaction is parameterized by the valuation of unbound vari-
ables, while in modal logics it is further parameterized by possible worlds.
Hence, stratified institutions allow for a uniform treatment of such param-
eterizations of the satisfaction relation within the abstract setting of logics
as institutions.
Another interest of the proposed approach is that mathematical mor-
phology provides tools for spatial reasoning. Inspired by the work that was
done in [3, 5] in the propositional and modal logic framework, we show how
logical connectives based on morphological operators can be used for sym-
bolic representations of spatial relations. Indeed, spatial relations are a main
component of spatial reasoning, and several frameworks have been proposed
to model spatial relations and reason about them in logical frameworks.
542
Sessions
References
1. M. Aiguier & R. Diaconescu, “Stratified institutions and elementary ho-
momorphisms”, Information Processing Letters, vol. 103(5–13), 2007.
2. J. Barwise, “Axioms for abstract model theory”, Annnals of Mathemat-
ical Logic, vol. 7, 1974, pp. 221–265.
3. I. Bloch, “Modal Logics on Mathematical Morphology for Qualitative
Spatial Reasoning”, Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics,
vol. 12(3–4), 2002, pp. 399–423.
4. I. Bloch, H. Heijmans & C. Ronse, “Mathematical Morphology”, in
Handbook of Spatial Logics, Springer, 2007, pp. 857–947.
5. I. Bloch & J. Lang, “Towards mathematical morpho-logics”, in Tech-
nologies for Constructing Intelligent Systems, edited by B. Bouchon-
Meunier, J. Gutierrez-Rios, L. Magdalena & R. Yager, Springer, 2002,
pp. 367–380.
6. R. Diaconescu, Institution-independent Model Theory, Birkhäuser, 2008.
7. R. Diaconescu, “Institutional semantics for many-valued logics”, Fuzzy
Sets and Systems, vol. 218, 2013, pp. 32–52.
8. J.A. Goguen and R.-M. Burstall, “Institutions: Abstract model theory
for specification and programming”, Journal of the ACM * , vol. 39(1),
1992, pp. 95–146.
References
1. M. Giry, “A categorical approach to probability theory”, in Categorical
aspects of topology and analysis, Proceedings of an International Confer-
ence held at Carleton University, Ottawa, 1981, edited
by B. Banaschewski, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 915, 1982,
pp. 68–85.
2. A. Jøsang, “Artificial reasoning with subjective logic”, in Proceedings
of the Second Australian Workshop on Commonsense Reasoning, Perth,
Australia, 1997, http://folk.uio.no/josang/papers/Jos1997-AWCR.pdf.
3. A. Jøsang, “Generalising Bayes’ Theorem in Subjective Logic”, in
IEEE * International Conference on Multisensor Fusion and Integration
for Intelligent Systems, Baden-Baden, Germany, 2016, doi:10.1109/MFI.
2016.7849531.
*
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers
544
Sessions
Hahn’s structure theorem [2] states that totally ordered Abelian groups
can be embedded in the lexicographic product of real groups. Residuated
lattices are semigroups only, and are algebraic counterparts of substruc-
tural logics [1]. Involutive commutative residuated chains (a.k.a. involutive
FLe-chains) form an algebraic counterpart of the logic IUL [3]. The focus
of our investigation is a subclass of them, called commutative group-like
residuated chains, that is, totally ordered, involutive commutative residu-
ated lattices such that the unit of the monoidal operation coincides with
the constant that defines the involution. These algebras are algebraic coun-
terparts of IUL plus t ⇔ f. We shall present a representation theorem for
the finitely generated algebras of this class, by using only totally ordered
Abelian groups as building blocks, and a here-defined construction, called
partial-lexicographic product. As a corollary, we shall extend Hahn’s em-
bedding theorem to this class, using partial-lexicographic products instead
of lexicographic ones. Its corollary is the finite strong standard complete-
ness of IUL plus t ⇔ f.
References
1. N. Galatos, P. Jipsen, T. Kowalski & H. Ono, Residuated Lattices:
An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics, Studies in Logic and the
Foundations of Mathematics book series, vol. 151, Elsevier, 2007.
2. H. Hahn, “Uber die nichtarchimedischen Größensysteme”, Sitzungsbe-
richte der Kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften, vol. 116, Mathe-
matisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Klasse, Vienna and Berlin, 1907,
pp. 601–655.
3. G. Metcalfe & F. Montagna, “Substructural Fuzzy Logics”, The Journal
of Symbolic Logic, vol. 72(3), 2007, pp. 834–864.
*
This work was supported by the GINOP 2.3.2-15-2016-00022 grant.
GINOP stands for Economic Development and Innovation Operative Programme.
545
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Manuela Busaniche
CONICET, Institute of Applied Mathematics of the Coast,
National University of the Littoral, Santa Fe, Argentina
[email protected]
546
Sessions
References
1. S. Aguzzoli & S. Bova, “The free n-generated BL-algebra”, Annals of
Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 161(9), 2010, pp. 1144–1170.
2. S. Bova, “ BL-functions and Free BL-algebra”, PhD thesis, Department
of Mathematics and Computer Science, University of Siena, Italy, 2008,
https://goo.gl/RCyfCU.
3. M. Busaniche & D. Mundici, “Geometry of Robinson consistency in
Lukasiewicz logic”, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 147(1–2),
2007, pp. 1–22.
4. P. Hájek, Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic, Springer, 1998.
and
547
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
define two kinds of modal frame algebras, the Boolean algebra B(F) of the
subsets of W , equipped with operation
2X ∶= {x ∈ W ∣ ∀y (xRy Ô⇒ y ∈ X)},
and the Heyting algebra H(F) of all SR -upward closed subsets of W , where
SR ∶= R ∪ {(x, x) ∣ x ∈ W },
also equipped with the same 2X. It has been shown [1] that B(F) val-
idates K4.Grz iff F is a K4.Grz-frame. It is easy to check that for any
transitive frame F, H(F) validates mHC. Given L ∈ NEK4.Grz, L is called
Boolean complete if L = LB(F). Given L ∈ NEmHC, L is called Heyting
complete if L = LH(F). Following [2], given L ∈ NEK4.Grz, we denote by
FcL = (WLc , RLc
) the “classical” canonical frame for L; and, following [3],
given L ∈ NEmHC, we denote by FiL = (WLi , RL i
) the “intuitionistic” canon-
i
ical frame for L. It is easy to see that RmHC is transitive.
We claim:
(I) τ does not preserve canonicity, since mHC is canonical, but K4.Grz is
not [1];
(II) for any L ∈ NEK4.Grz, L is Boolean complete iff ρ(L) is Heyting
complete with respect to a K4.Grz-frame;
(III) the logic mHC + (2p1 → p1 ) → p1 + ¬¬p1 → p1 is a canonical normal
extension of K4.Grz;
(IV) for any L ∈ NEK4.Grz, if L is canonical, so is ρ(L);
(V) for any L ∈ NEK4.Grz, L admits the rule 2α/α iff so does ρ(L);
(VI) K4.Grz admits the rule 2α/α and hence mHC does it too.
References
1. M. Amerbauer, “Cut-free tableau calculi for some propositional normal
modal logics”, Studia Logica, vol. 57(2–3), 1996, pp. 359–372.
2. P. Blackburn, M. de Rijke & Y. Venema, Modal Logic, Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, Cambridge, 2001.
3. M. Božić & K. Došen, “Models for normal intuitionistic modal logics”,
Studia Logica, vol. 43(3), 1984, pp. 217–245.
4. L. Esakia, “The modalized Heyting calculus: a conservative modal ex-
tension of the intuitionistic logic”, Journal of Applied Non-Classical
Logics, vol. 16(3–4), 2006, pp. 349–366.
5. A. Muravitsky, “Interconnection of the Lattices of Extensions of Four
Logics”, Logica Universalis, vol. 11(2), 2017, pp. 253–281.
548
Sessions
References
1. P.T. Johnstone, “Sketches of an Elephant: A Topos Theory Compen-
dium”, two volumes, Clarendon Press, 2002.
2. E. Ochs & P. Arndt, “Planar Heyting Algebras for Children, 3: Geomet-
ric Morphisms”, 2017, preprint available at http://angg.twu.net/math-
b.html#zhas-for-children-2.
549
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
The main objective of this study is to provide the basis for the elabora-
tion of a semantics for the Hilbert Spaces Category (Hilb), which requires,
in our view, the use of an algebra, necessary to interpret certain properties
of bifunctors and isomorphisms specific in (Hilb). Initially designed to deal
with certain problems characteristic of Quantum Computing, this category
later proved to be also effective in dealing with certain objects of Quantum
Mechanics. Thus, in addition to its notorious practical possibilities, this
same category possesses an enormous theoretical potential which, it seems
to us, deserves to be explored extensively, especially as this allows inte-
grating syntax, semantics and pragmatics of a category through which one
can easily and effectively transit both Mathematics and Physics, as well as
Logics. Preliminarily, we expose the syntax of (Hilb) based on the works of
Baez [1], Coecke [2] and Heunen [3]; then, we will make an interpretation of
certain properties of (Hilb) and at the end we will present a sketch of the
semantics that we are constructing for this category.
References
1. J.C. Baez, “Quantum Quandaries: a Category-Theoretic Perspective”,
arXiv:quant-ph/0404040, Cornell University Library, 2004.
2. B. Coecke, “Introducing categories to the practicing physicist”, arXiv:
0808.1032, Cornell University Library, 2008.
3. C. Heunen, “An embedding theorem for Hilbert categories”, Theory and
Applications of Categories, vol. 22(13), 2009, pp. 321–344.
550
Sessions
Philosophy of Mathematics
Universality and intersubjectivity of mathematical
constructions. Toward a dialogical reading
of Brouwer’s proof of the bar theorem
Clément Lion
STL* , CNRS , Charles de Gaulle University, Lille, France
[email protected]
551
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. M. van Atten, On Brouwer, Wadsworth Philosophers Series, Thom-
son/Wadsworth, 2004.
2. L.E.J. Brouwer, “Über Definitionsbereiche von Funktionen”, Mathema-
tische Annalen, vol. 97, 1927, pp. 60–75.
References
1. C.B. Boyer, The History of Calculus and Its Conceptual Development,
Dover Publications, 1959.
2. S. Dehaene, The Number Sense: How the Mind creates Mathematics,
Oxford University Press, New York, 1997.
3. E.R. Grosholz, Representation and Productive Ambiguity in Mathemat-
ics and Science, Oxford University Press, New York, 2007.
4. T. Nickles, “Discovery”, in A Companion to the Philosophy of Science,
edited by W.H. Newton-Smith, Blackwell Publishers, 2000, pp. 85–96.
Law controls our lives. We live under the rule of Law. We are everywhere
also subject to the laws of science. Law in one way or another affects every
facet of human life. We need therefore to understand better the way that
Law operates. Do we even know the nature of law? To understand it we
need to examine its roots. For they lie in logic. There is prima facie a
distinction between the scientific law and human civil and criminal laws in
that the former are always strictly obeyed whereas the latter may not be
observed. However delving deeper we find that scientific law is not always
universally obeyed. On the other hand it may come as a surprise to find
that there is a sense in that human law always does.
Law whether scientific or human operates from a higher level. Current
mainstream mathematics that derives from set theory cannot deal directly
with separate levels but only collapse them into a model of first order.
Alfred North Whitehead (1860–1947) who had established 20th Century
mathematics subsequently drew attention to the limitations of first order
models and advocated a move to Process at the higher level of metaphysics
[1]. Unfortunately Whitehead did not have a formal metaphysical language
to replace the flat mathematics of set theory.
Today Category Theory now fills that gap. It is a formal language that
operates across four levels recursively with features like adjointness between
universal limits and co-limits that were not appreciated until the 1970’s.
553
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
All Laws arise from this natural adjointness as underlying functors [2].
But there is the caveat that the current representation of Category The-
ory only holds up to the natural isomorphism of the axioms of set theory.
Applied Category Theory needs to hold up to the natural isomorphism of
Physics.
References
1. A.N. Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, Macmil-
lan Publishers, New York, 1929, corrected edition by D.R. Griffin &
D.W. Sherburne, Free Press, New York, 1978, https://monoskop.org/
File:Whitehead Alfred North Process and Reality corr ed 1978.pdf.
2. M. Heather & N. Rossiter, “Logical Monism: The Global Identity of Ap-
plicable Logic”, Philosophia Mathematica, vol. 14(2), 2006,
pp. 39–52.
Frege’s view that there cannot be a logic of discovery but only a logic
of justification is widely accepted. Even if there is no logic of discovery,
there still may be a dynamics of discovery, or at least systematic accounts
of ways that mathematical discoveries are made. As Lakatos [3] emphasised,
some account of discovery in mathematics is essential for understanding the
nature mathematical progress.
One (possibly) common aspect, to which philosophers nowadays pay
more attention, is the role of visual thinking in mathematical discovery.
Cellucci [1, chs. 20–21] gives rules of discovery. He illustrates use of non-
deductive rules by means of several diagrams and claims that diagrams
are “not only auxiliary means, they are also an important source of non-
deductive inferences on their own” [1, p. 357]. Indeed, mathematical senten-
tial non-visual thinking is normally used in conjunction with visual thinking.
The latter usually combines thinking with external visual representations
(e.g., diagrams, symbol arrays, kinematic computer images) and thinking
with internal visual imagery, and often involves imagining a certain spa-
tial transformation of an object represented by a diagram on paper or on
screen. Possible epistemic roles include contributions to evidence, proof,
understanding and grasp of concepts.
Though philosophical discussion of visual thinking in mathematics has
concentrated on its role in proof, visual thinking may be more valuable for
discovery than proof. Giaquinto [2] distinguishes three types of discovery
important in mathematical practice: (1) discovering a truth, (2) discovering
a proof-strategy, and (3) discovering a property or kind of mathematical
entity. He illustrates visual discovery of these kinds using examples and
555
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
infers that “It is hard to see how properties in these examples would have
been discovered without the use of visual resources” (ibid.). This claim
raises questions: images may be useful in mathematical discovery, but can
they play a crucial role? And if so, how? What properties make images
useful even in current mathematics (since some of his examples are relatively
recent and advanced)?
This talk is an attempt to go deeper into some of such examples focusing
on the third kind of discovery from Giaquinto’s list, with an aim to iden-
tify possible systematic elements of discovery involving visualisation. Are
there any repeated uses of visualisations in discovery? What are their key
components? Do they stabilise in visual practices? How do they influence
shaping the new concepts? These and related questions are to be discussed.
References
1. C. Cellucci, Rethinking Logic: Logic in Relation to Mathematics, Evo-
lution, and Method, Springer, 2013.
2. M. Giaquinto, “The Epistemology of Visual Thinking in Mathematics”,
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2016 Edition, edited
by E.N. Zalta, 2016, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/
epistemology-visual-thinking.
3. I. Lakatos, Proofs and Refutations, edited by J. Worrall & E. Zahar,
Cambridge University Press, 1976.
556
Sessions
The discussion has recently been given new impulses by the EIA (“en-
hanced indispensability argument”), where several cases from biology of
physics have been discussed, and the (possible) explanatory role of mathe-
matics has been the subject of analysis (the most famous examples are the:
periodical life-cycle of cicadas (and the fact, that they are prime numbers);
the honeycomb conjecture, the Borsuk-Ulam theorem — and many oth-
ers). These examples seem to be clearly non-causal, as mathematical facts
and properties are present in the explanans. The topic is much discussed,
and the problem, which constitutes the special character of mathematical
explanations in science, is acute.
The problem of explanation within mathematics, as well as the problem
of the explanatory role of mathematics has quite different aspects, but some
specific examples of the cases where the notion of explanation can be applied
are:
(a) the problem of explanatory role of mathematical proofs (in particular
the interplay between the real and formalized versions of mathematical
proofs);
(b) the problem of explanation in the context of justifying axioms.
(c) the problem of “local” versus “global” character of explanation within
mathematics (in particular the problem of extraneous elements in math-
ematical proofs; explaining one single mathematical fact versus provid-
ing a suitable conceptual framework for a particular branch of mathe-
matics);
(d) the problem of mathematical explanations in empirical science, espe-
cially in the context of the enhanced indispensability argument.
In the talk, I will focus on the last problem, and in particular present
some new examples inspired by the independence results (in arithmetic and
set theory). These results invite us to rethink the explanatory role of math-
ematics in natural science, as their status is quite different from the well-
known examples. I claim, that their analysis in the realism-antirealism
debate will give new, important insights (as the problem of the strength of
necessary “background resources” becomes more acute).
557
16 – Contest Logic Prizes
The jury will then give the Universal Logic Prize to the best of them. Be-
sides receiving this honorific prize, the winner will be an invited speaker at
the next UNILOG and will receive a purchase voucher of Birkhäuser/Sprin-
ger-Nature.
Jury Members:
Hartry Field
Department of Philosophy, New York University, USA
Michèle Friend
Department of Philosophy, Columbian College of Arts and Sciences,
George Washington University, USA
Grzegorz Malinowski
Department of Logic, University of Lódź, Poland
Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen
Tallinn University of Technology, Estonia
Nazarbayev University, Astana, Kazakhstan
Peter Schroeder-Heister
Department of Computer Science, University of Tübingen, Germany
Göran Sundholm
Department of Philosophy, University of Leiden, The Netherlands
559
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
560
Contest Logic Prizes
562
Contest Logic Prizes
563
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
565
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
Reference
1. S. French & D. Krause, Identity in Physics: A Historical, Philosophical
and Formal Analysis, Oxford University Press, 2006.
567
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
One of the main results of [3] states that the algebraic counterpart of
PWK is the class of Plonka sum of Boolean algebras. This observation
led us to investigate the relations between left and right variable inclusion
companions and Plonka sums in full generality. Our study is carried on in
the conceptual framework of abstract algebraic logic [5].
The starting point consists in generalizing the construction of Plonka
sums from algebras to logical matrices. This allows us to characterize the
matrix models for variable inclusion logics by performing appropriate Plonka
sums over direct systems of models of . As a matter of fact, variable
inclusion companions are especially well-behaved in case the original logic
has a specific kind of partition function [7,8], a feature shared by the vast
majority of non-pathological logics in the literature.
The use of the mentioned algebraic tools allow, on the one hand, to
produce a general method to transform every Hilbert-style calculus for a
finitary logic with a partition function into complete Hilbert-style calculi
l r
for both and . On the other hand, partition functions can be exploited
l r
to tame the structure of the matrix semantics ModSu ( ) and ModSu ( ),
l r
given by the so-called Suszko reduced models of and . As a byproduct
of our analysis, this formalism allows to provide topological dualities for the
algebraic counterpart of variable inclusion logics [4,2].
References
1. D. Bochvar, “On a three-valued calculus and its application in the analy-
sis of the paradoxes of the extended functional calculus”,
Mathematicheskii Sbornik, vol. 46, 1938, pp. 287–308.
2. S. Bonzio, “Duality for Plonka sums”, Logica Universalis, forthcoming.
3. S. Bonzio, J. Gil-Férez, F. Paoli & L. Peruzzi, “On Paraconsistent Weak
Kleene Logic: axiomatization and algebraic analysis”, Studia Logica,
vol. 105(2), 2017, pp. 253–297.
4. S. Bonzio, A. Loi & L. Peruzzi, “A duality for involutive bisemilattices”,
Studia Logica, 2018, doi:10.1007/s11225-018-9801-0.
5. J. Font, Abstract Algebraic Logic: An Introductory Textbook, College
Publications, 2016.
6. S. Halldén, The Logic of Nonsense, Lundequista Bokhandeln, Uppsala,
Sweden, 1949.
7. J. Plonka, “On a method of construction of abstract algebras”,
Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 61(2), 1967, pp. 183–189.
8. A. Romanowska & J. Smith, Modes, World Scientific, 2002.
568
Contest Logic Prizes
*
2018 Winner of Alfred Tarski Logic Prize, in Poland (page 564).
569
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. W. Brown, Z. Gyenis & M. Rédei, “The modal logic of Bayesian belief
revision”, submitted for publication, 2017.
2. Z. Gyenis, “On the modal logic of Jeffrey conditionalization”, accepted
for publication, 2018.
3. Z. Gyenis, “Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable”, submit-
ted for publication, 2018.
4. Z. Gyenis & M. Rédei, “General properties of Bayesian learning as a sta-
tistical inference determined by conditional expectations”, The Review
of Symbolic Logic, vol. 10(4), 2017, pp. 719–755.
570
Contest Logic Prizes
ways to add features so as to make them useful, while retaining their in-
tuitive appeal. At the end, we show some surprising results in the system
FDE [2,3], and its relationships with features of other logics. We close with
some new examples of “synonymous logics” [4]. An Appendix contains a
natural deduction system for our augmented FDE, and proofs of soundness
and completeness.
References
1. A. Avron, “Natural 3-valued logics: Characterization and proof theory”,
The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 56(1), 1991, pp. 276–294.
2. N.D. Belnap, Jr., “A useful four-valued logic: How a computer should
think”, in Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Volume II,
by A.R. Anderson, N.D. Belnap, Jr. & J.M. Dunn, Princeton University
Press, 1992, pp. 506–541, originally appeared as “A useful four-valued
logic”, in Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic, edited by J.M. Dunn
& G. Epstein, D. Reidel, 1977, pp. 3–37, also appeared before as “How a
computer should think”, in Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy, edited
by G. Ryle, Oriel Press, 1977, pp. 30–56.
3. J.M. Dunn, “Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and ’cou-
pled trees’ ”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 29(3), 1976, pp. 149–168.
4. F.J. Pelletier & A. Urquhart, “Synonymous Logics”, Journal of Philo-
sophical Logic, 32(3), 2003, pp. 259–285. [see also 5]
5. F.J. Pelletier & A. Urquhart, “Synonymous Logics: A Correction”,
Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 37(1), 2008, pp. 95–100.
6. G. Priest, In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, 2nd edi-
tion, Oxford University Press, 2006.
7. N. Rescher, Many-Valued Logic, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1969.
573
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
References
1. D. Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds, Blackwell, Oxford, 1986.
2. G. Priest, Towards Non-Being: The Logic and Metaphysics of Inten-
tionality, Oxford University Press, 2016.
3. W.V.O. Quine, “On What There Is”, The Review of Metaphysics, vol. 2(5),
1948, pp. 21–38.
*
2018 Winner of Bimal Krishna Matilal Logic Prize, in India (page 563).
574
Contest Logic Prizes
References
1. F. Baader, D. Calvanese, D. McGuinness, D. Nardi & P. Patel-Schneider
(editors), The Description Logic Handbook: Theory, Implementation
and Applications, Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition, 2007.
*
2018 Winner of Louis Couturat Logic Prize, in France (page 565), and of Universal Logic
Prize (page 559).
Centre de Recherche en Informatique de Lens
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
575
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
576
Part IV
Publishers, Sponsors
and Partners
577
17 – Book Exhibition
During the event there will be a book exhibition with the following
publishers:
Birkhäuser
College Publications
Peter Lang
World Scientific
579
18 – Sponsors and Partners
581
Index of Authors
583
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
584
Index of Authors
585
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
586
Index of Authors
587
Handbook of the 6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic
588
Index of Authors
589