Lexical Matters
Lexical Matters
Lexical Matters
M^TTPS
Lb!
Lecture Notes
No. 24
LEXCAL
MATTERS
COICO O_
Vd ^. SagdO ^nnaSaboIcsI
CSLI
LLJLh LhJLDJL1Y
L LFLLFLL
F11LhNF11L
Copyright 1992
Center for the Study of Language and Information
Leland Stanford Junior University
Printed in the United States
L data and other information appear at the end of the book
Contents
Introduction vii
Contributors xix
1 The Aspectual Interface Hypothesis l
CAROL TENNY
2 Thematic Relations as Links between Nominal Reference
and Temporal Constitution 29
MANFRED KRIFKA
3 Complex Predicates and Morpholexical Relatedness:
Locative Alternation in Hungarian 55
FARRELL ACKERMAN
4 On Obviation 85
DONKA F. FARKAS
5 Blocking of Phrasal Constructions by Lexical
Items 111
WILLIAM J. POSER
6 The Stress and Structure of Modifed Noun Phrases in
English 131
MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
7 Hungarian Derivational Morphology, Semantic
Complexity, and Semantic Markedness 183
FERENC KIEFER
8 Focus-Based Inferences in Sentence
Comprehension 209
GYORGY GERGELY
9 Combinatory Grammar and Projection from the
Lexicon 241
ANNA SZABOLCSI
vi / CONTENTS
10 The Lexical Entailment Theory of Control and the
Tough-Construction 269
PAULINE JACOBSON
1 1 A Lexical Analysis of Icelandic Case 301
IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
Author Index 319
Subject Index 323
Introduction
What is a lexical entry? What information does it include? How are
lexicons organized? In the early days of generative grammar, such questions
were given relatively simple answers. A lexicon was a list of entries, each of
which specifed a phonological shape, some representation of its meaning, a
grammatical category, and a specifcation of exceptionality. The excitement
concerning the lexicon was minimal, precisely because the grammatical
action, so to speak, wa elsewhere: lexical entries provided just enough
information to satisf the needs of elaborate syntactic rules.
In the thirty years that have passed since this era, grammatical theories
have changed in profound ways, the most striking of which may well be the
enhanced role of the lexicon. There is now considerable agreement within
the feld that lexical representations are highly structued and play an
essential role in grammatical description, as many burdens once borne by
transformations and other devices are now carried by lexical representations
or lexical rules of one sort or another.
In spite of this fundamental agreement, no real conensus ha yet been
achieved concerning the content of lexical entries, the precise nature of lexi
cal representations, the scope of the lexicon and lexical analyses in general,
or the matter of how the lexicon should be structured. It is evident that
lexical matters such as these will be of central concern well into the next
century, not just within the field of linguistics, but also in the neighor
ing disciplines where the study of language has assumed an increaingly
important role.
The contributions to the present volume, which (with the exception of
Gergely's) fall squarely within linguistics proper, illustrate very well the ex
treme diversity of empirical problems in this domain, as well as the variety
of techniques currently employed to investigate lexical matters. Despite
their diversity, the papers cluster naturally around four central themes,
which we have selected a the organizing foci of the volume:
Lexical Matters. Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabolcsi, eds.
Copyright 1992, Stanford University.
viii I LEXICAL MATTERS
1. Argument Structure and the Nature of Thematic Roles
2. Blocking and the Boundaries of the Lexicon
3. The Nature of Lexical Meaning
4. Lexical Alternatives to Syntactic Analyses
1 Argument Structure and the Nature of Thematic Roles
Thematic roles have long been the standard devices for organizing lexi
cal argument structures. Substantial theories of thematic roles have been
baed on the assumption that each individual argument type can be given
a grammatical characterization that determines its syntactic behavior. But
evidence against this view has been mounting for some time now. It ha
been observed, for example, that it is difcult to extend the rigorous treat
ment of thematic roles beyond the core set of Agent, Patient, Experiencer,
Stimulus, etc. It is perhaps surprising that certain combinations of these
roles, for example, Agent and Patient, are typical, whereas others, like
Agent and Stimulus, are not attested at all. Thematic roles, moreover,
may be impossible to defne in semantic terms (a point already recognized
by the grammarians of ancient India and carefully documented by Dowty
(1991)) and many important generalizations are statable only with refer
ence to semantically coherent clases of predicates.
It i presumably due to this growing dissatisfaction with the standard
notion of thematic roles that Dowty's proposal to take a fesh look at
the issue was received with such enthusiasm. Among other things, Dowty
suggested to shift the focus to verb meanings and to recognize at most a
very limited set of proto-roles. The content of these roles is, to a great
extent, characterizable in cognitive, rather than purely grammatical terms.
For instance, the Patient proto-role is characterized by (a) undergoing a
change of state, (b) being an incremental theme, (c) being causally afected
by the event, (d) being stationary, and (e) having a referent whose existence
may depend on the action denoted by the verb.
C
AROL TENNY'S contribution ( "The Aspectual Interface Hypothesis" )
and that of
M
ANFRED
K
RIFKA ( "Thematic Relations as Links Between
Nominal Reference and Temporal Constitution" ) have a close relation.
They provide, in fact, an interesting example of how scholars belonging
to two quite diferent research traditions may achieve converging results
and insights.
It is well-known that the distinction between cumulative and quantized
reference in the domain of nominal interpretation (e. g. , apples vs. fve apples
parallels the contrast between telic and atelic interpretation in the verbal
domain (cf. run vs. run a mile and, furthermore, that the two interact in
grammar. Exactly when and how the properties of the nominal argument
afect those of the complex predicate is the subject of both Tenny's and
Krifa's contributions.
INTRODUCTION I ix
Using the background assumptions of the MIT Lexicon Project, Tenny
proposes the Aspectual Interface Hypothesis, according to which ( 1) the
mapping between thematic structure and syntactic structure is governed by
aspectual properties and (2) only the aspectual part of thematic structure
is visible to syntax. The crucial constraint she proposes is that the internal
argument of a simple verb is constrained so that it either undergoes no
change or motion, or it undergoes change or motion which measures out
the event over time.
The precise interpretation of "measuring out an event over time" may
be explicated, at least in a signifcant subset of the caes, in the terms of
fered by Krifa, whose work proceeds fom the same fundamental insight.
Krifa develops a semantic system baed on the particular lattice-theoretic
properties he assigns to three sorts of entities: objects, events, and times.
In his system he is able to give a precise interpretation to notions like cumu
lative, singular, quantized, and atomic reference. Defning telic predicates
a event predicates all of whose subevents have the same terminal point,
Krifa goes on to show that all quantized event predicates, and only these,
have the property of telicity. The crucial technique that Krifa then intro
duces to explicate the notion of "measuring out an event over time" is that
of a homomorphic mapping fom objects to events which preserves lattice
structure. Such a mapping exists in the case of drinking wine, for example,
but not in the case of drinking a glass of wine, and thus provides a precise
model-theoretic construction of the intuitive notion whose empirical utility
is argued for by Tenny.
On the grammatical side, Krifa's insights also parallel Tenny's, in that
he conceives of cumulativity, uniqueness of events, and graduality a prop
erties of thematic relations. He uses these properties to clasif the Pa
tient relations of diferent verbs and to distinguish them, for example,
fom Stimulus. The empirical scope of Tenny's informal proposal is sig
nifcantly broader than Krifa's, however. It extends to objects undergoing
change that does not afect the existence of their parts but rather, their
color or location (cf. redden and push (the cart) to New York). Krifa,
on the other hand, explores applications of his theory to such problems
a Finnish progressivity (marked by the partitive case of the argument)
and the interaction of perfectivity and the quantizedness of arguments in
Slavic.
Krif's and Tenny's contributions, both agreeing with Dowty's work
in their Davidsonian spirit and their attitude towards thematic roles, ad
dress the general question of why and how certain internal arguments
determine the apectual properties of the containing verb phrase.
F
AR
RELL
A
CKERMAN, directly infuenced by Dowty's work on roles, explores
a set of particularly challenging empirical problems in his paper "Com
plex Predicates and Morpholexical Relatedness: Locative Alternation in
Hungarian" .
} / LEXICAL MATTERS
Ackerman's study is couched in the famework of Lexical Mapping The
ory, developed by Bresnan and Kanerva ( 1989) and Bresnan and Zaenen
(1990) , inter alia, which seeks to explicate the relation between seman
tic (or thematic) roles and grammatical relations in terms of a mapping
fom the former to the latter that obeys certain principles. These prin
ciples make reference to a featural decomposition of grammatical rela
tions (subject is decomposed as [-objective] and [-restricted] ; objects are
all [+objective] and may be (semantically) restricted or not; and oblique
dependents are [-objective] and [+restricted] ) . Among the principles that
constrain the role-relation mapping in Lexical Mapping Theory are certain
intrinsic feature classifcations, for example, the classifcation of agents as
[-objective] (this prevents agents fom ever being realized a direct objects,
for example) .
Ackerman's examination of the systematic correlations between the
meanings and grammatical relations associated with various perfective
and resultative preverbs in Hungarian leads him to a number of conclu
sions. First, the intrinsic clasifcations (following Zaenen ( 1990)), should
be baed on Dowty's notion of Proto-Role properties. Second, a clear dis
tinction should be drawn between two kinds of operations: morpho lexical
(those which afect the lexical semantics of predicates) and morphosyntac
tic (those which don't) . The basic analysis of Hungarian preverbs, Acker
man argues, should all be in terms of morpholexical relatedness (expressed
within the word formation component of the grammar), for they involve not
only the Proto-Role properties, but also the very kinds of aspectual proper
ties, for example, telicity, explicated in the work of Tenny and Krifa. His
paper thus illustrates a new domain (in a third research paradigm) where
these basic semantic properties are able to contribute to the explanation
of why lexical argument structures are the way they are.
2 Blocking and the Boundaries of the Lexicon
Though syntactic and semantic rules are in general asumed to be inde
pendent in their application, there are a variety of cases that indicate that
certain grammatical rules must "know about each other." The most strik
ing of these is the phenomenon of blocking, whereby the availability of a
better-suited form renders a less specifc one ungrammatical. In general,
these are all cases which can be conceptualized as instances of the Else
where Principle (an insight also due originally to the grammarian of an
cient India), which states in essence that the existence of particular rules or
exception blocks the application of more general rules. Although standard
examples of this principle seem purely morpho lexical in nature (e. g. , the
existence of went blocks the application of the regular past tense sufxation
rule (*goed)), various researchers (Householder, McCawley, Horn, Dowty,
Levinson) have studied similar efects in other domains, relating blocking
INTRODUCTION / xi
phenomena, for example, to independently motivated aspects of Gricean
pragmatic theory. This raises the important theoretical issue of clarifying
the nature of the domains in which the Elsewhere Condition applies.
D
ONKA
F
ARKAS, in her contribution "On Obviation," examines classic
examples of obviation, including the impossibility of coreference between
matrix subject and pronoun in French examples like Pierre veut qu'il parte
'Pierre wants that he leave' . Accounts of this efect have been ofered in
terms of Chomsky's "avoid pronoun" principle or else Binding Theory. In
the latter cae, the domain in which the embedded subject is not to be
bound is extended to include the matrix clause. Farkas argues, however,
on the bais of data fom Western Romance-as well as new data from
Romanian, Hungarian, and Serbo-Croatian, that these approaches to ob
viation are unsatisfactory. The alternative she proposes is based on the
notion of blocking, thereby tying this phenomenon to her earlier results
concerning subjunctives and control.
According to Farkas' proposal, the coreferential reading in the relevant
caes is blocked by the availability of a rival infnitival form in the lan
guage. This immediately explains why Romanian has no obviation: it
minimally difers fom Western Romance in lacking rival infnitives com
pletely. A wealth of further, often subtle contrasts are shown to follow fom
this blocking analysis. For example, coreference of the sort just illustrated
is blocked precisely when the infnitive and the subjunctive complement
clause both conform to the canonical case of control, that is, cases in which
both the matrix and the complement subject bear a responsibility relation
to the situation denoted by the complement. Farkas argues that such fne
distinctions in verb meanings are in general refected in degrees of obvia
tion, a point she attempts to justif on cross-linguistic grounds.
The mechanism underlying Farkas' analysis, despite its larger efect on
coreference relations, is lexical blocking of the familiar sort. Such an anal
ysis is possible precisely because the "competition" in question is between
two lexical forms, each subcategorizing for a distinct type of complement.
Yet whether or not blocking must be a purely lexical matter is precisely
the point taken up in
W
ILLIAM
P
OSER
'
S paper "Blocking of Phrasal Con
structions by Lexical Items."
Poser points out three unusual cases where lexical forms block phrasal
constructions. The frst is that of Japanese "incorporated" periphrastic
verbs formed with suru ' do' . There is phonological and syntactic evidence
that, contrary to the usual assumption, these are phrasal. The fact that
these periphrastics cannot be formed directly fom deverbal nouns is ar
gued to be a blocking efect, due to the existence of the corresponding lex
ical verb. The second case is English comparatives and superlatives. The
phrasal status of the more and most forms is clear, yet they are blocked
by the availability of the lexical forms with -er and -est. Third, synthetic
expression of tense in Basque blocks periphrastic expression with the defec-
xii / LEXICAL MATTERS
tive verb ari. The dilemma that these data indicate is this: either blocking
is not just lexical, or the lexicon needs to be "extended" to encompas the
sorts of phraal construction discussed.
The frst possibility is the pragmatic approach used, for example, by
Householder ( 1971), to explain why the existence of the simpler pink blocks
more complex pale red. This explanation does not extend to morphology,
for a number of reasons: ( 1 ) oxen, for example, is not simpler than oxes; (2)
the blocking efect in morphology is much stronger than the unacceptability
of pale red; (3) blocking requires that the two forms be morphologically
related; pure semantic relatedness is not enough.
The second possibility is to "extend the lexicon." Poser proposes that
a morphological category is one that is potentially instantiated by a word
formation rule. Phrasal constructs involving XO categories are allowed to
instantiate morphological categories. A periphrastic construction is, then,
a in grammatical tradition, one in which morphological categories that are
typically instantiated lexically are instead instantiated at a phraal level.
This, in turn, allows one to say that if instantiation by a lexical verb is
available, phrasal instantiation is blocked.
Poser's notion of phraal constructs involving XO categories may seem
unfamiliar to readers steeped in the tradition of modern syntactic theory,
yet
M
ARK
L
IBERMAN and
R
ICHARD
S
PROAT appeal to just such a notion
in their contribution to the present volume, "The Stress and Structure of
Modifed Noun Phraes in English. "
In standard treatments of English modifed phraes, the combination of
adjective and noun is presumed to be the result of a syntactic rule (build
ing Nl structures) , wherea the combination of noun and noun is taken to
be lexical (NO) in nature. And correlating with this diference in mode of
combination, is assumed to be a diference in prosody: in adjective-noun
collocations, the noun i stressed, in accordance with the Nuclear Stress
Rule; in noun-noun combinations the frst noun is stressed, in accordance
with the Compound Stress Rule. Standard examples of this contrat in
clude detective novel versus defective novel, bank check versus blank check,
and so forth.
On the basis of a detailed examination of a large variety of modifed
phraes, Liberman and Sproat challenge this standard wisdom. For ex
ample, sof spot and wad man are adjective-noun combinations with com
pound stress, and steel plate and rice pudding are noun-noun combinations
with nuclear stress. These facts, a the authors show at length, cannot be
explained by appeal to discourse factors (diferences in inherent contrat)
or a distinction between "fxed" expressions and others (e.g., hard liquor
and blue moon are lexicalized adjective-noun combinations bearing nuclear
stress) . Accent, on Liberman and Sproat's view, is only partly predictable
on grounds of category or meaning.
These observations lead in turn to the view that all combinations of
INTRODUCTION I xiii
modifer-noun in English are in principle ambiguous between NO and N1
structures-a surprising conclusion that raises new questions, only some
of which Liberman and Sproat address in detail, about the exact relation
among such notions as being lexicalized, being an NO expression, and being
a fxed expression (Le. , having a special meaning).
3 The Nature of Lexical Meaning
The analysis of fxed expressions and the treatment of argument structure
B,re of course only two of the many issues that arise in the area of lexical
semantics. Two other notions that have been asumed to play an important
role in the organization of the lexicon, in predicting acquisition order, and
also with respect to predicting blocking efects of the sort we have already
discussed, are semantic complexity and semantic markedness. Complexity
may be thought of simply a the amount of semantic material contained in
a lexical item, for example, sell is more complex than give. Markedness, on
the other hand, has to do with how restricted a term is in its utility-baic
level terms like pine are held to be less restricted, thus more natural and
less marked, than either more specifc or less specifc terms in the same
semantic domain.
Since complexity is usually considered with respect to verbs, and basic
level predictions (markedness) with respect to category names, the relation
between these two notions i seldom examined. In his paper "Hungarian
Derivational Morphology, Semantic Complexity, and Semantic Marked
ness," FERENC KIEFER investigates precisely this problem. Kiefer seeks to
develop an appropriate notion of markedness for verbs and, with that in
hand, to examine the interesting circumstance that arises when complexity
and markedness make conficting predictions.
The semantic feld he investigates is defned by the rules of Hungarian
derivational morphology, involving the formation of causative, pasive, fe
quentative and perfective verb forms (with or without idiosyncratic mean
ings) . Morphological, syntactic and semantic complexity are carefully dis
tinguished fom the corresponding kinds of markedness, and the relation
ship of semantic complexity to syntactic and morphological complexity is
examined. What Kiefer fnds is that, with an increase of semantic com
plexity, neither morphological nor syntactic complexity decreases. Fur
thermore, the semantic complexity relations among derivationally related
lexical items which are semantically opaque are the same as those between
transparent lexical items.
Kiefer then shows that semantic markedness may conict with com
plexity considerations. For instance, verbs with a perfective prefx are less
marked than the corresponding iterative/generic verbs, despite the fact
that they are semantically more complex. And, similarly, verbs with a
directional prefx are less marked than corresponding generic/directionless
xiv / LEXICAL MATTERS
verbs. In this way, Kiefer argues, the facts of acquisition can be explained:
acquisition order is determined by markedness, rather than by complexity
(though, if no special markedness relations obtain, semantic markedness
may be equated with semantic complexity) .
Kiefer's study thus brings rather subtle and indirect evidence t o bear
on questions having to do with the psychological reality of lexical informa
tion. The methodology of GYORGY GERGELY, by contrast, is more direct.
In his contribution, "Focus-based Inferences in Sentence Comprehension,"
Gergely is concerned with verifing experimentally the claim that massive
incremental integration of diverse types of information takes place rapidly
in real-time language processing.
Recent work in sentence comprehension has established that listeners
use a variety of cues interactively in the construction of discourse interpre
tational structures, even before the full syntactic and semantic processing of
the sentence is complete. Working within this research paradigm, Gergely
investigates the precise on-line efects of some specifc cues that have pre
viously only been examined indirectly, using of-line measures. These are:
( 1 ) topic-focus (TF) structure, (2) inter-clausal semantic relations, and (3)
script-based knowledge.
The initial though in sentences like Though Daddy praised his daughter,
she was still not happy invites script-based inferences concerning cause
efect relations, one of which will be denied in the second clause. Experi
ments with English speakers have indicated that the pertinent cause-efect
relation can only be identifed in retrospect, during the processing of the
second clause. Gergely's paper is based on experiments with Hungarian
speakers, due in large part to the fact that in Hungarian, the TF structure
is marked unambiguously by word order and intonation. Gergely hypothe
sized that listeners can rely on the TF structure of the initial though clause
to restrict the set of expectable consequences to those that arise fom the
focused part of the clause. For example, the example just cited is felicitous
when the verb praised, rather than, for instance, the object his daughter,
is focused. The reason for this is that praising Iuight be expected to cause
happiness.
Gergely's results support this hypothesis. First, naming times for a
word probe, whose meaning is in adversative relation to the focus-based
consequence of the initial though clause, were signifcantly decreased, even
when the probe appeared before the end of the clause. This indicates that
before the main clause is processed, subjects have generated predictive
inferences about its adversative content. The selective nature of facilita
tion demonstrates that subjects inferred only those consequences that were
based on the focused part of the clause. Such facilitation was not present
when the initial clause contained no connective with comparable seman
tics, suggesting that when focus-based inferences cannot serve a predictive
function, they are discarded fom working memory at the end of the clause.
INTRODUCTION / xv
Gergely's experiments thus provide key insight into the semantic nature
of certain kinds of connectives, as well a the highly integrative nature of
language processing in general. In addition, his experiments showed that
focus-based inferences directly access pragmatic knowledge structures such
a scripts, thus raising the question of whether the probe facilitation here
is a further case of lexical priming. In contrast to the automatic and short
lived nature of lexical priming, however, the selective nature of the observed
priming efects and their survival even over a clause boundary indicate, as
Gergely shows, that they are more like the robust higher-order facilitation
of script-asociated words.
4 Lexical Alternatives to Syntactic Analyses
As we noted at the outset, a striking trend in contemporary syntactic the
ory is the lexical analysis of phenomena previously treated in terms of
transformational rules or other syntactic devices. With this trend comes,
quite naturally, an uncertainty as to which linguistic phenomena should in
fact receive lexical treatment. Several of the papers in this volume propose
lexically baed solutions to problems that have ofen been assumed to be
within the scope of syntactic movement theory, binding theory, control the
ory or case theory. The reason, they argue, is that the standard accounts
are descriptively inadequate and/or have theoretically undesirable proper
ties. We have already seen an argument of this type in Farka's lexical
analysis of obviation.
ANNA
S
ZABOLCSI, in her contribution "Combinatory Grammar and
Projection fom the Lexicon," explores the possibility of articulating a
sumptions about the lexicon in such a way that they derive a set of gen
eralizations that are traditionally conceived of a purely syntactic. For
example, Szabo1csi proposes to eliminate the need for principles pertain
ing to empty categories and binding by exploring the consequences of the
central asumption of categorial grammar, namely, that lexical items with
subcategorization fames are to be looked upon a functions.
Her paper frst demonstrates the explanatory value of the concept of
lexical items as functions, by providing a detailed comparison of the treat
ments of unbounded dependencies in Government-Binding Theory (G B) ,
Head-driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), and Combinatory Cat
egorial Grammar (CCG) . Taking this concept fully seriously, CCG goes
beyond fnctional application and introduces a set of functional opera
tions, that is, combinators, into the grammar. In this way it can dispense
with bound variables corresponding to gaps, and turn the empirical gener
alizations that GB and HPSG express in terms of constructs like the Empty
Category Principle, the Subcategorization Principle, the Nonlocal Feature
Principle, etc. , into constructive procedures.
The main part of Szabo1csi's paper is devoted to issues that tradition-
xvi / LEXICAL MATTERS
ally belong to Binding Theory. These matters pose a special problem for a
grammar baed on combinatory logic since this logic does not merely allow
one to dispense with bound variables, it has no variable binding machinery
at all. Szabolcsi argues that this restriction is in fact a virtue of CCG,
in that it forces the correct efects to be derived directly fom the lexical
meanings of anaphors and bound pronouns (crucially involving the dupli
cator combinator), without invoking the apparatus of a syntactic Binding
Theory.
In the last part of her paper, she extends her proposal to VP-ellipsis.
The fact that even quantifcational antecedents support the strict read
ing of VP-ellipsis (cf. Every man mentioned his merits before Mary did
. . . before Mary mentioned his merits') ha been taken to argue against
Reinhart-like approaches like Szabolcsi's and to motivate the introduction
of a new logical device, co-parametrization (see Gawron and Peters 1990) .
Szabolcsi challenges this conclusion, arguing that composition and duplica
tion, the two combinators whose presence in CCG accounts for extraction
and anaphora in the general cae, are in fct sufcient to derive the strict
readings here a well as in examples involving anaphors and gaps.
In her paper "The Lexical Entailment Theory of Control and the Touh
Construction,"
P
AULINE
J
ACOBSON presents another purely lexical analysis
that challenges conventional syntactic wisdom. Sentences of the type That
rock is hard for me to move exhibit a set of seemingly contradictory prop
erties. The matrix subject appears to be selected by the infnitive, a in
a raising construction; however, the gap following the transitive infnitive
resembles wh-traces more than NP-traces. One solution to this puzzle, sug
gested by Chomsky, is to asume that the subject/gap relation is mediated
by a null operator.
Building on a number of earlier results (including her own), Jacobson
presents a careful examination of data pertaining to these points and to fr
ther properties of the construction, and concludes that there is no syntactic
relationship between the subject of the tough-adjective and the gap. One
crucial fact is that there is no syntactic category matching requirement (cf.
That language is learable is hard for any theory to capture versus This
theory captures that language is learable). On the other hand, the con
struction allows for null complement anaphora, which is characteristic of
control constructions.
Jacobson argues for the following specifc asumptions about the lexical,
syntactic and semantic properties of the tough-adjective: (1) it subcatego
rizes for an infnitival complement that lacks an object; and (2) its subject
is understood a flling the gap position purely in view of some entailment
that is part of the lexical meaning of the adjective. This account is modeled
after the lexcal entailment theory of control, defended by Dowty, Chier
chia and others, which holds that want, for instance, denotes a relation
between individuals and properties, such that for any individual 1 which
INTRODUCTION / xvii
stands in the want-relation to a property P, x ha the property P in the
"want-world" of 1. Showing that the same kind of explanation can han
dle the puzzling relation between the tough-subject and the gap, Jacobson
suggests an interesting extension of this inuential theory.
The fnal contribution to the volume, "A Lexical Analysis of Ice
landic Case," by
I
VAN
S
AG,
L
AURI
K
ARTTUNEN, and
J
EFFREY GOLD
BERG (SKG), provides an essentially lexical treatment of the long-standing
problem of "quirky" cae in Icelandic complementation.
Although subjects in Icelandic are in general marked with nominative
case, and objects are in general accusative, there are three well-studied
clases of verbs which are exceptional in requiring (respectively) dative,
accusative or genitive case on their subjects. The interesting problem that
arises with respect to these quirky-subject verbs is their behavior in raising
constructions. The generalizations can be stated simply as follows: (1) the
raised subject of a subject-raising verb (e.g., viroist 'seems') is nominative
if its infnitival complement is headed by a non-quirky verb; (2) the object
of an object-raising verb (e. g., telur ' believes' ) is accusative if its infnitival
complement is headed by a non-quirky verb; and (3) a raised argument
must bear the appropriate quirky cae if the head of the complement is a
quirky-subject verb.
These facts, well-known in the literature on Icelandic syntax, strongly
suggest a two-stage analysis-one where quirky cae is lexically assigned
in underlying syntactic structures, but structural case (nominative for sub
jects; accusative for objects) is assigned to very superfcial syntactic repre
sentations, but only to those nominals that did not receive (quirky) lexical
case at an underlying level of syntactic representation. The notions of
before transformations have applied (for quirky cae) and afer transforma
tions have applied (for structural case) appear to be indispensable for an
account of these facts.
SKG, motivated by their desire to formulate all of linguistic knowledge
a declarative constraints on possible structures, set forth a treatment of
these facts that makes no reference to "before" or "after" stages of a trans
formational derivation. Their analysis posits two attributes-CASE (re
alized case) and DCASE (default case) , and allows the possibility that a
particular nominal may bear distinct values for these features. On SKG's
analysis, a quirky-subject verb specifes only the CASE value of its subject,
but a non-quirky verb specifes only that its subject's CASE value matches
its DCASE value. These minimal specifcations, together with the indepen
dently motivated treatment of realized subjects as [DCASE nom] and real
ized objects a [DCASE acc], lead to an account of the data just described
that is nonprocedural, monotonic, and constraint-based, as intended, and
yet expresses all the relevant generalizations. The SKG analysis is thus
another example (like those proposed by Farkas, Szabolcsi, and Jacobson)
of how complex data that have been taken to motivate transformational
xviii / LEXICAL MATTERS
analyses, can be dealt with in alternative terms, without sacrifcing either
explanation or the design properties that are motivated by processing con
cerns.
The strong Hungarian presence in the volume at hand is no accident.
Several of the papers in this volume were originally presented at the Sym
posium on Lexical Semantics, held during the 1987 LSA Linguistic Institute
at Stanford University, which was attended by a delegation of Hungarian
linguists (including one of the editors) and a number of American linguists
of Hungarian descent including the other editor) . The editors both regret
the various unforeseen delays, in consequence of which the contributions of
Tenny, Krita, Farkas, Kiefer, Gergely, and Szabolcsi, which were complete
in 1989, are only now seeing the light of day.
Neither the 1987 symposium nor the present volume would have been
possible without the generous support of both the Soros Foundation and the
International Research Exchanges Board (IREX) (formerly sponsored by
the American Council of Learned Societies and the Social Science Research
Council) , whose assistance we gratefully acknowledge. In addition, we wish
to thank Ferenc Kiefer and Andras Kornai for their help in organizing
the symposium, a well as Dikran Karagueuzian, Jonathan Ginzburg, and
Jongbok Kim for their asistance in the preparation of this volume.
Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabolcsi
References
Bresnan, Joan, and Jonni M. Kanerva. 1989. Locative Inversion in Chichewa: A
Cae Study of Factorization in Grammar. Linguistic Inquiry 20: 1-50.
Bresnan, Joan, and Annie Zaenen. 1990. Deep Unaccusativity in LFG. In Grm
matical Relations: A Cross- Theoretical Perspective, ed. Katarzyna Dziwirek,
Patrick Farrell, and Errapel Mejias-Bikandi, 45-57. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic Proto-Roles and Argument Selection. Language
67(3) : 547-619.
Gawron, Jean Mark, and Stanley Peters. 1990. Anaphora and Quantifcation in
Situation Semantics. CSLI Lecture Notes No. 19. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
Zaenen, Annie. 1990. Unaccusativity in Dutch: an Integrated Approach. In
Semantics and the Lexicon, ed. James Pustejovsky. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Contributors
F
ARRELL
A
CKERMAN, Assistant Professor of Linguistics at the University
of California at San Diego, is interested in the interaction between lexical
semantics, morphology and syntax with special attention to the Finno
U gric languages.
D
ONKA
F
.
F
ARKAS is Associate Professor of Linguistics at the University
of California at Santa Cruz. Her research interests include the interface
between syntax and semantics (in particular, the semantics of complemen
tation), and morphology.
G
Y
O
RGY
G
ERGELY received his Ph.D. in 1986 in experimental psychology
at Columbia University, and has taught in the department of psychology
at the University of Rochester. His current research interests are language
processing, causal and intentional attribution in infancy, and experimental
and psychodynamic approaches to the development of the self.
J
EFFREY
G
OLDBERG, now a resident of Hungary, is a graduate student in
the linguistics department at Stanford University. His research interests
include syntactic theory and computational linguistics.
P
AULINE
J
ACOBSON is Professor of Cognitive and Linguistic Sciences at
Brown University. Her research centers largely on the syntax/semantics
interface. She is especially interested in investigating the feaibility of direct
model-theoretic interpretation of (surface) syntactic structures.
L
AURI
K
ARTTUNEN is Principal Scientist at the Xerox Palo Alto Research
Center and Consulting Professor of Linguistics at Stanford University. His
linguistic publications include works on pragmatics and semantics. In com
putational linguistics, he is best known for his contributions to unifcation
baed grammars and fnite-state morphology.
F
ERENC
K
IEFER is Senior Research Fellow at the Research Institute for
Linguistics of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. His main research in
terests are morphology, semantics and pragmatics.
Iexical Matters. Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabolcsi, eds.
Copyright 1992, Stanford University.
xx / LEXICAL MATTERS
MANFRED KRIFKA is currently Assistant Professor in the Department of
Linguistics at the University of Texas at Austin. His research interests in
clude the semantics of mas terms, count terms and aspectual classes, po
larity phenomena, and focus. He has also worked on the syntax of Swahili.
MARK LIBERMAN obtained a doctorate in linguistics fom the Masachu
setts Institute of Technology in 1975. Fom 1975 to 1990, he worked at
AT&T Bell Laboratories, for the lat three years as head of the linguis
tics research department. He is now Tustee Professor of Phonetics at the
University of Pennsylvania. His current research interests include prosody,
phonetics, and computational linguistics, especially the problem of linguis
tic inference.
WILLIAM POSER is Associate Professor of Linguistics at Stanford Unver
sity. His interests include the phonetics/phonology interface, the formal
properties of phonological rules, phrasal phonology, and Japanese.
IVAN A. SAG is Professor of Linguistics and Symbolic Systems at Stanford
University and Vice Chair of the Department of Linguistics. He ha worked
mostly in the area of syntax, semantics and language processing.
RICHARD SPROAT holds a doctorate in linguistics from the Massachusetts
Institute of Technology. His research interests include morphology, com
putational morphology, text-to-speech synthesis, Chinese computational
linguistics, phonetics, and Celtic syntax. He is a member of the technical
staf in the Linguistics Research Department at AT&T Bell Laboratories.
ANNA SZABOLCSI has worked on performatives and focus in Montague
grammar, on the structure of the noun phrase in government and binding
theory, and on binding and extraction in combinatory categorial grammar.
She is currently Associate Professor of Linguistics at the University of Cal
ifornia at Los Angeles.
CAROL TENNY is Assistant Professor of Linguistics at the University of
Pittsburgh. Her research interests include theoretical syntax, the intersec
tion of syntax and semantics, and the representation of time in natural
language.
I
The Aspectual Interface Hypothesis
CAROL TENNY
1.1 Introduction: The Linking Problem
The problem of the linking of thematic roles to syntactic argument positions
is of fundamental importance because it is part of the larger problem of the
connection between syntax and semantics. Theories of generative grammar
have adopted, to a greater or lesser extent, the view of an autonomous syn
tax operating independently fom the semantics of a language. Up to a
certain point, this view does seem to characterize the behavior of natural
language. However, the problem remains that, in spite of the evidence for
the autonomy of syntax and semantics, there are strong generalizations to
be made about correspondences between meaning and syntactic structure.
There are familiar facts that cannot be ignored; such the fact that in
general, agents are subjects, and themes or patients are objects. Lexical se
mantics and syntax clearly interact-the problem is how to constrain that
interaction. Various mechanisms that have been proposed to deal with
this, such lists of linking rules that connect particular thematic roles
with particular syntactic or confgurational argument positions, are some
what stipulative and not entirely satisfactory. More principled approaches
to the problem have been presented in the recent literature, in the form of
hypotheses that there are uniform and universal constraints on the map
ping between syntax and lexical semantics. Perlmutter and Postal (1984)
proposed the Universal Alignment Hypothesis (UAR) in the famework of
Relational Grammar:
This paper is a 1989 revision of material, some of which wa presented at LSA 1987
and NELS 1987 and appears in Prceedings of NELS 18, published by University of
Masahusetts at Amherst. am grateful to audiences at these meetings for their com
ments. have s benefted from comments by Jane Grimshaw, Beth Levin, James
Pustejovsky, Maika Rappaport, Anna Szabolcsi, and Robert Van Valin. This work ha
been supported by grants from the System Development Foundation and from the Kapor
Family Foundation. am grateful for their support.
Lexical Matters. Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabo1csi, eds.
Copyright 1992, Stanford University.
2 / CAROL TENNY
Universal Alignment Hypothesis (U
A
H): There exist principles of
universal grammar which predict the initial relation borne by each nominal
in a given clause fom the meaning of the clause.
And Baker ( 1985) proposed the Universal Theta Assignment Hypothesis
(UTAH) , in the famework of Government and Binding Theory:
Universal Theta Assignment Hypothesis (U
TA
H): Identical them
atic relationships between items are represented by identical structural
relationships between those items at the level of D-structure.
Both of these hypotheses propose a fundamental connection between
"meaning" and some level of syntactic representation. The UAH maintains
that general principles constraining the mapping fom lexical semantics
to syntax do exist, although it gives no indication of what they might
be. The UTAH claims that the mapping between thematic and structural
relationships is consistent, although it does not explain why the mapping
is the way it is. The UAH and the UTAH are elegant idea that explain
a variety of phenomena in a simple way. However, these hypotheses lack
an account of the central mechanism by which thematic structures and
syntactic structures are connected. The thesis of this paper is that certain
aspectual properties mediate between syntax and lexical semantics, and
provide a principled basis for hypotheses such a the UAH and the UTAH.
The Aspectual Interface Hypothesis (AIR) is proposed to supplant the UAH
and the UTAH:
Aspectual Interface Hypothesis: The mapping between thematic
structure and syntactic argument structure is governed by apectual prop
erties. A universal aspectual structure associated with internal (direct) ,
external and oblique arguments in syntactic structure constrains the kinds
of event participants that can occupy these positions. Only the aspectual
part of thematic structure is visible to the syntax.
This proposal takes a strong stand on the current controversy over whether
grammar needs to refer to thematic roles. Under this view, the syntax
proper does not need to "see" thematic roles. It only "sees" certain syn
tactic/
aspectual structures the thematic roles are asociated with.
This is also in the spirit of much recent work arguing that the thematic
content of thematic roles need not be referred to by syntactic operations.
See Belletti and Rizzi 1988; Rappaport and Levin 1988; Levin and Rap
paport 1986; Grimshaw 1987a; Rappaport, Laughren, and Levin 1987.)
This paper focuses on the central part of the aspectual structure pro
posed by the AIR: the correspondence between the argument in a semantic
representation which ha the special aspectual role of "meauring out the
event, " and the syntactic argument which may be characterized as the
verb's internal argument. The crucial constraint on this correspondence
may be stated as:
THE ASPECTUAL INTERFACE HYPOTHESIS / 3
( 1 ) The internal argument of a simple verb is constrained so that it either
undergoes no change or motion, or it undergoes change or motion
which "measures out the event" over time.
The statement above may be regarded as one clause in a fully articulated
set of principles of aspectual structure. The discussion in this paper is
concerned with simple nonstative verbs (although ( 1) is true of stative
verbs as well) . Verbs with more complicated argument structures, such
as propositional-argument-taking verbs, are unexplored in this paper and
must await further research.
Section 1. 2 outlines some assumptions about lexical and argument
structure on which the discussion in the paper depends. Then in Sec
tion 2, various lexical semantic phenomena are discussed which illustrate
the special aspectual role of the internal argument. These include afected
ness, unaccuativity, the locative alternation, and psych verbs. Section 3
addresses the question of what the AIR says about thematic roles. Section
4 considers the implications of the AIR for language acquisition, and points
out some constraints it places on the lexicon.
1. 2 Some Assumptions
The AIH as stated above adopts a certain view of argument structure and
lexical structure. It employs some ideas developed in the work of the MIT
Lexicon Project. The MIT Lexicon Project has been investigating what
information must be included in the lexical entry for a natural language
predicate; or (to look at it another way) what a native speaker must know
about predicates in his or her language, in order to be able to use them
correctly. (Hale and Keyser 1987; Rappaport and Levin 1986; Rappaport,
Laughren and Levin 1987. ) A structured lexical entry has been developed
which has two parts: a structural part and a conceptual part. For example,
Hale and Keyser (1988) show the lexical entry for cut as in Figure 1.
VP
.
V arg
T produces linear separation
I
in material integrity of y
by sharp edge coming into
contact with latter
Figure 1 Lexical Entry for English cut
The prose part of the entry expresses the conceptual part of the verb's
meaning, including the number of open arguments and the roles they play
4 / CAROL TENNY
in the event described by the verb. (Notice that thematic roles 6I S6 are
not mentioned. ) The structural part indicates how these roles are to be
mapped onto syntactic structures. The tree-like structure simply indicates
that the
u
g
y x] / 'z[
V
y[P(y
) y z]
-
x zlJ (fusion)
We now defne some higher-order predicates and relations to characterize
diferent reference types.
(Pl 1 ) 'P[ CUM(P)
'x, y[P(x) 1 P(y
)
-
P(x U y)lJ
(cumulative reference)
(PI2) 'P[SNG(P) f 3x[P(x) / 'y[P(y)
-
x = yJJJ (singular reference)
(PI3) 'P[SCUM(P) * CUM(P) 1 -SNG(P)]
(strictly cumulative reference)
(P14) 'P[ QUA(P) * 'x, y[P(x) 1 P(y
)
- - y L xlJ (quantized reference)
(PI5) 'P[SQUA
(P)
-
QUA(P) 1 'x[P(x)
- 3y[y L xJJJ
(strictly quantized reference)
(PI6) 'x, P[ ATOM(x, P) T P(x) 1 -3y[
y L x 1 P(y)l J
(x is a P-atom)
(PI7) 'P[ ATM(P)
'x[P(x)
t ::t"
)
/ [t ::t
' Y
t' ::tj / [t ::t'
/ t' ::t t = t')))
(:: is a linear order for time points)
(P20)
"t, t' [t :: t' ..Vt", t
il
' [t
il
t / t
il
' t'
t
il
::t
i l
'])
(extension of :: to times in general)
(P2I) Vt[CONV(t) ..Vt' , t", t"' [t' t / t
il
t / t' ::t
il
' :: t
i l
t
il
' t))
(convex times, or intervals)
Third, we assume a function
T
from the extension of to the extension of 1,
the temporal trace function; this function maps an event to its "run time,"
or temporal trace. It is a homomorphism relative to the join operation:
(P22) "e, e' [T(e) U T
(e' )
T(e U e' )
)
That is, the join of the temporal traces of two events equals the temporal
trace of the join of these events.
3 Cumulativity and Quantization for Object and
Event Predicates
In this section, we will apply the notions we have developed so far to
the semantic description of certain predicate types. First, we will look at
predicates on objects, and then at predicates on events.
Characterizing object predicates like wine versus a glass of wine, or ap
ples versus fve apples, is straightforward. If we represent these expressions
by predicates in the semantic representation languages, we have:
(4) a. wine 0 / CUM( wine)
b. a.glass. of. wine 0 / QUA(a. glass. of. wine)
c. apples 0 / CUM( apples)
d. fve.apples 0 / QUA(fve. apples)
(4a) says that wine is a predicate on objects (note that we make no dis
tinction between stuf and objects for reasons of simplicity) , and that it is
34 / MANFRED KRIFKA
cumulative. (4b) says t hat a.glass.of wine is also a predicate on objects,
but that this predicate is quantized. Similarly, apples is a cumulative ob
ject predicate, and fve. apples is a quantized object predicate. I will not go
into the semantic composition of predicates which are syntactically or mor
phologically complex, like a.glas.ofwine, apples, or fve.apples; see Krifa
1986, 1989 for a treatment.
Now look at expressions like run and run a mile. In the standard
treatment (5i) , one-place verbal predicates are reconstructed as applying
to objects, just as object predicates. For example, run is analyzed as
applying to every object that runs. However, there are good reasons to
assume that these predicates have also an argument place for events (cf.
Davidson 1967), as in (5ii), or even that they are predicates on events, and
that the participants are related to these events by thematic relations like
Agent, Theme, etc. (cf. Parsons 1980, Carlson 1984, Bauerle 1988), a in
(5iii):
(5) Mary runs. i. run(Mary)
. run(Mary, e)
iii. run (e)/ AG(e, Mary)
Obviously, if we want to model the temporal constitution of verbal expres
sions, we should choose either (5ii) or (5iii) a a representation format,
because the temporal constitution can most eaily be formulated with the
help of the event argument 6. Furthermore, it will turn out that the rules
can be more easily formulated in the format (5iii ) , which factorizes a verbal
predicate into an event property and the thematic information. So I will
base what follows on this representation format.
How can we characterize an atelic event predicate like run and a telic
event predicate like run.a. mile within our theoretical famework? We may
say that the frst is cumulative and the second is quantized: If we have
two events of running, then they form together an event of running; and if
we have an event of running a mile, then no proper part of it is an event
of running a mile. So we can reconstruct atelic and telic expressions by
cumulative and quantized event predicates, respectively:
|) a. run ^ CUM (run)
b. run.a.mile / QUA(run. a.mile)
We might ask how this characterization of telic and atelic predicates relates
to the traditional one, that telic predicates have a set terminal point and
atelic predicates lack such a set terminal point. There is, in fact, a close
relationship:
The notion of a "set terminal point" cannot be defned for bare events
or "event tokens" , but only for events with respect to a certain description,
event predicates, or "event types." For consider a concrete event of running
and a concrete event of running a mile; then surely both events have a
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 35
terminal point (both events might be even identical) . The diference is
that an event of running might be a part of another event of running which
has a later terminal point, whereas this is not possible for an event of
running a mile.
We can defne the notion of a telic event predicate like follows. First,
let H defne a function TP which maps events to the last time point in
their run time. Then we can defne the notion of event predicates which
have a set terminal point, STP.
(P23) 'e, t [ TP(e) = t T(t)
A
t r(e) A 't' [t' r(e) t' t
ll
(the terminal point of an event)
(P24) 'P[STP(P) 'e[P(e) 'e' [P(e') A e' e TP(e) = TP(e')
]
] ]
(event predicates with set terminal point)
An STP event predicate, then, applies to events such that all subevents
which fall under the predicate have the same terminal point. In a natural
interpretation of run and run.a.mile, we can assume the following proper
ties:
(7) a. run A
..STP( run)
b. run. a. mile A STP( run. a. mile)
That is, run. a. mile is a predicate with a set terminal point, as every
subevent of an event of running a mile ha the same terminal point. This
is diferent for run. In general, we may characterize telic predicates P as
STP(P) , and atelic predicates P a ..STP(P).
If we defned a mapping fom objects to spatial regions and defne the
notion of a border of regions, and hence, of objects, then we could character
ize nominal predicates like a. glass. of wine and wine similarly, as implying
a set border or a not implying a set border. In this way, we could capture
the similarity between expressions like 'run' and 'run a mile' with 'wine'
and 'a glass of wine' , respectively.
It turns out, however, that a good deal of the similarity can already be
covered by the notions of cumulative and quantized predicates. The reason
is that there is a relation between predicates with a set terminal point
and an interesting class of cumulative event predicates. This clas can be
defned as follows: With the exception of singular event predicates (that
refer to one event only) , event predicates in natural language typically have
the property that they apply to events which have diferent terminal points.
For example, a predicate like run, or run a mile, refers to events that end
at diferent times. Let us defne the notion of natural event predicates,
NEP, as an event predicates with that property:
(P25) 'P[NEP(P) P A
3e, e' [P(e) A
P(e') A
TP(e) = TP(e')]]
Now we can prove that cumulative natural event predicates cannot have a
set terminal point:
36 / MANFRED KRIFKA
(T5) VP[ CUM(P) / NEP(P) -STP(P)]
Proof: Assume an event predicate P with CUM(P) and NEP(P). As P is
natural, there are two events el , e2 such that P(el ) , P(e2) , and - TP( el )
TP(e2 ) . Assume that TP(el ) TP(e2 ) . As P is cumulative, it holds that
P(el U e2) . As r(el U e2) r(el ) U r(e2), we have - TP( el ) TP(el U e2) .
But i t holds that e
l ! el U e2 . Conequently, we have -STP(P).
This mean that, under the assumption that P is cumulative, CUM(P),
and not singular, -SNG(P), we can normally assume that P has no set
terminal point, -STP(P). That is, strictly cumulative event predicates
can safely be taken as atelic under the traditional defnition (lacking a set
terminal point) .
On the other hand, whenever we have a quantized event predicate P,
QUA(P), this will have a set terminal point, STP(P) . This is because when
QUA(P) and P(e), then e has no proper part; so all parts e' of e will have
the same end point, a e' and e are in fact identical. Therefore all quantized
event predicates will be telic, under the traditional defnition. But note that
there are predicates with set terminal points that fail to be quantized. One
example is 'walk to the station': If this predicate applies to an event e,
then it will also apply to the latter half of e; so it is not quantized.
In the following, I will view telic predicates simply as quantized event
predicates, and atelic predicates as strictly cumulative event predicates.
4 A Famework for Object and Event Reference
Before we turn to a formal description of the infuence of nominal arguments
to verbal predicates, I will sketch the syntactic and semantic famework I
am assuming by way of an example (see Krifa 1986 for a more explicit
treatment) .
I asume a categorial-like syntactic representation; this is, however, not
essential. Verb argument places come with features such as category (like
NP) , cae (like 8ubj, obj) , and theta-roles (like ag, pat) . The expressions
that fll these arguments must have the same values for these features.
The value of the theta feature is interpreted semantically by corresponding
thematic relations. In the derivation tree in (8), I specify the expression,
its syntactic category, and its semantic interpretation. The general syn
tactic operation is concatenation, and the semantic operation is fnctional
application.
A verb is interpreted as a one-place predicate of events; the syntactic
argument slots have no counterpart in its semantic representation, but
only in its syntactic categorization. The theta-role information, which is
specifed with the argument slots in syntax, is passed to the subcategorized
NPs, where it is realized as a part of the semantic representation of the
determiners (e. g. , pat is realized as PAT(e,x) ) . With free adjuncts like in 0
pen, the thematic relation are specifed within the adjunct. Here I assume
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 37
that the theta role is specifed in the preposition; the NP governed by the
preposition only has a dummy theta feature "empty" that is not realized
in the interpretation of the determiner.
(8) drank ; S/NP[subj, ag] , NP[obj, pat] ; -e[ drink(e)]
water ; N ; water
; NPlobj, patl/N ; ,P' ,P>e3x
IP(e) A PAT(e, x) A P' (x)]
water ; NP[obj, pat] ; -P-e3x[P(e) / PAT(e, x) / water(x)]
drnk water ; S/NP[subj, ag] ;
-P-e3x[P(e) / PAT(e, x) / water(x)] (-e[drink(e)] ) =
-e3x[ drink(e) / PAT(e, x) / water(x)]
in ; [S/S]/NP[obj, empty] ; IN
pen ; N ; pen
; NPlobj, emptyl/N ; ,P' MP>e3xIP( e) A R( e, x)
A p'
(x)
]
a pen ; NP[obj, empty] ; -
R-P-e3x[P(e) / R
(e, x) / pen (x)]
in a pen ; SIS ; -P-e3x[P(e) / IN(e, x) / pen(x)]
drank water in a pen ; S/NP[subj, ag] ;
-P-e3x[P(e) 1 IN(e, x) / pen(x)] (-e3x[drink(e) / PAT(e, x)
/ water( x)] ) =
-e3x, y[ drink (e) / PAT(e, x) / water(x) / IN(e, y) / pen(y)]
pig ; N ; pig
; NP
I.
ubj, a
.
] /N ;
,'
,P3x
IP(e) A AG(e, x) A P' (x)]
a pig ; NP[subj, ag] ; .P3x[P(e) / AG(e, x) / pig(x)]
a pig drank water in a pen ; S ;
-P-e3x[P(e) 1 AG(e, x) / pig(x)] (-e3x, y[ drink(e) / PAT(e, x)
/
water(x) / IN(e, y) / pen(y)] )
=
-e3x, y, z[ drink (e) / AG(e, x) / pig(x) / PAT(e, y) / water(y)
/ IN(e, z) / pen(z)]
After all fee variables are bound, we obtain a predicate on events with
out fee variables, the sentence radical ( S) . This can be transformed to
a sentence (S') by the application of a sentence mood operator, e. g. , the
declarative operator, which simply binds the event variable with an exis
tential quantifer.
38 / MANFRED KRIFKA
(9)
. ; D
/S
, .P3eP(e)
A pig drnk water in a pe
n. ; Sf ;
3e3x, y, z[ drink(e) / AG(e
, x) / pig(x) / PAT(e, y) / water(y)
/
IN(e, X)
/ pen(z)]
This representation of declarative sentences thus conforms to the truth
scheme of Austin ( 1961) , who asumed that a declarative sentence consists
of two baic semantic constituents, namely a specifcation of an event type
and a reference to a specifc event, which is claimed to be of the specifed
type. Types of events I capture by event predicates, and the reference to
a specifc event by the existential quantifer. Surely, both reconstructions
will turn out to be too simple, but they sufce for the present purpose,
and the analysis to be developed hopefully can be recat in more complex
representations.
5 The Impact of Arguments
In this section, which repeats part of Krita 1989, I will show how the
impact of the nominal reference of arguments on the temporal constitution
of verbal predicates can be captured formally.
The baic idea is that, with certain thematic relations, the reference
properties of the syntactic arguments carry over to the reference properties
of the complex construction. There is a way to visualize this transfer of
reference types, namely space-time diagrams. In these diagrams, space is
represented by one axis, and time by the other. Objects, with their spatial
extension, can be represented as lines, and events can be mapped to the
time axis. Now consider 6 the event of drinking a quantity of wine w
(which is gradually disappearing during the drinking):
( 10)
I
By this picture the intuitive notion that the object is subjected to the
event in a gradual manner should become clear. Consider two possible
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 39
descriptions of w and, consequently, e. First, let w be described as wine,
and hence e a drink wine. As wine is cumulative, it is normally the cae
that it can also be applied to proper parts of w, like w' . But then it should
be possible to apply the predicate drink wine to the corresponding proper
part of e, namely e', a well. Secondly, let w be described a a glass of
wine, and e consequently as drink a glass of wine. As a glass of wine is
quantized, no proper part of U can be described as a glass of wine. But
then no proper part of e can be described as drink a glass of wine either.
Technically speaking, we have to assume a homomorphism fom objects
to events which preserves the lattice structure. This should follow fom the
properties of the thematic relation that mediates between event and object.
To characterize these properties, I assume the following notions:
(P26) 'R[SUM(R) 'e, e' , x, x' [R(e, x) / R(e' , x')
R(e U e' , x U x')]]
(summativity)
(P27) 'R[ UNI- O(R) 'e, x, x' [R(e, x) / R(e, x'
) x = x']]
(uniqueness of objects)
(P28) ' R[ UNI-E(R) 'e, e', x[R( e, x) / R( e' , x) e e'
ll
(uniqueness of events)
(P29) 'R[MAP- O(R) 'e, e
' , x[R(e, x) /
e' ! e 3x' [x' !
x /R(e'
, x' )
)))
(mapping to objects)
(P30) 'R[MAP-E(R) 'e, x, x' [R(e, x) /x' ! x 3e' [e' !
e / R(e', x'))))
(mapping to events)
Summativity (that is, cumulativity for two-place relations) provides the
basic connection between thematic relations and the join operation U . For
example, two (distinct) events of drinking a glas of wine yield an event of
drinking two glasses of wine. Uniqueness of objects captues the fact that
an event is related to a specifc object, for example, a drinking of a glas of
wine is related via the patient role to this glas of wine, and to nothing else.
Uniqueness of events says that there is only one event related to the object
by the thematic relation; for example, for a specic glas of wine there can
be only one drinking event. Mapping to objects can be exemplifed by our
example a follows: every part of a drinking of a glass of wine corresponds
to a part of the glas of wine. And mapping to events says in the example
at hand that every part of the glas of wine being drunk corresponds to a
part of the drinking event. These are just informal characterizations of the
properties of thematic relations; they will be discussed in more detail below.
The following postulate covers the notion of iterativity. It is a relation
between an event e, an object x and a thematic relation R saying that at
leat one part of x is subjected to at least two diferent parts of e. This
notion applies to, e.g. , the reading of a book if at least one part of the book
is read twice. It is more permissive than the usual notion of iterativity,
40 / MANFRED KRIFKA
which would claim in the example at hand that the whole book must have
been read at leat twice.
(P31) 'e, x, R[ITER(e, x, R) - R(e, x) 1 3e' , e", x' [e' e l e" e
/
e'
= e" / x' x 1 R( e', x' ) / R( e", x' )
l}
(iterativity)
Which properties must we assume for thematic relations to derive their
homomorphism properties? Let us translate an expression like read a letter
by predicates ,
( 1 1 ) = Ae3x[a(e) 1 8(x) 1 O
(
e, x)]
where O represents the verbal predicate ( read), 8 represents the nominal
predicate ( a letter) , and 0 represents a thematic relation (here, a specifc
patient relation) . In the following, I will examine the efects of some prop
erties of 8 and 0 on . The verbal predicate a will be considered to be
cumulative throughout.
We start with the question: What are the conditions for to be cu
mulative? One set of conditions is: is cumulative if 8 is cumulative and
o is summative (an example is read letters) . Proof: Assume el , e2 (not
necessarily distinct) with (el ) , (e2). According to the defnition of ,
there are two objects Xl , X2 with a( el ) ' 8(X
I
) ' 6(el , x
I
) and a( e2) ' 8(X2) '
O(e2, X2 ) . Because a and 8 are cumulative, it holds that a(el U e2 ) and
8(X
I
U X2) , and because 0 i summative, it holds that O(el U e2, X
I
U X2).
Hence (el U e2), that is, is cumulative:
(T6) 'P, Q, R[ CUM(P) / CUM(Q) 1 SUM(R) CUM( Ae3x[P(e) /
Q(x) P R(e, x)])]
As singular predicates (e. g. , the letter) are cumulative a well, albeit in a
somewhat pathological way, this result holds for them, too. Consider the
following example, with the. letter as a predicate with singular reference
applying to the letter.
( 12) read the letter
Ae3x[ read(e) / PAT(e, x) 1 the. letter(x)]
But if we want to understand read the letter as atelic, a in he read the
letter for an hour, then we clearly have to asume either a partitive reading
or an iterative reading. Partitive readings will be treated in Section 7. As
for the iterative reading, it can be shown that if is strictly cumulative,
o is summative, and 8 has singular reference, then we get an iterative
interpretation.
Proof: If is strictly cumulative, then we have two distinct el , e2 with
(el ) , (e2) . According to the defnition of , there are two objects Xr ,
X2 with 8(X
I
) ' 6( er , xr ) and 8(X2) ' O(e2, X2) . Because 0 i s summative, it
holds that O(el U e2, Xl U X2), and because 8 has singular reference, it holds
that Xl X2 With O(el U e2 , X
I
) , O(el , x
I
) , O(e2, xr ) and - el e2, the
conditions for iterativity (P31) are met, as Xl is subjected to two diferent
parts of the event el Ue2, namely e
l
and e2. So the following theorem holds:
THEMATIC RELATIONS I 41
(T7) VP, R, e, x[SNG(P) / SUM(R) 1
SCUM( -e3x[P(x) / R(e, x)] ) -
ITER(e, x, R)]
If we exclude the iterative interpretation and retain singular reference of 6
and summativity of (, then it follows that cannot be strictly cumulative:
(T8) VP, R, e, x[SNG(P) / SUM(R) / -ITER(e, x, R) -
-SCUM(-dx[
P(x) / R(e, x)] )]
Hence a verbal predicate like read the letter, under a non-iterative and non
partitive interpretation, cannot be strictly cumulative, and hence cannot
be atelic.
Sometimes the iterative interpretation is excluded in the frst place,
namely with efected or consumed objects, as in write the letter or drink the
wine. The reason is that an object can be subjected to an event of drinking
or writing a maximum of one time in its career. Therefore, uniqueness of
events should be postulated for the respective thematic relations. And this
excludes an iterative interpretation. Proof: Assume to the contrary that (
is unique for events, ((eo, xo) and ITER(eo, xo, (). Because of iterativity,
it follows that there are el , e2, Xl with el eO, e2 eo, - el = e2 and
Xl Xo for which it holds that ((el , x
I
) and ((e2 , xd. But this contradicts
uniqueness of events.
(T9) VR, e, x[R(e, x)
1
UNI-E(R) - -ITER(e, x, R)]
Let us now investigate the infuence of quantized nominal predicates like a
letter. Under which conditions can we asume that they cause the complex
verbal predicate to be quantized as well? One set of conditions is that the
thematic role ( must satisf uniqueness of objects and mapping to objects,
and that iterative interpretations are excluded. Proof: We assume to the
contrary that ( is quantized, (e l ), (e2) and e2 e el . Then there are
Xl , X2 with 6(XI)
'
((el , xI ) and 6(X2) ' ((e2, x2), according to the defnition
of . Because e2 L el and ( satisfes mapping to objects, there is an X3
such that X3 Xl and ((e2, X3) . Because uniqueness of objects, it holds
that X3
= X2, and therefore X2 Xl . As we have (( e2, x2) , e2 e el and
-ITER(e
I
, XI , () , we can infer that -X
I
X2 . With X2 Xl , this yields
X2 L Xl , but this contradicts the assumption that 6 is quantized. Hence
there are no el , e2 as asumed above, and that means that is quantized.
(TID) VP, R, e, x[ QUA(P) / UNI- O(R) / MAP- O(R) / -ITER(e, x, R)
QUA(-e3x[P(x) / R(e, x)] )]
As a special case of (TID), we have the following theorem for thematic re
lations which satisf uniqueness of events (e. g. , efected and consumed ob
jects), a this property excludes an iterative interpretation in the frst place:
( TIl) VP, R[ QUA(P) / UNI- O(R) / MAP- O(R) / UNI-E(O) -
QUA(-e3x[P(x) I R(e, x)] )]
Even in the iterative cae it holds that examples like ' read a letter' are
atomic. The conditions for thematic relations which are relevant for this
42 / MANFRED KRIFKA
result are that they satisf uniqueness of objects and mapping to events.
We have to asume 6 not only to be quantized, but to be strictly quantized,
which is not a substantial limitation. Proof: Assume an el with <(ed,
hence an Xl with 6(Xl ) and B(e l , Xl ) ' Because 6 is strictly quantized, Xl
contains a proper part X2 , that is, X2 L Xl , with ,6(X2) ' Because of
mapping to events, there is an e2 with e2 !; el and ((e2, x2). Because of
uniqueness of objects, X2 is the only object with this property. Hence there
is no X with 6 (x) and B( e2, x). But then '<( e2) holds, and this means that
e l contains a <-atom, e2. As we made no special assumption for el l it
follows that < is atomic.
(TI2) VP, R[SQUA(P) " MAP-E(R) " UNI- O(R)
ATM(Ae3x[P(x)
" R(e, x)] )]
In Krifa 1986, 1989, I have shown how we can explain with the help of
these results why durative adverbials like for an hour select for atelic verbal
predicates, wherea time-span adverbials like in an hour select for telic
predicates. The underlying reaon is that durative adverbials presuppose
that the verbal predicate they are applied to is strictly cumulative, and
time-span adverbials presuppose that the verbal predicate they are applied
to is atomic. Now, quantized verbal predicates telic predicates) are
atomic and not strictly cumulative; hence their distribution with respect
to those adverbials is explained. Strictly cumulative verbal predicates
atelic predicates) can be combined with durative adverbials, and they can
also be combined with time-span adverbials under the presupposition that
they are atomic. Normally, this presupposition is not warranted, and hence
the combination with time-span adverbials sounds odd.
To conclude this section, let us use the properties of thematic relations
to clasif the patient relations of diferent verbs. It is usefl to introduce a
new notion that says that the object is subjected to the event in a gradual
manner, as visualized by the space-time diagram ( 10) . I call this gaduality;
it comprises uniqueness of objects, mapping to objects, and mapping to
events.
(P32) VP[ GRAD(P) UNI- O(P) " MAP- O(P) " MAP-E(P)] (graduality)
The criteria for the clasifcation of thematic roles can be applied to tran
sitive verbs. This yields at leat three interesting classes; two classes can
be further subdivided for independent reasons.
( 13) example summa- gradu- uniqu. label
tivity ality events
write a letter gradual efected patient
eat an apple gradual consumed patient
read a letter gradual patient
touch a cat afected patient
see a horse stimulus
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 43
I think the conditions of summativity, graduality and uniqueness of events
are intuitively plausible for the respective patient relations. In the next sec
tion, I will discuss the transfer properties for thematic relations in greater
detail.
6 Some Consequences for the Theory of Thematic
Relations
In this section, we will discuss some consequences which follow fom the
asumption of properties of thematic relations, a discussed in the last
section.
The most general property is 8ummativity, which obtains for all patient
relations, and probably for all thematic relations whatsoever. This means
that thematic relations are not sensitive to the "size" of the entities they
relate to each other.
One thing which summativity can buy us is a simpler and intuitively
more appealing treatment of cumulative reading than the one ofered in
Scha 1981. For example, if there are two events, one to be described with
(14a) , the other with ( 14b) ,
(14) a. John saw three zebra.
b. Mary saw four zebra.
and if the zebra John and Mary saw do not overlap, then the sentence John
and Mary saw seven zebras can be derived if one asumes summativity for
the experiencer relation and the stimulus relation, and that the count noun
relation contains extensive meaure fnctions compatible with the object
lattice, a notion introduced in Krifa 1986, 1989. EXP and STI should
represent the experiencer and stimulus relation, and zebra(x, n) says that x
and H are zebra.
(15) see(ed ^ EXP(e l > John) / STI(el , xt} ^ zebr(xl
'
3)
see(e2) ^ EXP(e2, Mary) ^ STI(e2, X2) ^ zebr(x2
'
4)
. Xl ~ X2
see(el U e2) / EXP(el U e2, John U Mary) / STI(el U e2, Xl U X2)
^ zebr(XI U X2, 7)
Note that the derived sentence ha rather weak truth conditions, a it re
mains unspecifed how the zebra relate to John and Mary individually.
This is a it should be, a the diferent possibilities are not diferent "read
ings" of the sentence. In contrat to other theories of cumulative predica
tion, for example the one by Gillon (1987) , this i a natural outcome of a
very simple rule and need not be stated by a complicated rule involving
quantifcation over partitions of sets and the like.
An objection against this treatment might be that a sentence like John
and Mary saw seven zebras are understood saying that they saw exactly
seven zebra, a reading which is not captured by 3e, x[ see( e )IEXP( e, JohnU
Mary) ^ STI(e, x) ^ zebra(x, 7)], a this representation allows for John and
44 / MANFRED KRIFKA
Mary to have seen more than seven zebras. But this problem can be han
dled if we assume a pragmatic rule that enforces maximally informative
readings, as the sentence x saw H zebras is more informative than x saw H
t
zebrs, if H ` H
t
(cf. Krifa 1986, 1989) .
To cover collective readings, a e. g. , John and Mary (jointly) own three
houses, we need of course a diferent representation, which will not be
developed here. And it should be clear that distributive readings can be
treated in this famework a well (cf. Link 1983 for distributivity in lattice
model structures) .
Uniqueness of objects has been discussed by several authors. For exam
ple, it corresponds to "thematic uniqueness" in Carlson 1984 and "unique
ness of role-bearers" in Dowty 1987, and it is a requirement for the treat
ment of thematic relations as functions, as e. g. , in Link 1987. Furthermore,
Carlson suggests that thematic roles may serve to discriminate events fom
one another on the basis of this property and the discrimination of ob
jects involved in the events: If 0 is unique for objects, then we can infer
fom O(e l , xd
A O(e2, x2) A "Xl X2 that . el e2 But note that I
do not assume uniqueness of objects for every thematic relation, as these
authors seem to do. Obviously, it does not hold for the stimulus rela
tion, a e. g. , I can see a zebra and, with the same event of seeing, see
the mane of the zebra as well. And it does not obtain with afected ob
jects, as e. g. , I can touch a shoulder and a person with the same event of
touching.
Next, consider mapping to events and mapping to objects, the two re
lations which constitute the core of the construction of the homomorphism
fom objects to events. They seem to be sound asumptions for gradual
patient relations. Take as an example the reading of a book; every part of
the book corresponds to a part of the reading and vice versa. With other
thematic relations, these properties normally do not obtain; for example,
there is no correspondence between parts of the person that is reading and
the reading event. But note that as we can have sum individuals, it is pos
sible that mapping to events and mapping to objects (a well as uniqueness
of objects) apply to other thematic relations in certain circumstances as
well. As an example, consider see seven zebrs. Even if a single experiencer
is involved, this predicate can be applied to events with diferent temporal
structues, for example to events where seven zebras are seen simultane
ously, or to the sum of seven consecutive events, in each of which a single
zebra was seen. Now, in the second case, it does make sense to speak of
mapping to events and mapping to objects, as for every part of the complex
seeing event (down to the observings of single zebras) there is a part of the
sum individual of the zebras which is seen in this event. Note that in cases
like this one, predicates as 'see seven zebras' can be understood as telic;
for example, ( 16) can be understood to say that the seven zebras were not
seen simultaneously.
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 45
( 16) John saw seven zebras in an hour.
Time-span adverbials like in an hour select for atomic verbal predicates
(cf. Krifa 1986, 1989). The simplest way to get an atomic reading of see
seven zebras is that in the relevant event, the zebras were seen in some
temporal succession.
The fact that the object roles of verbs like see sometimes have the
same mapping properties as the object roles of verbs like eat indicates
that the properties we have discussed so far are not "hard-wired" in the
thematic relations, but follow from other knowledge sources. Consequently,
we should asume that even the object role of verbs like eat does not exhibit
graduality as some grammatical feature, but simply because the normal
way of eating enforces the graduality properties.
However, there are some problems with the mapping properties. With
mapping to events, it is ofen the cae that only a certain class of parts of
the object are relevant. As an example, consider eat the apple and peel the
apple; in the frst cae, all the parts of the apple are involved, whereas in the
second cae, only the surface parts are. Another example is read the book
and bur the book; surely, there are parts of the book which are relevant in
the second cae (e.g. , the cover of the book) which do not count as parts
of the book in the frst case. To handle these phenomena, we may asume
that the verb selects specifc aspects of an object (e.g. , only its surface).
Perhaps more problematic is mapping to objects. As an example, con
sider build the house. There are surely parts of the event of building a
house which cannot be mapped to parts of the house. An example is the
erection of the scafold, which is clearly part of building the house, but the
scafold is not a part of the house, and even vanishes when the house is
fnished. Therefore, mapping to objects does not hold in a strict sense for
complex events.
This problem can be solved if we assume that predicates like build the
house refer to events consisting of events which themselves fall under difer
ent quantized predicates. A list of such predicates may be called a scenario,
after Link 1987. For example, the building of a house consists in raising
a loan, buying a place, and so on. This can be captured by a predicate
i ,e3el ' " en[il ( el ) / / in(en) / e e l | | en] , where all the
ii are quantized and disjoint from each other. It can be shown that i is
then quantized a well. Proof: Assume to the contrary that i(el)
'
i(e2)
and el g e2; then there is at least one ii , 1 : i : H, and e
3
, e4 such that
ii ( e
3
) , ii (e4) and e3 g e4, which contradicts the assumption that ii is
quantized.
However, an objection to this solution may be raised, as many events
lack a standard scenario (cf. Link 1987) . For example, with the building of
a house, there need not be an erection of a scafold. Therefore, we have to
assume that a complex event of a certain type ha to be related to some
46 / MANFRED KRIFKA
scenario of quantized subpredicates which need not be exactly specifed,
but which at least must qualify as being quantized, and this is all we need.
Uniqueness of events, fnally, characterizes those patient relations which
describe the coming into being and disappearing of objects, because there
can be only one such event for every object. This is another property that
should not be considered as a grammatical feature, but as an external fact
about the world.
Note that with many verba efciendi, we fnd a certain ambiguity: They
can be either token-oriented and type-oriented, so to speak. For example,
it is possible to write the same letter more than once, if one refers to the
letter type, not to the letter token. Such type-oriented verbs were called
"performance verbs" by Verkuyl ( 1972) . The approach outlined here can
be extended to type reference. Types may be conidered a abstract enti
ties with a part relation that corresponds to the part relation for concrete
entities we considered so far. For example, if y, y' are types and y' y,
and i f a concrete object or event T realizes the type y, then there should
be an object or event T
t
, T
t
T, that realizes type y'. The specifc pa
tient relation of performance verbs then describes the realization of a type.
Verbs like play and compose (as in play/compose a sonata) have patient
relations relating an event to types, whereas write can be analyzed as either
token-oriented or type-oriented. We cannot assume uniqueness of events for
the type-oriented patient relation of write and play, and therefore we can
understand a predicate as write a letter as atelic in its performance read
ing and under an iterative interpretation, as e.g. , in ( 17a). On the other
hand, with the patient relation of compose, we should asume uniqueness
of events, which explains why ( 17b) is bad.
( 1 7) a. The secretary wrote this letter for three years.
b. *Scarlatti composed this sonata for three years.
In this paper, I cannot go into the semantics of types, or kinds, and
their relation to tokens; see Krita 1986 for a more elaborate treatment.
7 Progressive and Partitive
The famework developed so far can be extended in many diferent direc
tions and applied to interesting problems. Here, I will treat two topics,
namely the marking of progressives in Finnish and German and an inter
action between aspect and defniteness in Slavic languages.
I start with progressives. There are two ways to mark progressives in
natural language. Most often, it is marked by verbal morphology, or by a
periphrastic verbal construction, as in Czech or English. Sometimes, it is
marked by some special prepositional or partitive case marking of an NP,
as in German or Finnish (cf. Moravcsik 1978 for the meaning of diferent
object markings in general and Heinamaki 1984 for the partitive objects in
Finnish) :
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 47
( 18) a. John snedl rybu.
b. John jedl rybu kdyz Mary vztoupila.
( 19) a. John ate a fsh.
b. John was eating a fsh (when Mary came in) .
(20) a. John aB einen Fisch.
b. John aB an einem Fisch (als Mary hereinkam) .
( 21) a. John soi kalan.
b. John soi kalaa (kun Mary tuli sisaan).
Progressivity normally is considered to be a verb-oriented category. How is
it possible, then, that it is marked on an argument of the verb? The theory
developed here provides an answer, because it predicts that a change of the
reference type of the nominal predicate will afect the temporal constitution
of the complete construction. This I want to show more precisely.
Although progressivity seems to elude a satisfing model-theoretic se
mantic description, it is clear since Bennett and Partee 1972 that some
notion of partiality is involved in it. As a frst approximation, which suf
fces for our purposes, we can consider a predicate like be drinking a glass
of wine a applying to events which are parts of events to which drink a
glass of wine applies. That is, progressivity is associated with the following
operator:
(22) PROG = APAe' 3e[P(e) 1 e' e]
On the other hand, one can assume that partitivity can be associated with
a similar operator (cf. Bach 1986) . For example, the partitive of 'fsh' can
be analyzed a referring to parts of a fsh.
(23) PART APAX' 3x[P(x) 1 x' x]
Although the partitive may be analyzed like this in languages as Finnish
which have a clear partitive cae marking, the German case probably ha
to be handled diferently because partitive objects like an einem Fisch
have a rather limited distribution. They should instead be analyzed as
prepositional objects governed by the verb. We have to assume a lexical
restructuring rule which takes verbs like (24a) with an accusative object
and a patient theta role and transforms them into verbs like (24b) with
a prepositional object and a "partitive" patient relation. The partitive
patient relation is related to the normal patient relation as in (24c) :
(24) a. essen S/NP[nom, ag] , NP[acc, pat]
b. essen S/NP[nom, ag] , NP[ an-obj, pan-pat]
c. 'e, x[ PART-PAT(e, x) 3x' [PAT(e, x' ) 1 x' x
l l
Now, consider the following two expressions, (25a) representing a verbal
progressive (English style, e.g. , be eating a fsh), and (25b) representing a
nominal progressive (Finnish or German style, e. g. , an einem Fisch essen) ,
with ( as verbal predicate ( eat) , 8 as nominal predicate ( a fsh) , and ( as
the specifc thematic relation.
48 / MANFRED KRIFKA
(25) a. <v -e
'
3e, x[a(e) A t
(x) A 8(e, x) A e
' I;
e]
b. <n -e3x, x' [a(e) A t
(x) A
8(e, x' ) A x' I; x]
We asume that 8 is gradual and unique for events. At least in German,
the progressive marking by prepositional phrase is possible only with verbs
like drink or write, marginally possible with read, but impossible with see
or pat:
(26) a. Hans schrieb/?la an einem Brief.
b.*Hans sah/streichelte an einer Katze.
Furthermore, the verbal predicate a should be divisive, that is, if it applies
to an event, it applies to every part of it as well. Even if this is not exactly
true, we can asume it in the general cae.
A fnal point is worth mentioning. In (25) , I used the general part
relation instead of the proper part relation. I think that this captures the
semantics of progressivity, but pragmatically one can infer from the use of
the progressive form, which is more complex than the corresponding simple
form, that the proper part relation holds. Therefore, we have to show that
<v is similar to <n using the proper part relation.
Proof: First I show that for all e, <v(e) <n (e). Let <v(e2) , then there
is an el with a(el ) and e2 L eb and an Xl with
t
(Xl ) and 8(el
'
Xl ) . Because
O is divisive, it holds that a(e2 ) . With mapping to objects, uniqueness for
objects and uniqueness for events, there is an X2 with X2 g Xl and 8(e2 , x2 ) .
But then <n(e2) holds, too. Secondly I show that for all e, <n (e) <v (e).
To do this, we have to make an additional asumption, namely that with
all nominal progressives, the whole object is eventually subjected to the
event (this means ignoring the problems of the imperfective paradox). Let
<n(e2 ) , then a(e2) holds, and there are X2 , Xl with 6(Xl ) , 8(e2 , x2 ) and
X2 L Xl . Now the additional asumption is that there is an el with a(el )
and 8(el , xl ) . Because of mapping t o events, there is an 3 with 8(e3, x2 )
and e3 I; el . Because of uniqueness of objects, X2 is the only X for which
8(e3, x) holds, and because of uniqueness of objects, e3 is the only e for
which 8(e, X2) holds, hence e3 e2 and ..e2 = el (because ..Xl X2) , and
therefore e2 e el . But then it holds that <v(e2 ) .
By this method, it can be explained how it i s that a marking on the
noun can serve to mark an essentially verbal category. Note that in Finnish
the partitive is used in many more caes; it serves to express the progres
sive even with nouns like read and buy, and it may be employed to mark
irresultative verbs, a e.g., to shoot and wound versus to shoot dead. This
can be explained by an analogical extension of this type of marking to
conceptually similar caes. The tertium comparationis of this extension is
that the expression with a partitive object denotes an event which is not
a complete a an event denoted by the corresponding expression with an
accusative object.
k
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 49
8 Perfective and Defniteness
Let us now look at defniteness in Slavic. We have seen how a nominal
predicate operator can have an efect that is similar to a verbal predicate
operator. As the transfer of reference properties works in both directions,
we should not be surprised to fnd the converse case as well, that is, a
verbal predicate operator afecting the meaning of a nominal predicate.
We observe this most clearly in Slavic languages. The observation and
data in this section are based on Wierzbicka 1968 for Polish and Filip 1985
for Czech.
As it is well known, Slavic languages mark perfective apect (or ak
tionsart; the diference does not matter here) , whereas they do not mark
defniteness of the NP. For example, the Czech NP vino can mean either
'wine' or 'the wine', hruska can mean either ' a pear' or 'the pear', and
hrusky can mean either ' pears' or 'the pears' .
(27) a. vno i. Ax[wine(x)]
ii. AX[X FU(wine) / wine(x)]
b. hruska i. Ax[pear(x, I)]
ii. AX[X FU(Axpear(x, 1)) / pear(x, 1)]
c. hrusky - Ax[pears(x)]
. AX[X FU(pears) / pears(x)]
I represent defnite NPs on the bais of a predicate P a predicates ap
plying to the fusion of all P-elements, given that the predicate P applies
to the fusion. For example, the wine will apply to the fusion of all wine
quantities (which is a wine quantity as well, a wine is cumulative). Sim
ilarly, the pears will apply to the fusion of all pears. And the pear will
apply to one pear if there is only one; otherwise, the fusion of the ob
jects which fall under the predicate (aJ pear would not fall under that
predicate.
According to this interpretation, hruska i s a quantized predicate in both
readings, wherea the two readings of vino and hrusky difer in their refer
ence type: in the defnite reading, they are quantized (as they have singular
reference), wherea in the indefnite reading, they are cumulative.
Now consider the following examples:
(28) a. Ota pil vino.
'Ota dran wine/?the wine' (imperfective)
b. Ota vypil vino.
' Ota drank the wine/*wine' (perfective)
(29) a. Jedl hruSku.
' He ate a pear/?the pear' (imperfective)
b. Snedl hrusku.
'He ate a pear/the pear' (perfective)
50 / MANFRED KRIFKA
(30) a. J edl hrusky.
'He ate pears/?the pears' (imperfective)
b. Snedl hrusky.
'He ate the pears/*pears' (perfective)
These data can be interpreted as follows: (28) and (30) show that aspect
marking can distinguish between the indefnite and the defnite reading of
mass nouns and bare plurals, as the perfective aspect is compatible only
with the defnite interpretation of the object. (29) shows that a verb in the
perfective aspect may have an indefnite object if this object is quantized.
Hence it is not defniteness, but quantization which is required by the
perfective aspect marking.
The data can be explained as follows: Let H assume that the perfective
operator has scope over the complex verbal predicate. One of its meaning
components is that the predicate it applies to is quantized. That is, at
leat part of the meaning of the perfective can be captured by the mod
ifer >P>e[P(e) / QUA(P)] . This follows fom the usual assumptions for
perfectivity which says that it conveys the meaning that an event is "com
pleted. " This makes sense only for events which are quantized (or have a
set terminal point), as events under a cumulative description have no set
terminal point and hence cannot be said to be completed.
If we assume the normal transfer properties for the object role of verbs
like eat and drink, then we see that only with a quantized object the
complex verbal predicate will be quantized as well. If the perfective as
pect forces a quantized interpretation of the complex verbal predicate, the
complex verbal predicate will again force a quantized interpretation of the
object NP. This means in the case of (28b) and (30b) the defnite interpre
tation of the object, as this is the ony quantized interpretation (note that
all singular predicates are quantized). In the case of (29b), we can assume
both the defnite and the indefnite interpretation, as the latter one will
also yield a quantized object.
In a similar way, the imperfective aspect may force a non-quantized
interpretation of the verbal predicate, which consequently enforces a non
quantized interpretation of the object NP. However, this requirement seems
to be much weaker.
Note that the treatment of the Slavic defniteness marking proposed
here is essentially compositional, although the phenomenon itself seems
not to be compositional at frst sight, as the interpretation of vino depends
on other constituents. It is simply that the unwelcome reading is excluded
by general principles, just as in rob the bank the unwelcome readings of
bank are excluded by the lexical meaning of rob.
It should be stressed here that perfectivity is not just an expression
of quantization. If it were just this, we could not explain why languages
typically use a variety of perfectivity markers, even for the same verb, with
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 51
slight meaning diferences. But quantization is at least a component of the
meaning of perfectivity. There seem to be interesting variations between
languages in what has been called "perfectivity." Singh ( 1991) , for example,
argues that perfectives in Hindi are not related to quantization, but to
atOInicity of the basic predicate.
9 Some Final Remarks
To summarize, I hope to have made it clear that a semantic representation
is feasible in which the intuitive similarities between the reference type of
noun phrases and the temporal constitution of verbal expressions is cap
tured in a simple way. I have shown how the reference type of a noun
phrase can afect the temporal constitution of a verbal expression and vice
versa. I have discussed the properties of thematic relations that allow this
transfer of reference properties. Finally, I have applied these insights to
explain the marking of progressives by the case of NPs, and the efects of
aspect to the defniteness of NPs.
In Krifa 1989, I have shown how the theory can be extended to cover
quantifcation and negation. Furthermore, I have explained why durative
adverbials like for an hour and time-span adverbials like in an hour se
lect for cumulative and quantized event predicates, respectively. In Krifa
1986, I also treated the infuence of locative and directional adverbials on
the temporal constitution of a complex verbal expression with examples
such as walk to the school in/
*
for an hour versus walk towards the school
*
in/for an hour. In Krifa ( 1990), I have shown how measure expressions
in nominal constituents can express a measure on events. For example,
the sentence '4000 ships passed through the lock last year' has a reading
in which it does not imply that there are 4000 ships that passed through
the lock, but that there were 4000 events of passing of a single ship. An
other area of application is the semantics of the frequentative aktionsart;
in many languages, it remains unspecifed whether a sentence with a fe
quentative predicate claims that there is more than one event or more than
one participant in an event, an ambiguity which can be rendered easily in
our semantic representation.
References
Austin, John. 1961. Tuth. In Philosophical Papers, 117-133. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bach, Emmon. 1986. The Algebra of Events. Linguistics and Philosophy 9: 5-16.
Bauerle, Rainer. 1979. Temporale Deixis, Temporale Frage. Tiibingen: Gunter
Narr.
Bennett, Michael, and Barbara Partee. 1972. Toward the Logic of Tense and
Aspect in English. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
Carlson, Gregory N. 1984. Thematic Roles and their Role in Semantic Interpre
tation. Linguistics 22:259-279.
52 I MANFRED KRIFKA
Davidson, David. 1967. The Logical Form of Action Sentences. In The Logic of
Decision and Action, ed. Nichola Rescher, 81-95. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh
University Press.
Dowty, David. 1979. Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Dowty, David. 1987. Events, Aspects, and NP Semantics. Paper presented at the
Conference on Logic and Linguistics, July 1987, Stanford University.
Dowty, David. 1989. On the Semantic Content of the Notion "Thematic Role" .
In Properties, Tpes and Meaning, Vol. 2: Semantic Issues, ed. Gennara
Chierchia, Barbara Partee, and Raymond Turner. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1978. Implication Reversal in a Natural Language. In Formal
Semantics and Pragmatics for Natural Language, ed. Fanz Guenthner and
S. J. Schmidt, 289-301. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Filip, Hana. 1985. Der Verbalaspekt und die Aktionsarten dargelegt am Beispiel
des Tschechischen. Master's thesis, Universitat Miinchen.
Fillmore, Charles. 1968. The Case for Cae. In Universals in Linguistic Theory,
ed. Emmon Bach and Robert T. Harms, 1-90. New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston.
Fancois, Jean. 1985. Aktionsart, Aspekt und Zeitkonstitution. In Handbuch
der Lexikologie, ed. Christopher Schwarze and Dieter Wunderlich, 229-249.
Kronberg: Athenaeum.
Garey, Howard B. 1957. Verbal Aspects in Fench. Language 33:91-1 10.
Gillon, Brendan S. 1987. The Readings of Plural Noun Phrases in English.
Linguistics and Philosophy 10: 199-220.
Gruber, Jefrey S. 1976. Lexical Structures in Syntax and Semantics. Amsterdam:
North Holland. Includes 1965 MIT PhD thesis, Studies in Lexical Relations;
reissued by Indiana University Linguistics Club (Bloomington, 1970).
Heinamaki, Orvokki. 1984. Aspect in Finnish. In Aspect Bound: A Voyage into
the Realm of Germanic, Slavonic and Finno- Ugrian Aspectology, ed. Casper
de Groot and Hannu Tommola, 153-178. Dordrecht: Foris.
Hinrichs, Erhard. 1985. A Compositional Semantics for Aktionsarten and NP
Reference in English. Doctoral dissertation, Ohio State University.
Hoepelman, Jakob. 1976. Mas Nouns and Aspects, or: Why We Can't Eat
Gingercake in an Hour. In Amsterdam Papers in Formal Grammar 1, ed.
Jeroen Groenendijk and Martin Stokhof, 132-154. Universiteit van Amster
dam. Centrale Interfaculteit.
Hoepelan, Jakob, and Christian Rohrer. 1980. On the Mas-Count Distinction
and the French Imparfait and Passe Simple. In Time, Tense, and Quantifers,
ed. Christian Rohrer. Tiibingen: Niemeyer.
Krifa, Manfred. 1986. Nominalreferenz und Zeitkonstitution. Zur Semantik von
Massentermen, Plurlteren und Aspektklassen. Doctoral dissertation, Uni
versitat Miinchen. Published 1989, Miinchen: Fink.
Krifa, Manfred. 1989. Nominal Reference, Temporal Constitution and Quan
tifcation in Event Semantics. In Semantics and Contextual Exressions, ed.
Renate Bartsch, Johan van Benthem, and Peter van Emde Boas, 75-115.
Foris: Dordrecht.
THEMATIC RELATIONS / 53
Krifa, Manfred. 1990. Four Thousand Ships Passed Through the Lock: Object
Induced Measure Functions on Events. Linguistics and Philosophy 13:487-
520.
Leisi, Ernst. 1953. Der Wortinhalt. Seine Struktur im Deutschen und Englischen.
Heidelberg: Quelle und Mayer.
Link, Godehard. 1983. The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A
Lattice-Theoretical Approach. In Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Lan
guage, ed. Rainer Bauerle, Christopher Schwarze, and Arnim von Stechow,
302-323. Berlin: Mouton.
Link, Godehard. 1987. Algebraic Semantics for Event Structures. In Proceedings
of the 6th Amsterdam Colloquium, ed. Jeroen Groenendijk, Martin Stokhof,
and Fank Veltman, 243-262. University of Amsterdam. Institute for Lan
guage, Logic, and Information.
L0nning, Jan Tore. 1987. Mas Terms and Quantifcation. Linguistics and
Philosophy 10: 1-52.
Moravcsik, Edith. 1978. On the Cae Marking of Objects. In Universals of Human
Languages, Vol. 4, ed. Joseph H. Greenberg, 249-289. Stanford University
Press.
Parsons, Terence. 1980. Modifiers and Quantifiers in Natural Language. Cana
dian Joural of Philosophy (Suppl) 4:29-60.
Platzack, Christer. 1979. The Semantic Interpretation of Aspect and Aktion
sarten: A Study of Interal Time Reference in Swedish. Dordrecht: Foris.
Quine, Willard V. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Scha, Rero. 1981. Distributive, Collective, and Cumulative Quantification. In
Formal Methods in the Study of Language, Vol. 2, ed. Jeroen Groenendijk,
Theo Janssen, and Martin Stokhof, 483-512. Amsterdam: Mathematisch
Centrum.
Singh, Mona. 1991. The Perfective Paradox, or: How to Eat a Cake and Have
It, Too. In Proceedings of the 1 7th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic
Society. University of California at Berkeley.
ter Meulen, Alice. 1984. Events, Quantities, and Individuals. In Varieties of For
mal Semantics, ed. Federick Landman and Frank Veltman, 259-280. Dor
drecht: Foris.
Vendler, Zeno. 1957. Verbs and Times. Philosophical Review 66: 143-160. (Also
in Vndler 1967, pp. 97-121. ).
Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Linguistics in Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Verkuyl, Henk J. 1972. On the Compositional Nature of the Aspects. Dordrecht:
Reidel.
Wierzbicka, Anna. 1967. On the Semantics of the Verbal Aspect in Polish. In To
Honor Roman Jakobson: Essays on the Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday,
Vol. 2, 2231-2249. Den Haag: Mouton.
h h
h h
Or, Or,
Morpholexical
Rule
Intrinsic Class
Morphosyntactic Rule
Defaults
SP. . . SP . . .
\ \
P' (^' ,^' ))
h h
h h
Or' ,Or')
Figure 1 Model of (Modifed) Mapping Theory
to those supplied by IC assignment: these operations can efect the fnal
GF assignments to arguments but cannot afect the lexical semantics or
consequent IC feature assignment of predicates: passive and locative in
version are two phenomena afected by morphosyntactic operations. These
operations will play no role in the present paper. In general, the bifurca
tion of lexical operations stipulated in a theory such as that proposed by
Zubizarreta ( 1987) follows naturally on the present account. The model of
mapping advanced here has the shape shown in Figure 1.
The immediately relevant information in this diagram concerns the
functions performed by morpholexical and morphosyntactic rules. Mor
pholexical rules manipulate semantic properties (SP) of arguments, i. e. ,
these are roughly the proto-role features of Dowty 1991. Arguments are
interpreted as hierarchically organized valence slots represented here as (.
Assemblages of semantic properties associated with arguments determine
the intrinsic (or, IC) feature assignments of arguments, i.e. , the values for
h. Morphosyntactic rules and defaults further determine the feature ma
trices of individual arguments, Le. , the values for 1, within the limits de
fned by monotonicity: this principle basically insures that the operations
responsible for complementing the IC features of arguments will neither
alter IC features nor align Ie features with incompatible and contradictory
features. The entire feature composition of arguments determines their GF
status: grammatical functions are not atomic, they are feature matrices.
The treatment of locative alternation phenomena as well as the well
known unaccusative efects exhibited by constraints on prenominal deverbal
adjectives, e. g. , the yellowed leaf vs. * the limped man, will be derived from
the operation of morpholexical rules. On the present account, locative al
ternation alters semantic information associated with lexical entries with
consequences for grammatical function realization, while de verbal adjective
formation appeals to the refexes of this information contained in lexical
entries: syntactic efects are attributed to manipulation of featural infor-
58 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
mation in lexical entries.4 The information accessed concerns the lexical
apect ( [TELIC] ) and the IC feature composition (specifcally, the [-0]
vs. [-r] status) of lexical entries. 5
The paper is organized as follows. Section 1 introduces the Hungarian
locative alternation constructions. Section 2 proposes a version of LFG
mapping theory appropriate for treating locative alternation phenomena
in terms of complex predicate formation. As will be seen, Hungarian loca
tive alternation constructions contain complex predicates consisting of a
Pre Verb (PV) and a verb stem: the relevance of PVs for establishing lex
ical aspect and for IC feature determination will be discussed. Section 3
examines constraints on pre nominal deverbal adjective formation in Hun
garian and explains the observed unaccusative efects associated with these
constraints in terms of the interaction between lexical aspect and the IC
feature composition of arguments motivated in Section 2.
2 Locative Alternation and Complex Predicates
Hungarian exhibits a productive means of predicate formation via prefx
at ion: a prefxal preverb
6
is juxtaposed to a verbal stem and-modulo the
(semantic class of the) preverb and the (semantic class of the) verb-the
combination results in an alteration of lexical meaning, changes in valence
and/or case government and/or changes in the GF status of arguments, as
contrasted with these properties of the simple verb stem. The constitutive
pieces of such morpho lexical compositions, i.e. , the prefxal preverb and
verbal stem, are separable under specifable syntactic conditions. 7
I turn now to a restricted domain of complex predicate formation,
namely, the domain of locative alternation. The Hungarian variants exhibit
all the characteristics of locative alternation constructions mentioned pre
viously: grammatical functions change, while the semantics of the variants
remains basically similar but difers along the so-called holistic dimension.
Consider the Hungarian constructions presented below. 8
4
The treatment of deep unaccusativity in Bresnan and Zaenen 1990 informs the present
speculations in this domain: they propose a way in which a monostratal thery with
rich lexical asumptions can accommodate the types of efects generally attributed to
underlying syntactic relations.
5
The present proposal parallels the position propounded in Zanen 1990 and was pro
posed in previous versions of the present paper. For the most, I will rely on Zaenen
'
s
formulations here.
6
1n Ackerman 1987 I distinguish between two basic types of PVs, specifically, those
which bear no synchronic syntactic relation to the verbal stem, i.e., prefixal preverbs,
and those that do bear some synchronic syntactic relation to the stem, i.e., argumen
tal preverbs interpretable a incorporated elements. For the most part this paper will
concentrate on prefxal preverbs.
'This syntactic behavior of ver bal prefxes explains the earlier reference to juxtaposition
rather than afxation.
B
lntransitive variants will be ignored in the present work although the basic analysis
proposed here extends without complication to them as well. The following abbreviations
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 59
(2) a. a paraszt (ra= )rakta a szenat
(3)
(4)
the peasant (onto)loaded-3sg/DEF the hay-ACC
a szekerre
the wagon-SUBL
The peasant loaded the hay onto the wagon.
b.*a paraszt (ra=)rakta a szekeret
the peasant (onto)loaded-3sg/DEF the wagon-ACC
szenaval
hay-INSTR
'The peasant loaded the wagon with hay. '
a. a parazt meg=rakta a szekeret
the peasant PERF-Ioaded-3sg/DEF the wagon-ACC
(szenaval)
(hay-INSTR)
'The peasant loaded the wagon (with hay) . '
b.*a paraszt meg=rakta a szenat
the peasant PERF-Ioaded-3sg/DEF the hay-ACC
a szekerre
the wagon-SUBL
'The peasant loaded the hay onto the wagon. '
a. a paraszt tele=rakta a szekeret
the peasant full-Ioaded-3sg/DEF the wagon-ACC
'The peasant loaded the wagon full with hay' .
b. * a paraszt tele=rakta a szenat
the peasant full-Ioaded-3sg/DEF the hay-ACC
a szekerre
the wagon-SUBL
'The peasant loaded the hay full onto the wagon' .
szenaval
hay-INSTR
In contrat to their English analogues, the Hungarian locative alternation
predicates are complex, i. e. , they consist of a Pre Verb (PV) and a verb stem.
The preceding sentences illustrate the types of complements permitted to
co-occur with three representative verb forms: (2) contains verb forms with
an optionally present directional preverb, (3) contains verb forms with the
Perfective preverb meg, and (4) contains verb forms with the Resultative
preverb tele.
The presence or absence of prefxes correlates with diferences in case
government and function assignment for nominal complements as well as
and conventions are employed in the Hungarian examples: ACC " accusative, SUBL =
sublative, INSTR = instrumental, DEL = delative, ABL " ablative, IN = inessive, PERF
" perfective, DEF = defnite conjugation, and '=' is employed a a juncture marker
between PV (preverbs) and verbal stems.
60 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
with aspectual diferences in the meaning associated with alternative pat
terns. In particular, wherea hay must be marked in the ACC and fnction
a the OBJ complement of the simple verb or complex verb with direc
tional prefx r 'onto' ) , it must bear INSTR marking and function as an
OBL when it co-occurs with complex predicates containing either the PERF
( meg) or resultative prefx ( tete ' full' ) . Conversely, wagon must appear
with a locational cae marker and fnction a an OBL with simple verbs or
complex predicates containing directional prefxes, while it must bear ACC
marking and function as an OBJ when it co-occurs with complex predicates
containing either a PERF or resultative prefx.
There is evident systematicity in the correlation of prefx, case-marking
and grammatical function: nominals fnctioning a loc arguments are al
ways marked with LOC cae and bear the OBL relation in conjunction
with directional preverbs, while these nominals are marked ACC and fnc
tion as an OBJ when they co-occur with PERF or resultative preverbs.
In a similar fahion, nominals functioning a th arguments are marked
with the ACC case and bear the OBJ relation when they co-occur with
directional preverbs, while these nominals are marked with the INSTR
cae and function as OBLs when they co-occur with PERF or resultative
preverbs.
It remains to be observed that the juxtaposition of pre verbs and verb
stems in Hungarian is traditionally asumed to alter the aspectual status
of the afected predicate. In particular, the presence of a preverb generally
confers perfective or completive aspect on the predicate. There are certain
preverbs such a meg which appear devoid of lexical semantic meaning and
seem to function almost exclusively a aspectual markers, while there are
other preverbs such a tele which simultaneously contribute lexical semantic
and apectual values to the predicate. For present purposes I will asume
that the presence of a preverb correlates with alteration of the lexical apect
of a predicate and that this is registered in the lexical entry for a predicate.
Following Zaenen 1990 I will assume that the preverb makes the afected
predicate [+TELICj .
Distribution of time adverbials
There is standard evidence which can be adduced for the claim that the
presence of a pre verb correlates with the aspect of a predicate. Follow
ing Vendler 1967 and Dowty 1979 (among others) there is a rich tradi
tion devoted to the interaction between predicates and temporal adjuncts.
Consider the tabular representation of predicate and adverb interactions
presented below:9
9It should be observed that Hungarian possesses a construction in which a directional
PV follows a verbal stem and conveys prgressivity. Example (5a) below reflects this
reading, e.g. raxta ra a szerat 'wa loading the hay onto'.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 61
(5) egy onin at egy ora alatt
' for an hour' 'in an hour'
a. rakta (ra) a szenat +
'loaded the hay'
b. ra=rakta a szenat +
'onto=loaded the hay'
c. tele=rakta a szekeret + .
' full-loaded wagon'
d. meg=rakta a szekeret +
'PERF-loaded wagon'
Fom the present perspective it is important to observe that the simple verb
stem (or verb stem with post posed directional prefx, cf. preceding footnote)
and prefxed verb stems display diferent co-occurrence options. The par
ticular correlation of adverbial and verb is signifcant for the present thesis:
prefxed verbal stems co-occur with an adverbial generally acknowledged to
correlate with perfective apect, while the simple stem (or, stem and post
posed directional prefx) co-occur with adverbials generally acknowledged
to correlate with progressive apect. IO
In summary, the assumption that prefxes are asociated with aspectu
ality is borne out in the co-occurrence constraints of time adverbials and
certain predicates. As previously mentioned, I will asume with Zaenen
( 1990) that the relevant apectual value is [+TELIC] : Dutch verbs contain
ing separable preverbs of direction are like Hungarian verbs in this respect.
Having seen the importance of pre verbs for determining lexical aspect, se
mantic interpretation of the variants and the grammatical function status
of arguments, it is necessary to investigate how complex predicate forma
tion should fgure in our theory of grammar.
3 A Version of Mapping Theory
In the version of mapping theory advanced here the slots representing the
valence of a predicate, i. e. , expediently expressed here in terms of thematic
role labels, are associated with Semantic Properties and these semantic
properties are partially determinative of the Grammatical Fnction status
of these arguments. All of this information is contained in lexical entries
a will be amply illustrated below.
The lexical mapping theory developed in Bresnan and Kanerva 1989
decomposes grammatical functions (GFs) into (sometimes underspecifed)
feature bundles. Two binary-valued features are postulated, namely, [o]
for Objective and [r] for (Semantically) Restricted and these feature bun-
l
O
Difrences betwen perfective vs. progressive apect will also be relevant in the dis
cussion of constraints on deverbaI adjective formation in Section 4.
62 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
dIes defne natural classes of functions. Both the feature composition of
GFs and the natural classes defned by these features are listed below.
l
1
Feature Composition of Grammatical Functions
SUBJ [-0] OBJ [-r] OBJe [+0] OBLe [-0]
[-r] [+0] [+r] [+r]
Natural Classes Defned by Features
[-r] SUBJ, OBJ [+r] OBLe , OBJe
[-0] SUBJ, OBLe
[+0] OBJ, OBJe
The basic question with respect to these features concerns the principles
which are responsible for associating them with the valence positions of a
predicate. One claim advanced in Bresnan and Kanerva is that a certain
class of features are determined by lexical semantic properties of the pred
icate. This is formulated by them in terms of Intrinsic Classifcation or IC
feature classifcation: certain features are assigned to arguments by virtue
of the thematic role of those arguments. This assignment is presented
below:
I (ntrinsic) C (lassifcation)
agent [-0] , patient/theme [-r] or [+0]12, other [-0]
3. 1 Partial Lexical Entries
In the present paper IC feature clasifcation will also be keyed to lexi
cal semantic properties of elements in the predicate's valence structure.
However, I will be assuming (along with Zaenen 1990) that thematic roles
are not atomic, but are rather abbreviations for constellations of semantic
properties as on the analysis of Dowty 1991. Dowty proposes that verb
meanings entail the existence of arguments defned schematically a con
stellations of a small set of recurring semantic properties. 13 The semantic
properties employed here follow those suggested by Dowty: 14
11 For the intuitive motivations underlying the postulation of these features see Bresnan
and Kanerva 1989.
1 2The optional asignment of [+0] to th is proposed for Chichewa double object con
structions in Alsina and Mchombo 1989. Since Hungarian does not contain double object
constructions this option will not play a role here.
1
3
Cf. Ladusaw and Dowty 1988 and Culicover 1989 for further discussion.
14The particular properties germane to the present discussion will be causally afected,
change of state and incremental theme so I will, for the most part, take no stand on the
precise repertoire of properties listed above. The delimitation of a reliable and explana
tory set of semantic properties, a Dowty acknowledges, is as fraught with vagueness a
the defense of particular collections of (atomic) thematic or semantic roles: in the present
paper I have nothing illuminating to say about these issues. For present purposes it is
sufcient to suggest that there is a natural partition of operations and that morpholex
ical operations a defned here are driven by lexicasemantic properties of predicates
irrespective of whether these be atomic thematic roles or features constitutive of such
arguments.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 63
Proto-Role Properties
Proto-Agent Proto-Patient
volition change of state
sentience incremental theme
causes event causally afected
movement stationary
referential possibly referential
On such a view, traditional thematic role labels are (misleading) abbre
viations for particular constellations of properties. That is, thematic roles
are interpretable as feature bundles. 1 5 On Dowty's account, the algorithm
for the grammatical function realization of feature ensembles is as follows:
Argument Selection Principle
The argument of a predicate having the greatest number of Proto
Agent properties entailed by the meaning of the predicate will, all else
being equal, be lexicalized as the subject of the predicate: the argu
ment having the greatest number of Proto-Patient properties will, all
else being equal, be lexicalized as the direct object of the predicate.
A corollary relevant to locative alternation, among other constructions con
taining OBL(ique) complements, is formulated as follows:
Corollary
With a three place predicate, the non-subject argument having a
greater number of entailed Proto-Patient properties will be lexical
ized as the direct object, the non-subject argument having fewer en
tailed Proto-Patient properties will be lexicalized as an oblique or
prepositional object . . .
In sum, the system of mapping proposed by Dowty directly associates an
unweighted inventory of semantic properties with specifc syntactic roles
via Argument Selection PrinciplesI6 and various corollaries.
On the present account, as in Zaenen 1990, I will be assuming that
(possibly weighted) constellations of properties determine the value for the
Intrinsic Classifcation feature of arguments: as will become clear below,
this means that semantic properties indirectly constrain the GF realization
of arguments.
The previous assumptions will yield partial lexical entries for predicates
as shown in Figure 2.
A constellation of semantic properties is associated with a valence po
sition, i. e. , B, and determines the values for the IC features, i. e. , h.
1
5
That the entities reified into role labels are organized into hierarchies will be asumed
in Section 3. 5 below.
1
6
Cf. Fillmore 1977a, 1977b and Gawron 1983 for discussion of SUBJ and OBJ selection
principles which are keyed to hierarchically arranged lexica-semantic features.
64 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
SP . . . SP . . .
\ \
P (, . . . ,)
L
Figure 2 Schematic Partial Lexical Entry
3. 2 Basic lexical entries: unmarked IC assignment
The principles for determining specifc Ie feature asignments for baic
or underived predicates, i. e. , for simple verb stems without PVs, roughly
follow those proposed by Zaenen (1990).
Principles of IC Feature Assignment
(1) The argument with the most or most heavily weighted proto-patient
properties is intrinsically clasifed a [-r] .
(2) The argument with the most or most heavily weighted proto-agent
properties is intrinsically clasifed a [-0] .
(3) All other arguments are intrinsically clasifed as [-0] .
These feature specifcation principles yield the following partial lexical en
try for the baic or underived predicate rk ' load' : the frst argument ha
a preponderance of proto-agent properties and is therefore asigned [-0],
the second argument ha a preponderance of proto-patient properties and is
therefore asigned [-r] , while the third argument has fewer of the preceding
properties or diferent properties and is therefore asigned [-0] P
(6) rak ( ag, th,
[-0] [-r]
loc)
[-0] Intrinsic Classifcation (Ie)
I will asume that the arguments expediently labelled a th and loc in
the preceding examples share the proto-patient property causally afected.
The proposed Ie feature asignment principles obtain, by hypothesis, for
basic predicates. The crucial characteristic of Hungarian locative alterna
tion predicates, however, is that they contain derived complex predicates.
As mentioned previously, the presence of a preverb correlates with the al
teration of inherent lexical apect and depending on the preverb and the
(clas of the) verb stem, with an alteration of the lexical semantics, cae
government and grammatical function asignment to arguments a well.
'' will employ thematic role labels for convenience, but they should be understood a
abbreviations of semantic properties in the same way that grammatical function names
should be considered a abbreviations for feature matrices.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS I 65
3.3 Complex lexical entries: marked IC assignment
I will asume that complex predicate formation with preverbs is a mor
pholexical operation. This means that the combination of a preverb and
verb stem can alter the lexical semantics of a basic predicate: this alter
ation is registered in the lexical entry of the complex predicate. Since
IC feature assignment is keyed to lexical semantic properties of predicates,
the application of such an operation can alter IC feature assignment. These
morpholexical operations are a way of relating predicates, i.e. , of account
ing for observed similarities, while also accounting for whatever diferences
they may display: the diferences are attributable to divergent inventories
of semantic properties and whatever refexes of these may be exhibited as
a function of diferent IC feature assignments. We have already seen that
the presence of a preverb alters lexical apect: the correlate of this will
be that the relevant complex predicate will be associated with the feature
[+TELICl . In addition, each preverb will confer certain other semantic
properties on arguments of the complex predicate. In general, morpholex
ical operation responsible for complex predicate formation will lead to a
marked IC feature assignment viz. the principles proposed for feature as
signment with basic predicates.
There are two marked feature assignments associated with preverbs
which are relevant for locative alternation. The preverbs will be divided
into two types. There are (uses of) preverbs which contribute a specifcation
of directionality to the action denoted by the verb stem: these PVs will be
subscripted with the diacritic [+dirl . This type i exemplifed by the PVs
r 'onto', be 'into', ki 'out of', etc. There are also (uses of) preverbs which
do not contribute any directional sense to the action denoted by the verb
stem. This type is exemplifed by the PVs meg PERF' and tele ' full'.
Whereas both types of preverb determine that the lexical aspect of the
complex predicate is [+TELIC] , each type yields a diferent distribution of
lexico-semantic properties to the arguments of the complex predicate.
3. 3. 1
PV
[+dirj
PV
[+dirj
S establish motional and topological constraints on the loe argument
of the complex predicate. The motional notions and topological constraints
are refected in the repertoire of surface case and post positions which can
be employed to encode the loe complement. These considerations become
evident with respect to locative alternation in the contrast between the
lexical entries for complex predicates baed on the verbal stem rak 'load'
when composed with either the directional preverb ki 'out of' or be 'into'.
Each of these PVs require their loe complement to be expressed by cases
or adpositions which encode certain features. For example, the PV ki re
quires its loe complement to be expressed by a morpheme which has the
features [-goal, +containmentl . 18 Two representative markers compati-
18
The cae features utilized here are intended to be heuristic: their theoretical status
66 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
ble with this requirement are the cae marker -b61 'from out of' and the
postposition al61 ' from under' . Similarly, the PV be constrains its loc com
plement to be expressed by any member of a set of morphemes which bear
the features [+goal, +containment] . Representative markers fom this set
are the case marker ba 'into' and the postposition ala 'to under' . The
presence of these PVs also determines the telicity value of the complex
predicate. The relevant lexical entries might be represented roughly as fol
lows, where the annotation for the function O
B
L is intended to convey the
requirement that this function must be encoded by markers that bear the
stated features:
ki=rak V ' unload' (ag, th, loc)
O
B
L
case
= O [-goal]
[+containment]
TELIC = +
be=rak V 'into load' (ag, th, loc)
O
B
L
case
= O [+goaIJ
[-containment
TELIC = +
In summary, PV
[+
dir
]
's alter the lexical aspect of a predicate and specif
the motional and topological features of loc arguments. This results in a
complex predicate with a lexical entry that contains the aspectual feature
[+TELIC1. The lexical entry for the complex predicate will difer minimally
from that for the basic or simple predicate: whereas the former will contain
a negative telicity feature value, the latter will have a positive value for this
feature. The partial representation of ni-rk 'onto-load' is presented below:
r1-rak V 'onto-load' ( ag, th, loc)
[-oj [-r] [+r]
TELIC = +
3.
4 PV[-dir]
I will assume here that PV
[
-
d
i
r
]
S correlate both with the association of
[+TELIC] and with a distribution of semantic properties among argu
ments. The resultative or purely aspectual [-dir] preverbs associate the
property chang
e of state with an argument containing the feature causally
afected which is associated with [-0] in basic predicates. The argument
now exhibiting a preponderance of proto-patient properties will be assigned
the [-r
J
IC feature value, while the argument with fewer (or less heavily
weighted) proto-patient values will receive [-0] .
The motivation for assigning [-oj to the th is based on three interrelated
is both arguable and irrelevant to the point at issue. [+goal] is intended to designate
centripetal or aferent motion, [-goal] designates centrifugal or eferent motion, [+con
tainment] designates that the location is construable U denoting a bounded space with
an interior.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS J 67
considerations: ( 1) [-0] is the feature assignment which follows fom the
principles of IC feature assignment presented previously, (2) Hungarian is a
language whose predicates can only have a single [-r] intrinsically classifed
argument (following the parametric diference between languages proposed
in Alsina and Mchombo 1989, and (3) the assignment of [-0] avoids a
violation of the constraint against multiple [-r] IC arguments, while yield
ing the correct function assignments for both transitive and intransitive19
variants of the locative alternation predicates.
In the predicates at issue, these assignments mean that the argument
which is roughly correlative with the loc role will receive [-r] , while the
argument roughly correlative with the th will receive [-0] . The PV
dir
also
determines the telicity value for the complex predicate as +. The resulting
partial lexical entry is presented below.
meg-rak V 'onto-load' ( ag, th, loc)
[-0] [-0] [-r]
TELIC +
3. 5 Full Lexical Entries
Since grammatical fnctions, on the present interpretation, are tiered fea
ture bundles, there must be additional ways to complement the IC feature
composition of arguments. Within mapping theory there are essentially
two ways to do this: there are morphosyntactic operations such as pas
sive which determine the argument inventory which will be syntactically
expressed and there are default asignments of features which are depen
dent on the IC features of arguments. These alternative ways of asigning
features are presented below:
Morphosyntactic Operations
e.g., Passive 0)
I
o i. e. , suppress the highest argument
The efect of passive is to "suppress" the highest argument (cf. below) .
This means that this argument will not be expressed syntactically. The
suppression of this argument would lead to the ostensible th playing the
role of SUBJ, given the well-formedness conditions stated below.
The basic default asignments are presented below:
Defaults (a) Subject default 0
|
[-r]
(b) Elsewhere default (
I
[+r]
19Though \ignore here the treatment of intransitive variants of this construction, there
is one apect of their analysis with respect to the alignment of th with [-oj which will
be addressed after the presentation of default asignments below.
68 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
These defaults function as instruction to associate arguments with par
ticular features. The arguments are organized in terms of a hierarchy. In
particular, the argument with the most proto-agent properties is higher
than the argument with the most proto-patient properties. Other argu
ments are arrayed within a hierarchy such a that presented below. The
hierarchy can be stated in terms of thematic role labels:
Argument hierarchy (partial)
ag < exp < ben/goal < th/pat <
loc
The highest argument will be referred to as 0. The SUBJ default asociates
the highest argument with the feature [-r] , while the (b) default asso
ciates other arguments with [+r], as long a this doesn't conict with the
argument S IC feature asignment (cf. below for monotonicity) . This pro
cedure leaves the argument with [-r] IC underspecifed and therefore able
to assume either the SUBJ or OBJ function (cf. below for well-formedness
conditions) .
The assignment of features to complement IC features is constrained by
Monotonicity:
Monotonicity Constraint on Feature Assignment
Feature assignment is additive, i. e. , neither rules nor defaults can
alter feature assignments nor result in contradictory assignments of
features for arguments.
Once the assemblages of features have been determined, there are two well
formedness conditions on fnal lexical entries for predicates:
Well-formedness Conditions on Lexical Forms
(1) Functional Uniqueness: Every grammatical function and every func
tional feature must have a unique value.
(2) SUBJ condition: Every lexical form must contain a SUBJ function.
2
o
The manner in which features are associated with arguments and result in
asignments of GFs can be illustrated in the cae of the basic Hungarian
verb rk 'load' .
(7) rak (ag,
[-0]
[-r]
th,
[-r]
SUBJ SUBJ/OBJ
SUBJ OBJ
TELIC "
loc)
[-0]
[+r]
OBL
OBL
Intrinsic Classifcation (IC)
Default
Bi-Uniqueness Constraint
The verb rk 'load' is asociated with a thematic argument inventory con
sisting of an 0g, th and loco The arguments are associated with features
2
0
A lexical form is the lexical representation that results from the mapping of arguments
into grammatical functions. The SUBJ condition is possibly parametric: there may be
some languages for which it does not obtain.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 69
following the algorithm for semantic determination of IC feature assign
ment. Specifically, the ag argument is associated with a [-0] IC since it
exhibits the most proto-agent properties, the th argument is associated
with a [-r] IC since it contains the most proto-patient properties, while
the loe argument is associated with the IC [-0] since it is the remaining
argument in the argument structure. Since there are no (morphosyntac
tic) operations such as passive which apply here, the defaults then apply:
the SUBJ default requires that the highest argument is associated with the
feature [-r] , while the elsewhere default, states that all other arguments
are asociated with the feature [+r] as long as this assignment does not
violate the monotonicity contraint. In the case of 'load', the highest ar
gument is ag which is associated with [-r] , while the loe is associated with
the feature [+r] . The th cannot be associated with [+r] without violating
monotonicity, so it remains underspecifed. The object created by the as
signment of features to arguments, namely, a Lexical Form is constrained
to conform to the two well-formedness conditions (1) functional uniqueness
and (2) the SUBJ condition. The result of assigning features to ' load' is a
representation in which the ag is fully specifed and must appear as SUBJ,
the th is underspecifed and can, consequently, appear as either a SUBJ or
an OBJ, while the loe is fully specifed and must appear as an OBL. The
SUBJ condition, which obtains in Hungarian, applies and determines that
the th is OBJ. The fnal GF assignments are indicated in the text: 0g is
mapped into SUBJ, th mapped into OBJ and loe into OBL.
The assignment of features to the basic verb 'load' is straightforward:
ag receives [-0] IC, th the [-r] IC, and loc the [-0] IC, then defaults apply
fully specifying the ag with [-r] by the SUBJ default, and fully specifing
the loe with [+r] by the elsewhere default, and leaving the th underspecifed.
These assignments result in the ag as SUBJ, th as OBJ and loe as OBL.
In the present instance, as in all others, the interaction between in
trinsic classifcation, rules and default assignments lead to an increasing
specifcation of the features associated with semantic roles and this results
in GF realizations for arguments.
The lexical entries for complex predicates containing PVs are derived
in the following way. Since both tele and H6g are [ -dir] the loe argument
is associated with [-r] IC, while the th argument is associated with [-0]
IC. The ag argument receives the [-oj IC. The SUBJ default applies to the
ag assigning it [-r] , while the elsewhere default applies to the th argument
assigning it [+r] : the loe argument remains underspecifed. Since the ag
is fully specified as [-0] and [-r] it surfaces as the SUBJ. Likewise the
th is fully specifed as [ -0] and [+r] and therefore surfaces as an OBLo
The loe is underspecifed and in principle could assume either the SUBJ or
OBJ function. However, a violation of functional uniqueness would ensue
if the th appeared as a SUBJ, so it assumes the OBJ function. The entire
predicate is, of course, associated with the feature TELIC ~ +.
70 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
Composition of Complex Predicates
ra=rak ' onto-load' ( ag, th, loc )
[-0] [-r] [+r] IC
[ -r] [-0] Default
SUBJ OBJ OBL
TELIC = +
tele=rak 'full=load' ( ag, th, loc )
[-oj [ -oj [-rJ IC
[-r] [+r] Default
SUBJ OBLo OBJ
TELIC +
meg=rak 'PERF-load' ( ag, (th) , loc )
[-0] ( [-0] ) [-r] IC
[ -
r] ( [+r] ) Default
SUBJ (OBLo) OBJ
TELIC ~ +
The derivation is somewhat diferent for complex predicates containing
[+dir] PVs. The th argument in predicates containing a [+dir] PV is asso
ciated with [ -rJ , while the loc argument receives the [ -oj IC feature. After
the defaults have applied the ag i fully specifed as [-0] and [-rJ , the th is
underspecifed as [-rJ, and the loc is fully specifed as [ -0] and [+r]. These
feature specifcations, in conjunction with the well-formedness conditions,
result in GFs assignments whereby the ag is SUBJ, the th is OBJ and the
loc is an OBLo .
21
2
1 The atute reader may have calculated that the conventions for default feature assign
ment might lead to incorrect function asignments for intransitive locative alternation
predicates. The apparent problem can be illustrated with reference to the intransitive
locative alternation predicate tele=folyik 'full fow' which is associated with the following
argument structure and presumable IC feature assignments:
tele=folyik 'full fow (th, loc)'
[-oj [-r
J
The straightforward application of the SUBJECT and elsewhere defaults would asociate
[-rJ with the highest argument, e.g., th, while the loc argument would remain underspec
Hied. This would yield function asignments where the th would be the SUBJECT and
the loc would be the OBJECT: locative alternation, in this instance, would appear to
be a transitivizing operation. These are, unfortunately, the wrong asignments: the
intransitive locative alternation predicates remain intransitive with the th functioning
a an OBL and the loc functioning a the SUBJECT. This situation might be explained,
a suggested by an anonymous reader, if we follow the spirit of Bresnan and Zaenen's
attempt to yield an external versus internal argument distinction within lexical mapping
theory. If we asume that an external argument 0 must bear a preponderance of proto
agent properties, while arguments with a preponderance of proto-patient properties are
always internal irrespective of the IC features they bear, then the SUBJECT default can
be interpreted a an instruction to asociate an external argument with [-rJ . For the
cae at hand, the predicate tele=folyik 'full=fow' does not have an external argument,
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 71
In this section we have seen that the conventions for composing [dir]
PVs with predicates act in conjunction with various assumptions of map
ping theory to yield the correct assignment of GFs to arguments of transi
tive predicates. I turn now to an investigation of how this analysis interacts
with observed constraints on deverbal adjective formation.
4 Deverbal Adjective Formation
The morpho lexical relatedness analysis of locative alternation constructions
refers criterially to the efects of composing complex predicates in the lex
icon: this composition process determines the apectuality of predicates
in terms of the feature [+TELIC] as well a the distribution of semantic
properties determinative of IC feature assignment. In this fnal section I
will demonstrate that reference to these features (or more accurately, to
the properties they denote) is central for explaining otherwise puzzling
constraints on deverbal adjective formation in Hungarian. In the course
of this presentation I will argue that proposals baed on thematic roles,
grammatical fnction (surface or deep), or morphology, i.e. , the presence
or absence of PVs, are inadequate.
Consider the following examples of deverbal adjectives formed fom
locative alternation verbs:22
(8) a.
b.
a rarakott
the onto-loaded
a telerakott
the full-loaded
,
/*
k '
szenath
sze erloc
hay/wagon
k'
/*
'
sze erloc szenath
wagon/hay
The examination of restrictions on perfect adjective formation in English
have led to the hypothesis that there is a thematic constancy constraint
underlying a similar distribution of judgments in that language: 2
3
roughly,
a verb can be adjectivalized only if it contains a th( ere) in its argument
array. The th argument functions as the head (or externalized argument)
of the NP in which the derived attributive adjective appears. This proposal
ha been challenged in Levin and Rappaport 1986 where it is argued that
data such as:
(9) the stuf ed pillO
Wloc vs. *the stufed featherst
h
Le. , it's th argument is still internal despite its [-0] IC feature. The elsewhere default
applies to the th providing a [+r] feature and insuring that it assumes an OBL func
tion, while the lac argument must assume the SUBJECT function in order to satisfy the
SUBJECT condition. It can do this since it is the underspecifed argument asociated
with a [-r] IC. The proposal to distinguish betwen external and internal arguments
on the bais of semantic properties and independent, in some sense, of the IC features
borne by the relevant arguments leads to various empirical consequences for phenomena
other than locative alternation. I will not explore these consequences here.
22The prefixal preverb in these examples is italicized and the diacritic for juxtaposition,
i. e. , '=', ha been omitted since in these adjectival forms the prefix is not separable from
the nominal stem.
2
3
Cf. Wasow 1977, Bresnan 1982.
72 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
run afoul of the such a hypothesis: among other problems, certain loc ar
guments can inexplicably head nominals containing deverbal adjectives,
while certain th arguments inexplicably cannot. Levin and Rappaport
propose that this distribution can be explained by the Sole Complement
Generalization:
Sole Complement Generalization
An argument that may stand as a sole NP complement to a verb can
be externalized by APF (= Adjectival Passive Formation)
This generalization attempts to relate the observation that acceptable ad
jectival passive constructions correlate with acceptable clauses containing
a single internal argument. In other words, we fnd clauses of the following
sort correlative with the previously cited j udgments for adjectival passive
forms:
(10) Henry stufed the pillow/
oc vs. * Henry stufed the feathersth
Two questions arise with respect to this sort of explanation for the observed
judgments: ( 1) if such a generalization actually obtains then it represents
a mystery eaily a arresting a the constraint on deverbal adjectivalization
which it is supposed to explain, and (2) it is not clear how or whether this
sort of "explanation" can be extended to account for similar constraints in
languages with null complements, i.e. , languages in which the notion "sole
complement" is difcult to defne.
In the following discussion I will argue that featural distinctions pre
viously referred to in order to account for locative alternation predicates
are likewise crucial for the explanation of constraints on deverbal adjecti
valization in Hungarian. In efect, we will see that neither thematic con
stancy nor the sole complement constraint provide explanations for these
data: in particular, the thematic constancy proposal, arguably, founders
on data such a those presented by Levin and Rappaport ( 1986) while the
baic efects of the sole complement generalization as well as constraints
on adjective formation follow from a feat ural treatment of the relevant
data.
The. Hungarian constructions (8a) and (8b) conict with the thematic
constancy condition in much the same fashion as the English examples
cited above: the loc argument is head of the NP, while the th cannot be
the head of this NP. In Hungarian, unlike in English, complements of the
verb may be omitted in surface syntax:
( 1 1 ) a paraszt ra=rakta
the peasant onto=loaded-3sg/DEF
'The peaant loaded (something determinate) (somewhere
determinate) ' .
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 73
( 12) a paraszt tele=rakta
the peaant full=loaded-3sgjDEF
'The peaant full-loaded (something determinate) (with something
determinate) . '
Wherea the notion of sole complement is difcult to defne in such a lan
guage, the notion of argument asociated with a [-r] IC feature is quite
transparent. Specifcally, the complex verbs presented above have [-r] as
sociated with the th argument of verbs containing a directional prefxal
preverb and with the loc argument for complex verbs containing tete or
meg. In other words, appeal to the feature [-r] explains the present distri
bution of grammaticality judgments. This treatment can be formulated as
follows:
[-r] Condition on Adjectivalization (Preliminary)
A verb O a is related to an adjective f if the argument structure of
O a contains an argument annotated with [-r] .
This condition claims that the presence of [-r] constitutes a necessary
condition on deverbal adjectivalization in Hungarian. 24
Given the fact that the arguments associated with [-r] in the preceding
examples are realized a ACC marked complements, it might be claimed
that surface OBJ(ecthood (correlative with accusative marking in the
present instances) is the determinant of adjectivalization rather than the
presence of [-r] . The inadequacy of this line of speculation becomes appar
ent by examining two types of evidence. First of all, there are verbs which
govern the ACC cae for their OBJ complements but which cannot undergo
the relevant adjectivalization process. Examples of this sort suggest that
neither cae marking nor the surface relation OBJ provide sufcient condi
tions for the formulation of a constraint on adjective formation. Second,
there are some intransitive verbs whose nominative marked SUBJ argument
appears a the modifed head in an NP containing its deverbal adjectival
form.2
5
These examples suggest that surface OBJecthood is not a neces
sary condition on the formulation of a constraint on adjective formation. I
examine each of these caes in turn below.
There are numerous simple (Le. , unprefxed) transitive verbs which gov
ern the ACC cae for their OBJ th arguments. Consider the two represen
tative lexical entries below:
2
4We will se below that restrictions on perfect adjective formation for one of the in
transitive variants of the locative alternation predicates precludes a stronger formulation,
i.e., one in terms of both necessary and sufcient conditions.
2
5
This latter phenomenon, obviously, raises the question about unacusativity or un
derlying objecthood in Hungarian. We will see below that the presumable unaccusative
verbs in Hungarian are those that bear an apectual feature [+TELIC] and contain a
[-r] argument.
74 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
( 13) keszit 'to prepare' (ag, th)
[-0] [-r]
( 14) sargit 'to yellow' (ag, th)
[-0] [-r]
The account of deverbal adjective formation presented thus far predicts
that verbal forms such as these should undergo perfect adjectivalization:
they contain arguments which have a [-r] . The judgments associated with
the following constructions are therefore surprising.
( 15) *a keszitett ruha
the prepared clothes
( 16) *a sargitott level
the yellowed leaf
The presence of [-r] in the lexical entries for these predicates make it
mysterious why such forms are prohibited. However, it turns out that
predicates related to those presented above can participate in adjective
formation of the relevant sort. Consider the following partial lexical entries
and nominal constructions in this regard:
( 17) el=keszit 'to prepare' (ag, th)
[-0] [-r]
(18) meg=sargit 'to yellow' (ag, th)
[-0] [-r]
( 19) az elkeszitett ruha
the PERF-prepared clothes
'the prepared clothes'
(20) a megsargitott level
the PERF-yellowed leaf
'the yellowed leaf'
In these constructions the [-dir] PV confers [+TELIC] lexical apect on
the complex predicate. In addition, the complex predicate contains an
argument with a [-r] IC feature. A revised version of the constraint on
adjective formation might be formulated a follows:
Condition on Adjectivalization (Revised)
A predicate L is related to an adjective 3if (i) the argument structure
of L contains an argument annotated with a [-r] IC feature and (ii)
the predicate bears the feature [+TELIC] .
The preceding discussion clearly demonstrates that a constraint on adjec
tive formation keyed to ACC case marking and/or the surface OBJ function
status of an argument alone is inadequate. The inadequacy of such a formu
lation becomes even more evident upon examining the behavior of certain
intransitive verbs with respect to perfect adjective formation.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 75
Consider the following partial lexical entries for the intransitive variants
of the transitive verbs presented in ( 1 7) and ( 18).
(21) a. kesziil 'to get prepared' (th)
b. el=kesziil
(22) a. sargul
b. meg=sargul
'to yellow' (th)
[-r]
(th)
[-r]
[-r]
(th)
[-r]
TELIC = +
TELIC = +
The revised analysis predicts that only adjectives based on the (b) vari
ants will be well-formed since only these forms contain both the aspec
tual feature [+TELIC] and an argument annotated with the [-r] IC fea
ture. The correctness of this prediction is exemplifed by the following
constructions.26
(23) a. *a kesziilt ruha
the prepared clothes
b. az elkesziilt ruha
the PERF-prepared clothes
'the prepared clothes'
(24) a. * a sargult level
the yellowed leaf
b. a megsargult level
the PERF-yellowed leaf
'the yellowed leaf'
The preceding distributions not only conform to the predictions of the
revised condition on adjective formation, but they illustrate clearly that
surface OBJecthood is not a determinant of candidacy for adjectivalization.
Some notion of "deep" or underlying OBJecthood would seem to be at issue:
such phenomena are ordinarily interpreted as indicative of unaccusativity.
2
6
It should be observed that there are other ways to save the ill-formed constructions
found in the text other than by providing simple verb stems with prefxes. In particular,
a observed in Laczk6 and Ackerman 1984 it is often possible to provide the simple verbal
stem with an adverbial; a balm keszilt ruha, 'the clothes prepared for a ball' (lit. the for
a ball prepared clothes) or, az e/sokent ftott fu, 'the boy who ran and came in frst' (lit.
'the frst run boy' ). In addition, there are certain constructions which are acceptable
without either prefxes or adverbials of the sort alluded to above. For example, ji stolt
hus 'smoked meat' and vagdalt hus 'ground meat' exemplif such constructions. These
forms raise questions which cannot be addressed here.
76 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
This is the nature of the analysis proposed by Rappaport and Levin (1988)
for somewhat similar distributions of data in English. The present analysis
yields the observed unaccusative efects by appealing to the presence of the
IC feature [-r] in the condition on adjective formation. Bresnan and Zaenen
(1990) argue for independent reasons that "deep" unaccusativity efects
can be captured by appealing to the IC feature [-r] . The present analysis
adduces the present distributions as further support for their proposal.
As on their analysis, there is no need in the present case to appeal to a
distinction between underlying vs. surface grammatical relations.
Given the determinative role attributed to aspectual considerations in
the analysis, one might ask whether aspectual considerations are relevant
for the other deverbal formations a well. The relevance of aspect becomes
clear when we see that forms such as kbziil and sargul can function as
progressive active adjectives, while their prefxed partner cannot: 27
(25) a. a keszillo ruha
the preparing clothes
' the clothes being prepared'
b. * az elkesziilo ruha
the PERF-preparing clothes
(26) a. a sargul6 level
the yellowing leaf
'the yellowing leaf'
b.*a megsargul6 level
the PERF-yellowing leaf
It is likely that constraints on the formation of deverbal adjectives such as
those listed above are keyed to aspectual properties of the base predicate.
For example, the base predicate arguably is asociated with the feature
[ -TELIC] . For present purposes it is sufcient to suggest that aspectual
properties of predicates are, at least partially, determinative of constraints
on word-formation.
In this section we have seen that constraints on perfect adjective for
mation rely on the joint presence of [+TELIC] and a [-r] IC feature: only
if these features are co-present is it possible to form perfect adjectives.
4. 1 Preverbs and Tansitivity
The preceding section argued for the inadequacy of IC feat ural information
alone to explain the observed constraints on adjective formation. Aspec
tual considerations appear to play a pivotal role. Since we have seen the
importance of aspectual information in constraining adjective formation it
2
7
The present examples illustrate the adjectives in their attributive use. These same ad
jectives can be employed predicatively with attendant progressive aspectuai distinctions,
e.g., a rha keszu/oben van 'the clothes are being prepared' (lit. the clothes in-preparing
are) vs. * a ruha meg=keszu/oben van.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPiOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 77
might well be asked whether aspectual information alone could explain the
relevant distributions. In the present section I investigate another class
of cases that contain complex predicates but which exhibit a restriction
on perfect adjective formation: perfect adjective formation is permitted
with complex predicates containing [-dir] PVs but prohibited with those
containing [ +dir] PVs: in both instances we are dealing with [+TELIC]
predicates but we find diferences in grammaticality along the line pre
dicted by the hypothesis that both apectual and IC feature information
play a central constraining role.
There are clusters of verbs in Hungarian where the PV
[-dir]
correlates
with a change in transitivity for an asociated verbal stem: the simple stem
or complex predicate with PV[+
dir
]
are intransitive, while the complex pred
icate containing a PV
[-di
r]
is transitive. These predicates generally denote
contrasts between activities vs. accomplishments/achievements following
the Vendler /Dowty typology of aspectual types. These pairs are exempli
fed by the constructions below:
(27) a. a paraszt (ni= )celzott a madarra
the peasant (at- )aimed-3sg the bird-SUBL
'The peasant aimed at the bird. '
b. * a paraszt (ra= ) celozta a madarat
the peasant (at-)aim-3sg/DEF the bird-ACC
c. a paraszt meg=celozta a madarat
the peasant PERF-aim-3sg/DEF the bird-ACC
'The peasant aimed at the bird. '
d.*a paraszt meg=celzott a madarra
the peasant PERF=aim-3sg the bird-SUBL
(28) a. a paraszt (ra= )nevetett a filra
the peasant (at-)laughed-3sg the boy-SUBL
'The peasant laughed at the boy.'
b. *a paraszt (ra= )nevette a flt
the peasant (at- )laughed-3sg/DEF the boy-ACC
c. a paraszt ki=nevette a filt
the peasant PERF=laughed-3sg/DEF the boy-ACC
'The peasant made fun of the boy. '
d. *a paraszt ki=nevetett a flira
the peasant PERF=laughed-3sg the boy-SUBL
The verbs in the preceding constructions yield the following distribution
with respect to perfect adjective formation:
(29) a.*a racelzott madar
the at-aimed bird
78 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
b. a megcelzott madar
the aimed bird
'the aimed at bird'
(30) a.*a ranevetett f
the at-laughed boy
b. a kinevetett fu
the PERF-laughed boy
'the made fun of boy'
This is precisely the expected scatter of grammaticality judgments, given a
condition which contains reference both to telicity and the Ie feature [-rJ.
It is not the distribution to be expected if reference to apectual properties
alone was a sufcient condition on adjectivalization. Consider the lexical
entries for the relevant verbs:
(31) (ra
[
+dir
)
=)celoz 'aim at' (ag, loc)
[-oj [-oj
(32)
(33)
(34)
meg
[
-dir)
=celoz
(ra
[+dir
)
= ) nevet
ki
f
-dir)
=nevet
'aim' (ag, loc)
[-oj [-rJ
' laugh at' (ag, loc)
[-oj [-oj
' make fun of' (ag, loc)
[-oj [-r
J
The argument inventories of the preceding verbs resemble the inventories
of locative alternation predicates with one crucial diference: they do not
contain a tho Recall the conventions for asociating features with arguments
of locative alternation predicates: [-dir
J PVs specif the association of
[-r] with loc, while for [ +dir] PVs [-r
J
is asociated with the th, i. e. , the
argument with most proto-patient properties. In the present instances,
these conventions will asSure that the loc arguments of (32) and (34) are
associated with [-rJ , while [-rJ will not be asociated with any argument
in (31) and (33) since these latter arguments are goals.
2
8
This contrats
with meg=celoz 'shoot down' and ki=nevet 'make fun of' : the prefxes
meg and ki determine the [-rJ Ie features for the original loc argument.
Since the argument structure of these verbs contain the requisite aspectual
and Ie feature specifcations they can serve as a base for perfect adjective
formation.
In summary, the analysis of the present data set suggests that a condi
tion relying on the mere presence of aspectual specifcations in complex
predicates is not sufcient to yield the observed constraints on perfect
adjective formation. Instead, the analysis proposed for locative alterna
tion constructions extends explanatorily into this domain. The empir-
2
8
Given our feature asignment conventions loe argument of the baic verb will asigned
a [-oj IC feature, while the variant with a PV [+dirJ will be asigned a [-oj IC feature.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 79
ical predictions of an analysis baed on the mere presence of preverbs
vs. an analysis baed on the presence of both aspect and a [-rJ IC fea
ture are further distinguished in the two classes of predicates examined
below.
4.2 Relatedness Between Manner of Motion and Change
of Location Predicates
Hungarian contains many intransitive verb clusters related by morpholexi
cal rule. In these complex predicates a [+dir] PV is composed with a verb
denoting motion. The preverb specifes the directionality of the motion and
sets constraints on the topological nature of a lac complement in the same
fahion a it does for locative alternation predicates. This phenomenon is
illustrated in the following constructions utilizing the manner of motion
predicate Jut 'run' .
(35) a. a paraszt futott a szobaban
the peaant ran the room-IN
'The peasant ran (around) in the room. '
b. a parazt be=ftott a szobaba/*szobab61
the peaant into-ran the room-ILL/*room-EL
'The peaant ran into the room.'
c. a parazt ki=futott a szobabOl/*szobaba
the peaant out-ran the room-EL/*room-ILL
'The peaant ran out of the room.'
The presumable lexical entries for these verbs are a follows:
(36)
(37)
(38)
fut 'run'
be
[+dir]
=ft
ki
[
+
dir]
=fut
(ag, (loc))
[-oj [-oj
'run-into'
'run-out'
(ag, locg
o
al)
[-oj [-oj
(ag, loc
source
)
[-oj [-oj
As in all previous instances, the directional preverb adds the apectual
feature [+TELICJ
to the lexical entry of the complex predicate. Both be
'into' and ki 'out of' are [+dir
J (in their use with the present class of motion
predicates) so that they correlate with the asignment of [-oj IC to their lac
arguments. The absence of [-rJ in the lexical entries of these predicates
predicts that they cannot serve as a base for perfect adjective formation.
Consider the following constructions containing the perfect adjective forms
baed on the predicate Jt 'run'.
(39) a.*a futott szoba
the run room
'the run-in room'
80 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
b. *a be-futott paraszt/szoba
the into-run room
'the peasant who ran in/the run-into room'
c. *a ki-futott paraszt/szoba
the out-run room
'the peasant who ran out/the run-out-of room'
As predicted, these prefxed manner of motion predicates cannot serve
a bases for perfect adjective formation. Once again, it is clear that the
presence of a preverb does not constitute a sufcient condition for the
application of deverbal perfect adjective formation.
The behavior of a fnal class of intransitive dyadic predicates likewise
suggests that the mere presence of a preverb is insufcient to license perfect
adjective formation. There are numerous unprefxed dyadic intransitive
verbs in Hungarian which govern an oblique cae for their OBL complement.
Their government pattern and GF selection requirements remain unaltered
when they compose with a [-dir] PV. This clas is exemplifed in the
following constructions containing the verb (meg=)art 'harm, hurt' which
governs the DAT case for its th argument.
(40) a. a nedvesseg (meg=) artott
the dampness (PERF= )damaged-3sg
'The dampness damaged the paper. '
b.* (meg)artott papir
'the damaged paper'
a papirnak
the paper-DAT
As can be seen, the mere presence of the [-dir] PV is insufcient to license
perfect adjective formation.
2
9
5 Conclusions
In this paper I have argued for a mapping theory which yields a natural
partitioning between operations which afect the lexical semantics of pred
icates, that i, Morpholexical vs. those which don't, that is, Morphosyn
tactic. I have argued that Hungarian locative alternation constitutes a
case of Morpholexical Relatedness. The clusters of predicates which par
ticipate in this alternation are created in the word formation component
of the grammar. The semantic properties which characterize the argu
ments asociated with these predicates are determinative of the Intrinsic
Classifcation features assigned to these arguments. The particular seman
tic properties conferred on arguments a well the value for the aspectual
feature [TELIC] , are correlative with the presence of directional uses of
Pre Verbs.
2
91 will not speculate here about the relation between lexical semantics, IC feature
asignment and invariant cae government with these predicates. It is not to clear
at this time whether the interaction between these phenomena is principled or simply
idiosyncratic.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 81
Finally, the basic ingredients for the thesis of morpho lexical relatedness
between locative alternation predicates is extended explanatorily to the
treatment of constraints on perfect adjective formation in Hungarian. In
particular, the independently required necessity to refer to telicity values
of predicates as well as the specifc way in which PV types help deter
mine IC feature values for arguments appears to be required for explaining
observed constraints on deverbal adjective formation. This reliance is en
coded in the proposed condition on adjectivalization. In sum, this analysis
relies on the interaction between semantic properties of arguments, aspec
tual values of predicates and the feature decomposition of grammatical
functions.
References
Abraham, Werner, and Sjaak de Meij . 1986. Topic, Focus, and Confgurationality.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Ackerman, Farrell. 1987. Miscreant Morphemes: Phrasal Predicates in Ugric.
Doctoral dissertation, University of California at Berkeley.
Ackerman, Farrell. 1990. Locative Alternation vs. Locative Inversion. In Pro
ceedings of the 9th Annual West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed.
Aaron L. Halpern. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Ackerman, Farrell, and Andras K6mlosy. 1987. Relatedness in Hungarian
Spray /Load Verb Clusters. Presented at LSA Lexical Semantics Workshop,
Stanford University.
Alsina, Alex, and Sam Mchombo. 1989. Object Asymmetries in Chichewa.
Manuscript, Stanford University and University of California at Berkeley.
Anderson, Stephen R. 1971. On the Roles of Deep Structure in Semantic Inter
pretations. Foundations of Language 6: 197-219.
Anderson, Stephen R. 1977. Comments on the paper by Wasow. In Formal
Syntax, ed. Peter Culicover, Thomas Wasow, and Adrian Akmajian, 361-
378. New York: Academic Press.
Brassai, Samuel. 1860, 1863-65. The Hungarian Sentence. Magyar Akademiai
E
rtesito. 1 :279-399, 3: 3-128, 173-409 (in Hungarian).
Bresnan, Joan. 1982. Control and Complementation. In The Mental Represen
tation of Grammatical Relations, ed. Joan Bresnan. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT
Press.
Bresnan, Joan, and Jonni M. Kanerva. 1989. Locative Inversion in Chichewa: A
Cae Study of Factorization in Grammar. Linguistic Inquiry 20: 1-50.
Bresnan, Joan, and Lioba Moshi. 1989. Applicative Constructions in Ki-Chaga.
Manuscript, Stanford University and University of Georgia.
Bresnan, Joan, and Annie Zaenen. 1990. Deep Unaccusativity in LFG. In Gram
matical Relations: A Cross- Theoretical Perspective, ed. Katarzyna Dziwirek,
Patrick Farrell, and Errapel Mejia-Bikandi, 45-57. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
82 / FARRELL ACKERMAN
Channon, Robert. 1980. On Place Advancements in English and Russian. In
Morphosyntax in Slavic, ed. Catherine V. Chvany and Richard D. Brecht.
Columbus: Slavica Publishers.
Culicover, Peter. 1989. On Thematic Relations. MIT Working Papers in Linguis
tics 10. Massachusetts Institute of Technology: Department of Linguistics.
Dowty, David. 1979. Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Dowty, David. 1989. On the Semantic Content of the Notion "Thematic Role" .
In Properties, Types and Meaning, Vol. 2: Semantic Issues, ed. Gennara
Chierchia, Barbara Partee, and Raymond TUrner. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic Proto-Roles and Argument Selection. Language
67(3): 547-619.
Fillmore, Charles. 1968. The Case for Case. In Universals in Linguistic Theory,
ed. Emmon Bach and Robert T. Harms, 1-90. New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston.
Fillmore, Charles. 1977a. Topics in Lexical Semantics. In Current Issues in
Linguistic Theory, ed. Roger W. Cole. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
Fillmore, Charles J. 1977b. The Case for Case Re-opened. In Syntax and Se
mantics, Volume 8, ed. Peter Cole. New York: Academic Press.
Foley, William, and Robert Van Valin. 1984. Functional Syntax and Universal
Grammar. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fkui, Naoki, Shigeru Miyagawa, and Carol Tenny. 1985. Verb Clases in English
and Japanese: A Case Study in the Interaction of Syntax, Morphology and
Semantics. Lexicon Project Working Papers 3. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Center for Cognitive Science.
Gawron, J. Mark. 1983. Lexical Semantics and the Semantics of Complementa
tion. Doctoral dissertation, University of California at Berkeley. Also appear
ing in Garland Outstanding Dissertations in Linguistics, 1989.
Gawron, J. Mark. 1986. Valence Structure Preservation and Demotion. In Papers
from the 22nd Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. University
of Chicago.
Jackendof, Ray. 1983. Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, Mas. : MIT Press.
Jackendof, Ray. 1985. Multiple Subcategorization and the 8-criterion. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 3(3): 271-295.
Jazay, Laszlo, and Laszlo TOth. 1987. Az orosz igeaspekusr61 magyar szemmel.
Budapest: Tnkonykiado.
Kiefer, Ferenc. 1982. The Aspectual System of Hungarian. In Hungarian Lin
guistics, ed. Ferenc Kiefer. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Kiss, Katalin E. 1987. Confgurationality in Hungarian. Budapest: Academic
Press and D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Laczko, Tibor, and Farrell Ackerman. 1 984. Nominal Passives and Thematic
Roles. Manuscript, Hungarian Academy of Sciences, Budapest.
Laczko, Tibor, and Anna Szabolcsi. 1988. A fnovi csoport szerkezete (The Struc
ture of Noun Phrases). In Magyar mondattan, ed. Ferenc Kiefer. Akademiai
Kiado.
COMPLEX PREDICATES AND MORPHOLEXICAL RELATEDNESS / 83
Ladusaw, William, and David Dowty. 1988. Toward a Nongrammatical Account
of Thematic Roles. In Syntax and Semantics: Thematic Relations, ed. Wendy
Wilkins, 61-73. New York: Academic Press.
Levin, Beth, and Maika Rappaport. 1986. The Formation of Adjectival Pasives.
Linguistic Inquiry 17:623-661 .
.
Levin, Lori. 1986. Operations on Lexical Forms. Doctoral dissertation, Mas
sachusetts Institute of Technology.
Pinker, Steven. 1989. Learability and Cognition: the Acquisition of Argument
Structure. Cambridge, Mas.: MIT Press.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1987. Information-Based Syntax and Semantics,
Vol. I: Fundamentals. CSLI Lecture Notes No. 13. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
Rappaport, Maika, and Beth Levin. 1988. What to Do with Thematic Roles. In
Syntax and Semantics: Thematic Relations, ed. Wendy Wilkins. New York:
Academic Press.
Salkof, Morris. 1983. Bees are Swarming in the Garden. Language 59: 288-346.
Simpson, Jane. 1983. Aspects of Warlpiri Morhology and Syntax. Doctoral
dissertation, Masachusetts Institute of Technology.
Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Linguistics in Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Wasow, Thoma. 1977. Tansformations and the Lexicon. In Formal Syntax, ed.
Peter Culicover, Thomas Waow, and Adrian Akmajian. New York: Aca
demic Press.
Waow, Thoma. 1981 . Major and Minor Rules in Lexical Grammar. In Lexical
Grammar, ed. Teun Hoekstra et al. Dordrecht: Foris.
Zaenen, Annie. 1990. Unaccusativity in Dutch: an Integrated Approach. In
Semantics and the Lexicon, ed. James Pustejovsky. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Zubizaretta, Maria-Luisa. 1987. Levels of Representation in the Lexicon and
Syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.
4
On Obviation
DONKA F. FARKAS
1 Introduction
This paper addresses the question of why, in many languages, the subject of
certain subordinate clauses must be disjoint in reference from certain NPs
in the immediately higher clause, as illustrated by the following French
example.
( 1) Pierrei veut qu'il.i
/
j parte.
P. wants that he leave.SUBJ(unctive)
In what follows, the complements whose subjects obey this restriction will
be called obviative.
This problem has been discussed in recent Government and Binding
literature especially in connection with Romance languages (see Picallo
1984, 1985; Meireles and Raposo 1983; Kempchinsky 1985; Bouchard 1982,
1983; among others) . Common to all these works is the attempt to account
for obviative complements within Binding Theory (BT) . In Section 2 I
will review previous solutions and then argue that the BT approach is
empirically inadequate. In Section 3 I will propose a new treatment, one
in which the restriction on the interpretation of the subject pronoun in
,1 ) appears as a consequence rather than as a cause. The solution I will
argue for rests on Kiparsky's notion of blocking applied in the realm of
subcategorization, as well as on lexico-semantic considerations involving
the semantic relations that obtain between the arguments of a verb in virtue
of its meaning. Under the analysis presented in Section 3 the phenomenon
of obviation is crucially connected to control.
I wish to thank Larry Horn, Nirit Kadmon, John Goldsmith, Nicolas Ruwet, and Draga
Zec for useful comments and criticisms of earlier drafts. Earlier versions of this paper
were presented at Stanford University, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Yale
University, and at the 1988 winter LSA meeting.
Lexical Matters. Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabolcsi, eds.
Copyright 1992, Stanford University.
86 / DONKA F. FARKAS
2 Previous solutions
2.1 The Pragmatic Approach
The simplest possible way of disposing of the problem illustrated in ( 1)
would be to invoke the Chomskian "avoid pronoun" commandment (or the
more general Gricean "be as concise a possible" maxim) , given that the
infnitive is used instead of the subjunctive in examples like ( 1 ) in Fench,
as well a in Spanish, Catalan and Portuguese. (Throughout this paper I
will use Fench for illustrative purposes. )
(2) Pierre veut partir.
P. wants to leave
As noted by Picallo ( 1985) , the immediate problem with a simple-minded
"avoid pronoun" approach is that the infnitive does not always block the
use of a fnite form in these languages. The verb promettre 'to promise' ,
for instance, may take both infnitive and indicative complements:
(3)
{ qu'ili
/
j part ira.
Pierrei
promis
that he
f
j will leave.
Pi proI
l
sed
de partIr.
Prep. leave.INF
Since in Romance languages all obviative complements are in the subjunc
tive, one could dispute the relevance of (3) by claiming that the efect of the
"avoid pronoun" commandment is somehow restricted to subjunctive com
plements. As shown in (4), however, there are subjunctive complements
which are nonobviative although an infnitive alternant is possible as well:
(4)
a.
{qU'ili s'en aille.
J' ai propose i Jeani
that hei leave.SUB
I have su
ggested to J'i
de s'en aller.
Prep. leave.INF
b.
{que je n'aie pas pu te voir.
Je regrette
that I not have.SUBJ been able to see you
I regret
de ne pas avoir pu te voir.
Prep. not have.INF been able to see you
I will nonetheless argue below that the ungrammaticality of ( 1 ) is indeed
connected to the grammaticality of ( 2) ; the correct solution has to account
both for this connection and for the data in (3) and (4). (A more complex
"avoid pronoun" solution will be discussed below. )
Finally, note that, although (5b) i s slightly worse than (5a),
(5) a. * Je veux que je parte.
I want that I leave. SUB
b.*Ili veut qu'ili parte.
Hei wants that hei leave. SUB
ON OBVIATION / 87
one cannot explain the problem away by invoking the Gricean "avoid am
biguity" maxim either, since there is no danger of ambiguity in (5a).
2. 2 The BT Approach
Researchers working in the GB famework have been exploring the attrac
tive possibility of assimilating the phenomenon illustrated in ( 1) to the
well-known case in (6) , covered by principle B of Binding Theory, which
forbids a pronominal fom selecting an antecedent within its binding do
main.
(6) * Johni saw himi .
In order to implement this idea, one has to analyze obviative subjunctive
clauses as not constituting a binding domain as far a their subjects are
concerned. Since obviative clauses in Romance languages are a subset of
subjunctive complements, one ha to fnd some special characteristic of
this subset which distinguishes its members from nonobviative subjunctive
complements as well as from indicative ones, and the boundaries of binding
domains have to be made sensitive to this characteristic. If the analysis is
correct, the characteristic in question should be connected to obviation in
other languages as well.
PicaBo (1984, 1985) , Meireles and Raposo ( 1983) , and Salamanca ( 1981 )
suggest that the distinctive feature of obviative clauses is located i n the
Tense component of their I(nfection) node. (AGR, the other component of
I cannot be responsible for obviation because its properties are the same
for all subjunctive clauses, and therefore it cannot be used to isolate any
subset thereof. ) The main idea behind all of these proposals i that the
Tense of obviative clauses is somehow dependent on the Tense feature of
the immediately higher clause, and it is this dependency that the defnition
of binding domains is sensitive to.
In order for any solution based on this idea to work, the set of obvia
tive clauses must turn out to be coextensive with the set of clauses whose
Tense is dependent. Suner and Padilla-Rivera ( 1984) and Zaring (1985,
chap. II) , convincingly argue that there is no notion of "dependent" Tense
which isolates the right class of clauses for Spanish, Fench, and Brazilian
Portuguese. Sequence of tense restrictions, for instance, hold not only in
obviative clauses but also in some nonobviative subjunctive clauses and
in certain indicatives. Strengthening the requirement to subsequent time
reference does not work for the same reason. Both complement clauses in
(7) have subsequent time reference and yet they are nonobviative.
(7) a. Mariei promet a Paul qu'ellei partira tot.
M' i promises P. that shei will leave soon
b. J'ai propose au professeur que je fasse l'experience moi-meme.
I proposed to the professor that I perform. SUB the experiment
myself.
88 / DONKA F. FARKAS
The independently detectable properties of Tense in obviative clauses in
Romance languages do not distinguish them fom nonobviative ones and
therefore obviation cannot be a consequence of any of these properties.
Before abandoning this approach I will discuss two further empirical
challenges to it. The frst comes fom Romanian, where subjunctive clauses
have semantic and morphological properties similar to those in other Ro
mance languages (except for the fact that the subjunctive is used in a wider
range of complements, a point we will return to below). Crucially, however,
subjunctive clauses are not obviative:
(8) Ion; vrea [ei
/
j sa pIece] .
Ioni wants [Proi
/
j SUBJ leave]
(The 'e' above marks the dropped pronominal subject. )
l
Now the Romanian facts come as a complete surprise under any BT ap
proach relying on Tense because there is no independently justifed reason
for treating Tense in (8) as essentially diferent fom the Tense in ( 1) .
The next problem i s brought up in Ruwet 1984, where it is noted that
the strength of obviation in Fench depends on the semantics of both the
matrix and the obviative clauses. The relevant generalization is that obvi
ation is weakened if the degree of "agentivity" of the subordinate or main
clause subject decreases:
(9) a. Je veux que je puisse partir.
I want that I can. SUB leave
b. Je veux que je sois autorise a partir tot.
I want that I be.SUB authorized Prep. leave early
c. Je veux que je guerisse aussi vite que possible.
I want that I recover. SUB as soon as possible
d. Je voudrais bien que je parte tot.
I would like it well that I leave.SUB early
of agentivity is the same as the notion of responsibility, (RESP) , which,
as argued in Farkas 1988, is involved in controller choice with verbs like
promise and persuade. Following Farkas 1988, I will asume that the RESP
relation obtains between an individual and a situation if the individual
brings the situation about. The sentences in (9a)-(9c) difer fom ( 1) in
that the embedded subject is understood as not being responsible over the
situation denoted by the complement. The switch to the conditional and
the addition of the adverb in (9d) afect the responsibility of the matrix
IThe fact that an overt pronoun is not possible in (8) under the coreferential reading
is not specifc to subjunctive clauses:
(i) Ioni tie ca ei
j j
/el
j
f
*i e detept.
Ion knows that he is clever.
The problem of obviation U defned above is connected to the alternation between null
and overt pronouns but the two issues are distinct and I will not deal with the latter
here. For discussion, see Montalbetti 1984 and Levinson 1987.
ON OBVIATION / 89
subject over the complement situation. Thus, one would say (9d) rather
than ( 1) just in case it is not up to the speaker whether he leaves or not.
Ruwet notes that, while judgments difer with respect to the acceptability
of examples like those in (9) , they are all signifcantly better than ( 1 ) .
He further notes that by removing responsibility from both subjects, one
arrives at practically perfect sentences, like the example in ( 10) .
( 10) Je voudrais bien que je puisse partir des aujourd'hui.
I would like well that I can. SUB leave aleady today
Ruwet's data are incompatible with any solution based on Tense since there
is no plausible way of making the contents of the Tense of the embedded
clause depend on the factors discussed above. As Ruwet correctly argues,
these data cannot be handled by any purely confgurational account.
An altogether diferent BT solution is proposed in Kempchinsky 1985.
She assumes that subjunctive clauses contain a subjunctive operator which
moves to their COMP at LF just in case the matrix verb subcategorizes for
the subjunctive clause. In Spanish or Fench this means that the whole
I node moves to COMPo As a result, the embedded clause is no longer a
binding domain for its subject (because it no longer contains a governor of
the subject) . Kempchinsky notes that the Romanian data are explained
under the assumption that the subjunctive operator in this language is not
under I and therefore its movement to COMP does not afect the binding
domain of the subject, which is governed by I .
The crucial ingredient of this analysis is the movement of the subjunc
tive operator to COMP at LF. This movement is supposed to be trig
gered by the fact that subcategorization requirements must be met at LF
and therefore, if a verb subcategorizes for a subjunctive complement, the
head of the complement must fulfll the subcategorization requirement.
Assuming that COMP is the head of S' , this means that the COMP of sub
categorized subjunctive complements must contain a subjunctive element
at LF.
The main shortcoming of this solution is that it incorrectly predicts
that the class of obviative complements is coextensive with the class of sub
categorized subjunctive complements in languages like Spanish or French.
There are, however, plenty of subcategorized subjunctive complements in
these languages which are nonobviative, such as the complements of neg
ative epistemic verbs ( nier 'deny' , douter 'doubt' ) or of factive-emotives
( tre heureux, 'be happy', regretter 'regret' ) . Note also that Ruwet's data
constitute just as much of a problem for this analysis as for the one dis
cussed previously. I therefore conclude that the BT solutions proposed
so far are inadequate because they fail to predict the class of obviative
complements in Romance languages and because they fail to account for
the role the semantic factors discussed by Ruwet play in obviation. These
shortcomings are shared by the pragmatic approach as well.
90 / DONKA F. FARKAS
Yet another approach is proposed in Bouchard 1982, 1983. Bouchard
takes obviation to be the manifestation of his own version of "avoid pro
noun," suggestively called the Elsewhere Principle. According to it, a pro
noun cannot be used in a position where an anaphor is possible, i. e. , in
a position where the pronoun will be interpreted as coreferential with an
NP that govern it.
2
Hermon ( 1985) , in discussing obviation in Imbabura
Quechua, proposes a version of Bouchard's Elsewhere Principle where the
presence or absence of [AGR] is the crucial factor in determining whether
PRO is an anaphor or a pronominal. In order to explain why only subjunc
tive clauses are obviative, Bouchard makes reference to the fact that both
subjunctives and infnitives have "unrealized tense" (see Bresnan 1972) . It
is not made clear, however, how and why this property comes to play a role
in obviation, and therefore there is no account of why promettre ' promise',
for instance, takes nonobviative complements, although their tense is also
unrealized.
Picallo (1985) correctly notes that Bouchard's solution fails to account
for the fact that in Fench, as well a in Catalan, obviation is BU(bject)
oriented, i. e. , its efect is weakened if the matrix argument involved is not
the Bu, a in (4a) or ( 1 1 ) :
( 1 1 ) ?Marie a convaincu Pauli qU'ili s'en aille. /de s'en aller.
M. ha convinced P' i that hei leave.SUBJ jPrep. leave.INF
Finally, note that this solution does not fare any better than the previ
ous ones with respect to the data discussed in Ruwet 1984. Hermon's ver
sion, if extended to Romance languages, would have the additional problem
of positing an abstract and unmotivated [AGR] diference between obviative
and nonobviative subjunctive clauses.
3 Towards a Solution
3. 1 Data To Be Accounted For
Below I will summarize the main facts discussed so far and bring in
some new data fom two non-Romance languages, Hungarian and Serbo
Croatian.
Within Romance
(i) We have seen above that in those Romance languages that have them,
obviative clauses are a subset of subjunctive complements. We therefore
have to account for the fact that indicative clauses are nonobviative (recall
the promettre 'promise' / vouloir 'want' contrast) . We also have to dis
tinguish obviative clauses fom nonobviative subjunctives (recall the nier
'deny' , regretter 'regret' jvouloir 'want' contrat a well as the data dis
cussed by Ruwet) .
2
For Bouchard PRO is an anaphor when referentially dependent on a governing NP and
a pronominal otherwise.
ON OBVIATION / 91
(ii) We also have to give an account of the diference between Roma
nian and the other Romance languages. Such an account should link the
non-existence of obviation to some other feature of Romanian, which dis
tinguishes it fom its better known Romance sisters.
(iii) Next, we have to account for the fact that obviation tends to be Su
oriented, Le. , the argument that the complement subject must be disjoint in
reference fom tends to be the matrix subject. Recall the contrast between
( 1 ) and (4a) or ( 11) . 3
(iv) Finally, one has to predict the locality of the phenomenon, i. e. , one
ha to predict that the two NPs that must be disjoint in reference are in
adjacent clauses:
( 12) Mariei souhaite que Jeannej veuille qu'ellei
/
*j parte.
Marie wishes that Jeanne want.SUBJ that she leave.SUBJ
Beyond Romance
The correct account of obviation for Romance languages should extend to
other languages a well. Below, we will consider the relevant data in Serbo
Croatian, which is a Balkan language, and Hungarian, which i neither
Balkan nor Romance.
In what follows, the complements of verbs like convince, try, or begin,
whose Su arguments are necessarily referentially dependent on a matrix NP,
will be called dependent Su clauses. The term accidental Su dependency
will be used for caes where the subject of a complement happens to be
referentially dependent on a matrix argument.
Hungarian
Hungarian ha both infnitive and subjunctive complements. The infnitive
i the only possible complement form in dependent Su clauses when the
controller is the matrix subject:
( 13)
{ elkezdett beszel-ni.
Janos
started talk-INF
J.
igyekszik kedves len-ni.
tries nice be-INF
When the controller is a non- Su, verbs subcategorize for either infnitive
or subjunctive complements:
( 14) a.
{ hogy ej
/
*i, *k men-jen vele.
Janosi
eggyozte Maritj ,
that (she) go-SUB with him.4
J. convInced M.
*men-ni vele.
go-INF with him
3
Subject orientation is only a tendency, rather than a clear cut phenomenon because
judgments concerning fnite clauses whose subjects are coreferential with a non-Stl ma
trix argument and which have an infnitive counterpart show considerable variation from
speaker to speaker and from verb to verb.
92 / DONKA F. FARKAS
b.
{ vasarol-ni.
Janos elkuldte Mariti
shopINF
J. sent M.
*hogy ei vasarol-jon. 5
that (she) shop-SUBJ
In cae of accidental Su dependency, the complement is either in the infni
tive or in the subjunctive and is obviative, i. e. , the subject of the subjunc
tive complement is disjoint in reference fom the matrix subject:
( 15) Janos moziba akar men-ni.
J. movie-into wants go-INF
Janosi azt akarja, hogy e.i
f
j moziba men-jen.
J.
it-ACC wants that (he/she) movies-into go-SUB
Not all subjunctive complements are obviative, however. The verb kovetel
'demand' , for instance, is like akar 'want' except that it takes only sub
j unctive complements. As shown in (16), its complement is nonobviative:
( 16)
{ k6veteli, hogy ei
f
j kapjon t6bb etelt.
Janosi
demands that (he/she) get-SUB more food
J.
*k6vetel kap-ni t6bb etelt.
demands get-INF more food
Obviation in Hungarian is infuenced by the following factors. First, in
certain contexts in which the whole complement is focused an otherwise
obviative clause becomes nonobviative:
( 1 7) Ha az-t akarod, hogy velunk gyere,
if that-ACC want that us-with come. SUBJ,
viselked-j szepen.
behave-SUBJ well
If you want to come with us, behave well.6
In this cae the demonstrative pronoun az-t 'that-ACC' , whose antecedent
is the clause, has to be used. The exact syntactic analysis of the construc
tion exemplifed above is immaterial for present purposes. What matters
is that this construction is not possible with infnitival complements:
4
Hungarian is a Su pro drop language too.
5
Examples like ( 14b) were brought to my attention by A. Szabolcsi. It is not clear,
however, that the relation between the infnitive and the direct object of the matrix
in ( 14b) is the same a in obligatory control caes but I will not pursue this issue any
further here. The subjunctive in ( 14b) is grammatical under an interpretation in which
the complement is understood a a purpose clause.
6
Thanks again to A. Szabolcsi for bringing this type of examples to my attention.
Exatly which contexts allow a focused nonobviative subjunctive clause u not clear to
me at present. The mere presence of the pronoun UZ 'that' appears to be insufcient,
since (i) is bad, or at leat signifcantly worse than ( 17).
(i) * Janosi a-t akarja, hogy ei jojjon veliink.
J. that-ACC wants that (hei) come.SUBJ with us.
( 18) * Janos azt akarja velunk jon-ni.
J. that wants with us come-INF
ON OBVIATION / 93
Obviative complements become nonobviative also if the complement sub
ject is focused. In this case the subject must occur immediately before the
subjunctive verb and it receives special stress, indicated by capitals.
(19) JanOSi (azt) akarja, hogy
O
i menjen Marival (es nem Laszlo).
Ji (it) wants that hei go.SUB M. with (and not L. )
Serbo-Croatian
The relevant facts in Serbo-Croatian (Belgrade dialect) can be summarized
as follows. In case the complement subject is obligatorily controlled by the
matrix subject or direct object, the complement form is a so-called "da2
complement" whose subject must be null. (Serbo-Croatian is a Su pro drop
language as well. )
(20) a. Petari je pokusao da ei
/
*j dodje.
b.
P. Aux tried Comp (he) come
*Petari je pokusao da oni dodje.
P. Aux tried Comp he comes
Ana je naterala Marijui
Comp (she)
.
come
{ da ei
/
*k dodje
A. Aux forced M i
*da onai dodJe.
Comp shei come
"Da2 complements" in Serbo-Croatian are not formally distinguished fom
so-called "dal complements" with respect to either the complementizer or
verbal infection. However, da2 complements are special in that they obey
tense restrictions and have modal connotations characteristic of subjunctive
complements (see Zec 1987 and references quoted therein).
Now in case the subject of a da2 complement is accidentally dependent
on some NP in the matrix, it must necessarily be null:
(21)
{ da ei
f
j dodje.
Petari je zeleo
Comp (hei
f
j)
.
come
Pi Aux wants
da Onj
/
*i dodJe.
Comp hej
/
*i come
Obviation in Serbo-Croatian reduces then to the null/overt pronoun choice
in da2 complements. In case the complement subject is accidentally depen
dent in reference the null pronoun must be chosen, i. e. , the overt pronoun
is obviative.
7
The data below come from Zec 1987.
SIn cae the matrix verb is an auxiliary, the infnitive is used. The use of a finite verb
form in obligatorily controlled complements is a Balkan trait that the Belgrade dialect
of SerboCroatian shares with Romanian.
94 / DONKA F. FARKAS
In Serbo-Croatian, just like in Hungarian, the obviation efect disap
pears in cae the complement subject is emphatically stressed: the exam
ples in ( 20b) and (21) lose their stars if there is emphatic stress on the
complement subject.
Since the facts from Hungarian and Serbo-Croatian are strongly remi
niscent of the Romance obviation data, we should seek a unitary account.
The main new facts concern the efect of emphasis on obviation and the
fact that in Serbo-Croatian obviation reduces to the contrast between a
null and an overt pronoun.
3. 2 The "Blocking" Approach
I suggest that we should view obviation as the manifestation of a constraint
on the use of certain complement forms rather than as a problem pertaining
to pronoun use or interpretation.9 According to this claim, in Romance
languages and in Hungarian obviation is due to the old rivalry between the
subjunctive and the infnitive. Under this proposal, ( 1) is ungrammatical
not because a pronoun selects its antecedent in the wrong domain but
rather because a subjunctive complement is used instead of an infnitive
one. This claim is diferent from Bouchard's in that it does not refer to
the choice between a pronominal and an anaphor directly. Recall now
that in Serbo-Croatian the two rival complement forms difer only with
respect to whether the subject is obligatorily null or not. What is common
to the innitive in Romance and Hungarian, and da2 complements with
null subjects in Serbo-Croatian is that they are the complement forms
used in dependent Su clauses. We can then start from the preliminary
generalization in (I):
(I) The complement form used to mark dependent Su clauses blocks the
use of the subjunctive under certain circumstances. 10
The term 'blocking' is used here in the sense used in lexical semantics and
morphology. Thus, Horn (1984) , in discussing semantic relationships be
tween items in the lexicon, notes that "the meaning, use, or very existence
of a given word or expression is afected by the existence and range of a
related and more baic or specifc entry in the lexicon" (p. 111) . (For rel
evant work in lexical semantics, see McCawley 1977 and Horn 1978, and
in morphology, Aronof 1976 and Kiparsky 1983. ) The existence of a more
specifc lexical item or construction is said to block the use of the more
general one in cases where a choice is theoretically possible. My claim
is that the same phenomenon is responsible for the obviation efect dis
cussed here, where the two competing expressions are complement forms.
In case the more specifc complement form, the one that marks Su depen-
9This suggestion is in the spirit of the pragmatic approah outlined in Section 2. 1. The
diferences will become clear below. Under the present proposal the term 'obviation' u a
misnomer for the phenomenon exemplifed by (1) but I will continue to use it nonetheless.
lOThe term 'subjunctive' is used loosely here. It will be eliminated below.
ON OBVIATION / 95
dence, can be used the use of the less specifc form, the subjunctive, is not
allowed.
Below I will frst point out the immediate advantages of this approach; I
will then briefy comment on the subjunctive/infinitive rivaly, and fnally,
I will turn to the mysterious "certain circumstances" in (I).
Viewing obviation a one complement form (the infnitive) blocking
another ( the subjunctive) allows us to correctly predict that subjunctive
clauses will be obviative only in contexts in which an infnitive is also
possible, i. e. , that obviative clauses are a subset of those subjunctive clauses
which can in principle alternate with innitives. The following facts are
thus accounted for:
(i) Romanian subjunctive clauses are nonobviative because in this lan
guage the complement form used to mark Su dependency is the sub
j unctive.
(22) loni a incercat ei
/
*j sa pIece.
I. tried SUBJ leavel l
loni a fortat-o pe Mariaj ej
/
*i, *k sa pIece.
I. forced M. SUBJ leave
The diference between Romanian and the other Romance languages con
cerning obviation is thus connected to the diference in the role played
by the infnitive. The relevant diference between Romanian and Serbo
Croatian is that in Romanian the null pronoun is more widely used than
in the Belgrade dialect of Serba-Croatian and therefore there is no spe
cial complement form indicating Su dependency and no signifcant difer
ence between indicative and subjunctive complements with respect to the
null/ overt subject pronoun contrat. 12
(ii) The complement of kovetel 'demand' in Hungarian is nonobvia
tive because this verb, unlike akar 'want', takes only subjunctive comple
ments. Subjunctive complements controlled by non-subjects in Hungarian
are nonobviative for the same reason.
(iii) The disappearance of obviation under emphasis in Hungarian and
Serba-Croatian is also explained. In Hungarian, in certain contrative con
texts illustrated in (17) in which the complement may not be infnitive, the
subjunctive is nonobviative. Note also that in both Hungarian and Serbo
Croatian emphatic subjects are nonobviative because they may not be null.
So far, the blocking approach shares advantages with the "avoid pro
noun" solution, except that the former can account for obviation in Serbo
Croatian while the latter cannot. The problem raised by Serbo-Croatian
1
1 For details see Joseph 1983 and Farka 1985b.
1
2
Comorovski (1985) finds that the "avoid pronoun" principle seems stronger in sub
junctive complements than in indicative ones. She connects this diference to the fact
that the use of an overt subject in subjunctive complements triggers the use of the
complementizer U well.
96 / DONKA F. FARKAS
for the "avoid pronoun" approach is to explain why the force of the com
mandment is so much stronger in obviative clauses than in nonobviative
ones. Of couse, we have not accounted for the Serbo-Croatian data ei
ther until the term 'subjunctive' is eliminated in (I) and until the "certain
circumstances" are specifed.
The fact that indicative clauses are nonobviative is stipulated in (I) .
Below I will ofer some justifcation for treating infnitive and subjunctive
complements in a clas that contrasts with indicative complements.
3.3 On the Infnitive/Subjunctive Rivalry
It wa proposed above that obviation in Romance and Hungarian should
be accounted for by claiming that the possibility of using an infnitive com
plement blocks the use of a subjunctive one under certain circumstances.
We have also seen that the infnitive does not block the indicative in these
languages. I will now attempt to justify this contrast by arguing that cer
tain subjunctive complements share with infnitive complements semantic
characteristics that set them apart fom indicative complements. Under
the assumption that we have the same type of blocking here as lexical
blocking, which requires the two forms involved to be semantically close,
we have some explanation for why the infnitive blocks the subjunctive but
not the indicative.
In what follows, I will assume that sentences, as well as infnitival
complements, can be used to denote situations, i. e. , individuals having
properties and standing in various relations at various spatio-temporal
locations. 1
3
I will also assume that verbs are lexically associated with
predicate-argument structures, where the arguments identif participants
in the situations denoted by clauses involving the predicate in question.
The arguments of the predicate end up being associated with syntactic con
stituents. The details of this association are irrelevant for present purposes.
Now in the case of complex sentences, one of the arguments of the
matrix predicate, namely the one linked to the complement, denotes a
situation. The situation denoted by the complement (se) is a constituent
of the situation denoted by the matrix (Sm) . The matrix predicate may
impose various restrictions on Se as part of its lexical meaning since Se is one
of its arguments. These restrictions may involve the immediate constituent
parts of Se, i. e. , the participants in Se, as well as its spatiotemporal location.
The more such restrictions are imposed on Se, the more dependent it is on
S
m. The parameters of semantic dependency that are most consequential
for linguistic phenomena are (i) Su dependency and (ii) world dependency.
The most important consequence of semantic dependency is its correlation
with the use of moods. 14 Below, I will briefy discuss each dependency
1
3
The term 'situation' is borrowed from Barwise and Perry 1983.
1
4Noonan (1985) and Ransom ( 1986) discuss the same question from diferent perspec-
ON OBVIATION / 97
parameter and in the process, I will argue that a third parameter, time
reference dependency is less basic.
A. Su Dependency
There are predicates which require that the "external" argument of 8, i.e. ,
the argument that would be linked to the subject of the complement, be
necessarily referentially dependent on some argument of the matrix pred
icate. This means that these arguments are referentially dependent on
some participant in @. 1 5 Complements realizing such arguments have
been called here dependent Su complements. Examples of verbs requiring
dependent Su complements are "aspectuals," such as begin, start, try, and
'directives', such as persuade or convince.
Note now that it is frequent for languages to use a special comple
ment form to indicate Su dependency, a form in which the Su is not ex
pressed. In languages that have infnitival complements, they are crucially
connected to Su dependency. These languages use infnitival complements
in at least some dependent Su complements. Concerning the languages
discussed here, in Western Romance the verb form in dependent Su com
plements is the infnitive and there are no infnitival complements whose
Su argument is fee in reference. The situation is similar in Hungarian, the
major diference being that in Hungarian the infnitive is exclusively used
only in Su dependent clauses controlled by a subject; 16 recall that if the
controller is a non-subject the subjunctive may be the only possibility (cf.
( 14a) ) . 1 7 Note also that the time reference of dependent Su complements is
also dependent on that of the matrix but there are complements whose Su
reference is fee and whose time reference is dependent, such as the com
plements of promise, or foresee. The claim that the infnitive is associated
with Su dependency rather than time reference dependency is justifed by
the fact that these verbs may always take indicative complements. There
tives. They both treat time-reference dependency as basic and do not discuss world
reference dependency at all.
1
5
The two arguments are nevertheless diferent qua arguments, each being constrained
by its own predicate.
1
6The diference is actually less sharp: in dependent Su complements where the con
troller is a non-subject the subjunctive is not ruled out in Western Rmance either, a
illustrated in (i):
(i)
?J'ai c
nvaincu Marie
that she come.SUBJ
{ qu'elle vienne.
I convInced M.
de venir.
Prep. come.INF
1
7
Nothing in what follows depends crucially on the syntactic status of complements and
therefore the remarks below are compatible with a syntactic treatment in which at leat
some of these complements are VPs, a well a with one in which they are all sentential.
An important question which I will not address here is how to ensure that only subjects
(i.e., external arguments) can be controlled.
98 / DONKA F. FARKAS
are no languages that use the infnitive just in cae Se is dependent in time
reference and fee in Su reference.
B. World Dependency
In order to introduce the notion of world dependency two more general
assumptions have to be stated. First, unlike in "situation semantics," I
asume that collections of situations, called "worlds" play a central role
in the interpretation of sentences. A sentence is true in a world w if the
situation it denotes is part of w. Second, the possible worlds framework
asumed here difers fom most in that partial worlds are admitted. (For a
discussion of partiality, see Landman 1986.) Thus, a sentence may be true,
false or undecided in a particular world.
In the case of verbs taking situation-denoting complements, it often is
the case that the world in which the complement is evaluated is diferent
fom the world in which the matrix is evaluated. Thus, it may well be the
case that (23a) is true in the real world (WR) , while (23b) is not.
(23) a. John thinks that Mary is home.
b. Mary is home.
What is required, however, is for (23b) to be true as far as John is con
cerned, i. e. , to be true in what John takes Reality to be. If know is substi
tuted for think, (23b) has to be true in both worlds.
What world the complement is interpreted in depends on the lexical
meaning of the matrix predicate, which is said to "introduce" (or "create" )
this world. In what follows the introduced world will be called "the new
world," while the world in which the matrix sentence is evaluated will be
called "the base world. " In the cases we will consider here the base world
will always be WR. The type of semantic dependency under discussion has
to do with the properties of the new world.
I will briefy argue now that there are two distinct ways of introducing
a world. One is to introduce a world whose situations are independent
of the base-world or any other world in the sense that the new world is
not asumed to inherit any parts fom any world. I will call such worlds
independent. Another way of introducing a world is to, in a sense, modif
another world, i. e. , introduce a world U
t
that is just like some other world
U, except that a particular situation, Se holds in w' . I will say that in this
case U
t
inherits fom w all those situations that do not confict with Se and
I will say that w' is dependent on w. One gets fom w to w' by adding Se
to w and performing all the accommodating changes required to maintain
consistency. I will call 8 in such cases a highlighted situation for which U
t
is a background world.
Independent Worlds
As an example of independent worlds, consider the worlds introduced by
"cognitive" verbs such as think, believe, and know, exemplifed in (23a).
ON OBVIATION / 99
(The former two are taken here in their "strong" sense, in which the referent
of their Su takes the complement to be true. ) The base world in this cae is
WR and the new world is one that represents Reality as John sees it, a world
that I will denote by WR(J). In what follows, I will call the referent of the
(active) subjects of predicates introducing worlds anchors of those worlds.
If instead of think we had know, the world introduced would be part of
WR(J). The point that is of interest here is that the world introduced by
these verbs is independent of the base-world or any other world, in the
sense that all we know about the new world on the basis of sentences like
(23) i that Se holds in them. There are no situations in the base world, or
any other world, that the new world inherits. Other verbs that introduce
independent worlds are dream, imagine, fantasize. The world introduced
by them is not Reality anchored to the referent of their subject but is a
world that plays that role under limited circumstances. The point again is
that these worlds are independent. No situations fom WR or wR(a), where
a is the anchor, are inherited by these worlds. 18
Dependent Worlds
Things are quite diferent in the cae of desideratives like want, wish, and
desire, exemplifed in (24) .
(24) John wants Mary to leave.
As noted in McCawley 1977, one cannot speak of a single buletic alterna
tive introduced by want since one may hold contradictory wishes simul
taneously without thereby being guilty of logical inconsistency. (This, of
course, i not so with cognitives. ) I will therefore assume that desidera
tives introduce a set of buletic alternatives anchored to the referent of their
subject, and that their complement holds D some world of this set. The
point that is of relevance here is that in this world Se is a highlighted sit
uation whose background is wR(a), i.e. , the world in which Se holds is one
where Se is added to wR(a). Viewing things this way helps us account for
several semantic properties of desideratives, which distinguish them fom
cognitives.
First, note that (25a) does not entail (25b) even if John is flly aware
that being away fom one's wife entails having a wife.
(25) a. John wants to be away fom his wife.
b. John wants to have a wife.
The highlighted situations are diferent in the two caes and therefore the
two worlds are diferent. In (25a) the situation added to WR(J) is one in
which John is away fom his wife, while the situation added to WR(J) in
the case of (25b) is one in which John has a wife.
l
8
The question of inheritance is independent from the pragmatic asumption, mentioned
in McCawley 1977 and discussed at length in Fauconnier 1985, according to which worlds
are not supposed to difer in relevant respects, unless explicitly stated.
100 / DONKA F. FARKAS
Second, having a background world and a highlighted situation helps
us account for the role Se plays in specifying the buletic alternative intro
duced by the verb. Thus, note that the buletic alternative introduced by a
desiderative cannot be just any world in which Se holds, i. e. , the realization
of Se cannot count as a sufcient condition for a world to be a buletic al
ternative of the anchor's. Presumably, a world in which John cannot bear
to be separated from his wife and in which he is away fom her is not a
buletic alternative of John's even if (25a) is true. The buletic alternative
introduced in (25a) is one where John's marriage is the way John thinks it
is in Reality. As mentioned before, realizing Se cannot count as a necessary
condition for a world to be a buletic alternative of the anchor's because one
may hold two contradictory wishes simultaneously without wanting them
to be realized simultaneously.
Thus, if (26) is true of John, there is a buletic alternative of John's in
which he is a lawyer and not a marine, and another, in which he is a marine
and not a lawyer.
(26) John wants to become a lawyer but if he can't get into a good school,
he wants to join the marines.
The two alternatives have diferent background worlds. The background
world of the frst is WR( J) , while that of the latter is one in which the
situation denoted by the if clause has been added to WR(J) .
I will end the discussion of desideratives by drawing attention to a
diference between want and wish concerning the nature of Se. Consider
the contrat in (27):
(27) a. I want it to be Friday.
b. I wish it were Fiday.
said by an ordinary person in our ordinary world. I suggest that (28a) is
strange because want imposes a further restriction on Se, namely that it
should be possible, for all that the anchor knows, for Se to be realized and
therefore Se cannot be counterfactual as far as the anchor is concerned. The
fact that it cannot be factual either follows fom pragmatic considerations,
since if it were, the conditions would be met for the use of an emotive
factive. The verb wish does not impose this requirement on Se. Note
that this diference correlates with time reference restrictions, since one
can know how things turned out in the past but usually one can only
conjecture about the future. The complement of want is acceptable with
past time reference in English, at leat for some people, if the anchor does
not know whether the situation it denotes is factual or not.
There is cross-linguistic variation with respect to the details of the con
straints particular desideratives impose on Se. For Fench, Ruwet ( 1984)
claims that the use of vouloir 'want' in the indicative implies that the an
chor is ready to do what it takes in order to bring Se about, while souhaiter
ON OBVIATION / 101
'wish' implies that the anchor's attitude towards the fulfllment of his wish
is passive.
"Directives," such as ask, order, demand, request can be analyzed as
similar to want except that the person responsible for bringing about Sc
is the individual denoted by the internal argument of the verb (the direct
object or the object of the preposition of or from) .
With respect t o time dependency, we have seen that it is associated
with Su dependency and that it may accompany world dependency as
well, as a result of a constraint on the realizability of Sc. We have already
seen that not all world-dependent complements have dependent time ref
erence (cf. wish) . Conversely, there are complements whose time reference
is dependent but which are neither world nor Su dependent. Consider, for
instance, the complements of promise and foresee. Their time reference
is dependent: it must necessarily be non-anterior to the time reference of
the matrix. As noted above, they are not, however, dependent Su com
plements and they do not introduce a new world, and therefore certainly
not a dependent one. Their complements are supposed to hold in the base
world at some non-anterior time. Promise difers from the other two in
that it imposes the realizability condition on the referent of its (active)
subject and sc, and therefore these two arguments must be in the RESP
relation.
Going back to the main point of all this, namely the subjunctive/in
finitive rivalry, note that world dependency, just like Su dependency, and
unlike time reference dependency, is associated with the use of a special
"non-indicative" mood. Thus, languages that have mood distinctions use
a non-indicative mood in world-dependent complements. In languages
that have a subjunctive, this is the mood used to mark world depen
dency, except, of course, under special circumstances, when the infnitive
blocks it. 19
Common to the infinitive and the subjunctive then, is that they mark
semantic dependency. The "rivalry" between them manifests itself in the
tendency of one "dependent" mood to take over the rightful domain of
the other. The existence of the rivalry is not surprising in view of the
fact that the domains of the two moods often overlap, as for instance in
the case of a verb like try or in the case of directives that take depen
dent Su complements, like persuade. Thus, we have already noted that in
Balkan languages the subjunctive has supplanted the infinitive to a large
extent, and therefore the subjunctive has come to be used to mark not only
world dependency but subject dependency as well. In English the reverse
has happened: the subjunctive has almost disappeared, its place having
19
Marking world dependency is only one of the uses the subjunctive may be put to.
Thus, in Fench it is used to mark subordination, in preposed complements, as well a
non-asertiveness, in emotive-fatives (cf. Palmer 1986).
102 / DONKA F. FARKAS
been taken by the infnitive. Consequently, we have infnitive complements
whose subject reference is fee, as in (28):
(28) John wants ( for) Mary to leave.
Recall also that in Hungarian and Western Romance the situation is mixed,
the infnitive marking Su dependency and the subjunctive marking world
dependency. In cases of overlap, the infnitive tends to win in cae of
Su control, while the subjunctive has at least a chance in case of non
Su control. (In Hungarian in these cases verbs select either the sub
junctive or the infnitive, while in Western Romance both complement
types are possible. ) The cae of Serbo-Croatian is diferent since there
only Su dependency is formally marked (by an obligatorily null subject
pronoun) ; recall that world-dependent complements ( da2 complements)
are only semantically distinguished fom independent ones ( dal comple
ments).
We are ready now to return to obviation. Languages which have ob
viative complements are languages which distinguish dependent Su com
plements fom world-dependent ones. The battleground between the two
forms is limited to those cases where the complement meets the semantic
requirements for both Su and world dependency, i. e. , Sc is world dependent
and the participant connected to its subject is referentially dependent on
some participant in Sm. The generalization in (I) can then be reformulated
a in (II) , which now covers Serbo-Croatian a well.
(II) In certain world-dependent complements, the form used to mark
subject dependency blocks the form used in world-dependent com
plements.
For Fench, for instance, (II) requires the choice of the infnitive over
the subjunctive in certain world-dependent complements, while in Serbo
Croatian the choice will be between an obligatorily null pronoun over a
potentially overt one. This gives the disjoint reference efect in both lan
guages. Blocking, of course, presupposes the existence of two complement
forms, and therefore no obviation efect exists in Romanian.
Note that calling this preference for the dependent Su construction
"blocking" is appropriate because this construction is semantically more
specifc than the world-dependent one. Recall that obviation manifests
itself in case of accidental Su dependency. Now the fact that the comple
ment is world dependent is predictable fom the meaning of the matrix
verb but the fact that its Su is referentially dependent is not. The use of
the dependent Su form in this case is therefore more informative than the
use of the world-dependent one. The less informative complement form
may be chosen only in case the conditions are not met for the use of the
more informative one, which results in the disjoint reference efect under
discussion here. Let us turn now to a less mysterious characterization of
the "certain" complements involved.
ON OBVIATION / 103
3.4 The Semantic Role of the Controller and of the
Controlled Argument
So far we have narrowed the range of obviation to world-dependent com
plements whose subjects are accidentally dependent on a matrix argument.
Obviation wa treated here a the result of one complement form blocking
another in these caes. Note, however, that nothing we have said so far
accounts for Ruwet's weakening factors. Recall that based on examples
such a (10), repeated here as (29),
(29) Je voudrais bien que je puisse partir des aujourd'huis.
I would like well that I can.SUBJ leave already today
Ruwet concludes that the semantic role of the two arguments involved
afects obviation. The remarks that follow are elaborations of ideas in
Sul er and Padilla-Rivera 1984, Zaring 1985 and Ruwet 1984.
We have seen above (cf. examples (9a)-(9c)) that obviation is weak
ened in cae the complement is passivized, or if it contains a modal or a
"non-agentive" main verb. Common to all these cases is the fact that the
controlled argument (the complement subject) is not seen as bringing Se
about, i.e., it is not in the RESP relation with the situation of which it is a
participant. The tendency of obviation to disappear when the complement
is pasivized, or when it contains a modal or a "non-agentive" main verb
leads me to conclude that the controlled argument must bear the RESP rela
tion to the situation denoted by the complement. This means that the con
trolled argument is the initiator of the situation in which it is a participant.
It wa also noted above that obviation is weakened if the controller is
not seen a being D the RESP relation with Se (cf. example (9d) ) . Relevant
here is Ruwet's observation that obviation is weaker in the complement of
souhaiter 'wih' than in that of vouloir 'want' . As mentioned in Section
3.3 above, Ruwet also notes that the Su argument of the latter is more
likely to be interpreted a being in the RESP relation with Se than the Su
argument of the former. Ruwet also notes that the complement of exiger
'demand' is not obviative. The relevant characteristic of this verb is that its
Su argument may not be in the RESP relation with Se. I conclude therefore
that the obviation efect is most robust if both controller and controlled
argument are in the RESP relation with Se, the former as a result of the
characteristics of Sm, the latter a a result of the characteristics of Se. (We
have here, of course, two distinct arguments of two distinct predicates even
though they happen to be referentially dependent. )
This situation is reminiscent of facts pertaining to controller choice,
discussed in Farkas 1988. It wa argued there that the unmarked controller
choice for infnitival complements falls on the matrix argument that bears
the RESP relation to Se, when the controlled argument bears this relation
to Be a well. This suggests that there is a correlation between the use
of dependent Su constructions and the RESP relation, which is the link
104 / DONJA F. FARKAS
between obviation and control. I suggest that there is a "canonical control
case," canonical for the use of a dependent Su complement. The semantic
characteristic of the canonical control case is that both the complement Su
and the matrix argument it is referentially dependent on bear the RESP
relation to sc. We expect then that if a language has a complement form
marking Su dependency, it will use it in complements conforming to this
characteristic and that if the characteristic is not met we will fnd cases in
which the dependent Su construction is not used. A case in point is the
Hungarian equivalent of exiger, kovetelni, which, as seen in (16) above, may
not take infnitival complements but only subjunctive ones. This property,
I claim, is not accidental but rather, it is the result of the fact that the
controller may not be in the RESP relation with sc.
lt is therefore not surprising that obviation is strongest in case the se
mantic characteristics of the "canonical control cae" are met, in view of
the fact that obviation is the result of preferring the dependent Su comple
ment form over some other complement form. The generalization in (II)
can now be rendered more precise:
(III) In world-dependent complements that conform to the canonical con
trol cae, the form used to mark Su dependency blocks the form used
for world dependency.
The generalization as formulated now accounts for Ruwet's weakening fac
tors. The proposal made here elaborates the suggestions in Ruwet 1984.
It difers fom both Suier and Padilla-Rivera 1984, and Zaring 1985. Ac
cording to Suner and Padilla-Rivera 1984 obviation is connected to the
semantic feature [+WILL] of the matrix predicate. In discussing this pro
posal, Zaring 1985 correctly notes that the role of the complement subject
is also relevant and proposes that a complement is obviative when the ma
trix subject is an "instigator" and the complement subject, an "instigatee."
Zaring does not, however, elaborate on the meaning of these terms. In par
ticular, it is not clear how to postulate a semantic relationship between the
matrix subject and the complement subject since they are not arguments
of the same predicate. In the analysis suggested above, the two subjects
are related by both bearing the RESP relation to the same situation, the
situation denoted by the complement.
The question to be addressed next is that of why the RESP relation
should play such a prominent role in control and obviation. The answer
is suggested by Ruwet ( 1984), who notes that when a matrix argument is
in what we call here the RESP relation to Sc there is a crucial diference
between the case when it is coreferential with the complement argument
bearing the RESP relation to the same situation and the case when it is
not. Let us call the matrix argument im (the matrix initiator) and the
complement argument ic (the complement initiator). If the two initiators
are referentially independent, im is indirectly responsible for Sc in that it
ON OBVIATION / 105
has to act on ie, who brings Se about. If the two initiators are referentially
dependent, on the other hand, the realization of Se depends on a single
individual and the ie has direct responsibility over Se. It is therefore not
surprising that languages will tend to mark this diference. What we have
called obviation here is one way of marking it. The generalization in (III)
then can be seen as a rule that limits the feedom allowed by subcatego
rization restrictions whose efect, besides limiting the number of ways one
can say the same thing, is to mark a relevant semantic diference.
3. 5 Locality and Su Orientation
There are two more characteristics of obviation that have to be accounted
for, locality and Su orientation.
Locality
Recall that the disjoint reference efect characteristic of obviation always
involves an argument of a matrix verb and the subject of its immediate
complement. This follows in our analysis fom the fact that obviation is
dependent on semantic characteristics of a matrix argument and Se, char
acteristics that are imposed by the lexical meaning of the matrix verb. It
follows therefore that Se must be an argument of that V since only the
immediate arguments of a verb may be afected by the verb's meaning.
Now imposing semantic constraints on a situation may involve imposing
semantic constraints on its participants. Further details of the situation in
question are unavailable.
Su Orientation
As noted before, Su orientation refers to the strong cross-linguistic ten
dency of obviation to disappear in cae the controller is not the subject
of the matrix clause. Recall that in Fench, vouloir 'want' contrasts with
persuader 'persuade' or convaincre 'convince' in that the complements of
the latter are nonobviative, (or less obviative) as shown in ( 11) , repeated
here as (30).
(30)
{qU'ili s'en aille.
?Marie a con
:
aincu Pauli
that hei leave.SUBJ
M. has convInced Pi
de s'en aller.
Prep. leave.lNF
The same appears to hold in Serbo-Croatian, as seen in ( 31).
(31)
da ei/j ostane na veceri.
Petari je molio Marijuj
P.i Au asked M.j
Comp (he/she) stay at dinner
*
da oni ostane na veceri.
Comp hei stay at dinner
?
*
da onaj ostane na veceri.
Comp shej stay at dinner
106 / DONKA F. FARKAS
I suggest that this property of obviation is connected to the general ten
dency of languages to formally mark coreference with a subject more
explicitly than coreference with a non-subject. Thus, note that cross
linguistically, refexive pronouns may always be bound by a subject but
not always by a non-subject. Second, in "switch reference" languages it
is again coreference with the subject that matters. Lat, note that there
is a cross-linguistic tendency for the infnitive to act a a "same subject"
construction. Recall that in Fench and Hungarian, for instance, depen
dent Su complements may be in the subjunctive only if controlled by a
non-subject .
We can account for these facts as well as for the Su orientation of
obviation by restricting the notion of canonical control cae to caes of Su
control. The defnition of canonical control case will then have a semantic
side, pertaining to the semantic role of the controller and the controlled
argument, and a syntactic side, pertaining to the grammatical role of the
controller. The blocking efect we have discussed here is strongest when
both requirements are met.
4 Conclusion
It ha been argued here that obviation i the efect of a blocking mecha
nism that limits the choice between two complement types subcategorized
for by a verb. The range of the phenomenon is limited to semantically
dependent complements and is most robust in canonical control situations.
The disjoint reference efect discussed here thus reduces to the requirement
of using a control construction, if possible, in canonical control situations.
The blocking mechanism we have invoked is the same as lexical blocking,
discussed in McCawley 1977, and Horn 1978, 1984, where it is argued that
the existence and interpretation of a lexical item may be afected by the
existence and interpretation of another. In these works it is shown that
the choice of a formally more complex and semantically less specifc form is
restricted to cases where the use of a formally less marked and semantically
more specifc form is not possible. What we have seen here is that, not sur
prisingly, the same is true with respect to the choice of complement forms.
The generalization in (III) can thus be seen as a principle operating in the
lexicon, which limits the choice between two subcategorized complement
forms, a principle driven by the same mechanism as lexical, morphological
or phonological blocking, expressed by some adequately generalized version
of the Elsewhere Principle.
Note that our proposal difers fom that in Bouchard 1983 in that no
mention is made of anaphors and pronominals here. As a result, we lost
the direct connection between obviation and the efects of principle B of
Binding Theory, a connection that is present in all the analyses of obviation
formulated within Government and Binding theory. Note, however, that
ON OBVIATION / 107
if one adopts an analysis of the coreference properties of anaphors and
pronominals along the lines proposed by Bouchard or Reinhart 1983, the
connection is regained. The fundamental reason for the ungrammaticality
of ( 1 ) and (6) , repeated here as (32a) and (32b),
(32) a. Pierrei veut qU'il.i/j parte.
P. wants that he leave.SUBJ
b.
*
Johni saw himi .
would then be the same: a less specifc form has been chosen when a more
specifc one was available, and a result, one has failed to formally mark
coreference with a subject. The diference in range between obviation and
the anaphor/pronominal choice results from the fact that the former con
cerns the choice between subcategorized forms, a choice sensitive to the
semantic characteristics of the two situations involved. The principle gov
erning the pronominal/anaphor choice and our generalization (III) are then
members of a family of constraints on choice, whose common denominator
is the Elsewhere Principle.
References
Aronof, Mark. 1976. Word Formation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge,
Mas.: MIT Press.
Barwise, Jon, and John Perry. 1983. Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, Mass. :
MIT Press.
Bouchard, Denis. 1982. On the Content of Empty Categories. Doctoral disserta
tion, Masachusetts Institute of Technology.
Bouchard, Denis. 1983. The Avoid Pronoun Principle and the Elsewhere Princi
ple. In Proceedings of NELS 13, 29-36. Amherst: University of Massachusetts,
GLSA.
Bresnan, Joan. 1972. Theory of Complementation in English Syntax. Doctoral
dissertation, Masachusetts Institute of Technology.
Comorovski, Ileana. 1985. Control and Obviation in Romanian. In Proceedings
of the 2nd Annual Easter States Conference on Linguistics.
Farkas, Donka. 1985a. Intensional Descriptions and the Romance Subjective
Mood. New York: Garland Publishers.
Farkas, Donka. 1985b. Obligatory Controlled Subjects in Romanian. In Pa
pers from the 21st Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 90-100.
University of Chicago.
Farkas, Donka. 1988. On Obligatory Control. Linguistics and Philosophy 1 1 : 27-
58.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1985. Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in
Naturl Language. Cambridge, Mas. : MIT Press.
Hermon, Gabriela. 1985. Syntactic Modularity. Dordrecht: Foris.
Horn, Laurence R. 1978. Lexical Incorporation, Implicature, and the Least
Efort Hypothesis. In Proceedings of the Parasession on the Lexicon, ed.
108 / DONKA F. FARKAS
Donka Farkas, Wesley M. Jacobsen, and Karol W. Todrys, 196-209. Chicago:
Chicago Linguistic Society.
Horn, Laurence R. 1984. Ambiguity, Negation, and the London School of Par
simony. In Proceedings fm NELS 14, ed. Charles Jones and Peter Sells,
108-31 . Amherst: University of Massachusetts, GLSA.
Joseph, Brian. 1983. The Synchrony and Diachrony of the Balkan Infnitive. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Kempchinsky, Paula. 1985. The Subjunctive Disjoint Reference Efect. In Pro
ceedings of the 1 5th Symposium on Romance Languages.
Kiparsky, Paul. 1982. Word Formation and the Lexicon. In Proceedings of the
1982 Mid-America Linguistics Conference, ed. Frances Ingemann, 3-29, 47-
78. Lawrence: University of Kansas.
Landman, Federick. 1986. Towards a Theory of Information. In GRASS 6.
Dordrecht: Foris.
Levinson, Stephen. 1987. Pragmatics and the Grammar of Anaphora: a Par
tial Pragmatic Reduction of Binding and Control Phenomena. Joural of
Linguistics 23:379-434.
McCawley, James. 1977. Conversational Implicature and the Lexicon. In Syntax
and Semantics
g
: Prgmatics, ed. Peter Cole, 245-259. New York: Academic
Press.
Meireles, J. , and Eduardo Raposo. 1983. Subjunctives and Disjoint Reference
in Portuguese: Some Implications for Binding Theory. Paper presented
at the Colloqui International de Linguistica Teorica i Llengues Romanicas,
Barcelona.
Montalbetti, Mario. 1984. Afer Binding: On the Interretation of Pronouns.
Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Noonan, Michael. 1985. Complementation. In Language Typology and Syntactic
Description Vol. J, ed. Timothy Shopen, 42-140. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Palmer, Fank. 1986. Mood and Modality. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Picallo, Carme. 1984. The InH-node and the Null Subject Parameter. Linguistic
Inquiry 15: 75-102.
Picallo, Carme. 1985. Opaque Domains. Doctoral dissertation, City University
of New York.
Ransom, Evelyn. 1986. Complementizers: How Do They Mean. In Proceedings
of the 2nd Annual Meeting of the Pacifc Linguistics Conference, ed. Scott
DeLancey and Russell S. Tomlin. University of Oregon.
Reinhart, Tanya. 1983. Coreference and Bound Anaphora: A Restatement of
the Anaphora Questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 6: 47-88.
Ruwet, Nicolas. 1984. Je veux partir /* Je veux que je parte. In Cahiers de
grammaire, chapter 7. Toulouse: Le Mirail.
Salamanca, D. 1981. Subjunctive Syntax. Manuscript, Massachusetts Institute
of Technology.
ON OBVIATION / 109
Suier, Margarita, and J. Padilla-Rivera. 1984. On the Subjunctive and the Role
of the Features of INFL: Evidence from a Null Subject Language. Manuscript,
Cornell University.
Zaring, L. 1985. The Syntactic Role of Verbal Infection in French and Brazilian
Portuguese. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University.
Zec, Draga. 1987. On Obligatory Control in Clausal Complements. In Working
Papers in Grammatical Theory and Discourse Structure, ed. Masayo !ida,
Stephen Wechsler, and Draga Zec, 136-168. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
j,j
j,
so
_
j
_
nice
}}}
One can then rule out the examples in (88) by asuming that only APs
possibly, in fact, maximally A
I
, can appear in prenominal position. This
is essentially what Abney argues, although, his analysis makes the rather
novel asumption that the adjective is the head in a construction like big
dog, that this construction is therefore an AP, and that the NP dog is
a complement of big. We have of course taken the more traditional view
that canonical prenominal modifers, namely the prenominal adjectives, are
adjoined to Nl in English.
So, it seems that for the canonical prenominal modifers, namely projec
tions of N and projections of A, there is some evidence that such modifers
are typically maximally single bar projections-Xl . If we look again at the
examples of highly-complex modifers in (67), we see that they are actu-
l3
0ne can say things like how large a house, so large a house. Such constructions are
limited, in the sense that only an indefnite singular NP can follow the degree-marked
adjective:
*
how large that house, how large houses. Abney argues that thee are
adjectival phraes (DegPs) where the head adjective takes a fully specifed noun phrae
a a complement.
164 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
ally consistent with this idea-they may be projected fom non-traditional
categories such as V, but may plausibly be analyzed as being of level X
l
or below.
4.2 More on the Distinction Between NO and NI Modifers
Having argued that the modifer of a noun is maximally X I , we now
overview the arguments for our assumptions about the structural relation
ship between the modifer and the head. It is worthwhile to start out by
placing this assumption about modifer-head relations in a broader context
of current ideas about phrase structure.
We have maintained that modifers are adjoined to either NO or NI .
The diagram in (90) illustrates the structure we have assumed for an NI
modifier such as the adjective red:
(90) [
DP
[
D
O the] [
N
2
[
N
1 [
A
red] [
N
1 [
N
O bookll]]]
We have assumed that most [N N] compounds are instances of modifer
head constructions, in this case involving adjunction to NO:
(91) [
N
O [
N
O dog] [
N
O house]]
However, we have argued at length that not all instances of [N N] modifi
cation are at the NO level; similarly, not all instances of [A N] modification
are NI . Thus we have posited structures like these: 1
4
(92) a. [
N
1 [
N
O kitchen] [
N
1 [
N
O sink]]]
b. [
N
O [
A
blind] [
N
O spot
}}
Our primary arguments involved default stress patterns and some infor
mal consideration of semantic relations, but there is also evidence from
sequence constraints among modifers. Note that one does not find [N N]
constructions which we would argue on stress grounds to be of the type
NI , occurring as the righthand member of a construction whose parent
node ought to be an NO. So, one can say cofee jar ( NO) , and plastic jar
(NI ), but one cannot get * cofee plastic jar (cf. plastic cofee jar) since
the structure would have to be *
[
N
o NO NI] , which is ruled out by X-bar
considerations given that the rightmost member of a compound in English
is generally the head (see ( 105) below).
On the other hand, complex expressions which look on the surface to be
phrasal constructions, but which we have argued on stress grounds to be
NO, can occur in the righthand position of compound nouns. The complex
14It is worth noting that the structure in (92a) is vaguely related to the proposal in
Selkirk 1984 (pp. 43-50) that right stressed compounds involve adjuncts, where the
modifer is in some sense more external than modifers in a left stressed compound,
which are taken to be arguments. Selkirk, however, s seems to suggest that at least
some compound-like constructions, such a slcl warehouse (i.e., warehouse made of
steel) might be viewed as phraal collocations (p. 247) a opposed to compounds of the
form ADJUNCT-HEAD. It is not clear from her discussion how one is supposed to
distinguish these caes.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 165
examples in the third column are all right-branching NOs having primary
stress on the penultimate member a predicted by the eSR:
(93) user's manual Unix manual [Unix [user's manual]]
dry dock trawler dock [trawler [dry dock]]
Needless to say, prenominal noun modifers that on our analysis are
dominated by Nl , are generally reasonable candidates to stack outside
adjectives that occur at the same level. Thus the right-dominant character
of plastic cup is consistent with the possibility of plastic disposable cup,
though the alternative ordering may be slightly preferred.
By giving a structural explanation for the unavailability of examples
like * cofee plastic jar, we are claiming that such examples are ill-formed
for the same kind of structural reason that * difcult the problems is ill
formed. It is worthwhile contrasting such rigid ordering restrictions with
the much softer ordering restrictions on pre nominal adjectival modifers,
which are all introduced at the same (Nl) level, but which nonetheless
display well-known ordering preferences:
(94) large red ball ?red large ball
oversize square table ?square oversize table
One could, of course, ask whether these ordering restrictions should also be
handled by assuming intermediate structural positions or levels? For exam
ple, meaure adjectives like large could be placed in a slot "outside" color
adjectives like red, since the former prefer to precede the latter. However,
it has been observed in the literature on prenominal adjective ordering (see,
most recently, Sproat and Shih 1990b) that these ordering restrictions are
only preferences, operating in the absence of pragmatic reasons to choose a
diferent order. It is perfectly possible to choose an alternative order, given
appropriate context:
(95) I want the red large ball, not the blue one.
So it seems best to agree with the traditional view that these ordering
preferences refect some sort of natural continuum of psychological afnity,
even though it seems difcult to defne such a scale in a non-circular way.
In contrast, ordering restrictions on what we have argued to be modifers
at the NO and Nl levels seem inviolable-like the ordering restrictions be
tween specifers and modifers, suggesting that the structural analysis pro
posed for these modifers is on the right track. Something seems defnitely
degraded about (96) as compared with (95):
(96) ??I need the cofee plastic jar, not the tea plastic jar.
These considerations, as well as the stress and semantic considerations
discussed throughout this paper have therefore led us to the conclusion that
modifer-noun constructions can be either N1 or NO, no matter whether the
modifer is adjectival or nominal. We now summarize the various classes
of cases we have examined in this paper giving examples to fll out the
166 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
structural possibilities. Non-Iexicalized [A N] combinations-instances of
normal prenominal adjectival modifcation-are mostly phrasal. At least
some of the productive cases of apparent NO- level [A N] combinations may
really involve [N N] modifcation at some level, as we argued in reference
to (50) , and as suggested by the discussion in Levi 1978. Lexicalized [A N]
forms-those forms that must be listed since they have more or less id
iosyncratic or idiomatic meanings-may be either Nl or NO:
(97) Lexicalized Non-Lexicalized
N yellow pages dental operation
Nl red herring red paint
With [N N] modifcation we clearly get all possible combinations of
Productive/Lexicalized and bar level. There is no sense that [N NJ NO are
more lexicalized than [N N] phrasal combinations:
(98) Lexicalized
eyeball
rice pudding
N on-Lexicalized
Capsicum leaf
dingo stew
Finally, we have noted compound-like examples where the modifer is a
possessive. These may be either Nl or NO. In both cases the expression
tends to be lexicalized, though there are some productive subsystems, such
a those left-stressed examples headed by milk:
l
5
(99) N
l
Swainson's thrush
NO: dog's body
4. 3 Some Other Compound-like Constructions in English
and Elsewhere
We have discussed apparently left-headed nominals in English. On the bais
of their stress behavior all such examples appear to be N
l
. Many of these
constructions have a questionable status in the minds of many speakers.
Thus the prescribed plural attoreys general, which is what is expected
given a lef-headed structure, has already lost to the alternative attorey
generals, suggesting that this form has been largely reanalyzed. Other
examples, possibly because of their productivity, seem more solidly lef
headed: Mounts Whitney and McKinley. One can link these cases of post
nominal modifcation with the slightly marked, though still very productive
clas of post-nominal modifcations with adjectives: a man proud of his son,
a river broad and long, a dragon fearsome to behold.
Other compounds and compound-like words which do not ft so neatly
into the discussion of most of this paper include exocentric bahuvrihi com
pounds. Bahuvrihi compounds have been analyzed (cf. Kiparsky 1982) as
1
5
Note that some left stressed examples function as proper names and disallow preceding
modifers or specifiers in most cases, e.g., Kayne 's generalization. There is nothing
particularly surprising in this, and it seems reasonable to analyze such expressions as
themselves being proper names, which typically lack articles in English.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIF1ED NOUN PHRASES / 167
modifers to an empty headed noun redneck T) . Such an approach seems
to solve the embarrassing problem that these constructions have no seman
tic head (a redneck is not in any sense a neck) ; however, we must assume
in addition that these cases are all NO, presumably a consequence of their
having undergone at least the second stage of lexicalization outlined in
Section 3. 1
Examples like those of (35) are presumably nominalizations of phrasal
fragments reminiscent of the Romance examples in ( 100) :
( 100) a. essuie-glace (wipe glass) 'windshield wiper'
b. tocadiscos (play records) 'record player'
c. guardaboschi (guard woods) 'forester'
Such examples are syntactic in appearance but have been transformed into
nouns, suggesting a structure along the lines of that argued for in Di Sciullo
and Williams 1987:
( 101)
toca]
discos]] ]
4.4 More on FCA-Only Theories: Ladd's Deaccenting
Argument
We have taken the traditional generative view that syntax determines stress
in the "normal" cae-abstracting away from FCA efects. In adopting this
view we are rejecting, among other approaches, Ladd's 1984 proposal that
compound stress is a result of deaccenting the head. His idea is that the
diference in representation between steel warehouse ( 'warehouse made of
steel') and steel warehouse ('warehouse for storing steel') is purely metrical,
the latter having the normal iambic phrasal structure w s and the latter
the trochaic, deaccented structure s w. This deaccenting in compounds is
explicitly claimed to be part of the more general phenomenon of phrasal
deaccenting in examples like (102) (Ladd 1984, p. 255) , where books is
deaccented for pragmatic reasons:
( 102) Ha John read Slaughterhouse Five?
No, John doesn't read books.
Ladd's baic claim is that in right-stressed modifer-head nominal construc
tions, the attribute (lefthand member) does not serve to subcategorize1
6
the
head. In the deaccented (CSR) cases the attribute does subcategorize the
head, hence the head contributes only part of what is necessary to identif
the new category. An obvious contrast is green house versus green house.
In the former the attribute green does not produce a new type of entity, but
merely serves to further specif the general category house; the accented
head therefore provides the category. A green house, on the other hand,
is a new category of entity, so house provides only part of the necessary
information, which results in its being deaccented relative to green, which
16
Ladd is not using the technical linguistic sense of subteorze, but intends the sense
of "making a subcategory out or' the head.
168 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
provides crucial additional information. The approach is argued to work
not only in cases where semantic categorization is involved, but also in cases
where this is much less clear, such as in the domain of place names. So, the
contrast between First A venue and First Street is argued to derive fom
the fact that Street, within the category of names for roads, is the more
common or expected term, and also gives the least semantic information
about what kind of road is involved (terms like Avenue, Boulevard, Alley,
carry with them connotations which Street does not have) . Thus Street is
deaccented.
While there are surely areas in which notions of subcategorization
conditioned deaccenting plays a role, the idea is problematic as a general ex
planation for the stress patterns we have seen. For example, one pragmatic
test proposed by Ladd to distinguish "favors" fom real "(sub)categories"
in food terms falls far short of correlating with stress. Ladd's idea is that
cheese sandwich is a sandwich favored with cheese and cheese merely
serves to further specify sandwich, not form a separate category: thus the
stress is phrasal. In contrast, for banana bread, one clearly needs the in
formation provided by the left hand member to determine the category of
food involved since banana bread is not really a kind of bread favored with
banana, but a new category of food similar to bread in some ways. Now,
Ladd notes that while one can felicitously ask do you want a sandwich?
and subsequently ofer a cheese sandwich, one cannot felicitously ask do
you want some bread? and ofer banana bread. It is claimed that one can
only felicitously ofer XY if XY is merely a Y favored with X, and not
a diferent category of food. This test is then supposed to correlate with
stress, right hand stress if the ofer is felicitous, left hand if it is not, for the
reasons given above. However, this test makes the wrong predictions in
whole categories of examples. For instance, most words headed with bread
are left-stressed even when their referent is a canonical instance: one can
felicitously ofer a person bread and then give them any one of wheat bread,
rye bread, white bread and a number of others. On the other hand, while
steak and kidney pie follows the normal pattern of righthand stress for
words headed by pie, it would come as quite a surprise to most Americans
to get some after assenting to an ofer of unmodifed pie. 17.
Another problem with Ladd's reduction of compound stress to general
mechanisms of phrasal deaccenting is that phrasal deaccenting can easily
produce examples of right-branching structures where all the right hand
material is deaccented:
( 103) I don't [like [buckwheat
griddle cakes]]]
Ladd's theory therefore predicts that left dominance in right-branching
compounds is possible, if the subcategories fall out right. This does not
1 7This point can be made even more strikingly with shepher's ge, a concoction wherein
ground lamb is topped with mahed potatoes and then baked.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 169
seem to be true, even where one might expect such stressing given the
behavior of binary compounds with identical heads and lefthand members:
( 104) a. buckwheat cakes
b. griddle cakes
c. buckwheat griddle cakes
d.*buckwheat griddle cakes
Of course, (104d) is possible in FeA contexts, but it is not the default
case for such compounds, contrary to what we might expect given Ladd's
theory.
1O
4.5 Are NO Compounds Formed "in the Lexicon"?
In assuming, as we have been, that NO compounds are instances of mod
ifcation constructions on a par with N
I
modifcation constructions, we
have been at least implicitly assuming that such compounds are syntactic
objects. Doing so, of course, runs counter to most theories of morphology,
which assume that compounds are dealt with in the morphological compo
nent and that if compounds seem to share some properties with syntactic
constructions this should nonetheless not be taken as evidence that they
are syntactic (Selkirk 1982, Hoeksema 1984, Mohanan 1986, Di Sciullo and
Williams 1987, among many others) .
We would like to consider one recent attempt to justif this separa
tion of compound formation fom syntax, namely that of Di Sciullo and
Williams 1987 (henceforth D&W) , and consider whether the evidence they
adduce for this separation is reasonable. D&W suggest an approach to mor
phology whereby words are constructed in a component of the grammar,
the morphological component, which is in many ways similar to syntax,
but is both (i) diferent in detail fom syntax and (ii) separate fom syntax.
We discuss each of these points in turn. 19
Diferences of detail. A crucial diference of detail is that compounds
are right headed in English, whereas phrases are left headed, at least at a
very macroscopic level of analysis.
There are actually two issues relevant to comparing the headed ness of
phrases and compounds. One, D&W claim, is that one can always pick out
the head in a phrase because it is "the item with one less bar level than the
phrase" (p. 23) and which is generally of the same category a the phrase:
1
8
Ladd's own examples involving the head noun warehouse might seem to be a contra
diction to what we have just said since warehouse is, historically at leat, a compound.
However, it seems well within reason to asume that the analysis of warehouse as a
compound is only of historical interest and that the word today lacks an internal word
boundary. Certainly productively formed constructions with unequivocally complex
heads do not seem to stress a Ladd ought to predict: a department store for electronics
would be a electrnics deartment store, except of course in clear FCA-contexts. Yet
surely an electronics department store must be considered a subcategory of department
store, at leat if a steel warehouse is considered to be a subcategory of warehouse.
19See also Baker 1988 for a review of problems with D&W.
170 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
( 105) xn - . . . YP . . . xn-l . . . ZP . . .
They contrast this situation with the situation in a canonical compound
where the two daughters of the NO are themselves NO. They suggest that
compounds follow a diferent, non-syntactic, morphological component rule
for determining headedness, namely a modifed version of the Righthand
Head rule of Williams 1981, which states roughly that the head of a word
is its rightmost morpheme. In compounds, it seems, the syntactic notion
of head would not work.
Still, it is important to bear in mind that the ease with which one can
apply the syntactic notion of head in phrases, and the seeming difculty of
using that notion in compounds derives fom theoretical prejudice. To see
this point, consider the structure of noun phrases in Welsh such a:
( 106) meibion athrawon (sons teachers) 'teachers' sons'
This noun phrase consists of two plural nouns with no other markings, and
yet there is no question that it is left-headed, as are all noun phraes in
Welsh. In order to apply the syntactic notion of head, one would clearly
want to argue that the right hand noun athrawon 'teachers' is really the
sole member of a DP-hence could not count as the head under ( 105)
although there would be no way to ascertain the presence of the DP fom
the existence of athrawon alone. Returning to English compounds, there
is no absolute reason why one cannot assert that all prenominal modifers
within NO are phrasal; we have already discussed examples which show
that at least in some cases the prenominal modifer in the NO level must
be an Xl . So, one might assume that all pre nominal modifers are Xl just
as we tend to assume that the noun athrawon in ( 106) is really a DP, de
spite the lack of direct evidence in the particular construction in ( 106) . If
we were to take that tack, we could clearly modif the syntactic notion of
headedness to allow that the head of a construction must match the cate
gory of the parent and have a bar level not greater than that of the parent;
something like this condition must be right more generally anyway if we
are to defne headedness correctly on adjunction structures under normal
notions of adjunction. Then, the head of dog house would be clear: the
prenominal modifer dog would be an N
I
, whereas house would be an NO,
thus satisfying the conditions for headedness under the revised defnition.
Still, we don't have to adopt this strategy. The other issue, raised by
D&W's claim that English phraes are left headed is the question: left
headed at what level? Clearly, modifers, whether phrasal or not, precede
their heads in the typical case in English, and since we have assumed that
NO compounds are merely a type of modifcation, we would expect that
compounds are right-headed. Thus in order to determine the head, the
syntax would merely need to take note of the kind of relationship-i. e. ,
modifcation-holding between the members of the compound, and fx the
head on the right. D&W, in claiming that English phrases are left headed,
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 171
have missed the locally more relevant point that in modifer-head construc
tions in English the head is on the right.
Of course, in deriving compound headedness in this way, we fail to link
the right-headedness of compounds with the right-headedness of words in
English: for example, many people (e.g. , see Williams 1981, and also Lieber
1980) have argued that the head of, say, grmmaticality is the sufx -ity
since that determines the category. Williams' Righthand Head Rule explic
itly links compounds with afx right-headedness. We think, in contrat,
that the two should not be linked, at least synchronically. The fact that it
is typically sufxes and rarely prefxes that function a heads of words is
almost surely related to the cross-linguistic prevalence of sufxation, which
in turn may have psycholinguistic bases (see Cutler et al. 1985) . Thus it
seems plausible to view the right-headedness of English compounds and the
right-headedness of English afxation a a coincidence, in the sense that
they are not diverse expressions of a single fact about English grammar.
20
Indeed, we would expect languages with left-headed modifcation struc
tures by and large to also show left-headed compounds if they have com
pounding, no matter what the headedness of afxation is. This appears
to be correct, a examples fom French, discussed in Selkirk 1982, or from
Spanish, Breton "loose compounding" (Stump 1989) or Zhuang (Ramsey
1987) .
2
1
For frther discussion of this and related points see Lieber 1988,
1992, Baker 1988, and especially Clements 1989:
( 107) a. timbres-poste (stamps post) ' postage stamps'
b. los coches Chevrolet
c. Breton: kaoc' h kezeg (dung horse) ' horse dung'
(cf. paotr brav (boy fne) 'a fne boy' )
2
0
0f course, this is not to say that all other patterns would have been equally likely, or
that the two fats about English are not connected historically. As Cutler et al. 1985
show (see, e.g., pp. 727f), there is a positive cross-linguistic correlation between sufxing
and phrasal right-headedness. In particular, right-headed languages-Object-Verb and
Postpositional languages-show an overwhelming preference to be exclusively sufxing.
Left-headed languages mostly have both prefxes and sufxes, and prefx-only languages
are very rare and are apparently always phraally left-headed. English descends from
languages which were phraally right-headed, a did Latin, from which half of English
afxational morphology comes. English prehead modifcation is likely to be a living fossil
of the former right-headed syntax. So right-headed compounding may be historically
related to right-headed afxation in English, by a history which makes crucial excursions
into the syntax.
2
1We should note that Welsh, which ha left-headed modifcation structures, has a
number of frozen right-headed compounds: ysgolfeistr (school-mater) 'school mater';
rheilfordd orsaf (rail road station) 'railway station'. Some examples, such a the second
one, are clearly translation borrowings from English, and in any event this kind of
compounding is not productive in Welsh. Breton "strict compounds" (Stump 1989) are
also right-headed. Note that Welsh (and also Irish, Breton, French and Spanish) does
retain a few prenominal adjectival modifiers and so it may well be the cae that Celtic and
Romance languages are only somewhat further along the transition to left-headedness
than is English.
172 I MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
d. Zhuang: kaiS-pou4 (chicken male) 'rooster'
(cf., sail moS rau2 (book new our) 'our new book')
Concerning the Fench examples, D&W claim (p. 83) that "Selkirk misanal
ysed fxed phrases such as timbres-poste as 'lef-headed compounds, ' thus
concluding that Fench morphology is a mixture of left- and right-headed
structures (since afxation in Fench is clearly right-headed) . This is a
clear example of a generalization compromised by the failure to properly
separate syntax and morphology. "
This attack can easily be turned around, however: by insisting that mor
phological constructions, including compounds, must obey the Righthand
Head Rule, D&W make it impossible both to recognize as compounds many
constructions which any frst-order description would classif as such, and
to state the very clear generalization that compounds in a language gen
erally follow the ordering of modifer-head constructions in that language.
In the other direction, relying on the Righthand Head Rule as a correlate
of "morphological" constructions would prevent us fom noting properties
that left-headed examples in other languages may share with English com
pound nouns. Thus in caes like carne de burro (meat of donkey) ' donkey
meat' in Spanish, it is essential that the complement phrase de burro, like
the modifers in English compounds, not be a full DP. With an article,
the phrase care del burro ' meat of the donkey' would not serve to refer
to the generic substance donkey meat. Care de burro, while having clear
phrasal properties, equally clearly has properties commonly associated with
compounds.
Separation from syntax. The other half of D&W's claim about the sta
tus of compounds is based upon the apparent atomicity of words fom
the point of view of syntax. In saying that compounds are atomic, D&W
are buying into the familiar claims of lexical integrity (see, e. g. , Mohanan
1986, pp. 24-2S) which say that the syntax (or subsequent components) can
have no access to the internals of words. To substantiate this claim, D&W
present evidence that appears to show that various syntactic phenomena
fail to make use of information internal to compounds. The strength of the
evidence, however, fades rapidly on serious examination.
Consider, for example, the observation (D&W, p. 49) that rules of syn
tax cannot "discriminate among compounds whose nonhead members are
plural or singular, " so that the parks commissioner is treated by all rele
vant syntactic rules exactly the same way as the park commissioner. This
seems simply to be an observation about headedness: in exactly the same
way, relevant syntactic rules will not distinguish the commissioner of meats
from the commissioner of meat. Since plurality is not being registered on
the head of the noun phrase in either case, any syntactically relevant rule
which cares about number (such as verb agreement) will register the gram
matical number of the head and not be afected by the plurality of modifers
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 173
or complements. In this respect there is absolutely nothing special about
the compound case: one does not need to appeal to the existence of a
separate morphological component to derive the relevant properties of the
parks commissioner.
A second set of examples concerns cases like * it robber (see D& W, p. 50)
or * who killer, which are argued to show that referential expressions, which
are relevant to the syntax, may not occur within words. But, as we have
already suggested (Section 4. 1 ) , there seems to be a constraint ruling out
any kind of derivation fom closed-class items; alternatively, one could claim
that no projection of functional categories can serve as modifers. In any
case, we have argued that modifers-whether at the NO or the N
1
level
are maximally X
l
, thus ruling out a whole clas of DP or DegP modifers.
These considerations subsume D&W's facts. Referential expressions are
not in principle ruled out from occurring within words, but only those
expressions which have the above mentioned forms. Proper names can
certainly occur within compounds although D&W suggest that: (i) only
famous names really allow this, since * Bill admirer is supposedly unac
ceptable; and that (ii) even in such cases a Nixon admirer, Nixon doesn't
really refer to Nixon. We briefy examine these claims.
With respect to the second claim, it has been argued extensively in
Sproat and Ward 1987 and Ward et al. 1991, that names which are mor
phologically contained within compounds can indeed be used to refer to
particular individuals, and this can be seen by the fact that such names
can function as antecedents to pronouns:
22
( 1 08) a. There's a Thurberi-story about hisi maid . . .
b. I was reading this Peggy Noonalli book on heri years at the White
House . . .
c. We went up to Constablei country; we stayed in the village hei
was born in.
D&W's own evidence for their claim concerning the referentiality of Nixon
in Nixon admirer is the assertion that in ( 109a) , admiring Nixon is not an
essential property of a Nixon admirer, since this example is not a contra
diction, unlike ( 109b) :
( 109) a. John is a Nixon admirer i n every sense except that he does not
admire Nixon.
b. John admires Nixon in every sense except that he does not admire
Nixon.
Ward et al. ( 1991 , footnote 16) have argued that ( 109a) is only non
contradictory under the interpretation of Nixon admirer as a person with
a reliable set of traits (such as being clean-shaven, wearing a three-piece
suit and always carrying an attache case) which are independent of the
22
Contrary to the predictions of the socalled Anaphoric Island constrint (Postal 1969).
174 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
property of admiring Nixon: in other words, Nixon admirer would have to
have accreted additional meanings via institutionalization, along the lines
of Maoist. In that case a person might be said to have those properties and
thus qualif as being a Nixon admirer, even if he or she does not actually
admire Nixon; hence ( 109a) would not be a contradiction. Needless to say,
Nixon admirer has not achieved this institutionalized status in the minds
of most speakers, and the contrast in ( 109) is therefore very hard to get.
More important for D&W's argument, however, is the observation that
the putative accretion of such institutionalized meanings is largely orthog
onal to the issue of whether Nixon in Nixon admirer can be used to refer
to Nixon. Hence, even making the counterfactual assumption that the con
trast in ( 109) were a clear one, that would not serve to support D&W's
claim concerning the referential properties of compound-internal elements.
Returning to point (i), the obvious question which arises when con
fonted with an example like Bill admirer is: who is Bill? One might
suppose that Bill admirer ought to be able to mean something like 'one
who admires people with the name Bill' , but there is really no reason to
believe that it should have this reading: in its typical phraal usage, a
proper name like Bill is invariably used to refer to a specifc individual.
Therefore one would expect Bill in Bill admirer also to be used to refer
to some specifc individual, and if we do not know who that individual is,
the example seems odd. The oddity is reinforced by the fact that, as is
well-known, "agentive" nominals tend to have a "habitual" reading, and
are typically used to refer to characteristic properties. To ascribe to some
one the characteristic property of admiring some unspecifed person named
Bill seems odd indeed. Naturally, famous names do not have this problem,
since there is no question about the intended referents of the names. And
Bill admirer is, it seems to us, fne in a context where the interlocutors can
assign a defnite referent to Bill.
Still, there is no question that frst names generally seem somewhat
degraded over last names in such contexts: compare ? Noam admirer with
Chomsky admirer. At least in part this seems to have to do with the fact
admirer has an institutionalized connotation of 'admires in the professional
sense' , and this in turn requires that the admired individual be referred
to using their normal professional designation, typically the lat name. 23
But familiarity or conventional designation are clearly extragrammatical
considerations, and there is no reason to suppose that there should be a
statement in the grammar of English nominal compounds restricting the
occurrence of proper names in that context.
23
A similar constraint applies to cases of deferred reference (thanks to Mats Rooth for
the second example):
i. You'll fi nd Chomsky on the top shelf.
ii. ?#You'll fnd Noam on the top shelf.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 175
In summary, we do not fnd any of the reasons adduced by D&W for sep
arating compounding from phrasal constructions to be compelling. There
fore it seems possible to accept the assumption that English NO compounds
are word-level objects that are formed in the syntax.
5 Two Approaches to Parsing and Stress Assignment
We turn now fom the descriptive and theoretical issues which have occu
pied us for the bulk of this paper to the issue to which we would ultimately
like to provide a solution, or at least a good approximation thereto, namely
the correct parsing of and stress assignment to modifed nominals as they
occur in unrestricted text. We outline here some of the methods we have
applied to solving this problem.
It is of practical concern that the correct stress pattern for a sequence
[N N] or [A N] cannot be generally predicted fom the preterminal sequence
of categories alone. That is, if we know that we have a sequence of two
nouns, we cannot be certain that we have an NO as opposed to an N1 for
a parent category, though if the preterminal sequence were all we could
compute, guessing NO would more often lead to a correct stress assignment
than guessing N
1
. In general, some other type of analysis is necessary. In
addition to the problem of deciding upon the appropriate stress assignment
to a binary modifed noun, there is the at leat equally difcult problem
of parsing more complex cases. As we shall see, the two problems, stress
assignment and parsing, are related in the methodologies which one can
apply to them. We shall frst turn to the problem of stress assignment, and
then consider parsing.
5. 1 Stress Assignment in Binary Nominals
The phrase safety board has main stress on the left. As we have argued
for other cases in the text, we might decide this because the phrase is an
instance of a semantic pattern, informally stated as Nl GROUP-WHOSE
CONCERN-IS-Nl. In Sproat and Liberman 1987 and Sproat 1990, we show
that a rather crude implementation of such a method can improve consid
erably on the performance of an approach based purely on the syntactic
categorization of the words in the text stream. However, as we noted in
our discussion of the semantic patterns of argument-argument compounds,
it is not at all clear on what basis a single, consistent, coherent set of such
schemata can be defned.
Alternatively, we might depend on the fact that the words in the phrase
safety board tend to yield a left-dominant stress pattern in other cases. So
one might expect that the probability that the nominal will be stressed on
the left given that the frst word is safety and the second board is greater
than the probability of righthand stress under those conditions, or in other
words:
176 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
p(s
l
l w
l
=safety) p(S
l
l w2
=board) ` p(s
2
l wl =safety) p(s
2
I
w
2
=board)
A survey of examples fom a large corpus of naturally-occurring pre
modifed nominals shows that this is indeed the case-safety as a noun
modifer wa always stress-dominant, while board when pre-modifed by a
noun was never stress-dominant. A representative sample:
( 110) a. safety belt, safety binding, safety council, safety devices, safety
equipment, safety feature, safety glasses, safety harness, safety
margin, safety meaure, safety net, safety nut, safety precautions,
safety problem, safety procedure, safety razor, safety record, safety
regulations, safety requirement, safety rule, safety school, safety
shoes, safety standards
b. Federal Reserve board, advisory board, bulletin board, chalk
board, chess board, circuit board, cutting board, dart board, draf
board, drawing board, governing board, ironing board, memory
board, particle board, planning board, promotion board, school
board, score board, skate board, supervisory board, surf board,
wall board, zoning board
Although most examples are not as clear-cut as this one, we believe that
the method can work fairly well if properly trained. Its main drawback is
that many words do not occur often enough in the needed constructions to
generate useful statistics-it seems appropriate, in such cases, to depend
on the observed behavior of "similar" words. The crux of the matter is
then the similarity metric to be used.
5. 2 Parsing Premodifed Nominals
Again, we have explored two methods. One approach would use phrasal
schemata of the kind used in assigning stress to decide upon a possible
analysis for a modifer-head string; one might frther extend such a method
along the lines of Finin 1980 by adding scores for the various schemata, and
pick the parse whose cumulative score is highest. This approach ha the
previously noted difculties of creating a reasonable set of schemata, and,
if scores are used, also the problem of juggling the interaction of possibly
ad hoc scores, endemic to diagnostic systems of this type. Nevertheless,
if the schemata are chosen so as to refect the patterns found in a certain
genre of text, the technique can work reasonably well.
A system of this kind currently under development in the context of
Bell Labs ongoing text-to-speech efort is reported in Sproat 1990,2
4
and is
an extension of earlier work reported in Sproat and Liberman 1987. The
program depends on semantic patterns of the kind described in this paper
a well as large lists of common binary nominals to attempt to compute
24
The scoring method alluded to above for picking among various possible semantic
interpretations is not implemented in the system reported in Sproat 1990, though various
a hoc heuristics are used to pick one of several possible analyses.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 177
a reasonable structure of multiply modifed nominal phrases. As a simple
example consider a semantic grammar which contains information that ta
ble, chair and some other items are HOUSEWAR&j that kitchen, bathroom
and living room are ROOMs (and incidentally also NO, this latter informa
tion being crucial for the binary cases) j and that there is a pattern, which
says that a ROOM word and a HOUSEWARE word may be combined into
an Nl , which we will call a ROOM&THING. this rule can be thought of
a an instance of the pattern PLACE-WHERE-N2-IS-FOUND N2 discussed in
( 70). In addition to semantic grammar rules and the rather large lexicon
of binary cases, there are more traditional syntactic rules which handle
syntactic aspects of noun phrase structure, such as the treatment of deter
miners. The system in its current form can asign appropriate structure
and stress to noun phraes such as the following:
( 1 1 1 )
John's]
large
(t',ROOM&THING)
(t,ROOM)
living
room]
(t ,
HOUSEWARE)
table]]]]
In this example, living room is correctly analyzed as a modifer of N
l
.
Another module of the program responsible for assigning stress can then
take this assigned structure and determine that the main stress should be
placed on the head noun in this case.
The second approach to parsing again relies on the statistical behavior
of individual words, identifing the afnity of two adjacent words with the
extent to which they occur together more often than one would predict
baed on how often they occur individually. One reasonable measure for
such afnity might be MUTUAL INFORMATION, where the mutual informa
tion I(a, b) between events A and B with probabilities p(a) and p(b) is
defned a
( 1 12) I(a, b) log
2
J
Mutual information meaures have been used recently by Sproat and Shih
( 1990a)25 in a domain rather similar to the current one, namely the prob
lem of locating word boundaries in Chinese text. Chinese orthography, of
course, traditionally does not indicate the location of word boundaries, but
it turns out that considerations of the strengths of association between ad
jacent characters in a Chinese text, as measured by mutual information can
achieve about 95% retrieval and precision for two-character words (which
constitute the bulk of multicharacter words in Chinese text) .
However, there is a problem with defning the association measure
strictly in terms of mutual information as defned above. Instances of the
sequence ABC in fact give us no information about the relative afnity of
B for A a opposed to C, so if a signifcant faction of (say) AB instances
occur in ABC sequences, while BC is quite a bit more common outside
2
5
8ee also Magerman ad Marcus 1990 for more extensive use of mutual information in
parsing.
1 78 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
A B C AB BC ABC
F F F F I IX F I I X F
i
nteragency task forcers)
35 756 6909 4 10.83 00 287 10.07 IUU 4
environmental imp
act statement(s)
801 1110 4626 25 8.40 7.U 1 6 5.23 3.25 12
p
rivate arm
s
d
ealer(s)
3296 3822 1059 21 4.32 4.02 57 7.40 7.U 4
electoral college system(s)
405 1949 4691 93 10.47 9.29 62 9. 23 2.04 59
Table 1
these sequences, then a high value for I(A, B) will be misleading. It is bet
ter to compute a mutual-information-like afnity measure that excludes
the useless ABC instances fom the counts. If we use -T to refer to the
complement of the cases in which T is found, our afnity estimate for words
A and B within the ternary unit T becomes:
( 1 13)
Now, compare the right-branching ternary nominal interagency task jorce
and private arms dealer with the left-branching ternary nominals environ
mental impact statement and electoral college system. In a 12-million-word
sample of the Associated Press newswire, things work out as in Table 1 .
I n this example, the IX measure
2
6 gives the correct analyses, while the
I measure fails for the case of interagency task jorce, which ha the noted
property in that the sequence interagency task never occurs other than
in the larger fame. In general, the IX measure gives a stronger indica
tion of afnity in the correct direction, even where the I measure is also
correct.
Methods of this general type have a great deal of promise as aids to
parsing in the all-too-common cases where structural indications are weak
or lacking. However, it would be desirable to consider, in estimating the
afnity between two words, the distribution of "similar" words. 27 Also,
the generalization of the simple ternary cae to more elaborate structures
can be done in a variety of ways, and it is not trivial to fnd methods
that are both tractable and correct. We believe that the analyses given in
this paper will help to guide such explorations in sensible and productive
directions.
26
Note that we are using JJ to refer to the cae where a pair does not occur other than
in the triple.
2
7
Indeed, one of the problems encountered in using this statistical meaure a an a
ditional option in the system reported in Sproat 1990 is that there is often not enough
data about particular pairs of words in a gven triple to estimate IX, even if one uses a
moderately large corpus of about 10 million words.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 179
References
Abney, Steven. 1987. The English Noun Phrase in its Sentential Aspect. Doctoral
dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Baker, Mark. 1988. Morphological and Syntactic Objects: A review of Di Sciullo
and Williams' LL ILC 1CDL1I10L 0!W01O. Morhology Yearbook 1 :259-283.
Bauer, Lauri. 1983. English Word-Formation. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Bliberg, O. 1988. A Study of Swedish Compounds. Doctoral dissertation, Umea
University.
Bolinger, Dwight. 1967. Adjectives in English: Attribution and Predication.
Lingua 18: 1-34.
Bolinger, Dwight. 1972. Accent is Predictable (if you're a mind-reader) . Language
48:633-644.
Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on Nominalization. In Readings in English
Transformational Grammar, ed. Roderick A. Jacobs and Peter S. Rosenbaum,
184-221. Waltham, Massachusetts: Ginn and Company.
Chomky, Noam, and Morris Halle. 1968. The Sound Patter of English. New
York: Harper and Row.
Clements, J. 1989. Lexical Category Hierarchy and Syntactic Headedness in
Compounds. In Proceedings of the 6th Annual Easter States Conference on
Linguistics, 46-57.
Cutler, Anne, John Hawkins, and Gary Gilligan. 1985. The Sufxing Preference:
A Processing Explanation. Linguistics 23: 723-758.
Di Sciullo, Anne-Marie, and Edwin Williams. 1987. On the Defnition of Word.
Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Downing, Pamela A. 1977. On the Creation and Use of English Compound
Nouns. Language 53:810-842.
Dowty, David. 1979. Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Fabb, Nigel. 1984. Syntactic Afxation. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts
Institute of Technology.
Finin, Timothy W. 1980. The Semantic Interpretation of Compound Nominals.
Doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Fudge, Erik. 1984. English Word-Stress. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Hayes, Bruce. 1980. A Metrical Theory of Stress Rules. Doctoral dissertation,
Masachusetts Institute of Technology (distributed by IDLe) .
Hirschberg, Julia. 1990. Using Discourse Context to Guide Pitch Accent Deci
sions in Synthetic Speech: The given/new distinction and deaccentability. In
Proceedings of AAAI-90, 952-957.
Hoeksema, Jacob. 1985. Categorial Morphology. New York: Garland Publishers.
Jackendof, Ray. 1977. X-bar Syntax: a Study of Phrase Structure. Cambridge,
Mass. : MIT Press.
Kiparsky, Paul. 1982. Lexical Morphology and Phonology. In Linguistics in the
Moring Calm, ed. I.-S. Yang, 3-91. Seoul: Hanshin.
180 / MARK LIBERMAN AND RICHARD SPROAT
Ladd, Robert. 1984. English Compound Stress. In Intonation, Accent and
Rhythm, ed. Dafydd Gibbon and Helmut Richter, 253-266. Berlin: Mou
ton de Gruyter.
Lees, Robert B. 1960. The Grammar of English Nominalizations. Interational
Joural of American Linguistics, Publication 12.
Levi, Judith N. 1978. The Syntax and Semantics of Complex Nominals. New
York: Academic Press.
Levin, Beth, and MaIka Rappaport. 1992. -Er Nominals: Implications for a
Theory of Argument-structure. In Syntax and Semantics 26: Syntax and the
Lexicon, ed. Eric Wehrli and Tim Stowell. New York: Academic Press.
Liberman, Mark, and Alan Prince. 1977. On Stress and Linguistic Rhythm.
Linguistic Inquiry 8:249-336.
Lieber, Rochelle. 1981. The Organization of the Lexicon. Doctoral dissertation,
Masachusetts Institute of Technology.
Lieber, Rochelle. 1983. Argument Linking and Compounds in English. Linguistic
Inquiry 14:251-286.
Lieber, Rochelle. 1988. Phrasal Compounds in English and the Morphology
Syntax Interface. In Papers from the 24th Regional Meeting of the Chicago
Linguistic Society, 398-405. University of Chicago.
Lieber, Rochelle. 1992. Deconstructing Morhology: Word Formation in Syntac
tic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Magerman, David, and Mitchell Marcus. 1990. Parsing a Natural Language Using
Mutual Information Statistics. In Proceedings of AAAI-90, 984-989.
Maidment, J. A. 1989. On the Accentuation of Compounds in English. In Speech,
Hearing and Language: Work in Progress, 181-188. University College, Lon
don.
Marantz, Alec. 1989. Projection vs. Percolation in the Syntax of Synthetic Com
pounds. Manuscript, University of North Carolina.
Marchand, Hans. 1969. The Categories and Types of Present-Day English Word
Formation. Miinchen: C. H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
Mohanan, K. P. 1986. The Theory of Lexical Phonology. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Postal, Paul. 1969. Anaphoric Islands. In Papers from the 5th Regional Meeting
of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 205-239. University of Chicago.
Ramsey, S. Robert. 1987. The Languages of China. Princeton: Princeton Uni
versity Press.
Roeper, Thomas, and Mufy Siegel. 1978. A Lexical Tansformation for Verbal
Compounds. Linguistic Inquiry 9: 199-260.
Safr, Ken. 1987. The Syntactic Projection of Lexical Thematic Structure. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 5:561-602.
Selkirk, Elizabeth. 1984. Phonology and Syntax. Cambridge, Mas. : MIT Press.
Selkirk, Elizabeth O. 1982. The Syntax of Words. Cambridge, Mas. : MIT Press.
Sproat, Richard. 1985. On Deriving the Lexicon. Doctoral dissertation, Mas-
sachusetts Institute of Technology.
Sproat, Richard. 1990. Stress Assignment in Complex Nominals for English Text
to-Speech. In Proceedings of ESCA Workshop on Speech Synthesis, 129-132.
STRESS AND STRUCTURE OF MODIFIED NOUN PHRASES / 181
Sproat, Richard, and Mark Liberman. 1987. Toward Teating English Nominals
Correctly. In Proceedings of the 25th Annual Meeting of the Association for
Computational Linguistics, 140-146. Association for Computational Linguis
tics.
Sproat, Richard, and Chi-lin Shih. 1990a. A Statistical Method for Finding Word
Boundaries in Chinese Text. Computer Processing of Chinese and Oriental
Languages 4:336-351 .
Sproat, Richard, and Chi-lin Shih. 1990b. The Cross-linguistic Distribution of
Adjective Ordering Restrictions. In Interdisciplinary Approaches to Language,
ed. Carol Georgopoulos and Roberta Ishihara, 563-593. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers.
Sproat, Richard, and Gregory Ward. 1987. Pragmatic Considerations in
Anaphoric Island Phenomena. In Papers from the 23rd Regional Meeting
of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 321-335. University of Chicago.
Stump, Greg. 1989. A Note on Breton Pluralization and the Elsewhere Condition.
Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 7: 261-273.
Thomaon, Richard. 1985. Some Issues Concerning the Interpretation of Derived
and Gerundive 'Nominals' . Linguistics and Philosophy 8: 73-80.
Ward, Gregory, Richard Sproat, and Gail McKoon. 1991 . A Pragmatic Analysis
of So-called Anaphoric Islands. Language 67(3) :439-474.
Williams, Edwin. 1981. On the Notions 'Lexically Related' and ' Head of a Word' .
Linguistic Inquiry 12:245-274.
.
Figure 1
produces the causative irat ' make write', which can further be expanded
by adding to it the perfectivizing prefx meg- resulting in megirat or one of
the prefxes Jel-, ki-, le- yielding Jelirat , kiirat, ldrat .
It should also be noted that each form i n Figure 1 can further be ex
panded by the possibility sufx - hat meaning 'may, can', e. g. , irhat ' may
be writing', megirathat 'may make write down', kiir6dhat ' may get writ
ten/copied out' , etc.
Notice that all the derivatives except for those with the prefxes Jel-,
ki-, le-, have got a transparent semantics, their meanings are fully pre
dictable on the bais of the meanings of their constituent morphemes. In
other words, the meanings of these derivatives are compositionally deriv
able. In contrast, the derivatives with the prefxes Jel-, ki-, le- are, in
general, semantically not transparent, their meanings cannot be predicted
on the basis of the meaning of their constituent morphemes. That is, these
meanings are not compositionally derivable.
It should be noted that the verbs with the prefxes Jel- 'up', ki- 'out',
le- 'down' , be- 'in' , el- 'away' , etc. , are semantically opaque just in case
they don't denote mere direction. As long as they are used in their original
meanings, they are completely transparent, e. g. , ki +megy 'go out' , be+nez
'look in' , Jel+huz 'draw up, hoist' .
194 / FERENC KIEFER
Since we have been assuming that the more semantic material a form
contains, the more complex it is semantically, in order to establish the se
mantic complexity relationship between two derivationally related forms it
sufces to determine the relative amount of the semantic material contained
in the two forms. As we saw above, perfective forms contain more semantic
material than the corresponding imperfectives and some perfective forms
(i. e. , those with a prefx whose function is more than just perfectivization)
are semantically richer than simple perfective forms, where the perfective
prefx carries perfective meaning only. In what follows we will reserve the
label 'perfective' to denote such simple perfective forms, the semantically
more complex perfectives will be termed 'qualifed perfective' . The above
observations yield the following complexity relationships.s
( 12) a. imperfective <sem
perfective
b. perfective <sem
qualifed perfective
It is also evident that causatives are semantically more complex than non
cauatives. Furthermore, it would seem that passives are, in general, se
mantically more complex than the corresponding actives. That is, we get
( 13a)-( 13b). 9
( 13) a. non-causative <sem
causative
b. active <sem
passive
Frequentatives contain more semantic material than the corresponding du
ratives, as pointed out above, hence
(14)
durative <sem
fequentative
The impersonal passive and the passive do not seem to difer fom each
other with respect to semantic complexity, that is, the relationship (13b)
is valid for both passives.
In sum, the operations denoted by PERF, CAUS, PASS, IMP.PASS,
FREQU introduce additional semantic material which motivates the rela
tionships ( 12a), (13a)-( 13b) and ( 14) . In Hungarian these operations are
refected in morphology as shown by Figure 1.
If we also take into account the possibility sufx -hat/-het, we may posit
( 15) non-modal <sem
modal
where ' modal' refers to a form expressing possibility and 'non-modal' to
the corresponding "factual."
8
We have already introduced the symbol ' <' for the relation of morphological com
plexity (cf. example (3) ) . For syntatic complexity we may use the symbol ' <_` , for
semantic complexity the symbol ' <_,` and for pragmatic complexity the symbol ' <g` ,
respectively.
9
Complexity relationships such a ( 12a) and ( 13a)-(13b) have been treated in earlier
literature under the heading of markedness. See, for example, Lapointe 1986, or for
structuralist treatments of the problem, Greenberg 1966 and Hjelmslev 1953. It ha,
however, not always been made clear whether these relationships refer to the "content
plane" or to the "expression plane."
HUNGARIAN DERIVATIONAL MORPHOLOGY / 195
Informally, the active, the passive and the causative may be character
ized by ( 16a)-(16c), respectively.
( 16) a. T does g
b. g is done by T
c. T causes to do g
It is therefore not at all surprising that on any analysis suggested so far the
causative is considered to be semantically more complex than the passive
and the passive semantically more complex than the active. lO That is,
we get
( 17) active <sem
passive <sem
causative
For the lexical feld of ir 'write' in Figure 1, the complexity relations for
mulated thus far yield, among other things, the following complexity or
derings.
(18) a.
b.
c.
d.
e.
ir
'write'
<sem irogat
'write little
by little'
<s
em
felirogat
<se
r felirogathat
'write up little ' may write up
by little' little by little'
ir <sem
megir <sem
megirhat
'write' ' write down'
ir <sem
irat
'write' ' make write'
' may write down'
<se
r megirat <s
em
'make write
down'
ir <se
r ir6dik <sem {rat
'write' ' be/get written' ' make write'
megirathat
' may make
write down'
felir
<sem
felir6dik <sem
felirat
'write down,
prescribe'
'befget written 'make write down,
down, be/get make prescribe'
prescribed'
In the cases discussed thus far there is an interesting correlation be
tween semantic complexity and morphological complexity. There are no
two forms such that the semantically more complex form be morphologi
cally less complex. In the case of ( 18d) , on the other hand, the semanti
cally more complex form does not always show an increase in morphological
complexity. In particular, the forms ir6dik 'be/get written' and irat ' make
write' are both bimorphemic. In sum, it would seem that the following rule
holds. 1 1
( 19) By increasing semantic complexity, morphological complexity does
not decrease.
l
OSee Lapointe 1986 (p. 224).
l l
This holds within a semantic feld defned by the rules of derivational morphology,
of course. In view of the language-specifc defnition of morphological complexity, this
correlation, too, ha to be considered to be language-specifc.
196 / FERENC KIEFER
As to the syntactic properties, the situation is as follows: ir 'write' and
irogat 'write little by little, write fequently' do not require an overt object
in contrat to irat ' make write' , megirat ' make write down' , felirt ' make
write down, prescribe', felirogat 'write down repeatedly' , megir 'write
down' , felir 'write down' which cannot occur without an overt object (ex
cept elliptically) . The impersonal passive (refexive) forms are used with
out an agent: ir6dik 'be /get written', megir6dik 'be/get written down',
felir6dik 'be/get prescribed'. The pasive form irtik, megiratik, felirtik
with the same meaning may be used with an agent, the agent is expressed
by a by-phrae. That is, we have to do here with four degrees of syntactic
complexity: the forms with an optional object are syntactically less com
plex than the forms that require an overt object which in turn are less
complex than the passive forms. Furthermore, the impersonal pasive is
syntactically less complex than the agentive passive. For the forms of ir,
then, it would seem that a similar correlation holds between semantic and
syntactic complexity as between semantic and morphological complexity.
The following rule seems to be valid:
(20) By increasing semantic complexity syntactic complexity does not
decrease.
1
2
The following example shows that the derivational expansions of a word
may all be opaque. Figure 2 depicts the derivational expansions of the verb
beszel 'talk' .
DUR PERF
'talk' 'chat, converse' 'chat, converse'
~
beszel beszelget ---. elbeszelget
DUR 1
elbeszel
,
,
t '
megbeszel
narra e
' d'
,
I5CH55
rabeszel
'persuade'
lebeszel
'dissuade'
Figure 2
What may strike us at frst glance is that, in general, the various
derivational expansions of beszel 'talk' are not semantically transparent:
beszelget 'chat, converse' is not simply the durative counterpart of beszel,
similarly megbeszel 'discuss' is not the perfective variant of beszel. Nev-
12
Since the defnition of syntactic complexity given above, however restricted it may be,
is not language-specifc, (20) could, in principle, be a good candidate for being universal.
HUNGARIAN DERIVATIONAL MORPHOLOGY / 197
ertheless, the forms beszelget and elbeszelget, 'chat, converse' are dura
tive and the prefxed variants of beszel are in a way perfective. Conse
quently, megbeszel ' discuss' , in contrast to beszel, must contain a resul
tative component in its semantic representation. Furthermore, beszelget
'chat, converse' presupposes at least two participants, which beszel does
not. Consequently, it seems to be quite plausible to assume that beszelget
'chat, converse' is semantically more complex than beszel and elbeszelget
(at least if used transitively with the meaning 'pass time in conversation',
see below) semantically more complex than beszelget. Similarly, megbeszel
should be considered to be semantically more complex than beszel since
it demands that the topic be explicitly specifed. The verb elbeszel ' nar
rate' is even more complex than megbeszel ' discuss' since (i) the topic must
be a story and (ii) the report must be rather detailed. Furthermore, it
is easy to see that the verbs nibeszel 'persuade' and lebeszel 'dissuade' ,
too, contain more semantic material than megbeszel ' discuss' . That is, the
complexity relations are not afected by the fact that all derivatives are
semantically opaque. This leads us to the formulation of the following
principle.
(21) The semantic complexity relations among derivationally related lex
ical items which are semantically opaque are the same as if these
lexical items were semantically transparent.
Principle (21) should be considered a a hypothesis about semantic com
plexity which must be tested on further material. 13
As to the relationship between semantic and morphological complexity,
the derivational expansions, a can easily be seen, obey rule ( 19).
Syntactically, beszelget 'chat, converse' requires either a plural argu
ment or two arguments but it is still intransitive. The verb elbeszelget has
two uses. On one of its uses it is synonymous with beszelget (i. e. , it is nei
ther transitive nor perfective). However, it may also be used transitively
with the object 'time' : 'pass time in conversation' . Megbeszel 'discuss'
and elbeszel ' narrate' always require an overt object, rabeszel 'persuade'
and lebeszel 'dissuade' have three arguments. All this seems to indicate
tat, in the cae of the derivational expansions of the verb beszel, too,
the relationship between semantic and syntactic complexity is governed by
rule (20).
The next example which we will discuss i s the basic verb of movement
mozog ' move' with the root moz- , whose derivational expansions are shown
in Figure 3.
The basic verb mozog is unspecifed as to direction and it is intransitive
and durative. From the root moz- one can derive the punctual mozdul
1
3
Principle (21) claims that the perfective operator makes the form more complex inde
pendently of whether the meaning arrived at is transparent or opaque. The same holds
true for the durative operator.
198 FERENC KIEFER
ERF
..
PUNCTUAL "
. .
..
. ..
TRANS-/ \ TRANS-
PERF-DIR {!:: }
FREQU PUNCTUAL
..
. .
. .sh
'
PEERF-DIR PERFR
.. .
..
{
. }
.
.
sh
I
f
.
..
Figure 3
' make a move' which can receive the perfective prefx meg- yielding meg
mozdul. Mozdul can also be prefxed by a directional prefx, e. g. , ki- 'out'
or el- 'away' resulting in kimozdul ' move out' or elmozdul ' move away' .
The intransitive mozog ,more precisely, the root moz- ) can be transitivized
in two diferent ways. The fequentative sufx -gat yields mozgat ' move
repeatedly' which is transitive and frequentative. This verb can be perfec
tivized by means of the perfective prefx meg- ( megmozgat ) or by means
of the perfective-directional prefx el- ( elmozgat ' move away' , . The other
transitive verb derived fom moz- is the punctual mozdi to which either
the perfective prefx meg- or one of the perfective-directional prefxes el
'away' , ki- 'out' can be added, which results in megmozdi ' move, shift' or
in elmozdi ' move away' , kimozdi ' move out' .
Notice that all the derivatives i n Figure 3 are semantically transparent.
Moreover, almost all of them can be rendered in English by the verb ' move'
which is a clear indication of how diferent Hungarian and English can be
with respect to lexical structure.
The complexity relations among the forms in Figure 3 are partly de
termined by directionality. In particular, the following complexity relation
holds.
(22) unspecifed <ser direction
where ' unspecifed' should be read "unspecifed with respect to direction."
(22) does not only account for the complexity relation between, say, meg
mozdi 'shift' and kimozdit 'get out of place' ,where both verbs are perfec
tive, but also covers the complexity relationship between such verb pairs
as nez 'look' and benez 'look in' ,where the frst verb is imperfective and
the second one has a perfective and an imperfective reading, .
Punctual verbs are more complex than durative verbs ,other things
HUNGARIAN DERIVATIONAL MORPHOLOGY / 199
being equal) , since only the latter, but not the former, are compati
ble with both durative and nondurative adverbials. Frthermore, punc
tual verbs can be used to express perfectivity even if they occur with
out a perfective prefx. The two sentences in (23a)-(23b) have identical
meanings.
(23) a. A ko mozdult egyet .
the stone move-Past one-Acc
'The stone made a move'
b. A ko megmozdult.
'The stone made a move'
Consequently, we may posit
(24) durative <
se
r punctual
However, mozdul and megmozdul are not synonymous. Consider
(25) a. Mar mozdul a ko.
already move the stone
'The stone starts moving'
b.
*
Mar megmozdul a ko.
As testifed by (25a) mozdul 'start moving' has an inchoative meaning
which is absent in megmozdul. In general, verbs with a perfective prefx
cannot refer to on-going processes or activities, they don't have any present
tense meaning. The verb megmozdul is semantically more complex than
the verb mozdul.
4 Pragmatic Complexity
As we have seen above, each derivational morpheme contributes to the
meaning of the "input. " There are no derivational afxes (in Hungarian)
without any content. Their contribution need not be semantic, however.
Let's explore this question in some more detail.
The diminutive sufx -i is used to form nouns fom nouns in two
ways.
(i) -i is added to the truncated form of the initial noun, e. g. , csok+i
(from csokotadi 'chocolate' ) , dir+i (fom direktor 'director' ), ov+i
(from ovoda 'kindergarten' ) , fagy+i (fom fagylalt ' ice cream' ).
(ii) The sufx - i i s added to the stem of the noun, e. g. , tab+i (fom tab
' foot' ) , comb+i (from comb ' thigh' ) , has+i (fom has 'belly' ), husi
(from hus 'meat' ) .
Words i n group ( i ) belong to school slang. They presuppose a cer
tain degree of intimacy and have ofen a jocular touch. The form in (ii),
on the other hand, belong to nursery talk: they are typically used in a
discourse in which at leat one small child participates. In neither cae,
however, does the sufx -i denote smallness. In fact, pairs such a fagy+i
200 / FERENC KIEFER
and fagylalt ' ice cream' or has+i and has 'belly' are truth-conditionally
identical. What is then the contribution of the sufx -i to the meaning
of the stem noun? It can determine the social setting of the speech sit
uation (in the case of (i) ) . The second case can also be characterized by
the label ' endearments'. Though these aspects of meaning are clearly con
ventional (they are not implicated "conversationally" ) , they are not truth
functional. Since, in principle, any conventional meaning can be accounted
for in semantics, the sufx i does not necessarily call for a pragmatic
explanation. 14
There are, however, cases which show that a derivational afx may
introduce non-conventional meaning as well. The example we are going
to consider comes from adjective morphology. 15 In addition to the posi
tive, the comparative and the superlative, Hungarian has got an excessive.
Consider
(26) a. nagy
'big'
b. okos
nagy+obb leg+nagy+obb legesleg+nagy+obb
'bigger' 'biggest' ' very biggest'
okos+abb leg+okos+abb legesleg+okos+abb
' clever' 'cleverer' 'cleverest' ' very cleverest'
The question immediately arises what the excessive means. The superla
tive already defnes the highest degree of the property at hand, Le. ,
T is
the biggest' means that fom among the things considered T possesses the
highest degree of the property at hand, that is, of being big. The excessive
cannot change this state of afairs; what it does is to introduce a presuppo
sition (and special discourse functions) . Recall that what is biggest need
not be big and who is cleverest need not be clever. In contrast, the thing
that is the very biggest must be big and the person who is the very clever
est must be clever. That is, the excessive turns a relative property into an
absolute one. The introduction of a (semantic) presupposition, as we saw
above, leads to a higher degree of semantic complexity.
As to its discourse function, notice that the excessive can be considered
as the emphatic variant of the superlative in a way. Emphasis is not neutral
contextually. For example, in general, one cannot start a conversation by
using the excessive. The excessive requires a context in which there is
a discussion about the highest degree of a property (or at least such a
discussion must be implicit in the context) . The person who uses the
excessive wants to emphasize his belief about the question: 'believe me,
this is the very best solution' or the like.
14This problem and similar phenomena were treated under the heading of morphoprag
matics in Dressler and Kiefer 1990.
1
5
Comparison of adjectives is traditionally treated in infectional morphology. In quite
a few respects, however, it is more like derivation. First of , the superlative prefx lQ-
can in no way be considered to be an infectional afx since Hungarian infectional afxes
are sufxes. Second, the semantic properties of the superlative are not comparable to
those of infectional paradigms.
HUNGARIAN DERIVATIONAL MORPHOLOGY / 201
The excessive does not always introduce a presupposition, however. I6
Take, for example,
(27) a. csunya csunYl+bb leg+csunyt+bb legesleg+csunyt+bb
' ugly' ' uglier' ' ugliest' 'very ugliest'
b. buta butt+bb leg+butt+bb legesleg+butt+bb
'stupid' ' more stupid' ' most stupid' lit. 'very stupidest'
Adjectives which express negative evaluation are, in general, used in an
absolute sense, i. e. , ' uglier' induces the presupposition that the things com
pared are both ugly and 'more stupid' induces the presupposition that the
things compared are both stupid. Similarly, if
HERCEGETI
IThough 1
in
( =V-mod 'be-')] showed \=introduced\ 1 the baron ( =nom) \to\
the . . . 1 I
( ' Though at the party the prince was introduced by the baron to
the . . . ' )
TOPIC
b. Ugyan 1 az estelyenl a herceget l mutatta be 1 a baro a . . . 1 *******
1
HERCEGETI
IThough 1
.
|
I
(' Though at the party it was the prince whom the baron intro
duced to the . . . ' )
(7) a. Ugyan 1 a gerillakl a herceget l elraboltak, 1 az ornagy a . . . 1 ******
1
HERCEGETI
IThough 1 the guerrillas (=nom) 1 the prince +t (=acc)]
1
Before the
clause-boundary
MAIN
`
`
`
`
g THOUGH /=' UGYAW/
IF /=' HA' /
After the
clause-boundary
Figure 2 The Accessibility of Initial Clause Topic Objects
as a Function of Clause Type and Clause Completeness:
Mean Probe Recognition Times
RT
920
(osee)
900
880
860
840
820
800
780
760
740
720
700
Before the
clause-boundary
MAIN
g THOUGH /='UGYAN'/
-
After the
clause-boundary
Figure 3 The Accessibility of Initial Clause Focus Objects
as a Function of Clause Type and Clause Completeness:
Mean Probe Recognition Times
Figure 2 shows that, as predicted, the topic objects from initial subor
dinate clauses (both 'if' and 'though' ) were more accessible when tested
222 / GYORGY GERGELY
during the second clause than before the end of the initial clause (F( l, 92)
12. 62, p < . 01) . In contrast, when the corresponding object noun were
contrastively focused, no increase in target accessibility was observed a
a function of the clause-boundary (see Figure 3). These fndings support
the hypothesis that topic objects fom initial subordinate clauses are fore
grounded at the clause-boundary as likely candidates for second clause an
tecedent matching.
The results also indicate that the selective foregrounding of an initial
clause constituent is a joint function of (i) the discourse role (topic versus
focus) of the constituent, and (ii) the sentence-initial conjunctions (' if' and
'though') marking the particular semantic relation between the two clausal
propositions. Thus, when no information is available about the interclausal
semantic relation, as in initial main clauses, the listener ha no sufcient
basis to compute predictive inferences about the expectable content of the
next clause. As a result, neither topic nor focus targets get foregrounded
at the clause-boundary (see Figures 2 and 3). In fact, irrespective of their
discourse role in the initial main clause, constituents became less accessible
after the claue-boundary than before it ( F( 1, 92) 14.04, p < . 01). This
can be interpreted a being due to a process of recoding at the end of
the clause, which discards the clausal representation from working memory
when no predictive hypothesis about its likely involvement in the processing
of the next clause can be generated.
To sum up: the results of the experiment support the hypothesis that
the asignment of discourse functions to constituents, apart fom initiating
a backward search for antecedent, also starts a complementary predictive
process. As a result, the initial clause constituent, that can be expected to
serve a the discourse antecedent for the next clause, is fore grounded (Le. ,
diferentially activated) at the clause-boundary. The discourse integra
tional function of the hypothesized process is that of feeding the backward
search for an antecedent in the upcoming clause by making the most likely
candidate fom the initial clause more accessible for efcient antecedent
matching.
8 Focus-Based Predictive Inferences in Clausal Processing
8. 1 Introduction
In this section I shall report an experiment to test the hypothesis that
during the comprehension of an initial ' though' clause (see Figure 1 ) the
listener computes focus-based inferences to predict the propositional con
tent of the upcoming clause. The hypothesized function of computing such
a predictive inferential structure is to facilitate the processing of the main
clause by anticipating its content.
I assume (see also Crain and Steedman 1985, Johnson-Laird 1984,
Marslen-Wilson et al. 1978) that as the listener proceeds in the sentence,
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 223
he attempts to directly construct an interpretational model of the speaker's
intended meaning. In doing so, he accesses his general pragmatic knowl
edge represented in memory structures such as scripts. The activated script
structure (together with the overall discourse structure) serves as the in
terpretational domain for the constructed representation. I assume that
TF structure guides the construction of such a representation by fore
grounding the focus-related parts of the interpretational domain. I hy
pothesize that the foregrounded parts receive a higher level of temporary
activation than the remaining ( backgrounded) aspects of the constructed
representation.
Consider the contribution of TF structure to the interpretation of initial
main clauses such as (5a) and (5b) above repeated here as (8a) and (8b):
TOPIC FOCUS
(8) a. Nagymama elmosta a tanyerokat a tegnapi Mzibuli utan, . , .
/[T: Grandmother ( =nom)] [F: away ( =V-mod)] + washed the
plates +t (=acc) yesterday +i (=adj ) party after, . . . /
( ' Grandmother ha washed the plates after yesterday's party')
TOPIC FOCUS
b. Nagymama a trnyerokat most a el a tegnapi Mzibuli utan, . . .
/[T: Grandmother (=nom)] [F: the plates +t (=acc)] wahed
away (=V-mod) yesterday +i (=adj ) party after, . . . /
( 'It was the plates that Grandmother has washed after yesterday's
party')
When hearing these clauses, the listener accesses the corresponding 'dish
washing' script in his memory. The script specifes that the typical input
state of the object (DIRTY) is transformed into its characteristic output
state ( CLEAN) as a result of washing. In (8a) the focus position is flled by
the verbal modifer el ( elmosta = 'has washed') which expresses the perfec
tivity of the wahing event. By hypothesis, then, the representation of the
object ('the plates' ) will be foregrounded with its output state property,
i. e. , CLEAN.
The situation i s diferent, however, i n (8b). Here the fact that Grand
mother has washed something is not in focus, and so it will be in the
backgrounded part of the representation. The contrastive focus on the ob
ject 'the plates' implies a set of other things which also could have become
washed, but were not. Therefore, it is hypothesized that in the constructed
representation for (8b) this implicit contrastive set will be foregrounded.
Since this set contains potential objects of washing, it is predicted that they
will be represented with the foregrounded property of their characteristic
input state, i. e. , DIRTY.
The present study tested these predictions i n an on-line probe nam
ing task. Subjects were presented with a word probe describing either the
224 / GYORGY GERGELY
foregrounded, or the backgrounded part of the constructed representation.
I assume that if foregrounding results in higher level of activation, then
a related word probe will be relatively more accessible (see e. g. , Morton
1969, Marslen-Wilson and Welsh 1978) due to spreading activation (e. g. ,
Collins and Lofus 1975) fom the foregrounded aspects of the interpreta
tional structure. Thus, the word probe ' dirty' , which describes the typical
input state of the potential objects of a washing-event, should be primed
in (8b), where DIRTY is hypothesized to be a foregrounded property of
the representation. It should be less accessible, however, in (8a) , where the
foregrounded object property is CLEAN.
Similar predictions can be developed for corresponding initial 'though'
(=' ugyan' in Hungarian) clauses, as in (9a) and (9b) below:
(9) a. Ugyan Nagymama elmosta a tanyerokat a tegnapi hazibuli utan,
b. Ugyan Nagymama a tanyerokat mosta el a tegnapi hazibuli utan,
In Section 4 I argued that the sentence-initial 'though' cues the listener to
generate predictive inferences about the content of the upcoming clause.
Let us consider (9a) . For the corresponding main clause in (8a) it wa
predicted that focusing the perfective verbal modifer 'el' would foreground
the representation of the object of washing with its typical output state
property, CLEAN. The initial 'though' , however, indicates that the next
clause will contain the denial of the focus-based consequence of the initial
clause (see Figure 1) . As a result, in (9a) the construction of the predictive
structure involves a further, adversative inferential step that transforms
the foregrounded representation of the output state of the object into its
opposite, i. e. , DIRTY. Therefore, in contrat to (8a) , the word probe 'dirty'
should become relatively more accessible in (9a) .
For (9b) , however, no corresponding facilitation of 'dirty' is predicted.
Here the predicate is not focused, and so the consequence of wahing
( CLEAN) will be in the backgrounded part of the representation. The
foregrounded focus-based consequence, that is expected to be denied in the
next clause, has to do with the contrstive choice as a result of which ' the
plates' became the object of washing rather than the other potential objects
in the implied contrative set. Therefore, the listener's hypothesis about
the content of the speaker's denial will not involve the opposite ( DIRTY)
of the typical consequence of washing ( CLEAN). By hypothesis, then, in
(9b) the word probe " dirty" should not be primed.
For initial ' though' clauses the hypothesized predictive inferences are
jointly determined by the TF structure of the clause and by the semantic
value of 'though' . This suggests that, in general, the content of the con
structed representation for an initial subordinate clause varies as a function
of the kind of interclausal semantic relation. To test this hypothesis, the
Focus- BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 225
experiment also examines 'while' mialatt in Hungarian) clauses such as
( lOa) and ( lOb) below:
( 10) a. Mialatt Nagymama elmosta a tanyerokat a tegnapi Mzibuli utan,
b. Mialatt Nagymama a tanyerokat mosta el a tegnapi Mzibuli utan,
The initial ' while' in ( 10) instructs the listener that the event in the up
coming main clause takes place simultaneously with the event expressed in
the initial clause. This predictive cue does not imply adversative content for
the main clause. For 'while' clauses, therefore, the projected expectations
about the simultaneous event should not contain the meaning of 'dirty' as
a foregrounded element in either the verb-focus or the object-focus version
of ( 10). Thus, no facilitation of the word probe 'dirty' is predicted in either
( lOa) or ( lOb).
Finally, the experiment also examined the temporal characteristics of
the hypothesized priming efects. Are the inferential processes initiated as
soon as their basis in the clause (i. e. , the element in the focus position) is
identifed, or are they delayed until the full clause has been processed? To
fnd out, the word probes were presented in two serial positions: either (i)
before the end of the clause (but following the focus position) , or (ii) after
the clause-boundary.
Another question concerns the diference in the processing functions of
the hypothesized inferences in initial subordinate clauses, on the one hand,
and in corresponding main clauses, on the other. I argued that in initial
'though' clauses the focus-based inferences are predictive: t heir function is
to facilitate the processing of the main clause by anticipating its content.
Therefore, the priming efect in (9a) should be present at (or carry over to)
the beginning of the main clause.
In initial main clauses, however, the hypothesized focus-based infer
ences have no predictive function. The results of the previous study
(Gergely 1986, 1991a, 1991b), discussed in Section 7 above, indicate that
an initial clause representation is discarded fom working memory due to
recoding at the clause-boundary, unless the presence of an initial sub
ordinate conjunction overrides this process. In (8b), therefore, the hy
pothesized priming efect is predicted to disappear following the clause
boundary.
8. 2 Method
The experiment examined naming times for visually presented word probes
at diferent points in the sentence. Subjects heard three kinds of Hungarian
initial clause ( main, 'though' , and 'while' ), each in two focus versions: (i)
with a perfective verbal modifer in focus position prefxed to the verb, and
(ii) with a contrastively focused object noun in focus position. The verbs
226 / GYORGY GERGELY
always expressed causative events (e. g. , ' wash' ), which imply pragmatically
(but not necessarily) a typical change of state in their object (e. g. , from
DIRTY to CLEAN) . Probes were presented either (i) before the end of the
clause, or (ii) after it. The critical probes always expressed the state (e.g. ,
DIRTY) that is the opposite of the typical output state of the object (e. g. ,
CLEAN) implied by the clausal predicate (e.g. , ' wash' ) .
Subjects
Forty eight subjects (28 females and 20 males, with a mean age of 24
years) participated in the experiment. They were all students at the Eotvos
L6nind University in Budapest; their mother tongue was Hungarian.
Materials
Twelve lists were created, each containing 12 experimental and 16 filler
sentence fagments. A given experimental fagment appeared in a list in
one of two Discourse Type versions: (i) the focus position being flled by
the verbal modifer prefxed to the verb (the "verbfocus" version) as in
( 1 1a) , or (ii) with the object in focus ( "object-focus" version) as in ( 11b)
below:
TOPIC FOCUS
( 1 1 ) a. Ugyan Nagymama elmosta a tanyerokt a tegnapi hazibuli * utan,
**
/Though [ T: Grandmother (=nom)] [ F: away- (=V-mod 'el- ' )] +
washed the plates + t (=acc) yesterday + i ( =adj ) party * after,
. . . **/
( 'Though Grandmother has washed the plates after yesterday's
party' )
TOPIC FOCUS
b. Ugyan Nagymama a tanyerokat mosta el a tegnapi hazibuli * utan,
**
/Though [T: Grandmother ( =nom)] [F: the plates +t ( =acc)]
washed away (=V-mod 'el' ) yesterday +i ( =adj ) party * after, . . .
**/
( ' Though i t was the plates that Grandmother has washed after
yesterday's party')
The verb-focus fagments always had an ' S V-mod + V L Adv Phrase'
constituent order. The object-focus versions were always ' S L V V-mod
Adv Phrase' . That is, the object-focus fagments were identical with the
verb-focus versions, except for the change in word order: the object NP ap
pearing in the preverbal focus position, and the verbal modifer surfacing in
a post verbal position. All experimental fagments contained equal number
of words. Across subjects each fagment appeared equally often in the three
Clause Types: either as an initial main, 'though', or 'while' clause. Thus,
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 227
an experimental fagment was tested in six Clause Type/Discourse Type
versions. The sixteen fllers varied in length, and were either initial main
or subordinate clauses introduced by conjunctions other than 'though' or
'while'.
Each fragment was paired with two kinds of probes: "related" or "unre
lated. " The "related" probes were always state-descriptive terms express
ing the opposite of the typical output state of the object implied by the
verb. Thus, the "related" probe for ( l la) and (Ub) was 'dirty'. The "un
related" probes, however, described a state that was not related to the
state of the object (either before or after the causative event has occurred) .
For example, the "unrelated" probe for ( l la) and ( l lb) was 'torn'. Each
"relevant" probe of a fagment also appeared as an "unrelated" probe for
another fagment, and vice versa. The two kinds of probes appeared with
equal frequency throughout the lists in a random order. The fllers were fol
lowed by probes that either could or could not be part of a typical, "good"
second clause continuation of the fragment.
Across subjects, an experimental fragment appeared in each of the 12
combinations of the three Clause Types, two Discourse Types, and two
Probe Types. Accordingly, 12 lists were created and a fagment appeared
once in each list as a token of one of the 12 combinations. The 12 fagment
types appeared in an identical randomized order in each list, randomly
intermixed with the 16 fllers. The order of the 12 experimental types was
randomized so that the three clause types appeared with equal frequency
over the list. Across lists the 12 experimental fagments were rotated so
that a fagment appeared once in each of the 12 experimental positions.
Each list was presented to two subjects.
The lists were recorded in two completeness versions with normal in
tonation. In the Incomplete Clause version the experimental (but not the
fller) fagments were recorded so that the last word of the clause wa not
heard by the subjects. Instead, they heard a 50 msec 1000 Hz warning tone
in both ears at the point where the experimental fragment wa interrupted
(as indicated by the single asterisk , *
,
in ( l la) and ( Ub) ) . The fller fag
ments were flly complete even in the Incomplete Clause condition so that
subjects would not develop strategies to cope with truncated, incomplete
fagments only.
In the Complete Clause condition, both the experimental and the fller
fagments were complete initial clauses. Just after the end of the clause
( indicated by two asterisks ' **
' in ( Ua) and ( Ub) ) subjects heard a 50
msec 1000 Hz warning tone in both ears. In normal speech there is a short
pause between the end of the frst clause and the beginning of the second
clause. To allow for clause-boundary bound processes to take efect before
the on-line test, the probe word in this condition followed the warning tone
by a 250 msec delay. The lists were preceded by 8 practice trials that varied
in length and structural type similarly to the fllers.
228 / GYORGY GERGELY
Procedure
Subjects sat in an armchair in a dimly lit room facing a screen placed
approximately 12 feet in front of them. A microphone was placed at the
level of the subject's head slightly to his right in such a way that it would
not block his view. The lists were presented through headphones to both
ears. Subjects heard a 50 msec 1000 Hz warning tone in both ears two sec
before the presentation of a fagment.
The subjects were instructed to listen to the clause fagments trying
to fully comprehend their meaning. They were told that the sentences
would be interrupted at some ( unspecifed) point by a warning tone fol
lowed by the presentation of the probe on the screen. In the Incomplete
Clause condition the warning tone immediately started the timer, stopped
the tape-recorder, and opened the shutter of the slide projector. In the
Complete Clause condition, there was a 250 msec delay between the warn
ing tone and the appearance of the probe. There were 24 subjects in both
completeness conditions.
Subjects had to perform two tasks. First, they had to name the probe
word as fast as they could. Naming times fom the appearance of the probe
until the subject's verbal response were recorded automatically by a timer
(BP 2045982) located in the other room. To insure that subjects fully
understood the fagments, a second task was introduced. After they had
named the probe, subjects had to judge whether or not it "would ft into
a good, typical, well-sounding continuation of the interrupted sentence. "
Their response was recorded by the experimenter. Following the completion
of the second task, the experimenter restarted the tape-recorder to present
the next sentence. Each list was preceded by 8 practice trials. Overall, the
experiment lasted for approximately 45 minutes.
8. 3 Results
Scores that were more than two standard deviations above each subject's
mean on a given condition were excluded fom the data analysis. Such
scores constituted less than 3% of the responses. The results were ana
lyzed by a three-way analysis of variance with one grouping factor and two
within-subject variables. The grouping factor had two levels: the Incom
plete Clause and the Complete Clause conditions. The two within-subject
variables were: (i) Clause Type with three levels (main, 'though' , and
'while' ), and (ii) Discourse Type with two levels ( "verb-focus" and "object
focus" ) . Since both sentence fragments and subjects were fully crossed with
experimental types, separate subject-based and item-based ANOVAs were
performed.
Overall, Clause Completeness did not show a main efect (Subjects:
F( 1, 46) . 63, ] ` .6; Items: F( 1, 22) 2.07, ] < . 2). There was no main
efect of Clause Type in the item-based analysis (F(2, 44) 1 .57, ] < .25),
however, the subject-based analysis showed a slight efect (F(2, 92) 2. 81,
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 229
] < . 07) . The subject analysis also showed a marginal interaction between
Clause Type and Clause Completeness (F(2, 92) 2.42, ] < . 1) , but no
such interaction was apparent in the item-based analysis (F(2, 44) 1 .07,
] < . 4).
There was a signifcant main efect of Discourse Type in both the subject
(F( I , 46) 5. 15, ] < .03) and the item ( F( I, 22) 4.48, ] < .04) anal
ysis. Furthermore, Discourse Type and Clause Type showed a signifcant
interaction (Subjects: F(2, 92) 6.09, ] < .005; Items: F(2, 44) 3. 71,
] < . 04). Clause Completeness, however, did not interact signifcantly with
either Discourse Type or Clause Type.
Figures 4 and 5 illustrate the pattern of "related" probe naming times5
for the 'incomplete clause' , and for the Complete Clause conditions, re
spectively.
RT
960
(osec)
940
920
900
880
860
840
820
800
780
760
740
Verb-Focus
>
..
. THOUGH /;' UGYAN' /
WHILE /;' MIALATT'/
MAIN
Object-Focus
Figure 4 Mean "Related" Probe Recognition Times
in the Incomplete Clause Condition
Overall, the results supported the tested hypotheses. As predicted, Dis
course Type had a clear efect on probe recognition in both initial main and
initial 'though' clauses in the Incomplete Clause Condition (see Figure 4).
Furthermore, for 'though' clauses this efect carried over to the Complete
Clause Condition as well ( Figure 5).
The signifcant Clause Type Discourse Type interaction is largely
due to the opposite efect of Discourse Type on main versus 'though' in the
Incomplete Clause condition. Figure 4 shows that the verb-focus version of
initial 'though' clauses resulted in signifcantly fater probe naming times
than the corresponding object-focus version (Subjects: F( I, 92) = 8.90,
5
The relatively long mean probe naming times are due to the fact that the probes were
often rather long (ranging from 2 to 5 syllables, with a mean syllable length of 2.95),
morphologically complex word-formations (e.g., ' megsavanyodott' 1= [it] turned sour/,
'kiszaradtak' 1= [they] dried out/)
230 / GYORGY GERGELY
H
_ 960
(m-ec)
940
920
900
880
860
840
820
800
780
760
740
..
.
.
.
o
Verb-Focus
.
.
.
.
,
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
q wutLE)=' tL11)
'
.
utN
.
q 1uCUcu )=ucvN')
.
.
.
.
Lb ject-Focus
Figure 5 Mean "Related" Probe Recognition Times
in the Complete Clause Condition
p < . 001; Items: F( 1, 44) ~ 1 1.94, p < .001) . The opposite prediction for
initial main clauses was also borne out by the data (Subjects: F( 1, 92) =
6. 18, p < . 01; Items: F( 1, 44) = 7.37, p < 0. 01) (see Figure 4).
Figure 5 illustrates that for the object-focus version of initial main
clauses, the probe facilitation, present in the "incomplete clause" condi
tion, disappeared afer the clause-boundary. In contrast, for initial 'though'
clauses the probe facilitation efect observed in the verb-focus version of the
Incomplete Clause condition was present in the Complete Clause condition
a well (Subjects: F( 1, 92) = 5.32, p < 0. 01; Items: F( 1, 44) ~ 6.34,
p < 0. 01) . Finally, as expected, the diferent discourse versions of initial
'while' clauses showed no priming efect in either completeness condition.
8.4 Discussion
The results of the experiment make it possible to evaluate three alterna
tive hypotheses about how the listener identifes .he implicit consequence
of an initial 'though' clause that is denied by the speaker in the fnal main
clause. First, Townsend and Bever (1978) proposed that the listener can
not anticipate fom an initial ' though' clause which cause-efect relation
the speaker is denying. As a result, he computes no inferences based on
the adversative clause until the main clause is reached. In this view, the
identifcation of the particular consequence denied by the sentence takes
place only retrospectively, during the processing of the fnal main clause.
Alternatively, the listener, when processing the initial 'though' clause,
could immediately compute fom his pragmatic knowledge the exhaustive
set of typical consequences based on all parts of the clausal proposition. He
would select the intended one only later, on the bais of the second clause.
Finally, according to the present hypothesis, the listener could rely on
the TF structure of the initial 'though' clause to restrict the set of ex-
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 231
pectable consequences to only those that follow from the focused part of
the clause. This way he could anticipate the adversative content of the
fnal clause even before the clause-boundary.
The results support the fnal hypothesis. First, naming times for a word
probe, whose meaning is in adversative relation to the focus-based conse
quence of the initial 'though' clause, were signifcantly decreased both when
tested before the end of the clause (Figure 4) and following the clause
boundary ( Figure 5). This indicates that by the time the main clause is
reached, subjects have generated a predictive hypothesis about its adver
sative content, resulting in the observed probe facilitation. This rules out
the frst hypothesis that listeners postpone the inferential processing of an
initial 'though' clause.
The result demonstrates that when the TF structure of an initial ad
versative clause is clearly marked (a in the cae of the tested Hungarian
sentences) , the listener accesses his knowledge of typical cause-efect re
lations to compute focus-based predictive inferences about the content of
the fnal clause. This is also in line with the results of the replication
of Townsend and Bever ( 1978) using Hungarian sentences ( Gergely 1986,
1991a) , where, in contrast to the English results, no evidence was found
for a relatively shallow processing of initial 'though' clauses (see Section
5 above). Furthermore, the fact that probe facilitation was present al
ready before the end of the clause ( Figure 4) indicates that the focus-based
inference is generated even before the full clause has been processed.
This fnding, however, is not sufcient to rule out the second hypothesis
that the whole set of typical consequences, based on all parts of the initial
clause, would be computed from pragmatic knowledge. But the fact that
the word probes were primed only in the verb-focus version of the initial
' though' clause, rules out the latter alternative as well. The selective na
ture of the facilitation efect demonstrates that subjects inferred only those
consequences that were based on the focused part of the clause.
The results indicate that the sentence-initial ' though' modifes the pro
cessing of the frst clause by invoking a focus-baed adversative inference
whose function is to predict the content of the upcoming clause. This is
also supported by the fnding that when no initial conjunction is present,
as in the corresponding main clauses (see Figures 4 and 5) , the verb-focus
version does not result in probe facilitation.
Furthermore, the priming efect present in the initial 'though' clauses,
was absent in the corresponding 'while' clauses in both completeness con
ditions. This can be attributed to the diferent semantic value of 'while'
whose dominant interpretation is temporal rather than adversative. As
such, it is likely to cue the listener to develop predictive hypotheses about
a simultaneous event in the upcoming main clause. Since there was no spe
cifc contextual information to suggest that this next clause event would
have an adversative content, the predictive structure computed did not
232 / GYORGY GERGELY
contain the opposite of the output state of the object in either the verb
focus or the object-focus version of the initial 'while' clause. As a result,
no probe facilitation was observed in either of these conditions (see Figures
4 and 5).
It seems, however, that some predictive inference of a diferent con
tent was, nevertheless, computed during the initial 'while' clause as well.
This is suggested by the fact that the 'while' clause data do not show
the object-focus probe facilitation that was present in corresponding ini
tial main clauses. It seems, therefore, that the sentence-initial 'while' also
modifes the processing of the initial clause, but in a manner diferent from
'though' .
These findings are in line with the general hypothesis that the focus
based inferential structures computed for initial subordinate clauses serve a
diferent processing function than those generated for corresponding main
clauses. I argued that sentence-initial conjunctions, cueing the listener
about the interclausal semantic organization of the sentence, invoke focus
based inferences to predict the content of the second clause. In initial main
clauses, however, no such predictive cues are available, and so the observed
focus-based inferences have no interclausal predictive relevance.
This interpretation is also supported by the temporal characteristics of
the priming efects. On the assumption that the focus-based inferences in
the initial 'though' clause serve to facilitate the processing of the upcom
ing clause, it was predicted that the resulting probe facilitation would be
present at the beginning of the fnal clause. The fact that the priming ef
fect in the verb-focus version was present afer the clause-boundary in the
case of initial 'though' clauses (Figure 5) clearly supports this hypothesis.
In contrast, since the focus-based inferential structure constructed for an
initial main clause serves no predictive function, it becomes discarded from
working memory at the end of the clause. This is shown by the fact that
the priming efect, present in the object-focus version before the end of the
main clause (Figure 4), disappears in the after-clause condition (Figure 5) .
This fnding is also in line with the results of my earlier study ( Gergely
1986, 1991a, 1991b) discussed in Section 7, where targets fom an initial
main clause were found to be less accessible after the clause-boundary than
before it.
The relatively early presence of the priming efects in both the main
and the adversative clauses indicates that the focus-based inferences tested
are computed more or less directly, certainly before the full syntactic and
semantic processing of the clause is completed. This supports the interac
tive models of speech comprehension (e. g. , Marslen-Wilson and Tyler 1980,
Johnson-Laird 1984, Crain and Steedman 1985), which hold that the difer
ent sources of discourse-relevant information are employed as they become
available to constrain the direct construction of a discourse representation
of the sentence.
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 233
The results also support the assumption that the focus-based inferences
directly access pragmatic knowledge of the typical structure of events. The
critical verbs in the experiment (e. g. , 'wash') always expressed a typical
(but not necessary) change of state in their object (e. g. , fom DIRTY to
CLEAN) .
6
It was hypothesized that when the object is contrastively fo
cused, the listener constructs a representation of the implied set of poten
tial objects. In doing so, he accesses his pragmatic knowledge in which the
typical input state of the predicate event is specifed, and so the objects
in the contrastive set will be represented with the input state property
foregrounded. The fnding that the object-focus version of the main clause
primed the adjective probe that described this input state, dearly supports
the hypothesis. Thus, it can be concluded that the on-line construction of
an interpretational representation during sentence comprehension has di
rect access to pragmatic knowledge structures such as (e. g. , Schank and
Abelson 1977, Bower et al. 1979, Sharkey and Mitchell 1985) and lexical
stereotypes ( Gergely and Bever 1986).
Finally, let us compare the focus-based inferential priming efects dem
onstrated in the present study to other cases of contextual facilit0ry efects
on word recognition such as lexical priming (e.g. , Becker 1979; Fischler
and Goodman 1978; Meyer and Schvaneveldt 1971; 1975) or script-based
priming (see Sharkey and Mitchell 1985). In lexical priming the presence
of a prior context word (e. g., DOCTOR) that is semantically or associa
tively related to a target word (e.g. , NURSE) results in faster recognition
of the latter. Current theories of word recognition (e. g. , Morton 1969,
Marslen-Wilson and Welsh 1978) assume that such priming efects are due
to the temporal lowering of the recognition threshold of the target word as
a result of spreading activation coming through the semantic/associative
links fom the context word that has just been activated ( see Collins and
Lofus 1975) .
At frst, one might think that the probe facilitation in the present exper
iment is a further case of lexical priming. For example, spreading activation
propagating through the associative link fom the focused predicate ' wash'
could prime the word probe 'dirty' . However, there are two aspects of the
results suggesting that the priming efect brought about by focus-based in
ferences is a qualitatively diferent kind of contextual facilitory efect than
associative lexical priming.
The frst concerns the selective nature of the observed priming efects.
Focus-based priming of e.g. , the probe 'dirty' (with the perfective verbal
modifer 'el' of the complex predicate 'elmosta' (=' has washed') in focus
position) occurred only when the clause was introduced by 'though' . Had
6
Note that 'wah' is only a "quasi-causative" verb in so far a it is possible to wash
clean things, a well a to wah something without succeeding in making it clean. All
the critical verbs were quai-causatives of this kind.
234 / GYORGY GERGELY
this efect been due to automatic activation through associative lexical
connections, one would have expected comparable probe facilitation in the
corresponding verb-focus versions of initial 'while' and main clauses as well.
However, no such efects were observed.
Secondly, focus-based inferential priming seems to have a diferent time
course than lexical associative priming. Previous studies indicate that
lexical priming is both very short lived (e. g. , Warren 1972, Neely 1977,
Loftus 1973) and can be easily disrupted by even one single unrelated
intervening item (e. g. , Meyer and Schvaneveldt 1971; Gough, Alford, and
Holley-Wilcox 1981; Foss 1982). However, in this study there were always
fve or six intervening words between the focused item and the word probe
(see ( l la) and ( l lb) ) . In addition, the priming efect in the 'though' clause
condition survived even an intervening clause-boundary.
These considerations indicate that the observed facilitory efect is not
a case of simple lexical priming, as the latter is more localized and subject
to rapid automatic decay. Focus-based inferential priming seems to be a
more robust, higher-order contextual facilitation efect. It disappears only
when the representational structure underlying the efect is discarded fom
working memory. In main clauses, this takes place at the clause-boundary
as shown by the lack of priming in the afer-clause condition. In initial
'though' clauses, however, where the function of the focus-based inferential
structure is predictive, the probe facilitation is present even after the clause
boundary.
Inferential priming seems more similar, therefore, to the robust higher
order contextual facilitation of script-associated words demonstrated by
Sharkey and Mitchell ( 1985) . These authors found that the facilitation of
words associated with a script that was activated by the previous text, is
not subject to automatic decay, but is deactivated by discourse-relevant
control cues indicating script-switch in the text.
However, it seems that the priming efects in the present study cannot
be accounted for solely in terms of script activation either. Rather, the
observed probe facilitation is the result of an interactive inferential process
that is a joint function of (i) script-based knowledge, (ii) TF structure, and
(iii) interclausal semantic relation. The respective contribution of these fac
tors to the construction of the inferential structure underlying the priming
efect can be characterized a follows:
The predicate expression of the initial subordinate clause (e.g., 'washing
the plates') activates the corresponding script structure in memory (e. g. ,
the "dishwashing" script) which acts as the interpretational domain over
which the inferential structure is computed. The semantic value of the
particular subordinate conjunction restricts the size of the active interpre
tational domain by identifying those parts of the script that are relevant for
the computed inference. For example, the initial 'though' indicates that the
next clause will relate to an implicit consequence of the adversative clause.
Focus-BASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION / 235
This information restricts the active interpretational domain to that part of
the script which specifes typical cause-efect relations. Then TF structure
further restricts the active script domain to only those cause-efect rela
tions that are based on the focus of the clause. 7 Finally, the conjunction
'though' , which cues the listener that the next clause will deny the implicit
consequence, specifes a further adversative inferential step in constructing
the predictive structure, which transforms the focus-based consequence in
the active script domain into its opposite.
9 Conclusions
To sum up: the studies discussed in this paper examined the role of three
sources of discourse information in the on-line processing of complex sen
tences: (i) TF structure, (ii) interclausal semantic relations, and (iii) prag
matic knowledge. The results indicate that listeners employ these cues
interctively, as they become available in the clause, to constrain the con
struction of an interpretational model of the speaker's intended meaning.
Overall, the reported experiments support recent interactive models of
speech processing (e.g. , Marslen-Wilson et al. 1978, Marslen-Wilson and
Tyler 1980, Johnson-Laird 1984, Crain and Steedman 1985) , which argue
that the listener accesses the available contextual information directly, and
starts to construct a discourse interpretational representation for a sentence
even before its full syntactic and semantic structure has been identifed.
The present studies demonstrate that in this process a central role is played
by focus-based inferences that have direct access to pragmatic knowledge
represented in script-like memory structues. Focus-based inferences serve
several diferent processing functions during clausal processing: they are
involved in establishing implicit discourse antecedent relations as well as
in setting up implicit inferential structures linking clausal propositions in
discourse. 8
7
Discourse context typically provides even more information helping the listener to
further constrain the set of expectable consequences that the speaker's choice of focus
implies. Consider the sentence 'Though it was the plates that John ha wahed, Mother
was still not satisfied' in a context where it is known that (i) Mother had asked John
to wah the dishes, and (ii) the bulk of the dirty dishes consisted of plates. Clearly, the
listener could anticipate from the initial 'though' clause that the main clause will deny
John's expectation that his choice to do the plates would be sufcient to satisfy mother.
B
It should be pointed out that the discourse inferential processes demonstrated in the
present experiments seem to ft well the more recent discourse-oriented approaches to
lexical semantics, such as the one proposed by Kalman and Szab6 (1990). Kalman
and Szab6 distinguish a part of the discourse representation, called an "enclosure,"
that contains implicit pragmatic information asociated with predicates, which, however,
doesn't belong to the propositional content to which the speaker has committed himself
truth-conditionally, called the "rigid" part of the discourse representation. Under certain
conditions (e.g., for recovering implicit antecedents), enclosures can be "unpacked,"
i.e., their contents can be raised into the rigid part of the discourse representation.
Within this framework, the demonstrated focus-baed inferences can be interpreted as
236 / GYORGY GERGELY
The observed priming efects indicate that focus-based inferences result
in the foregrounding of certain parts of the constructed representation mak
ing them more accessible for on-line processes of discourse integration. The
temporal pattern of this selective activation process is related to the partic
ular processing function that the focus-based inference serves. For example,
in an initial main clause, where the inference which contributes to the con
struction of the clausal representation is nonpredictive, the foregrounded
inferential structure becomes deactivated at the clause-boundary due to
recoding at the end of the clause. On the other hand, when sentence-initial
conjunctions provide predictive cues about the likely content of the next
clause, as in initial subordinate clauses, focus-based inferences generate in
terclausal predictive hypotheses to facilitate the integrational processing of
the upcoming clause. In such cases, the presence of the sentence initial
subordinate conjunction acts as a cue to block the process of recoding at
the end of the clause, and so the predictive inferential structure does not
get deactivated at the clause-boundary.
References
.. 1986. Topic, Focus, and Confgurationality.
1983.
.
1973.
A Festshrif for Moms Halle,
...
1979. .
.Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
and Performance 5:252-259.
.1979. .
.Sentence Processing:
Psycholinguistic Studies Presented to Merrill Garrett, .
. ..
..1981. ..
The Child's Construction of Language, .
.. 1979. .
Cognitive Psychology 1 1 : 177-220.
.1970. Meaning and the Structure of Language.
.1976.
.Subject and Topic, 26-55. .
one kind of processing operation which accesses the encyclopedic knowledge represented
in enclosures during discourse processing.
ocusASED INFERENCES IN SENTENCE COMPREHENSION /
...
Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguis
tics, and Psychology, .
.
.. Lectures on Goverment and Binding.
.. ..
Exlaining Linguistic Phenomena,
. .
.. ..
.Discourse Production and Comprehension,
.
.
.Psychological Review
..
Natural Language
Processing, ...
.
...
Perception and Psychophysics
..
Cognition
Joural of Linguistics
..
Computational Linguistics
.
.Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory
.
..Joural of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and
Performance
.
.Linguistic Inquiry
.. The Psychology
of Language. ....
..Cognitive Psychology
Discourse Integrational Processes in Sentence Compre
hension: A Study in Comparative Psycho linguistics.
.
Free Word Order and Discourse Interpretation: Ex
perimental Studies on Hungarian Sentence Processing. .
..
Language and Cognitive Processes.
/ GYORGY GERGELY
..
.Cognition
. .
Joural of Psycholinguistic Research
... .
Perception of Print: Reading Research in Experimental
Psychology, ...
.. .
Journal of Linguistics
......
..Joural of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior
. Aspects of Hungarian Syntax and the Theory of Grammar.
. .Approaches to
Hungarian, Vol. 1: Data and Descriptions,
. .Proceed
ings of the 7h Amsterdam Colloquium, .
..
.
.
.
Approaches to Hungarian, Vol. 2: Theories and Analyses.
Z/X
Concatenation interpreted as connection:3
I. a b ii.
(Z/Y)/X Y/X
Z/X
Z/X
Ax[a' (x) (b' (x))]
b a
Y/X (Z\Y)/X
Z/X
(21) Category lifing interpreted as: Af[J(a')]
i. a
Z
T
Y/(Y\Z)
.
The derivation of (2) will proceed a follows:
2For the choice of index letters, see (23) below.
a
Z
Y\(Y/Z)
3The connection operation, introduced in Szabolcsi 1 983, is renamed U substitution in
Steedman 1987, 1988.
250 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
(22) who relatives of thought Kim eliminated
S/( S/NP) (S/(S\NP)) /NP (S\NP)/S S/( S\NP) (S\NP)/NP
Bi
S/NP
Bi
(S\NP)/NP
S
i
S/NP
Ai
S
The (S\NP) /NP category of eliminated specifes that it is a functor with
two NP arguments, of which the frst (object) is expected from the right
and the second (subject) is expected from the left. In this sentence there
is nothing in the position where eliminated expects its object to be, and it
is a remarkable feature of the grammar that it does not insert a phonet
ically empty element, either. So eliminated combines directly with Kim.
This cannot be by application, though, since the subject NP is not the frst
argument of the transitive verb (and there is nothing in the grammar to
change argument order) . The subject and the transitive verb can combine
via composition, which is possible ifthe subject also bears an appropriate
functor category, cf. the input conditions of ( 19i) . (Whether a noun phrae
in the nominative comes with the functor category S/(S\NP) fom the lex
icon, or ( 21i) lifts NP to S/(S\NP) , is immaterial for our present concerns. )
The composed functor Kim eliminated i s exactly like eliminated i n that it
expects an NP fom its right. The same holds for thought Kim eliminated
that we compose in the next step.
Now comes relatives of. Its internal structure can be ignored; the im
portant point is that, once more, it has nothing in the position of the
prepositional object and is therefore a functor. Relatives of and thought
Kim eliminated match the input conditions in (20i) , so they can be con
nected into a big "forked" fnctor that is looking for one NP ( who) which,
when found, will satisfy both prongs. (This grammar, just like that of Pol
lard ( 1988) , would require an extra restriction to rule (4) out. As things
stand now, S\NP can be lifted to S\(S/( S\NP) ) , whence thought that Kim
died can compose with relatives of of ( S/(S\NP))/NP. ) The trivial com
position steps that take care of said and Mary are omitted to save space.
Finally, accusative who must bring its S/(S/NP) category fom the lexicon.
The reason is partly semantic ( who does not denote an entity, hence can
not be just NP), and partly syntactic (lifting as in (21) preserves the order
of combination and hence cannot be responsible for the "left-extracting"
property of who) . Wo combines with (Mary said) relatives of thought
Kim eliminated by application.
Now, do the lack of traces and the use of complex operations, as in
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 251
( 17ab), represent two arbitrarily juxtaposed grammatical strategies, or are
they logically coherent? It seems they are, since as Steedman ( 1987, 1988)
observes, there exists a system of logic that has essentially these features as
its defning properties. This is combinatory logic, initiated by SchOnfnkel
( 1924), developed, among others, by Curry and Feys (1958), and expanded
in a most enjoyable fashion by Smullyan ( 1985) . Combinatory logic is a sys
tem with the same potential expressive power as the lambda calculus. But
while the lambda calculus uses abstraction and bound variables, combina
tory logic appeals solely to functional operations (combinators), to achieve
the same results. That is, it difers from the lambda calculus in precisely
the same way as the grammar just sketched difers fom GB and HPSG.
For a fast-and-easy introduction to combinators, note the following. In
( 15)-(16) and ( 19)-(21) we were dealing with "composed functions" , "con
nected functions" , and "lifted objects" . The combinators "compositor"
(B), "connector" (S) and "lifter" (T) are the operations themselves that
we get by abstracting fom those functions/objects. In (23) I defne them
both in usual lambda terms and in standard combinatory notation. The
latter should be read as follows: B is that operation which, when applied to
f, g, and x in this order, returns f(gx) , etc. Left-associativity is asumed,
i. e. , (ao)c aoc.
(23) a. Compositor: B Af AgAx[f(gx)]
Bfgx f(gx)
b. Connector: S AhAgAx[h(x) (gx)]
Shgx hx(gx)
c. Lifer: T AxAg[g(x)]
Txg gx
Application is not a combinator; it is the interpretation of the concate
nation of any two combinatory terms. However, it is possible to defne a
combinator
A
that does exactly this, AgAx[g(x)] .
The fact that combinatory logic has the same potential expressive power
a the lambda calculus entails that variable binding can be dispensed with.
To illustrate what sameness of expressive power means in more complex
caes, consider two examples in (24), which will also be useful below:
(24) a. ST expresses the same as AfAx(f(x) (x)] because
STfx Tx(fx) fxx
b. BB(ST) expresses the same as VAgAx[f(gx) (gx)] because
BB(ST)fgx B(STf)gx STf(gx) T(gx)(f(gx
f
gx) (gx)
It may be interesting to point out that the operations we found useful
in devising a grammar of English are not merely defnable in combinatory
terms but actually all correspond to rather fundamental combinators. B,
S and T represent those independent operation types which, were they
supplemented with an identifcator or a cancellator and allowed to apply
recursively, would actually yield the power of the full lambda calculus.
252 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
Since that power is neither necessary nor desirable in our syntax, I will
continue to restrict my attention to combinators with specifc linguistic
motivation. Another important assumption that I make is that combinators
are typed (cf. Hindley et al. 1972 and Morrill and Carpenter 1987. For
instance, in (23a,b,c), f is to have a type of the form P * R, g of Q P,
1 of Q, and h of Q " (P R) . Typing will be assumed but not notated
throughout the discussion.
In sum, the pursuit of the "function metaphor" appears to have led us
to the "combinator metaphor" . Again, the question is whether we should
leave it as a metaphor, or we should asign it the status of a theoretical
claim. The latter possibility would mean that we try to devise a restrictive
theory of grammar by letting the spirit and techniques of combinatory logic
delimit our analytic options.
In what follows I will make one move in this direction. I will present a
case study of anaphors and pronouns, and argue that, in view of both its
positive and negative results, combinatory logic can serve a a guideline for
their study.
Caveat: In the rest of the paper I will continue to use lambda terms
alongside with, and sometimes even instead of, combinatory terms. I wish
to point out that this is only because combinators are unfamiliar to many
readers. Lambda terms will merely serve the purpose of exposition; they
have the same status as a paraphrase in ordinary English would.
2 Anaphora-Lexical Semantics and Syntax
The suggestion that natural language syntax implements combinators,
rather than explicit variable binding, wa motivated above by a specifc
kind of example in which the variable would be phonetically empty. In
those caes it i easy to argue that we only need to account for the place
ment and interpretation of overt words, and thus the use of variables is
a mere artifct of some theories. Consider the phenomenon of anaphora,
however. The items himself and him below can be looked upon a bound
variables, but both they and their binders are in every respect normal ar
guments of the verb, so they cannot be dispensed with:
(25) a. Everyone loves himself.
b. Everyone thinks that Mary loves him.
Modulo technical details, standard theories of anaphors and pronouns
have two components. The lexical component is rather meager; these items
are assigned a so-to-say minimal interpretation, namely, that of a fee vari
able. The syntactic component is rather rich: it consists of a mechanism
for binding those variables plus a set of constraints on what they can, or
must, be bound to. See Chomsky 1981, 1986b; Chierchia 1988; Pollard
1984; among others.
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 253
The crucial binding component of these theories is not reproducible in
our grammar. The reason is that combinatory logic does not merely allow
us to handle specifcally extraction and parasitic gap structures without
bound variables: it has no variable binding at all. 4
Alongside with the above theories of binding, a number of proposals
have been put forth to the efect that (sentences containing) a refexive
can be interpreted as (containing) a kind of argument reducer, in lambda
terms, A/AX(fXX] . Applied to a two-place function, say, AZAy[SEE(z) ( y)] it
returns a one-place function obtained by identifing SEE's arguments, viz. ,
Ax[SEE(x)(x)]. See, for example, Quine 1 960, Geach 1972, von Stechow
1979, Keenan 1987, and Kanski 1987.
Given that combinatory logic has the same expressive power as the
lambda calculus, this proposal does have a straightforward equivalent in
our grammar. The requisite combinator is known as W, the duplicator in
Curry and Feys 1958.
(26) Duplicator: W VAX[/XX]
W/x /xx
where / is of P (P Q), x of P
Notice that W is the combinator that we defned a ST in (24a) .
The argument reducer proposals in literature have been essentially se
mantic in nature. They were not intended to account for the syntactic
constraints that binding theories are preoccupied with. Keenan 1987 even
argues that semantics is all that there should be to it: matters of interpre
tation are independent of matters of form like constituency.
The question that is interesting to H is this: What happens if we
incorporate the duplicator account of anaphors into the grammar outlined
in 1 .2? In the rest of the paper I will focus on three aspects of this question.
In 2. 1, I will examine how the duplicator account of refexives interacts with
the syntax of CCG as in ( 18)-(21 ) to make predictions concerning "Principle
A" properties. In 2. 2, I will examine what the theory entails for pronouns,
free and bound, and point out that it practically derives Reinhart's ( 1983)
results. In 2. 3, I will extend the proposal to VP-ellipsis to resolve a problem
facing any Reinhart-like theory of anaphora.
2. 1 Refexives
Standard binding theories attribute three primitive properties to anaphors:
the necessity for there to be a binder, the prominence condition on the
binder, and the locality condition on the binder. I suggest that the simplest
possible account of the frst of these is to interpret refexives as duplicators
in the lexicon. Given that refexives are lexical items in need of some
4That is, we have combinatory terms with the same meaning B f(x) and combinatory
terms with the same meaning U AX[J(X)
'
but the latter is not obtained from the former.
254 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
meaning in any cae, any other treatment would involve that we assign the
"wrong" lexical meaning to them, and go on to put it "right" in syntax.
Note a problem now: W is an operation over functions, whereas himself
is an argument of the verb. But notice that turning a two-place fnction
into a one-place function is essentially the same as providing one of its
arguments. The conceptual gap is bridged by function-argument structure
reversal, viz. , lifing. This tells H what kind of a noun phrase a refexive
is: nothing but a lifed kind.
Lifting has ample syntactic motivation in our grammar (see especially
Steedman 1986 and Dowty 1988), so refexives are by no means excep
tional in having lifted kind of categories. The only peculiarity is that while
an entity-denoting item like Ma may come fom the lexicon with the
category NP and get lifed in syntax, the same categories are assigned to
refexives directly in the lexicon, matching their meaning. In this regard
the treatment of refexives is like that of quantifers. See (27) , in which
items in the frst row are annotated with a category and an interpretation
that suit the subject position, and those in the second, the object position.
I continue to use lambda terms for the reader's convenience:
(27) everyone Mary * sheself
S/(S\NP) S/(S\NP) S/(S\NP)
V
Vy[fy] -t[ f
m
]
everyone Mary herself
(S\NP) \ ( (S\NP) /NP) (S\NP)\ ( (S\NP) /NP) (S\NP) \ ( (S\NP) /NP)
-g-yVx[gxy] -g-y[g
m
y] -g-x[gxx]
A simple example is then derived as below. Herself is a leftward-looking
functor with the duplicator interpretation AgAX[gXXJ . It applies to the
transitive verb sees to yield a verb phrae S\NP with the interpretation
Ax[SEE(x) (x)J . The subject quantifer everyone is a rightward-looking
functor with interpretation VVy[fyJ . It applies to the verb phrase and
yields a sentence with the desired interpretation Vy[SEE(y)(y)J .
(28) Everyone sees herself
S/(S\NP) (S\NP) /NP (S\NP) \ ( (S\NP) /NP)
A
ii
S\NP
Ai
S
Now consider how this proposal accounts for the ungrammaticality of
(29a,b) : 5
5
(29a,b) cannot be ruled out with reference to a morphological gap. They are equally
ungrammatical in Hungarian, a language that ha nominative anaphors in the subject
position of NP. (On the clause-like structure of the Hungarian noun phrae, see Szabo1csi
1984.)
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 255
(29) a.
*
Sheself lef.
b.
*
Sheself sees everyone.
As for (29a), the non-existence of sheself of category S/(S\NP) is due to the
fact that the duplicator is by defnition a two-place function, which cannot
be the interpretation of a one-place functor. No such simple semantic
explanation can be given for ( 29b) , however. To wit, shes elf might also
be expected to bear the lexical category (S/NP) /( (S\NP) /NP
)
, which may
well be interpreted a a duplicator and bind the subject to the object.
This is essentially what Keenan points out when he invokes his Nominative
Reference Condition to eliminate (29b).
The situation i n our grammar i s slightly diferent, however. Notice that
the dangerous category above cannot be obtained by lifting NP but only
by applying the compositor B to S/(S\NP) unarily. To make this more
transparent, in (30) let u use the ad hoc labels subj and obj, and ignore
directionality:
(30) a. (S/NP) /((S\NP) /NP) is ( Sl obj) I ((Sl subj) l obj)
S/(S\NP) is SI (Sl subj)
b. T of subj may be (Sl obj) I ((SI obj) l subj)
T of obj may be (Sl subj) ! ((S! subj) l obj)
c. B of S! ( S! subj) may be ( S! obj) ! ( ( S! subj) ! obj)
Now, i n distinction to Lambek calculi, for instance, the syntax i n ( 18)
(21) does not include unary B (division) . We only used B to interpret
concatenation. This is not accidental. There are various kinds of disaters,
some but not all mentioned in (the revised version of) Szabolcsi 1987,
that unary B may cause in syntax. Hence the problematic category is not
a standard category for noun phraes in English: even Mary will never
acquire it. So all we need to assume in order to exclude ( 29b) is that
refexives may not have lexical categories that are not available in syntax
to normal noun phrases. Which, in fact , is the null hypothesis.
It may be concluded that by lexically interpreting refexives a dupli
cators, plus assigning them to categories in conformity to independently
motivated syntactic assumptions, we predict that they "are bound by a
more prominent argument" . But no binding mechanism and c-command
condition need to be stipulated. Further details of this proposal, including
the treatment of two-complement verb cases, pied piping, and interaction
with extraction and coordination are developed in Szabolcsi 1987.
That said about the requirement of a more prominent binder, let us
turn to the locality condition on anaphors. It is to be observed that locality
cannot appear as a natural condition in a system that includes composition.
Consider, for instance:
(31) a.
*
Mary believes that John loves herself.
b. Who does Mary believe that John loves?
The extraction structure (31b) shows that believe that John loves of cate-
256 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
gory ( S\NP) /NP can be obtained by composition. If herself in (31a) applies
to such a composed transitive verb, it will "get bound" by the subject Mary.
So, in case the treatment of anaphors is to be part of this system, we must
resort to brute force to capture the locality condition. The brute force
method is, basically, to require that the duplicator only apply to functors
that are lexical in some sense. (Cf. Chomsky's 1986b minimal complete
functional complex. )
Without going into details regarding the precise defnition of lexicality,
let us ask how sad one should be about this. Is the locality condition part
and parcel of the notion anaphor, where by "anaphor" we mean an item
that must be bound by a c-commanding argument, i.e., which is interpreted
as a duplicator?
The existence of long-distance anaphors has been widely recognized
for quite some time. Most of them reside within NPs and are exclusively
subject oriented, that is, they appear to have rather peculiar restrictions.
A very interesting cae fom Modern Greek is reported by Iatridou 1986,
however. Greek ha two anaphors in our sense, of which ton eafon tau
is bound within, and ton idhio outside, its governing category. The data
Iatridou presents also indicate that this latter, long-distance anaphor has
no funny restrictions:
(32) 0 Yanisi ipe ston Costaj oti i Maria
k
aghapa ton idhio
i/j/
*k
said to that loves himself
A plethora of further relevant data can be found in Keenan 1988.
This indicates that locality can in general be divorced fom the core
notion of anaphor, contrary to what binding theories suggest. The local
ity condition (lexicality requirement) may really be a brute force device
employed by natural language to facilitate processing. Clearly, it is very
useful for the hearer if binding ambiguities are reduced by having diferent
forms for the duplicator; but there may be nothing more to it. While my
proposal (as it stands, at leat) is unrevealing with respect to what locality
conditions diferent languages may impose on their anaphors, it may be
taken to be revealing in the sense that it predicts locality to be a more or
less ad hoc matter.
2.2 Pronouns
There is another phenomenon that the present theory makes predictions
about, namely, bound versus fee pronouns.
If the local binding condition on refexives is a more or less ad hoc
matter, there is in principle no obstacle to extending the class of anaphors
i. e. , lexical duplicators-to include items which only difer from refexives in
that they are subject to no, or diferent, locality conditions. This is good
news because, given that our combinatory logic ha no variable binding
(assignment switching) mechanism, having a duplicator kind of meaning is
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 257
the only chance for an item to get interpreted as a bound variable in the
usual sense. Besides this, combinatory logic only ofers free variables. But
those are like any name: they start out free and remain fee. They may
only co-refer with other referential expressions on independent grounds.
These considerations imply that pronouns must be multiply ambiguous.
(33) a. He[bound] is a member of the class of anaphors. As a frst approx
imation, it may be assigned the same lexical meaning(s) as refex
ives, whence it is subject to the same prominence/constituency
requirements, and to possibly diferent locality conditions.
b. He[free] is baically deictic. It represents arbitrarily many difer
ent fee variables, each having its value fxed once and for all.
Consider now the anti-locality condition on pronouns ( "free in its gov
erning category" ) . The main point to note is this. The relation between
he [bound] and its antecedent is recognizable within the combinatory the
ory, but the relation between he [fee] and the item it happens to co-refer
with is not. Hence we may hope to be able to impose an anti-locality
condition only on the former, but not on the latter.
Anti-locality for he (bound] can be captured by something like the op
posite of the lexicality requirement for refexives or, more interestingly, by
utilizing a combinator that is independently necessary for standard cases of
pied piping. The combinatory equivalent of having a feature inherited by
mother fom daughter is discussed in Szaholcsi 1987, following Steedman
(p.C. ) :6
(34) If a noun phrase is interpreted as a, its pied piper version is inter
preted as C(B(Ba)B)or B(Ba)B,and has a matching category. For
example: X\( X/NP)-its pied piper version: (X\( X/Y \( Y/NP) .
For instance, if a is Wand Y is PP, the use of the pied piper category will
allow to himself to inherit anaphorhood fom himself. 7 But notice now
that the "feature" that "percolates" from NP to Y is necessarily "inert"
within Y. Thus, by making pronouns obligatory S-pied pipers, we let S
inherit anaphorhood fom he and him and, at the same time, we guarantee
that him has no antecedent within its minimal S. So let us assume that
he(bound] has no simple W interpretation but is at least C(B(BW)B) or
B(BW)B,viz. , AgAfAX[f(gx)(x)] .
(35) a. Everyone thinks he[bound]
S/VP VP/S (VP\(VP/S /(S\NP)
likes John
S\NP
Ai
VP\(VP IS)
AfAx[f(likes(j)(x (x)]
6
C i the permutator, B(T(BBT (BBT) or V>XAy[YXJ .
7
Pace Pollard's "Evidently, there is no principled analysis of pied piping in an ex
tended categorial framework like Steedman's without the addition of a feature-passing
mechanism for unbounded dependencies" (1988, 421).
258 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
b. Everyone thinks John likes him[bound] .
S/VP VP/S S/VP VP/NP (VP\(VP /S
) )
\(S/NP
)
+
c. Everyone thinks John likes hi m [bound]
S/VP VP/S S/Vp VP/NP (VP\(VP /S
) )
\(S/NP
)
S/NP
A
.
VP\(VP/S
)
>1 >x[J(likes(x ) (
j
) )
(x)]
He/him [bound] , the S-pied piper, can only combine with S/NP or S\NP,
whence it cannot be bound to anything within its own clause. As was
pointed out above, anti-locality for he/him[fee] cannot be accommodated
in this way and must therefore be attributed to independent mechanisms.
The pictue emerging here is not only technically but also conceptually
diferent fom that of standard binding theory, which specifes only that
pronouns are fee in their governing category. However, it squares rather
well with an alternative theory proposed in Reinhart 1983. Reinhart ar
gues that the conation of coreference and bound variable interpretation
leads to enormous complications because the two are empirically diferent.
A pronoun may be coreferential with another referential expression even
if the latter does not c-command it; moreover, their (non-)coreference is
afected by pragmatic factors. On the other hand, a pronoun can only be
bound by a quantifer that c-commands it fom a distance at s-structure:
i.e. , bound variable interpretation is as strictly syntactic a refexivization.
In conclusion, she proposes to distinguish the syntactic theory of bound
anaphora from the pragmatic theory of coreference. See also Partee 1978.
It is extremely interesting to note here that acquisition studies by
Wexler and Chien fom 1988 provide evidence in support of Reinhart's dis
tinctions. In previous experiments they had found that English-speaking
children's performance on locality properties of refexives increaes steadily
fom age 2;6 to ahnost perfect performance at 5; 6. On the other hand,
children in the age range 5; 6 to 6; 6 still do not show that they have the
knowledge that a pronoun may not have a local c-commanding antecedent.
However, in the study reported in this paper they tested the hypothesis
that, in line with Reinhart's proposal, principle B really applies to bound,
and not coreferential, pronouns. They found that children at age 6 violate
principle B approximately 50% of the time with coreference, but less than
15% of the time in the case of a bound variable pronoun. s
B
The signifcance of Chien and Wexler's earlier results ha been challenged by Grimshaw
and Rosen 1988: they argue that children know, although they may not obey, principle B.
The 1988 study involving bound variables is not subjected to criticism i n Grimshaw and
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON I 259
These results, if correct, are especially important for combinatory gram
mar. As was pointed out, the above treatment of refexives and bound ver
sus free pronouns is the only kind of treatment the logical foundations make
available. Therefore it makes a much stronger case than Reinhart's the
ory, which formulates empirical observations within a grammar explicitly
incorporating the lambda-calculus.
Despite its acknowledged appeal, Reinhart's theory ha been criticized
in the literature fom various angles. In this paper I will not be concerned
with the problem raised by the possibility of a pronoun being bound by
a quantifer that does not c-command it at s-structure. (See a suggestion
in the revised version of Szabolcsi 1987. ) Rather, I will turn directly to a
third crucial binding phenomenon in Reinhart's theory, viz. , VP-ellipsis.
2. 3 VP-Ellipsis
It is well-known that elliptical VPs may be ambiguous between the "strict"
and the "sloppy" readings in the following kind of context:
(36) Felix hates his neighbors and so does Max.
a. sloppy reading: "and Max hates Max's neighbors"
b. strict reading: "and Max hates Felix's neighbors"
Reinhart ( 1983, 150-51) points out that the sloppy reading is obtained if
Felix binds his in the antecedent claue, and the strict reading is obtained
if his is merely coreferential with Felix. Reinhart is primarily interested in
the sloppy case, and her pertinent claim is generally accepted. On the other
hand, her claim concerning the strict reading faces a serious problem. If the
strict reading is contingent on accidental coreference, then it is predicted to
be available only if the antecedent itself is referential. But this prediction
is refuted by quantifcational antecedents, which also support the strict
reading in a slightly diferent context, viz. , when we are not dealing with
coordination:
(37) Every man mentioned his merits before Mary did.
a. sloppy: "before Mary mentioned her merits"
b. strict: "before Mary mentioned his merits"
Gawron and Peters ( 1990) discuss this point extensively and take it to be
one important piece of evidence against the correctness of Reinhart-like
theories of pronominal anaphora. They propose a system whose innova
tions include the postulation of three, rather than two, kinds of anaphoric
relations: co-variation (cf. co-reference) , role-linking (cf. binding) and, cru
cially, co-parametrization for cases like (37b) . The reader is referred to
their book for details.
Rosen's paper, however, and it appears to me that Grimshaw and Rosen's fndings are
perfectly compatible with the results concerning the diferential acquisition of conditions
on binding and coreference.
260 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
Let us see what the combinatory theory of anaphora has to say about
example (37). At frst glance, it appears to be impossible to give an account
of (37b) . The reasoning, along the lines of Gawron and Peters, goes as
follows. We have binding in the frst clause, so its VP must be interpreted
a >x[ mentioned(x
'
s merits) (x)J . If the ellipted VP echoes this, we get the
sloppy reading; fne. In order to get the strict reading, we should start
out with an antecedent VP meaning containing a fee variable, echo this,
and then bind both occurrences of that variable. But we cannot get free
variables bound. Hence (37b) seems disatrous. In a sense, it is even more
disatrous for this theory than for Reinhart's since, a I noted above, what
is stipulated in her theory is a matter of logical necessity here.
This reaoning ha an important presupposition, namely, that strict
readings with non-referential antecedents need to be accounted for specif
ically by the machinery for pronominal anaphora and, therefore, if the
pronominal anaphora machinery ha nothing to say about it, the availabil
ity of this reading is evidence against the machinery.
In what follows I will suggest that this presupposition is false, and
hence the reasoning is wrong. First, I will observe that strict readings
with non-referential antecedents arise even in contexts without any overt
anaphora. Therefore the existence of (37b) does not directly refect on
the viability of proposals concerning pronouns. Second, I will ask whether
the treatment of the natural clas of phenomena to which (37b) belongs
really requires that we go beyond the tools of combinatory grammar and
introduce a novel device like co-parametrization. I will argue that it does
not. I will outline an account in CCG, and point out that it requires only a
minimal extension of what we already have, because good old composition
plus duplication will do "co-parametrization" for us. In this paper I will
not investigate how other theories that do not have these would derive the
critical examples.
The frst step is entirely theory-independent. The consideration of two
examples will sufce to show that the problem and, consequently, the treat
ment of (37b) is independent of the specifc abilities of pronouns. One
is (38):
(38) Every man mentioned himself before Mary did.
a. sloppy: "before Mary mentioned herself"
b. strict: "before Mary mentioned him"
Given that (38) contains a refexive, it shows that we must be able to
produce the strict reading with a non-referential antecedent even under
the canonically syntactic conditions refexive binding is subject to. Second,
consider (39):
(39) Who did you mention before Mary did?
"Which T, you mentioned x before Mary mentioned x"
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 261
As the interpretation makes clear, 39)presents precisely the same problem
as 37b) and 38b) . But it is a simple extraction structure, so the prob
lem must be independent of the treatment of overt anaphoric elements on
the whole.
With these observations in mind we may now proceed and see how the
phenomenon can be handled in CCG. It is to be emphasized that in this
paper I will not develop a detailed account of VP-ellipsis but concentrate
only on the points relevant for the argument as sketched above. The frst
task is to accommodate the simplest case of VP-ellipsis, with which we start:
40) John lef before Mary did.
Observe that the interpretation of 40) involves duplication, namely: be
fore ( lef( Mary ( lef) . One way to capture this would be to say that did
is a duplicator, i.e. , it has the same meaning as items like himself, but
its typing is diferent: the function whose arguments it identifes has VP,
rather than NP, arguments. This proposal encounters two kinds of dif
culty. One is the fact that many of the pertinent examples work also in
the absence of did ( John lef before Mary, etc. ) . The second is that this
proposal would extend easily to 39) but, for rather technical reasons, not
to 38b) . Therefore I will largely ignore the contribution of did and use
the same Wa the interpretation of a syntactic operation. Technically, W
can be implemented as a new interpretation for concatenation, see 41a) ,
or as a unary type-change) rule that applies to the material in the second
clause, as in 41 b) . Given that here the use of W is followed by applica
tion, the choice makes no diference. I sketch both options because binary
W may be more intuitive, but subsequent steps will have to utilize the
unary one.
41) a. lef before Mary did
S\NP ( (S\NP) \ (S\NP) )/S S/(S\NP)
B
.
( (S\NP) \ (S\NP /(S\NP)
W
..
S\NP
b. lef before Mary did
S\NP ( (S\NP) \(S\NP /S S/(S\NP)
B,
( (S\NP) \ (S\NP / (S\NP)
W
(S\NP)\(S\NP)
A
..
S\NP
For the reader's convenience, in what follows I will spell out the interpre
tation of each line in lambda terms. Intermediate steps will be omitted if
given in a previous example:
262 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
(41' ) a. B(before) (Mary did)
AaAbAc[a( bc)] (ApAgAX [before (
p
) (g ) (x )] ) (AJ[J( m)] )
AbAC[A
p
AgAX
[before (
p
)(g ) (x
) ] ( bC)](AJ[J(m)])
= AbAcAgAx[b
efore(bc) (g) (X)] ( AJ[J(
m)] )
=
AcAgAx[bef
ore(
V
[J(m)] (
c)) (g) (x)]
ACAgAx[before(cm) (g) (x)]
W(B(before) ( Mary-did)) (left)
= AaAb[abb] (AcAgAx[before(cm) (g )(x )] )( left)
Ab[AcAgAx[before( cm ) (g ) (x ) ] ( b )(b )] (left)
AbAx[before(bm) (b) (x)] (left)
Ax[before(left( m) ) (left ) (x)]
b. B(before) (Mary-did) = ACAgAx[before(cm) (g) (x)]
W(B(before) ( Mary-did))
= AaAb[ abb] ( ACAg AX [before( cm ) (g) (x )] )
AbAx[before(bm)(b) (x)]
W( B(before) (Mary-did)) (left)
AbAX [before(bm) (b) (x)] (left)
= Ax[before(lef(m) ) (left ) (x)]
This accommodates the simplest cae of VP-ellipsis. Now consider ( 39):
(39) Who did you mention before Mary did?
Sentence (39) presents a problem on its own right. W echoes a VP-meaning
but, the direct object being extracted, there is no VP in the antecedent
clause. Recall that our grammar ha no traces.
The problem of (39) is in fact eay to solve with the tools our grammar
ha had al along. In (41b) the segment W(B(before Mary)) is combined
with lef by application. But it can equally well combine with mention by
composition-and that is all we need. A straightforward execution of this
idea is given in (42a). Once more, (42b) presents an alternative that makes
no diference here but will underlie the next derivation. In (42b) a unary
combinator BBW is used, followed by application. BBW is obtained by
composing the above motivated steps W and B, and serves no other end
than lumping these two together in the said order. For its expression in
lambda terms, recall (24b) .
(42) a. mention before
Mary did
(S\NP) /NP ( (S\NP) \(S\NP))/S S/(S\NP)
Bi
S\NP) \
( S\NP) ) / (S\NP)
--W
(S\NP) \ (S\NP)
B
ii
(S\NP)/NP
COMBINATORY GRAMMAR AND PROJECTION FROM THE LEXICON / 263
b. mention before Mary did
(S\NP)/NP ( (S\NP)\(S\NP) )/S S/(S\NP)
B
.
( (S\NP) \ (S\NP / (S\NP)
BBW
( (S\NP) /NP) \ ( (S\NP) /NP)
^
(S\NP)/NP
Note the replacement of the two occurrences of b in (42'a) with cd: this
has the efect of "co-parametrization" .
(42' ) a. W(B(before) (Mary-did)) = AbAx[before(bm) (b)(x)]
B ((W (before) (Mary-did ) (mention)
= AaAcAd[a( cd)] (AbAx[before(bm) (b ) (x )] ) (mention)
= Ac'd[ 'b'x[before( bm) ( b) (x)] (cd)] (mention)
= Ac,d,x [before ( cdm) c)(x)] ( mention)
= Ad'x[before( mention( d) (m (mention( d (x)]
b. B(before) (Mary-did) = 'cAg'x[before(cm)(g) (x)]
BBW = ,f'h,y[f(h
y
) ( h
y
)]
BBW(B(before) (Mary-did
= AI 'hAy[f(hy) ( hy
)] (AcAg'x[before(cm) (
g
) (x)] )
= AhA
y
'x[before( hym)(h
y
) (x)]
BBW(B(before)(Mary-did (mention)
= AYAx[before(mention(
y
) (m( mention(
y
(x)]
In view of the informal suggestion made at the outset, with these we
must have everything ready to cater to the ambiguity with anaphors. To
avoid the treatment of possessive pronoun, I will only consider (38) here.
The sloppy reading is derivable by mimicking (41b). For compactness,
S\NP will be abbreviated as VP whenever this does not afect intelligibility.
(43) mention himself before Mary did
VP/NP VP\(VP/NP) B
i
A
..
W
VP (S\NP)\ VP
^tt
S\NP
(43' ) W(B(before) (Mary-did = 'bAx[before(bm) (b) (x)]
himself = W = AI Ay[fyy]
W(mention) = AI,y[fyy] (mention) = ,y
[mention(
y
) (
y
)]
W(B(before ) ( Mary-did) ) (W(mention) )
= AbAx[before( bm) ( b) (x)] (AY[ mention(
y
) (
y
)] )
= Ax[before( mention( m)( m (mention( x )( x ]
264 / ANNA SZABOLCSI
Consider now the strict reading. The correct semantic result obtains if we
apply himself, the duplicator to the interpretation of mention before Mary
did derived in (42) :
(44) W(BBW(B(before) (Mary-did) ) (mention) )
>f >z[f zz] ( >
y
>x[before(mention(y) (m) ) (mention(y)) (x)] )
>z[>y
>x[before(mention(
y
) (m) ) (mention(y
) ) (x )] (z ) (
z
) ]
>z[before( mention( z) ( m) ) ( mention( z) ) (z)]
We could indeed do this and thus derive the strict reading by simply mim
icking (42) if we had a wrap operation in syntax:
( 45) mention himself before Mary did
AhAqAx
(x) (
R
) (y)lll
What this means is that if some individual @ (the denotation of the sub
ject argument) stands in the a; relation to the relation R denoted by the
VP /NP complement, then there is some individual 2 such that @, Z, and R
stand in the a relation. Now this is not quite right, since the missing PP
complement is not understood as existentially quantifed. The most natu
ral reading for (70) is one where the missing PP is understood generically,
or has an interpretation much like the NP one. Thus let us reformulate the
semantic part of Chierchia's proposal as in (72) :
(72) a
;
= A
R
[Ay[a
(
on
e' )(
R
) ( y)]]
The key point is that it follows that one' is also the understood subject
of the VP; this basic point is discussed in detail in Chierchia 1984. Take
the case where this rule applies to a lexical item like impossible. The
lexical item derived by the rule (71-72) is such that if a sentence like
(70) is true, then the-rock' and one' stand in what we will now call the
impossible-relation to move'. Note, though, that impossible is simply
the relation discussed earlier, and it therefore entails something about one'
and the-rock' standing in the move'-relation. It follows, then, that the
understood argument of impossible is also the understood subject of the
complement.
296 / PAULINE JACOBSON
But this is not a fll account, for the missing argument of impossi
ble need not be understood a one'. As detailed in Kimball 1971 , it
can also be understood as the meaning of some NP in a higher clause,
a in ( 73):
(73) a. John thought that the rock would be impossible to move.
b. John thought that the movie would be hard to convince himself
to like.
Just how to account for this second reading is unclear. It is tempt
ing to posit another lexical rule here by which a free variable is sup
plied in the relevant argument position, where the value of that vari
able will be contextually supplied. However, this predicts that the value
for this variable can be any individual salient in the discourse. Yet it
seems difcult, if not impossible, to get the relevant reading in a case
like (74) :
(74) John is always procrastinating. ?
*
This last homework assignment
was particularly difcult to convince himself to do on time.
Compare (74) to ( 75) , where the PP i overt:
(75) John is always procratinating. This lat homework asignment was
particularly difcult for him to convince himself to do on time.
Thus the problem of how to establish the control relation between John
and the "missing PP" in (73) remains an unsolved problem.
There are, then, several peculiarities of the tough construction which
remain unexplained. Nonetheless, I hope to have established two main
points. First, there is no syntactic linkage between the tough subject and
the gap. Second, the semantic linkage can be handled straightforwardly
under the lexical entailment theory of control. Thus this construction pro
vides additional evidence for the hypothesis that control is only a matter
of entailments associated with lexical items.
References
Akmajian, Adrian. 1984. Sentence Types and the Form-Function Fit. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 2: 1-23.
Bach, Emmon. 1979. Control in Montague Grammar. Linguistic Inquiry 10: 515-
532.
Bayer, Samuel. 1990. Tough Movement Function Composition. In Proceedings
of the 9th Annual West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Peter
Sells. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Berman, Arlene. 1973. Adjectives and Adjective Complement Constructions in
English. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.
Brame, Michael. 1979. Essays Toward Realistic Syntax. Seattle: Noit Amrofer.
Bresnan, Joan. 1971. Sentence Stress and Syntactic Tansformation. Language
47:257-281.
CONTROL AND THE TOUGH-CONSTRUCTION / 297
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1984. Topics in the Syntax and Semantics of Infnitives and
Gerunds. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts. Distributed by
the Graduate Linguistics Student Association, University of Massachusetts.
Chierchia, Gennaro. To appear. Anaphora and Attitudes De Se. In Language in
Action, ed. Renate Bartsch et al. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chierchia, Gennaro, and Pauline Jacobson. 1985. Local and Long Distance
Control. In Proceedings of NELS 16, 57-74. Amherst: Univeristy of Mas
sachusetts, GLSA.
Chomsky, Noam. 1973. Conditions on Tansformations. In A Festschrif for
Morris Halle, ed. Stephen R. Anderson and Paul Kiparsky, 232-286. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Chomsky, Noam. 1977. On Wh-movement. In Formal Syntax, ed. Peter Culicover,
Thoma Wasow, and Adrian Akmajian. New York: Academic Press.
Dowty, David. 1985. On Recent Analyses of the Semantics of Control. Linguistics
and Philosophy 8:291-331.
Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic Proto-Roles and Argument Selection. Language
67(3):547-619.
Dowty, David, and Pauline Jacobson. 1988. Agreement as a Semantic Phe
nomenon. In Proceedings of the 5th Annual Eastern States Conference on
Linguistics, ed. Joyce Powers and Ken de Jong. Columbus: Ohio State Uni
versity.
Fodor, Janet D. 1983. Phrase Structure Parsing and the Island Constraints.
Linguistics and Philosophy 6: 163-223.
Gazdar, Gerald. 1980. English as a Context-fee Language. Manuscript, Univer
sity of Sussex.
Gazdar, Gerald, Ewan Klein, Geofrey K. Pullum, and Ivan A. Sag. 1985. Gen
eralized Phrase Structure Grammar. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, and Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Grimshaw, Jane. 1976. Wh-Constructions and the Theory of Grammar. Doctoral
dissertation, University of Massachusetts.
Grimshaw, Jane. 1982. Grammatical Relations and Subcategorization. In Sub
jects and Other Subjects: Proceedings of the Harvard Conference on Gram
matical Relations, ed. Annie Zaenen, 35-55. Bloomington: Indiana University
Linguistics Club.
Hankamer, Jorge, and Ivan A. Sag. 1976. Deep and Surface Anaphora. Linguistic
Inquiry 7:391-426.
Hukari, Thomas, and Robert Levine. 1987. Rethinking Connectivity in Un
bounded Dependency Constructions. In Proceedings of the 6th Annual West
Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Megan Crowhurst, 91-102. Stan
ford University: Stanford Linguistics Association.
Hukari, Thomas, and Robert Levine. 1990. The Complement Structure of Tough
Constructions. In Proceedings of the 7th Annual Eastern States Conference
on Linguistics. Columbus: Ohio State University.
Hukari, Thomas, and Robert Levine. 1991. On the Disunity of Unbounded
Dependency Constructions. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 9( 1) :97-
144.
298 / PAUL1NE JACOBSON
Jackendof, Ray. 1972. Semantic Interretation in Genertive Grmmar. Cam
bridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1982. Evidence for Gaps. In The Nature of Syntactic Repre
sentation, ed. Pauline Jacobson and Geofrey K. Pullum, 187-228. Dordrecht:
Reidel.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1984. Connectivity in Phrase Structure Grammar. Naturl
Language and Linguistic Theory 1: 535-581.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1987a. Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar (review arti
cle). Linguistics and Philosophy 10: 389-426.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1987b. Phrase Structure, Grammatical Relations and Dis
continuous Constituents. In Syntax and Semantics 20: Discontinuous Con
stituency, ed. Geofrey Huck and Almerindo Ojeda, 27-69. New York: Aca
demic Press.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1989. A(nother) Categorial Grammar Account of Extrac
tion. Paper presented at the Conference on Categorial Grammar at the LSA
Summer Linguistic Institute, Tucson.
Jacobson, Pauline. 1990. Raising as Function Composition. Linguistics and
Philosophy 13:423-475.
Jacobson, Pauline. To appear. Raising Without Movement. In Control and
Grammatical Theory, ed. Richard Larson et al. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Kimball, John. 1971. Super-Equi-NP-Deletion as Dative Deletion. In Papers from
the 7th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, ed. D. Adams et al.
University of Chicago.
Klein, Ewan, and Ivan A. Sag. 1985. Type-driven Tanslation. Linguistics and
Philosophy 8: 163-202.
Ladusaw, William, and David Dowty. 1988. Toward a Nongrammatical Account
of Thematic Roles. In Syntax and Semantics: Thematic Relations, ed. Wendy
Wilkins, 61-73. New York: Academic Press.
Lanik, Howard, and Robert Fiengo. 1974. Complement Object Deletion. Lin
guistic Inquiry 5:535-571.
Levine, Robert. 1991. On Missing Object Constructions and the Function
composition Analysis of Raising. Manuscript, Ohio State University.
Oehrle, Richard. 1990. Categorial Frameworks, Coordination, and Extraction. In
Proceedings of the 9th Annual West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics,
ed. Peter Sells. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1987. Information-Based Syntax and Semantics,
Vol. I: Fundamentals. CSLI Lecture Notes No. 13. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1988. An Information-based Theory of Agreement.
In Proceedings of the Parasession on Agreement, ed. Diane Brentari, Gary
Larson, and Lynn McCleod, 236-257. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1992. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grmmar.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, and Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Postal, Paul. 1970. On Coreferential Complement Subject Deletion. Linguistic
Inquiry 1 : 439-500.
CONTROL AND THE TOUGH-CONSTRUCTION / 299
Postal, Paul. 1971 . Crss- Over Phenomena. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and
Winston.
Postal, Paul, and John R. Ross. 1971 . Tough Movement Si, Tough Deletion No!
Linguistic Inquiry 2:544-546.
Rosenbaum, Peter. 1967. The Grammar of English Predicate Complement Con
structions. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Sag, Ivan A. 1982. A Semantic Theory of NP-movement Dependencies. In The
Nature of Syntactic Representation, ed. Pauline Jacobson and Geofrey K.
Pullum, 427-466. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Schachter, Paul. 1981. Lovely to Look At. Linguistic Analysis 8:431-448.
Steedman, Mark J. 1987. Combinatory Grammars and Parasitic Gaps. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 5(3): 403-349.
Wasow, Thomas, Ivan A. Sag, and Geofrey Nunberg. 1983. Idioms: An Interim
Report. In Proceedings of the XIIIth Interational Congress of Linguists, ed.
Shiro Hattori and Kazuko Inoue, 102-115. Tokyo: CIPL.
II
A Lexical Analysis of Icelandic Case
IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
1 Introduction
The facts of performance have much to tell us about our knowledge of lan
guage. In performance-that is, in real-time language use-our knowledge
of language is deployed in wondrous harmony with knowledge of the world,
knowledge of the utterance situation, knowledge of our fellow interlocutors,
and so forth. Given the extent to which interpretation depends on such fac
tors, i. e. the extent to which linguistic knowledge alone fails to determine
interpretation, it remains quite mysterious how we humans are able to use
language to communicate determinate messages accurately and efciently.
One fndamental problem that will occupy the study of language in the
decades to come is one we will refer to here a the Resolution Problem: the
problem of how diverse kinds of knowledge-linguistic and otherwise-are
efciently integrated in real-time language processing. Fom a linguistic
perspective, taking this problem seriously means that we must ask our
linguistic descriptions to do more for us than they have in the past. It is not
enough that grammars express linguistic generalizations. If our grammars
are ultimately to help us address the Resolution Problem (and explain other
properties of performance) , then they should be designed in accordance
with certain criteria that emerge fom basic observations about the nature
of performance. Some of the relevant observations about human language
processing are these:
( 1) Partiality: In real-time, partial descriptions of linguistic structure
are accessed incrementally.
Flexibility: The partial information from these descriptions may be
We would like to thank Avery Andrews, Joan Maling, and Annie Zanen for their help.
This research wa supported in part by a gift to Stanford University from The System
Development Foundation, and in part by a grant from the National Science Foundation
(BNS-8511687).
Leztccl Mctter Ivan A. Sag and Anna Szabo1csi, eds.
Copyright 1992, Stanford University.
302 / IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
fexibly integrated with non-linguistic information in real-time pro
cessing.
Order-Independence: Linguistic information is not consulted in any
fxed order; there may be task-specifc variations in the order in
which relevant information is accessed.
Reversibility: In general, linguistic knowledge is consulted equally
well by diverse kinds of processors, e. g. , those that perform compre
hension and those that perform production.
While such observations about language use could in theory be explained
in a variety of ways, and perhaps made consistent with a number of ar
chitectures for the design of grammar, it is evident that certain existing
grammatical architectures-and not others-begin to make sense of these
facts of performance.
We are in a better position to begin to explain the observations in ( 1)
i f we render linguistic knowledge declaratively, i. e. , as a static system of
constraints, as is the cae, for example, within work in the traditions of
phrase structure and categorial grammar. These systems of grammar em
ploy no destructive rules whose order of application with respect to other
rules must be crucially fxed. Hence these systems of grammar are appro
priately unbiased with respect to comprehension and production. Lexical
entries and grammar rules in phrae structure and categorial systems can
be interpretd a nothing more than constraints on structures that provide
reliable partial information about linguistic structures, rather than infor
mation that is true of a structure only at some point in its derivation. And
because the information involved is highly restricted, the data structures
to be computed in incremental processing of substrings are highly con
strained. It thus becomes possible to formulate precise models of process
ing that attempt to reflect the observed properties of partiality, flexibility,
and order-independence.
By contrast, transformational models including GB models where
' Move a' is interpreted literally) provide little help in explaining the per
formance properties listed above. Rules perform mappings fom total rep
resentations of a sentence at a particular "level of representation" to other
total representations, and these mappings have typically involved deletions,
permutations, insertions, and the like. Moreover such mappings are not in
general reversible; nor are their computational properties in general well
understood. There is no clear way to model fexible, integrative process
ing of partial transformational descriptions, though one can imagine that
a performance model based on transformational grammars would require
some mechanism for mapping transformational descriptions onto some set
of constraints that either are otiose or else closely resemble those posited
within phrase structure and categorial theories.
These considerations strongly suggest that constraint-based linguistic
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 303
descriptions like phrae structure grammars and categorial grammars hold
greater promise for reconciling the theory of linguistic knowledge (or "com
petence" ) with the facts of language processing (performance) . However,
the fact remains that many complex and well-studied sets of language data
constitute a serious challenge for purely constraint-based, non-derivational
linguistic theories such a these. 1 In this paper, we discuss one of these chal
lenges, namely the problem of "quirky" case in Icelandic, which has been
analyzed by Thrainsson ( 1979) , Andrews ( 1976, 1982, 1990) and Yip et al.
(1987), among others. The data we discuss appear to warrant an analysis
that employs transformational rules, constraining equations (Kaplan and
Bresnan 1982), or some other non-monotonic syntactic device. The analysis
we propose, however, functions in a purely monotonic, order-independent,
process-neutral fashion, and hence constitutes a performance-compatible
description of this troublesome set of facts. This description involves only
lexical entries and schematic phrase structure rules, which together spec
if a set of constraints that the well-formed structures of Icelandic must
satisf.
Constraint-baed analyses in general, and ours in particular, rely heav
ily on lexical information. The complexity of this information raises new
questions about how lexical information is structured and how lexical
generalizations are expressed. In light of these concerns, we also dis
cuss the implications of our analysis for the organization of the Icelandic
lexicon.
2 The Problem of "Quirky" Case
Icelandic verbs, in the default circumstance, take subjects whose cae must
be nominative:
(2) Drengurinn kyssti stWkuna bilnum
the-boy.NOM kissed the-girl.ACC in the-car.DAT
'The boy kissed the girl in the car. '
But Icelandic ha a number of verbs that assign quirky (i. e. , non
nominative) case to their subjects. In (3)-(6) we see examples with ac
cusative subjects.
2
(3) Mig langar ao fara
me.ACC longs to to-go
'I long to go to Iceland. '
til
i
slands.
to(LOC) Iceland
(4) Hana dreymdi ur haf.
she.ACC dreamed about the-sea
'She dreamed about the sea.'
For some discussion, see Kay 1986, Sag et al. 1985, and Sag 1991.
2
All of the data we will discuss here are taken from Andrews 1982.
304 / IVAN SAG, LAURl KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
(5) Mig velgir vic setningafroi.
me.ACC is-nauseated at syntax
' Syntax turns my stomach. '
( 6) Drengina vantar mat.
the-boys.ACC lack food.ACC
'The boys lack food. '
In (7)-( 10) we see examples with dative subjects.
(7)
(8)
Honum mrltist vel i kirkjunni.
He. DAT spoke well in the-church
' He spoke well in church.'
Henni akotnaoist bill.
her.DAT lucked-onto car. NOM
' She got possession of a car by luck. '
(9) StUlkunni svelgdist a sUpunni.
girl.DAT mis-swallowed on the-soup
'The girl swallowed the soup wrong. '
( 10) Barninu batnaoi veikin.
the-child. DAT recovered-from the-diseae.NOM
'The child recovered fom the diseae. '
And we also fnd verbs that take genitive subjects a shown i n ( 1 1 )-(12).
(11) Verkjanna grtir ekki.
the-pains.GEN is-noticeable not
'The pains are not noticeable'
( 12) Konungs var pamgao von.
the-king.GEN wa thither expectation. NOM
'The king wa expected there. '
I n all three instances, the quirky case i s the only possible one for the subject
in question.
Raising verbs are what makes Icelandic cae assignment intriguing. If
the infnitival complement's verbal head does not asign quirky cae, then
the "raised" subject of a fnite form of a subject raising verb must be
nominative in cae:
( 13) Hann viroist elska hana.
he.NOM seems to-love her.ACC
'He seems to love her. '
This i s what one might expect. But i n examples like the following, the
raised subject takes the quirky case assigned by the verb that is the head
of the infnitival complement:
(14) Hana viroist vanta peninga.
her.ACC seems to-lack money
' She seems to lack money. '
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 305
( 15) Barninu viroist hafa batnao veikin.
the-child. DAT seems to-have recovered-from the-disease
'The child seems to have recovered from the disease. '
(16) Verkjanna viroist ekki grta.
the-pains. GEN seems not to-be-noticeable
'The pains don't seem to be noticeable.'
Note that in ( 15) , the quirky case NP is separated from its case assigner
by two subject raising verbs ( viroist and hala) .
Similar facts may be observed i n the case of object raising constructions.
If the head of the infnitival complement is a quirky case assigner, then the
raised object NP must bear the appropriate quirky case:
( 17) Hann telur mig vanta peninga.
he.NOM believes me.ACC to-lack money
'He believes that I lack money. '
( 18) Hann telur barninu hafa batnao veikin.
he believes the-child.DAT to-have recovered-fom the disease
'He believes the child to have recovered from the disease. '
( 19) Hann telur verkjanna ekki grta.
he believes the-pains.GEN not to-be-noticeable
' He believes the pains to be no noticeable. '
But if the infnitival complement's verbal head is not a quirky case assigner,
then the raised NP must be accusative in cae a shown in (20).
(20) peir telja Mariu hafa skrifao ritgeroina.
they believe Mary. ACC to-have written the-thesis
' They believe Mary to have written her thesis. '
In short, Icelandic exhibits what appears to be a syntactic non-mono
tonic case assignment system. It is one that could be described in trans
formational terms by assuming ( 1 ) that quirky verbs assign case to their
subjects prior to the application of raising rules (or, if one prefers, ' Move
a' ) , (2) that fnite subject raising verbs optionally assign nominative case
to their subjects, (3) that object raising verbs optionally assign accusative
case to their objects, and that (4) all NP's must be assigned case somehow
(the "Case Filter" ) . 3
But the derivational (movement transformations) and non-monotonic
(fltering conditions) character of such an analyses is inconsistent with the
performance-based design considerations we discussed at the outset. Per
haps there is a version of this analysis that can be made to provide answers
to the puzzles posed by performance, but it is certainly not any analysis
based on the Cae Filter that has been discussed in the literature we are
3
Chomsky 1981 and elsewhere.
306 / IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
familiar with. All such analyses presume derivational mappings between
fully specifed syntactic representations, with the Case Filter functioning
a a non-monotonic constraint that must be checked only afer all trans
formational rules have had an opportunity to apply.
In another infuential analysis of Icelandic cae dependencies, Yip et al.
( 1987) explain an impressive array of complex facts by adapting certain
idea fom non-linear phonology (Goldsmith 1976, 1990) . The essence of
their analysis is a factoring of the case assignment patterns into the inter
action between a basic nominative-accusative tier and a restricted set of
lexical and semantically based exceptions. Their analysis also relies on a
principle fltering derivations where an NP receives no cae. Moreover, their
approach clearly employs cyclic application of syntactic rules (p. 241f.)
whose efect is to destructively modify the initial (lowest cycle) cae value
asigned to a given NP. Although their analysis expresses generalizations
about Icelandic cae not captured by previous approaches, it fails to do
so in a way that is compatible with the declarative, constraint-satisfaction
architecture for the design of grammar.
There are alternatives that one can imagine. Following the style of
Neidle's (1982) LFG analysis of Russian, one might employ constraining
equations (Kaplan and Bresnan 1982) to ensure that case is asigned to
every NP in a syntactic structure. Like the transformational analysis, this
approach would have quirky verbs obligatorily assign cae to their sub
jects, while raising verbs asigned the appropriate default case optionally.
A raised NP is identifed with the subject of the appropriate complement,
hence if nouns are lexically specifed with constraining equations requiring
that the appropriate cae must get asigned to them, then this analysis
accomplishes the same efect a the transformational one, without trans
formational rules.
But such an analysis is also potentially objectionable on performance
grounds, for the constraint that it relies on functions in a non-monotonic
fashion. Constraining equations are defned as conditions that must be
met by functional descriptions, that is, they are not just constraints on
functional structures. Rather, they are crucially defned as flters on the
process that maps constituent structures to functional structures.4 Perhaps
models of language processing could be devised to deal with limited non
monotonicity of this sort, S but this remains an open issue. 6
The question of how to reconcile limited non-monotonicity with the
facts of performance is one that need not arise. Appearances to the contrary
4 An analysis essentially equivalent to this can be formulated using Kay's ANY variable,
one which must receive a value in a complete linguistic description.
5
So, for example, Johnson's (1988) discussion of completeness and consistency con
straints in LFG.
6We will not discuss here the alternate LFG analysis of Icelandic cae proposed by
Andrews ( 1990).
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 307
notwithstanding, the generalizations of Icelandic quirky case asignment
can be elegantly expressed within an analysis that involves no destructive
operations, no non-monotonic constraints, and no transformational deriva
tions. It is to this analysis that we turn directly.
3 A Lexical Solution
In any adequate lexical theory, verbs must be provided with some mecha
nism for selecting for their various dependents, including subjects, objects,
oblique NP's or PP's, and complements of various sorts. We will asume,
following a long-standing tradition of research in Categorial Grammar,7
that the syntactic arguments of a verb are hierarchically arranged accord
ing to a more or less traditional notion of "obliqueness" . This notion ha
also played a role i Relational Grammar analyses of grammatical relations,
in Keenan and Comrie's (1977) cross-linguistic work on relative clause for
mation, and in the LFG theory of default controller assignment (Bresnan
1982) .
To implement this idea, we will asume a simplifed version of the notion
of SUBCAT list, developed independently by Pollard and Sag within Head
Driven Phrae Structure Grammar (Pollard and Sag 1987, 1992) and by
researchers developing the PATR-I I system at SRI International (Shieber
et a1. 1983) . The order of elements on the SUBCAT list corresponds not to
surface order (Le. , the linear order in which the phonological realizations
of the elements occur), but rather to the order of obliqueness, with more
oblique elements appearing later than (i. e. , to the right of) less oblique
elements. Following long-standing tradition, PP (or VP or S) complements
are treated a more oblique than direct objects when both occur, and direct
objects in turn are more oblique than subjects. Thus the SUBCAT list for
an intransitive verb contains exactly one NP, corresponding to the verb's
subject; and the SUBCAT list for a (strict) transitive verb contains exactly
two NP signs, the frst corresponding to the verb's subject and the second
to its direct object. Verbs of higher valence have appropriately specifed
longer SUBCAT lists.
Thus the lexical representation of each verb specifes partial information
about the number and kind of syntactic dependents that that verb can
combine with. Each element on the SUBCAT list is a partial specifcation
of information about a particular syntactic dependent of the verb, and
the actual complements the verb combines with must be consistent with
the partial information the verb selects for. Verbs may thus select (for
any of their dependents) : grammatical category, agreement features, cae,
valence, and so forth.
A typical fnite, transitive verb form like kyssti ('kissed' ) would be spec
ifed a follows:
7See, for example, Dowty 1982a,b.
308 / IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
( 21)
[
.
nom
np
1
3;d
smg
Fom this lexical specifcation, it follows that kyssti can combine only with
an accusative object and a 3rd person singular subject
And we have already introduced sufcient machinery to provide an anal
ysis of the fnite forms of quirky subject verbs in Icelandic. These forms
simply specif diferent information about their subjects' cae, a illustrated
in (22)-(24) .
( 22) langar:
(23) askotnaoist:
(24) grtir:
np ]
acc .
np ]
dat
But this simple method of imposing case restrictions on verbal dependents
is insufcient for the raising constructions discussed earlier, as we will now
show.
The most straightforward treatment of raising constructions in lexically
baed theories of grammar (e. g. , Bresnan 1982, Pollard and Sag 1987, 1992)
involves identifing the raised element with the unexpressed subject of the
complement. Under the assumptions we are making here, com
plements are phrases whose value contains exactly one element,
corresponding to the unexpressed subject of the "downstairs" verb. Rais
ing is thus accomplished by positing lists like the following for
raising verbs.
(25) Simple subject raising verb:
np| ,
. 1
np| , .
vp
l )
inf
, J
)
BWe use the attribute CAT here U an expository convenience. In the theory of grammar
developed in Pollard and Sag 1987, 1992, category information is analyzed partially in
terms of values for the feature HEAD. In virtue of the Head Feature Principle, category
information is projected from verbs to VPs and Ss, from nouns to 'N's and NPs, and so
forth. Nothing hinges on this in the present discussion.
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE ] 309
Here the tags (e.g., I) indicate identity (or structure-sharing) between the
VP complement's unexpressed subject (the one element on its SUBCAT
list) and the appropriate other dependent of the verb.
This lexical approach to raising phenomena would appear to give the
right result for complements headed by quirky verbs. Assuming the
SUBCAT specifcations given above hold for both fnite and non-fnite verbal
fonns, the infnitive form of an accusative subject verb (e.g., vanta) would
give rise to a VP specifed as [SUBCAT (NP[acc] ) ] . The subject raising verb
viroist, specifed a in (25), would then combine with the VP vanta peninga
to form a VP that is also specifed a [SUBCAT (NP[acc] ) ] , a shown in (26) .
(26) VP[SUBCAT ([) ]
.
V
[SUBCAT ( [, ) ]
I
VP[SUBCAT ([)]
6
viroist vanta peninga
And this VP can combine only with an accusative subject to form such
sentences a Hana.ACC viroist vanta peninga.
Similarly, the lexical analysis of raising correctly predicts that quirky
case selections will be inherited in object raising:
(27) VP[SUBCAT { ilNP [nom] ) ]
V
[SUBCAT ( il, , I) ]
|
NP[gen] !VP[SUBCAT () ]
1 6
telur verkjanna
ekki grta
The object of telur ('believe' ) must appear in whatever case the VP com
plement requires of its (unexpressed) subject.
The problem that now arises concerns non-quirky verbs. If we assume
that non-fnite fonns of non-quirky verbs select for nominative subjects
(like their fnite counterparts) , then the lexical raising analysis works fne
for simple subject raising cases, but incorrectly predicts that the object
of telur will also be nominative when the VP complement is headed by a
non-quirky verb. As we saw earlier, such raised objects must be accusative
in case. If, on the other hand, we were to assume that the non-fnite forms
of non-quirky verbs selected for accusative case subjects, then we would
have no account of the fact that in subject raising, the matrix subject
(e.g., of viroist must be nominative if the VP complement is headed by a
non-quirky verb. Nor can we allow such verbs to make disjunctive cae
selections (nominative 0I accusative) for their subjects, because this is not
sufcient to block the incorrect choice of cae in either raising construction.
The problem here is that the notion of default case assignment is not
being expressed. The default case for subjects of fnite verb forms is nom-
310 / IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
inative; the default case for direct objects is accusative. The non-quirky
verbs obey these defaults; the quirky verbs do not. This is the fundamental
intuition of the solution we now propose.
Let us assume that there are two distinct features that nominals bear:
CASE and DCASE, where CASE, as before, corresponds to the actual cae
that the NP in question will bear and DCASE corresponds to the default
case that a nominal bears in a given syntactic position. Nominals have no
inherent DCASE value, but verbs may subcategorize for subjects or objects
that have particular CASE values or particular DCASE values. The difer
ence between quirky and non-quirky verbs can now be analyzed a follows:
(28) Non-quirky verbs require that the DCASE and CASE values of their
subjects be identifed (structure-shared) .
Quirky verbs impose no such identity, and select a particular CASE
value for their subject.
Thus the SUBCAT lists for all forms of quirky verbs are just a before
(see (19) above). They specif CASE values for their subjects, but say
nothing about the subjects' DCASE values. The lexical entries for non
quirky verbs, on the other hand, will all contain the following information:
(29)
( [CAT
SUBCAT CASE
DCASE
Note that no particular value for either CASE or DCASE is assigned to the
subject in (29) . The only information specifed i that the two features
have the same value, however that may be determined.
We may now articulate the rest of our analysis and illutrate its conse
quences. First, it is a general fct about realized subjects in Icelandic (in
fnite and non-fnite contexts alike), that their default cae value i nomi
native. This information is presumably to be asociated with the grammar
rule that introduces subjects. The fact that a realized subject9 must bear
the specifcation [DCASE nom) has important consequences for non-quirky
verbs. Since the CASE and DCASE values of the realized subject of a non
quirky verb are identifed, it follows that the actual cae (determined by
the CASE value) of such a subject must be nominative. This is true not
only for the subjects of fnite forms of non-quirky verbs, as we saw earlier
(e.g., (2) ) , but also for examples like (30), where the subject of a non-fnite
form is realized.
(30) Mer viroist hun elska hann.
me. DAT seems she. NOM to-love him.ACC
'It seems to me that she loves him.'
9Given the range of modifers that exhibit default nominative cae (Andrews 1990),
this analysis may have interesting consequences for the treatment of the unexpressed
subjects in such modifers.
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 311
For quirky verbs, on the other hand, the constraint that realized subjects
are specifed as [DCASE nom] has no particular consequence. The actual
case of the subject (determined by the CASE value) is assigned by the
individual quirky verb, and nothing requires the CASE and DCASE values
of the subject to be the same.
Second, the SUBCAT specifcations for object raising verbs will no longer
be as in (25) above, but rather will be as shown in (31 ) .
(31) Simple object raising verbs:
(
[CAT
S
U
BCAT
[
CAT np
[
,
J
DCASE
np
FORM
[CAT
acc]
,
SUBCAT
vp
l )
inf
,J
|
Again, this will have important consequences when the VP complement
of an object raising verb is headed by a non-quirky verb. In that event,
since the complement's subject's DCASE and CASE values are identifed
and since the complement's subject is identifed with the direct object of
the object raising verb, it follows that the object must be accusative. If the
VP complement is headed by a quirky verb, again nothing of consequence
follows-the case of the raised object will be determined by the CASE value
asigned by the downstairs quirky verb.
These observations are illustrated in fgures (32)-(35) .
(32)
(33)
Finite non-quirky verb:
S
.
[
CAT np
1
[CAT
CASE
vp ]
nom
SUBCAT _,
DCASE nom
V[fn] NP[acc]
| '
Drengurinn.NOM kyssti stulkuna.ACC
'The boy' 'kissed' 'the girl'
Finite quirky verb:
S
.
[
CAT
CASE
DCASE
np
1
acc
nom
Mig.ACC
'me'
[CAT vp ]
SUBCAT _,
.
V [fn]
langar
' longs'
[CAT VP]
FORM inf
telja
'believe'
VP[SUBCAT ([))
[CAT
m CASE
DCASE
np
1
ace
ace
Marfu.ACC
'Mary'
[CAT vp ]
@
SUBCAT (m)
ekki grta
'not be-noticeable'
In our analysis, subject raising verbs are exceptional only in not spec
ifying that their subject's CASE and DCASE values are identifed. Finite
forms of subject raising verbs, e.g. , viroist, like all fnite verb forms, select
for subjects that are [DCASE NOM] . Again, this ha consequences when
the VP complement is headed by a non-quirky verb, but not when the VP
contains a quirky head. This is illustrated in (36) and (37) .
(36) Subject raising verb with non-quirky VP complement:
S
.
[
CAT
[ CASE
DCASE
np
1
nom
nom
Hann. NOM
'he'
[CAT vp ]
SUBCAT ([)
V [fn] [CAT vp ]
[SUBCAT ( [, m)]
m
SUBCAT ( [)
'
viroist
'seems'
elska hana.ACC
't<love her'
(37) Subject raising verb with quirky VP complement:
S
.
[CAT
[ CASE
DCASE
np
1
ace
nom
Hann.ACC
'he'
[CAT vp ]
SUBCAT (m)
V [fn] [CAT vp ]
[SUBCAT ( [, m)]
m
SUBCAT ( [)
viroist
'seems'
vanta peninga
't<lack money'
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 313
The lexical entries we have proposed, together with general principles
that directly constrain syntactic information in phrase structure all pro
vide partial information that must be satisfed by the phrase structures of
Icelandic. But the constraints need not be satisfed in any particular or
der. Our analysis thus accounts for the puzzles of quirky cae in Icelandic
in a purely monotonic fahion, i.e. , in terms of constraints that may be
satisfed in any order and which provide fexible, process-neutral, partial
information about the structures of the language.
4 Expressing Lexical Generalizations
Although fully specifed attribute-value matrices for individual verbs in
our analysis of Icelandic may appear to be somewhat complex, their lexical
entries may be stated very concisely by generalizing over classes of similar
lexical items. A set of features common to a clas of words can be defned
just once so that the defnition is shared by all the entries which have
that property. In the P ATR-I I notation, such named properties are called
templates.
1O
A simple template defnition consists of path equations that
describe an attribute-value matrix. Templates can also be defned in terms
of other templates; in this way a lexicographer may construct inheritance
hierarchies of generalizations. In the PATR-I I formalism, such defnitions
are not necessarily monotonic because the information in a higher ranked
template may override some specifcation that is inherited fom a template
with a lower rank. However, our analysis of Icelandic verbs can be stated
under the simpler asumption that templates are composed by unifcation
without overriding.
In this section we show how the complex feature structures for Icelandic
verbs can be decomposed to a small number of simple lexical properties.
The only technical problem in converting from the semi-formal notation we
have used so far to explicit attribute-value structures is the representation
of a list-the value of the SUBCAT feature. In a manner reIniniscent of
CAR and CDR in Lisp, we use the attributes FIRST and REST for the head
and the tail of a list, respectively. A special atom, none, marks the end of
a list. For example, a list of two elements, (A B) , would be designated a
in (38) .
(38) (FIRST) = A
(REST FIRST) = B
(REST REST) = none
In defning our frst template, Verb, we leave the REST argument un
specifed so that this basic defnition can be shared by all types of verbs
that have at least one argument-a subject-on their SUBCAT list:
10
A very similar device is incorporated into the theory of the "hierarchical lexicon"
presented in Flickinger 1987 and Pollard and Sag 1987, Chapter 8.
314 / IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
(39) Verb: (CAT) verb
(SUBCAT FIRST CAT) np
In terms of the semi-formal notation we have used so far, the defnition of
Verb in (39) is equivalent to (40) , where ' . . .' means that the number of
elements on the list is unspecifed.
(40) SUBCAT ( [CAT np] . . . )
The next two defnitions are straightforward:
(41) Finite: (FORM) fn
Infnitive: (FORM) inf
And the following set of templates serve to subcategorize verbs on the bais
of the number and type of their non-subject arguments:
(42) Strict-Intransitive: (SUBCAT REST) none
(43) Transitive: (SUBCAT REST FIRST CAT) = np
(SUBCAT REST FIRST DCASE) acc
(44) Strict- Transitive: (SUBCAT REST REST) = none
The efect of (42) is to limit the SUBCAT list of the verb to a subject. Note
that (43) makes the default case of an object be accusative irrespective of
whether the verb is fnite or non-fnite.
The two types of complementizable verbs we have discussed are char
acterized by the templates (45)-(46). The subject raising verbs merge the
subject role of the complement with the subject role of the matrix verb,
the object raising verbs equate the object of the matrix with the subject
of the complement clause.
(45) Subject-Raising:
(SUBCAT REST FIRST CAT) = vp
(SUBCAT REST FIRST FORM) inf
(SUBCAT REST FIRST SUBCAT FIRST) = (SUBCAT FIRST)
(SUBCAT REST REST) none
(46) Object-Raising:
(SUBCAT REST REST FIRST CAT) = y
(SUBCAT REST REST FIRST FORM) inf
(SUBCAT REST REST FIRST SUBCAT FIRST)
(SUBCAT REST FIRST)
(SUBCAT REST REST REST) = none
The next two templates characterize non-quirky intransitive and transitive
verbs.
(47) Normal-Subject:
(SUBCAT FIRST CASE) = (SUBCAT FIRST DCASE)
(48) Normal-Object:
(SUBCAT REST FIRST CASE) = (SUBCAT REST FIRST DCASE)
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 315
Templates (49) and (50) defne two types of quirky verbs. ll
(49)
(50)
Accusative-Subject: (SUBCAT FIRST CASE) = acc
Genitive-Subject: (SUBCAT FIRST CASE) gen
Using the defnitions in (45)-(50) , we can now defne useful composite
templates:
(51) Intransitive Verb: Verb ^ Strict-Intransitive
Tansitive Verb: Verb ^ Tansitive / Strict-Transitive
Subject-Raising- Verb: Verb ^ Subject-Raising
Object-Raising- Verb: Verb ^ Tansitive ^ Object-Raising.
Because the defnitions of individual templates do not introduce any con
ficts, the interpretation of these composite defnitions is straightforward:
the defnition of an object raising verb, for example, is a simple union of
the path equations that defne the templates Verb, Transitive, and Object
Raising. It describes the attribute-value matrix in (52).
(52) Object raising verb:
CAT verb
FIRST [CAT np]
SUBCAT
REST
FIRST m
[CAT np ]
DCASE acc
REST
[
FIRST
[
M
:
lJ
SUBCAT [FIRST m]
REST none
Note that this is a notational variant of (31) above.
We now have all the general properties needed for the entries of indi
vidual verbs. For example:
(53) a. kyssti:
Finite / Trasitive- Verb ^ Normal-Subject / Normal-Object
b. langar:
Finite ^ Equi- Verb ^ Accusative-Subject
c. telja:
Infnitive / Normal-Subject / Object-Raising- Verb
d. grta:
Infnitive / Intransitive- Verb ^ Genitive-Subject
e. viroist:
Finite ^ Subject-Raising- Verb
I1
We leave open here the possibility, sugeted by Yip et ( 1987), that there are
semantic regularities underlying some of the quirky cae asignments we assume here.
316 I IVAN SAG, LAURI KARTTUNEN, AND JEFFREY GOLDBERG
As a consequence of the defnitions we have given for the various lexical
classes, the syntactic behavior and case assignment properties of these verbs
are correctly and completely specifed by the simple lexical entries in (53) .
5 Conclusion
At frst glance, The problem of "quirky" cae in Icelandic seems to involve
non-monotonic (overriding) behavior of default and exceptional cae as
signment principles. However, a we have shown in this paper, the relevant
information, reifed in terms of the attributes CASE and DCASE, can be
treated quite naturally in terms of simultaneous constraint satisfaction.
An interesting feature of the analysis we have proposed is that it cru
cially depends on partial information. For example, the subject raising
verbs asign cae to their subject by letting it be determined by the verb
in the complement clause. When a subject is overtly realized, the relevant
grammar rule also requires that subjects be specifed a [DCASE nom] . And
the lexical entry for object raising verbs require their objects to be speci
fed a [DCASE acc] . These specifcations, together with a set of identities
specifed by the constraints of the grammar interacting with those of the
lexicon, are what account for the realization of case when the complement's
verb is non-quirky.
And because the CASE and DCASE values of the subjects of quirky
verbs are distinct, it follows that when a quirky verb appears within the
complement of a raising verb, the DCASE specifcations just mentioned have
no efect on the cae of the raised element, which is determined entirely
by the quirky verb within the complement. It seems to us that the use
of partial information, together with the distinction between default case
and actual case, provides a much simpler and more satisfactory account of
Icelandic cae than earlier descriptions.
One shortcoming of the analysis presented here is that it provides no ac
count of the nominative-accusative template efect whose utility is demon
strated by Yip et al. (1987) . We believe, however, that their generalizations
can be introduced into our analysis, once rules of case association are seen
to apply not to ordered phrase structures (as Yip et al. assume) , but rather
to hierarchical syntactic argument structures of the sort provided by our
SUBCAT feature. In this way, we can incorporate the central insight of
the Yip et al. analysis into an analysis that avoids the destructive rule
application (cyclical reasignment of non-lexical case) that their analysis
employs.
Finally, our analysis embodies a lexical architecture that we believe
to be of considerable value in the context of the increasing trend within
grammatical theory to locate crucial syntactic information within more
complex lexical entries. The lexicon need not be just a list of forms and
meanings, coupled with idiosyncratic grammatical information. Rather,
A LEXICAL ANALYSIS OF ICELANDIC CASE / 317
i n virtue of the organization provided by templates of the sort we have
used here, the lexicon can be viewed as an elegant hierarchical (or even
heterarchical) databae, where every signifcant generalization about classes
of words may be expressed in compact terms. As complexity of syntactic
rules is continually eliminated in favor of more complex lexical entries, the
development of such methods for achieving lexical compaction is not just
a desideratum, it is a necessity.
References
Andrews, Avery. 1976. The VP Complement Analysis in Modern Icelandic.
In Proceedings of NELS 6 (Montreal Working Papers in Linguistics) , 1-22.
Amherst: University of Massachusetts, GLSA.
Andrews, Avery. 1982. The Representation of Case in Modern Icelandic. In The
Mental Representation of Grammatical Relations, ed. Joan Bresnan. Cam
bridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Andrews, Avery. 1990. Case Structures and Control in Modern Icelandic. In
Syntax and Semantics 24: Modern Icelandic Syntax, ed. Joan Maling and
Annie Zaenen, 187-234. San Diego: Academic Press.
Bresnan, Joan. 1982. Control and Complementation. In The Mental Represen
tation of Grammatical Relations, ed. Joan Bresnan. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on Goverment and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Dowty, David. 1982a. Grammatical Relations and Montague Grammar. In The
Nature of Syntactic Representation, ed. Pauline Jacobson and Geofrey Pul
lum, 79-130. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Dowty, David. 1982b. More on the Categorial Analysis of Grammatical Relations.
In Subjects and Other Subjects, ed. Annie Zaenen, 115-153. Bloomington:
Indiana University Linguistics Club.
Flickinger, Daniel. 1987. Lexical Fules in the Hierarchical Lexicon. Doctoral
dissertation, Stanford University.
Goldsmith, John. 1976. An Overview of Autosegmental Phonology. Linguistic
Analysis 2: 231-68.
Goldsmith, John. 1990. Autosegmental and Metrical Phonology. Oxford: Bail
Blackwell.
Johnson, Mark. 1988. Attribute- Value Logic and the Theory of Grammar. CSLI
Lecture Notes No. 16. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Kaplan, Ronald, and Joan Bresnan. 1982. Lexical-Functional Grammar: A For
mal System for Grammatical Representation. In The Mental Representation
of Grammatical Relations, ed. Joan Bresnan. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Kay, Martin. 1986. Parsing in Functional Unifcation Grammar. In Natural
Language Parsing, ed. David Dowty, Lauri Karttunen, and Arnold Zwicky.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Keenan, Edward, and Bernard Comrie. 1977. Noun Phrase Accessibility and
Universal Grammar. Linguistic Inquiry 8:63-99.
318 / VAN 5AG, AlRI hARTTUNFN, AND JFFFRFY lOIDBFRG
Maling, Joan, and Annie Zaenen (eds. ). 1 990. Syntax and Semantics 24: Modem
Icelandic Syntax. San Diego: Academic Press.
Neidle, Carol. 1982. Cae Agreement in Russian. In The Mental Representation
of Grammatical Relations, ed. Joan Bresnan. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
PoUard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1987. Information-Based Syntax and Semantics,
Vol. I: Fundamentals. CSLI Lecture Notes No. 1 3. Stanford: CSLI Publica
tions.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan A. Sag. 1992. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, and Stanford: L5 Publications.
Sag, Ivan A. 1991 . Linguistic Theory and Natural Language Processing. In
Natural Language and Speech, ed. Ewan Klein and Frank Veltman. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag. Symposium Proceedings. Brussels, November 1 991 .
Sag, Ivan A. , Ronald Kaplan, Lauri Karttunen, Martin Kay, Carl PoUard, Stu
art Shieber, and Annie Zaenen. 1985. Unifi cation and Grammatical Theory.
In Proceedings of the 5th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed.
Mary Dalrymple, Jefrey Goldberg, Kristin Hanson, Michael Inman, Christo
pher Pinon, and Stephen Wechsler. Stanford University: Stanford Linguistics
Association.
Shieber, Stuart, Hans Uszkoreit, Fernando Pereira, Jane Robinson, and Mabry
Tyson. 1983. The Formalism and Implementation of PATR-II. In Research
on Interactive Acquisition and User of Knowledge, ed. Barbara Grosz and
Mark Stickel. Menlo Park, CA: SRI International. (SRI Final Report 1 984) .
Thrainsson, Hoskuldur. 1979. On Complementation in Icelandic. New York:
Garland.
Yip, Moira, Joan Maling, and Ray Jackendof. 1987. Case in Tiers. Language
63: 21 7-250.
Author Index
Abelson, Robert P., 211, 213, 233
Abney, Steven, 1 33, 162, 163
Abraham, Werner, 218
Ackerman, Farrell, x, 55, 58, 75, 218
Ades, Anthony, 248
Akmajian, Adrian, 277
Alford, Jack A. , Jr., 234
Allen, Margaret R., 111
Alsina, Alex, 62
Anderson, Mona, 8
Anderson, Stephen R. , 14, 55, 1 1 1
Andrews, A very, 303, 306, 310
Aronof, Mark, 94, 111
Bach, Emmon, 31 , 47, 285, 292
Baker, Mark, 2, 169, 171
Barwise, Jon, 96
Bauer, Lauri, 156
Bayer, Samuel, 271, 275, 279, 280,
282, 283
Becker, Curtis A., 233
Belletti, Adriana, 17
Benesova, Eva, 212
Bennett, Michael, 47
Berman, Arlene, 271
Bever, Thomas G. , 209, 210, 213,
216, 230, 231, 233
Bierwisch, Manfed, 201, 209
Blaberg, L., 146
Black, J. B., 21 1
Bolinger, Dwight, 133, 135, 159
Bouchard, Denis, 85, 90, 107
Bower, Gordon H., 211, 213, 233
Brame, Michael, 293
Bresnan, Joan, 56, 58, 61, 62, 71,
76, 274, 276, 303, 306-308
Brown, Roger, 206
Burzio, Luigi, 1 1
Carlson, Greg, 44
Carpenter, Bob, 252
Chafe, William L. , 212, 215
Chien, Yu-Chin, 258
Chierchia, Gennara, xvi, 252, 269,
272, 273, 278, 283, 295
Chomsky, Noam, xi, xvi, 132, 139,
147, 212, 252, 256, 270,
271 , 275, 277, 278, 292
Clark, Eve, 111, 183, 186, 206
Clark, Herb, 111, 183, 206, 211, 212
Clements, J. , 171
Collins, Allan M. , 224, 233
Comorovski, Ileana, 95
Comrie, Bernard, 307
Crain, Steven, 210, 212, 222, 235
Culicover, Peter, 62
Curry, Haskell B. , 251, 253
Cutler, Anne, 171, 212
Dakin, Julian, 213
de Meij, Sjaak, 218
Dezso, Laszlo, 217
Di Sciullo, Anna Maria, 123, 124,
133, 150, 162, 167, 169
Downing, Pamela A., 141, 143
Dowty, David, viii, x, xvi, 5, 7, 13,
21, 22, 30, 31, 44, 57, 60,
62, 63, 142, 254, 269, 272,
320 / LXlCAL NATTR5
273, 279, 283, 286-288, 290,
292
Dressler, Wolfgang U. , 186, 187
Dufy, S. , 21 1
Esau, Helmut, 1 1 1
Fabb, Nigel, 138, 162
Farkas, Donka, xi, xv, xvii, 88, 95,
218
Fauconnier, Gilles, 99
Fazekas, A. , 206
Fellbaum, Christiane, 8
Feys, Robert, 251, 253
Fiengo, Robert, 270, 271 , 274
Filip, Hana, 49
Fillmore, Cnar!tH, bb, 63, 128
t u| u, Timothy W. , 176
Fischler, Ira, 233
Flickinger, Daniel, 313
Fodor, Janet D. , 210, 271, 278
Fodor, Jerry A. , 210, 212
Franlois, Jean, 30
Fudge, Erik, 143, 156
Garrett, Merrill F. , 210
Garrod, Simon L. , 211
Gawron, Jean Mark, 63, 259, 260
Gazdar, Gerald, 271 , 275, 278-280,
283, 287, 289, 293
Geach, Peter T. , 253
Gergely, Gyorgy, xiv, 209, 21 0, 21 1 ,
213, 214, 221 , 225, 231 ,
233
Gibbs, Ray W. , 21 1
Gleitman, Lila, 23
Goldberg, Jefrey, 23
Goldsmith, John, 306
Goodman, George \. , 233
Gough, Phillip B. , 234
Greenberg, Joseph H. , 194
Grimshaw, Jane, 1 1 , 1 13, 258, 283-
285
Gropen, Jess, 23
Gruber, Jefrey S., 7
Hajicova, Eva, 212
Hale, Kenneth, 8
Halle, Morris, 132, 147
Halliday, Michael A. K. , 212
Hankamer, Jorge, 280
Hasegawa, Nobuko, 1 13, 1 14
Haviland, Susan E. , 21 1 , 212
Hayes, Bruce, 132, 147
Heinamaki, Orvokki, 46
Hindley, J. Roger, 252
Hinrichs, Erhard, 7, 31
Hirschberg, Julia, 1 34
Hjelmslev, Louis, 194
Hoeksema, Jacob, 169
Hoepelman, Jakob, 31
Holley-Wilcox, Pamela, 234
Horn, Laurence R. , x, 94, 106, 286
Horvath, Julia, 21 7
Householder, Frederick W. , x, 123
Hualde, Jose Ignacio, 122
Hukari, Thomas, 270, 275, 276, 278,
283, 286, 288, 290, 293
Inoue, Kazuko, 1 1 3
Jackendof, Ray, 7 , 56, 1 3 1 , 132,
21 2, 21 5, 216, 273
Jacobson, Pauline, xvi, xvii, 271-
274, 277-283, 285, 286, 288,
289, 292, 294
Johnson, Mark, 306
Johnson-Laird, Phillip N. , 190, 210,
222, 235
Joseph, Brian, 95
Kageyama, Taroo, ll3, ll 6
Kalman, Laszlo, 218, 235
Kanerva, Jonni M. , 61 , 62
Kanski, Zbigniew, 253
Kaplan, Ronald, 303, 306
Kawakami, Shin, 115
Kay, Martin, 128, 303
Kayne, Richard, 242, 243, 245, 247
Keenan, Edward L., 253, 255, 256,
307
Kempchinsky, Paula, 85, 89
Kenesei, Istvan, 21 8
Keyser, S. Jay, 8
Kiefer, Ferenc, 201, 21 7
Kimballg John, 296
Kiparsky, Paul, 85, 94, 1 1 1 , 163, 167
Kiss, Katalin E., 217
Klein, Ewan, 271, 275, 278-280, 283,
287, 293
Koml6sy, Andras, 218
Koster, Jan, 242
Kriia, Manfred, viii-x, 7, 31, 36, 38
Laczk6, Tibor, 55, 75
Ladd, Robert, 133, 135, 161, 167
Ladusaw, William, 62, 274, 290
Landau, Barbara, 23
Lang, Ewald, 201
Lapointe, Steven G. , 194, 195
Lasnik, Howard, 270, 271, 274
Lees, Robert B. , 137
Leisi, Ernst, 31
Levi, Judith N. , 137, 141, 142, 151,
166
Levin, Beth, 14, 55, 56, 71, 72, 76,
137
Levine, Robert, 270, 275, 276, 278,
283, 286, 288, 290, 293
Levinson, Stephen, x
Liberman, Mark, xii, 132, 147, 175,
176
Lieber, Rochelle, 137, 156, 171
Link, Godehard, 31, 45
Loftus, Elizabeth F. , 224, 233, 234
Magerman, David, 177
Maidment, J. A. , 135
Maling, Joan, 270
Marantz, Alec, 137
Marchand, Hans, 145
Marcus, Mitchell, 177
Marslen-Wilson, William D. , 210, 222,
224, 233, 235
Mayerthaler, Willi, 186
McCawley, James, x, 94, 106, 123
Mchombo, Sam, 62
Meireles, J., 85, 87
Mester, Armin, 113
Meyer, David E. , 233, 234
Miller, George A. , 190
Mitchell, D. C. , 21 1, 233, 234
Miyagawa, Shigeru, 111, 1 13
Mohanan, t P., 169, 172
AUTHOR INDEX / 321
Moravcsik, Edith, 46
Morton, J. , 224, 233
Neely, James H. , 234
Neidle, Carol, 306
Nunberg, Geofrey, 288
O'Connor, Mary Catherine, 128
Oehrle, Richard, 248, 277
Padilla-Rivera, J., 87, 103
Panagl, Oswald, 186
Partee, Barbara, 47, 258
Paul, Hermann, 1 1 1
Perlmutter, David, 1 , 1 1
Perry, John, 96
Peters, Stanley, 259, 260
Picallo, Carme, 85, 87
Pinker, Steven, 23, 55
Platzack, Christer, 31
PlEh, Csaba, 206, 217
Pollard, Carl, 242-244, 247, 252, 271,
274, 278, 285, 288, 307,
308, 313
Poser, William J. , 113
Postal, Paul, 1 , 11, 173, 271, 273,
279
Prince, Alan, 132, 147
Pullum, Geofrey t, 271 , 275, 278-
280, 283, 287, 293
Pustejovsky, James, 7
Quine, Willard van Orman, 30, 253
Ramsey, S. Robert, 171
Raposo, Eduardo, 85, 87
Rappaport, Maika, 14, 55, 56, 71,
72, 76, 137
Reger, Zita, 206
Reinhart, Tanya, 107, 212, 258-260
Riesbeck, Christopher , 210, 21 1
Rizzi, Luigi, 17
Roberts, Ian, 8
Rochemont, Michael, 218
Roeper, Thomas, 137
Rohrer, Christian, 31
Rooth, Mats, 174
Rosch, Elinor, 206
322 / LXlCAL ATTER5
Rosen. Carol, 258
Rosenbaum, Peter, 271, 279, 284
Ros, John R. , 279
Ruddy, Margaret G. , 233
Ruwet, icola, 88, 89, 103
Safr, Ken, 139
Sag, Ivn A., 243, 272, 274, 275,
278-280, 283, 285, 288, 293,
303, 307, 308, 313
Saiki, Mariko, 1 16
Salamanca, D. , 87
Salkoff, Morris, 55
Sanford, Anthony J. , 2 1 1
Scha, Remko, 43
Schachter, Paul, 278
Schnurr- Wolles, L. , 187
Schank, Rogrr L. , 2 1, 2 1 1 , 2 1 3, 233
Srh111l`I1ing, Susan, 218
Schonfinkel, M. , 251
Schvalleveldt, Roger W. , 233, 234
Schwartz-Norman, Linda, 14
Seidenberg, Mark, 210
Selkirk, Elizabeth, 137, 145, 164,
1 69, 171, 218
Sgall, Petr, 212
Sharkey, Noel E. , 211, 233, 234
Shih, Chi-lin, 165, 177
Siegel, Mufy, 137
Simpson, Jane, 56
Sproat, Richard, xii, 1 37, 139, 165,
1 73, 1 75-178
Steedman, Mark, 210, 2 12, 222, 235,
248, 249, 251, 254, 257,
277, 278, 290
Stump, Greg, 171
Suner, Margarita, 87, 103
Szabo, Zoltan, 235
Szabolcsi, Anna, xv, xvii. 55. 92.
21 2, 21 7, 2 1 8. 248. 249.
254, 257, 259. 264
Tenney, Yvette J. , 2 1 1
Tenny, Carol, viii , 7 , 1 9
ter Meulen, Alice, 3 1
Thomason, Richard, 139
Thrainsson, Hoskuldur, 303
Toman, Jindrich, I I I
Townsend, David J. , 2 1 1 , 2 13, 216,
230, 23 1
Turer, T. J. , 2 1 1
Tyler, Lorraine K. , 2 1 0, 235
Van Val i n, Robert, 1 1 , 1 3
Vendlrr, Zeno, 30, 60
Verkuyl , Henk J . , 7, 3 1 , 46
Verschueren, Jef, 201
von Stechow, Ari m, 253
Ward, Gregory, 1 73
Warren, R. E. , 234
Was ow , Thomas, 71, 288
Welsh, A. , 224, 233
Wexler, Ken, 258
Wierzbicka, Anna, 49
Williams, Edwin, 4, 1 23, 124, 133,
1 50, 162, 167, 169-171
Wurzel, Wolfgang V. , 1 86
Yip, Moira, 303, 31 5, 316
Zaenen, Annie, x, 11, 56, 58, 60-64,
76, 270
Zaring, L. , 87, 1 03
Zec, Draga, 93
Zubizarreta, Maria-Luisa, 57
Zwanenberg, Weicher, 1 1 1
Subject Index
Accomplishment, 29, 30
acquisition, 23
order, xiii, xiv, 206
activities, 29
adjective
comparative, 120
superlative, 120
adjective-noun compounds, xii, 148,
151
adverbial
apect-marking, 218
directional, 51
durative, 30, 51
locative, 51
time-span, 30, 51
adversative, xiv
inference, 231
subordinate clauses, 213, 214
afected arguments, 9, 10
afectedness, viii, 8, 10, 23
agentive-headed compounds, 137
pseudo-object le
f
hand members,
138
restrictions on lef hand mem-
bers, 138
agglutinative language, 209, 217
agreement, 274, 288, 292
aktionsart, 29, 189
fequentative 51
anaphora, xvi, 241, 252, 253, 255-
260, 265, 266
deep, 280
null complement, xvi, 280, 281,
289, 291
anaphoric island constraint, 173
antecedent matching, 222
argument structure, viii, x, xiii, 2, 3,
21, 23
argument-argument compounds, 137,
140, 143
argument-predicate compounds, 137,
140
aspect, D, x, 2, 4, 10, 11, 13, 16-18,
20, 21, 23, 29, 31, 38, 60,
189, 192
apect-marking adverbial, 218
atelic predicate, viii, 30, 34, 35
atomic reference, D, 32
atomicity of word, 172
Backward search for discourse an-
tecedent, 212, 213, 216
basic lexical entry, 64
baic-level term, 183
Baque, xi, 122
binding, xi, xv, xvi, 251-253, 255,
256, 258-260
blocking, viii, x-xiii, 94, 1 1 1
Brazilian Portuguese, 87
Breton, 171
Cae, xv, xvii, 303, 305
flter, 305, 306
case-marker sufxes, 217
categorial grammar, xv, 241 , 248,
272, 277, 294, 302, 303,
307
causativization, xiii, 56
324 / LXlCAL NATTR5
cause-efect relation, xiv, 213, 230,
235
change, 3, 6, 8, 19-21
of location, 79
Chinese, 1 77
closed class IlCm8, 1 63
collective rC0dtug8, 44
combinator, xv, 241 , 248, 251-253,
256, 257, 259, 260, 262,
264-266
competence, 303
complex predicate, , 58, 65, 70,
21 8
complexit.y, formal, xi i i , I b4
compound
bnhuvrihi , I 4b, 1 66
derived-nominal headed, 1 39
EUglIsh
orthographic conventions, 1 36
modifers, 132
stress rule, 146
with possessive modifiers, 153
implicit contrast theories, 1 55
conjunction, 232
constraining equations, 303, 306
constraint, xvii, 302, 303, 306, 31 3,
31 6
construction grammar, 1 28
control, xi, xv, xvi, 269-272, 280,
289, 291 , 295, 296
controller choice, 88, 103
count nouns, 29
cumulative
readings, 43
reference, ix, 30, 32
Czech, 46, 49
Deep anaphora, 280
default cae, 307, 309, 310, 314, 316
deferred reference, 1 74
defniteness, 49
degree of agentivity, 88
delimitedness, 5, 7, 1 1 , 19, 24
derivational morphology, xiii, 185,
1 92
derived-nominal headed compound,
1 39
direct internal argument, 4, 6-8, 10,
1 5, 23
directional adYerbial 5 1
discourse
uncIIOu8 In !uug0tI0n, 21 7
informational cues, 210
representation, 232
disjoint reference, 85
dummy, 276, 287, 288
durative adverbial, 30, 51
Efected object8, 41
elementary predicates, 1 91
elsewhere pri nci ple, x, xi , 90, 1 07,
J
tng\8h, xii, xiv, 120
compound, 136, 1 69
noun phrases, 1 31
epithets, 149
event, 4, , 1 2
tokens, 34
types, 34
external argument, 4, 1 1 , 1 7, 18, 24
extraction, xvi, 243, 253, 255, 261,
262, 265
gap, 277
Finnish, i x, 46
"fat" sentences, 21 8
focus, 2 12, 21 4, 21 7, 2 1 8
movement, 2 1 7
focus-based inference, xv, 209, 210,
21 5, 231-236
in discourse antecedent match
ing, 21 9
predictive, 2 10, 231
clausal processing, 222
priming, 233
processes, 21 9
foregrounding, 222, 223, 236
formal complexity, 184
"free" word order, 209, 21 7
Fench, 86-89, 167, 1 71
frequentative
verb form, xiii
aktionsart , 5 1
function composition, xvi, 247-249,
251, 260, 271, 279, 280,
282
Gap, xv, xvi, 247
extraction, 277
parasitic, 243, 244, 270, 278
German, 46
gerund-headed compounds, 139
pseudo-object left hand members,
139
given information, 212
goal, 14, 15, 19
government-binding theory, xv, 4,
85, 241-243, 247, 248, 302
graduality, 42
Gricean convention, 214, 215
Head-driven phrase structure gram
mar, xv, 241-244, 247, 248,
307
head feature principle, 308
head-fnal flter, 162
headedness
of afxed words, 171
of compounds and phrases in
English, 169
hierarchical lexicon, 313
Hindi, 51
Hungarian, ix-xi, xiii, xiv, xviii, 55,
58, 64, 71, 72, 81, 90-92,
95, 96, 184, 185, 209, 217,
254
discourse functions, 217
sentence structure, 217
topic-focus structure 219
Icelandic, xvii, 301-317
idiom chunks, 288
incremental theme, viii, 7, 22, 62-63
indirect internal argument, 4, 7
inference
adversative 231
focus-based, xv, 209, 210, 215,
231-236
predictive, 213, 222, 224
information
cues, 210
SUBJECT INDEX / 325
given, 212
new, 212
mutual, 177
inheritance hierarchy, 313
interactive model, 232, 235
interclausal semantic relations, xiv,
209, 213, 232, 235
internal argument, ix, 3, 4, 10, 11,
13, 17-20
indirect, 4, 7
island, 292-294
Italian, 167
iterativity, 39, 40
Japanese, 112
Language processing, 301, 303
lattice, ix, 31, 32
left-headed modifed nominals, 166
stress pattern in, 151
lexical
apect 60
entry, vii, 3
form, 69
integrity, 172
item, xiii, 241-244, 248, 253,
265
mapping theory, x, 55-81
priming, 233
semantics, x, xiii, 1, 18, 21, 60,
252-256
versus syntactic analysis, xv,
241-244
lexicalization, xiii, 150
lexicon, vii-xv, 241, 242, 254, 264
locative
adverbial, 51
alternation, D, 14, 15, 23, 55,
56, 58, 64
inversion, 57
Manner of motion, 79
mass nouns, 29
measure constructions, 29, 51
measuring out the event, D, 2-7,
12-20, 23
middle, 10, 11
monotonicity, xvii, 57, 68, 248, 303
326 / LXlCAL ATR
morpholexical operation, x, 55, 56,
80
morphological
complexity, xiii, 184-187, 191,
192, 194-197, 201 , 206, 207
component, 133, 169
construction, 125
markedness, 187
morphosyntactic operation, 7 56,
80
morphotactic transparency, 187
motion, 3, 21
moV(' I t , 302, Jh
IIIl1tllal informat ion, 1 77
DI\mrH H modifirr8, 1 73
lI('gation, 5 1
new information, 2 1 2
nominal reference, 30
with possessive modifers, 154
non-binary premodifed nominal, 146,
161
nondelimited event, 5, 7
nonstative verb, 3
noun phrase, xii, 1 31
noun-noun compound, xii, 156, 1 60
noun-PP expressions
left-stressed caes, 155
nuclear stress rule, xii, 1 46
null complement anaphora, xvi, 280,
281, 289, 291
O-ellipsis, 1 16
obliqueness, 307
observed object, 31
obviative complement, 85
overlap, 32
overriding, 313, 316
Paraitic gap, 243, 244, 270, 278
partitive, ix, 46
pasive, xiii, 8, 11, 57, 285
path equations, 313, 315
lAH-\, 307, 313
perfective, D, x, xiii, 49
performance, 301-306
periphratic verb, xi, xii, 1 12, 122
phraal modifers, 132
plural, 29
Polish, 49
possessives, distributional propertie
of, 1 54
pragmatic complexity, 201 , 206, 207
predicate-argument structure, 188
predictive inference, 213, 222, 224
pre modifed nominal
P
9
versus P
I
caes, I b4
automatic parsing
statistical methods, 1 77
and stress assignment, I Tb
:utc strrss- patter, 1 48
except. ions, 1 48
"i mplicit contrast" , I h/
i ntcrspeakcr variation, I 49,
1 57
Ladd's "subcategorization" the-
ory, 167
deaccenting in, 168
determiners in, 162
non-binary, 146, 161
pronouns in, 162
quantifers in, 162
semantics of
classifcatory schemes, 141
'connected-with' theory, 142
structure of, 162
syntactic restrictions on left hand
member, 162
with phrasal modifer, 156, 161
prenominal adjective ordering restric-
tions, 165
presuppositional properties, 189
pro-arb, 273
process nominals in compounds, 139
processing time, xiv, 206
productivity, 186
progressive, i x, 46
proto-agent, 21, 22, 63
proto-patient, viii, 7, 21, 22, 63, 78
protorole, viii, x, 63
prototype semantics, 191
psych verb, 16
Quantifcation, 51
quantized reference, ix, 30, 32
quirky cae, xvii, 303-316
Raising, 304-316
construction, xvii, 270, 271, 279-
282, 286, 288
function composition analysis
of, 279, 280
recoding
at clause-boundary, 225
at end of clause, 222, 236
reference
atomic, ix, 32
cumulative, ix, 30, 32
deferred, 174
disjoint, 85
nominal, 30
with possessive modifers, 154
quantized, 30, 32
singular, 32
referential expressions within com-
pounds, 173
relational grammar, 307
resolution problem, 301
result nominal, 139
resultative preverb, x, 18, 59
Romance, xi, 85, 87, 96
compounds, 167
Romanian, xi, 88, 89, 95
Scenario, 45
script, xiv, 211, 233, 234
selectional restriction, 270, 271, 274,
276, 290, 293
self lefthand member of compound,
140
semantic
complexity, 7111 xiv, 183-186,
189-192, 194-197, 200-202,
206, 207
felds, 185
markedness, xiii, 184, 185, 191,
205-207
representations, 189
transparency, 186
semantics
lexical x, xiii, 1 , 18, 21, 60,
252-256
of pre modifed nominal, 141, 142
prototype, 191
Serbo-Croatian, xi , 90, 93-95
SUBJECT INDEX / 327
set terminal point, 34
singular reference, ix, 32
Slavic, D, 46
Spanish, 87, 89, 167, 171, 172
stress patterns, 131
discourse-conditioned vs. discourse
neutral, 134
of argument-argument compounds,
143
structure sharing, 309, 310
SUBCAT, 307-316
subject, 85, 308, 309
postposing, 217
summativity, 39, 43
Swedish, 146
syntactic
complexity, xiii, 184, 188, 207
markedness, 188, 206
Telic predicate, viii-x, 30, 34, 35,
61, 69, 74, 80
template, 313-317
temporal
constitution, 29, 30
order, 33
trace, 33
thematic relations, N1117 1, 2, 11,
19, 31, 34, 62, 71
theme, 14
-criterion, 274
8-role, 270, 271, 274, 291
'though' clause, 213, 214, 231
time dependency, 101
time-span adverbial, 30, 51
topic, 212, 217
topic-focus structure, xiv, 209, 211,
214, 217, 219, 223, 230,
235
topicalization, 218, 286
tough construction, xvi, 269-283, 288-
296
transformational rules, xv, xvii, 302,
303, 305
transitivity, 76
Unaccusative, 1 1 , 12, 57, 58, 73, 76
unbounded dependencies, xv, 241
unergative, 11, 12
328 / LBXlCAL NATTBR
unifcation, 313
uniqueness
of events, 39, 46
of objects, 39, 44
universal alignment hypothesis, 2
universal theta assignment hypoth
esis, 2
Variable, 241 , 251-253, 256-258, 260,
265
verba efciendi, 46
verb
compound, 145
frequentative, xiii
nonstative, 3
performance, 46
periphrastic, xi, xii, 1 1 2, 122
psych, 16
quirky, 309
verbal modifers, 21 8
VP-ellipsis, xvi, 241, 253, 259-262
Welsh, 170, 171
wh-construction, 270, 271, 277, 292,
293
wh-extraction case, xvi, 294
'while' clause, 225, 231
word
afxed, 1 71
atomicity, 1 72
order, 209, 217
Zhuang, l 71
Lb uDCaOD5
CCutC OC5
The titles in this series are distributed
by the University of Chicago Press
and may be purchaed in aademic
or university bookstores or ordered di
rectly from the distributor: Order De
partment, I Ic1c S. Langely Avenue,
Chicago, Illinois rcrz.
A Manual oj Intensional Logic. Johan
van Benthem, second edition, revised
ad expaded. Lecture Notes No. I.
I5BN 0-937073-29-6 (paper) , 0-937073-
30-X (cloth)
Emotion and Focus. Helen Fay Nis
senbaum. Lectue Notes No. 2. I5BN
0-937073-20-2 (paper)
Lecture, on Contemporary Syntactic
Theories. Peter Sells. Lecture Notes
No. 3. I5BN 0-937073-14-8 (paper) ,
0-93707313-X (cloth)
An Introduction to Unifcation-Based
Approache, to Grammar. Stuart M.
Shieber. Lecture Notes No. 4. I5BN
0-937073-00-8 (paper) , 0-937073-01-6
(cloth)
The Semantics oj Destructive Li,p. Ian
A. Maon. Lecture Notes No. 5. I5BN
0-937073-06-7 (paper) , 0-937073-05-9
(cloth)
An Euay on Facts. Ken Olson. Lec
tue Notes No. 6. I5BN 0-937073-08-3
(paper) ,
0-937073-05-9 (cloth)
Logics oj Time and Computation.
Robert Goldblatt, second edition, re
vised and expanded. Lectue Notes
No. 7. I5BN 0-937073-94-6 (paper) ,
0-937073-93-8 (cloth)
Word Order and Constituent Structure
in German. Hans Uszkoreit. Lecture
Notes No. 8. I5BN 0-937073-10-5 (pa
per) , 0-937073-0-1 (cloth)
Color and Color Perception: A Study
in Anthropocentric Realism. David
Russel Hilbert. Lecture Notes No. 9.
I5BN 0-937073-16-4 (paper) , 0-937073-
15-6 (cloth)
Prolog and Natural-Language Analysis.
Ferando C. N. Pereira and Stuart M.
Shieber. Lecture Notes No. 10. I5BN
0-937073-180 (paper) , 0-937073-17-2
(cloth)
Working Papers in Grammatical The
ory and Discourse Structure: Inter
action, oj Morphology, Syntax, and
Di,course. M. Iida, S. Wechsler, and
D. Zec (Eds.) with an Introduction by
Joan Bresnan. Lecture Notes No. 11.
I5BN 0-937073-04-0 (paper) , 0-937073-
25-3 (cloth)
Natural Language ProceS6ing in the
I 80s: A Bibliography. Gerald Gaz
dar, Alex Franz, Karen Osbore, and
Roger Evans. Lecture Notes No. 12.
I5BN 0-937073-28-8 (paper) , 0-937073-
26-1 (cloth)
InJormation-Based Syntax and Seman
tics. Carl Pollard and Ivan Sag.
Lecture Notes No. 13. I5BN 0-937073-
24-5 (paper) , 0-937073-23-7 (cloth)
Non- Well-Founded Sets. Peter Aczel.
Lecture Notes No. 14. I5BN 0-937073-
22-9 (paper) , 0-937073-21-0 (cloth)
Partiality, Truth and Persistence. Tore
Langholm. Lecture Notes No. 15.
I5BN0-937073-34-2 (paper) , 0-937073-
35-0 (cloth)
Attribute- Value Logic and the Theory oj
Grammar. Mark Johnson. Lecture
Notes No. 16. I5BN 0-937073-36-9
(paper) , 0-937073-37-7 (cloth)
The Situation in Logic. Jon Barwise.
Lecture Notes No. 1 7. I5BN 0-937073-
32-6 (paper), 0-937073-33-4 (cloth)
The Linguistics oj Punctuation. Geof
Nunberg. Lecture Notes No. 18. I5BN
0-937073-466 (paper) , 0-937073-47-4
( cloth)
Anaphora and Quantifcation in Situa
tion Semantics. Jean Mak Gawron
and Stanley Peters. Lecture Notes
No. 19. I5BN 0-937073-48-4 (paper) ,
0-937073-49-0 (cloth)
Propo,itiofl1 Attih,u: The Role of
Cont.nt in Logic. Lang"age. and
Mind. C. Anthony Anderon ad
Joe ph Owens. LectU Notes No. 20.
ISBN (937073-5(4 (paper). (937073-
51-2 (cloth)
Lite ..t. 4d Cognition. Jerry R.
Hobbs. LectU Notes No. 21. ISBN
(937073-52-0 (paper). (937073-53-9
(cloth)
Sitution Theory and It, Application,.
lol. t . Robin Cooper. Kuniaki Mukai.
and John Perry (Eda. ) . Lecture Notes
No. 22. ISBN (937073-54-7 (paper).
093773- 55-5 (cloth)
Thc Llnguge of Fir.t- Order Logic
(i"c1"ci"g the Mlcinto,h program_
7areki , World). Jon 8Mwise atd
John Etchemendy. second edition. re
vaed atd expanded. Lecture Notes
No. 23. ISBN (937073-74-1 (paper)
Lexical Maller . Iva A. Sag and Anna
Szabolcsi. editors. Lecture Notes
No. 24. ISBN (9370736&O (paper) .
(93707365-2 (cloth)
Tar.ki, World. Jon BMwise and John
Etchemendy. Lecture Notes No. 25.
ISBN (937073-67-9 (paper)
Situation Theory and It. Application"
Vol. 2. Jon Bawise. J. Mark Gawron.
Gordon Plotkn. Syun Tutiya. editors.
Lecture Notes No. 26. ISBN 0-937073-
7(9 (paper). (937073-71-7 (cloth)
Literlte Programming. Donald E.
Knuth. Lecture Notes No. 27. ISBN
(937073-8(6 (paper). (937013-81-4
(cloth)
Normalization, Cut-Elimination and
the Theory of Proof,. A. M. Ungar.
Lecture Notes No. 28. ISBN 0-931013-
82-2 (paper) . (931013-83-0 (cloth)
Lect"re, on Linear Logic. A. S. Troel
stra. Lecture Notes No. 29. ISBN
(937073-17-6 (paper). (931013-18-4
(cloth)
A Short Introd"ction to Modal Logic.
Grigori Mints. Lecture Notes No. 30.
ISBN (93701315-X (paper) . 0-931013-
16-8 (cloth)
Lther Lo11 tes
1strDuteU Dj 1L
Agree ment i n Nat ural Language: Ap
proach." Theorie., DelCr.ption, .
Michael Barlow and Chales A. Fergu
son (Eds. ) . ISBN 0-937073-02-4 (cloth)
Paper. from t he Second International
Work,hop on Japane.e Syntax.
William J. Poser ( Ed. ) . ISBN
931073-38-5 (paper) . 0-937073-39-3
(cloth)
The Proceedi"g. of the Seventh W.,t
Coa,t Conference on Formal Ling"i,.
tiel (WCCFL 7). ISBN 0-937073-4(7
(paper)
The Proceeding. of t he Eighth W .. t
Coa.t Conference on Formal Ling"i.
tic. (WCCFL
8
). ISBN 0-937073-48
(paper)
The Phonology-Syntax Connection.
ShMon Iea ad Draga Zec (Eds.)
(copublished with The University of
Chicago Press) . ISBN (226381Q5
(paper). 0-22&38101-3 (cloth)
The Proceeding. of the Ninth We.t COalt
Conference on Formal Lingui.ti"
(WCCFL 9). ISBN 0-937073-64-4
(paper)
Japane .. /Korean Lingui.ti". Hajime
Hoji (Ed. ) . ISBN 0-93107351-1 (pa
per) . 0-931013-563 (cloth)
Experiencer Subject. in South A,ian
Language.. Manindra K. Verma
and K. P. Mohanan (Eds. ) . ISBN
931073-60-1 (paper) . 0-937073-61-X
( cloth)
Grammatical Relation.: A Cro .. -
Theoretical Per'peclive. Katarzyna
Dziwirek. Patrick Farell. Errapel
Mejia Bikandi (Eds. ) . ISBN (9370
73
-
63-6 (paper) . 0-937013-62-8 (cloth)
The
Proceeding. of the Tenth Welt
COI.t
Conference on Formal Lingui.ti"
(WCCFL 10). ISBN 0-931073-19-2
(paper)
OOK5 )5tDuCU
D Lb
The Proceedinga of the Third Weat Coaat
Conference on Formal Linguiatica
(WCCFL 3). (ti e.ss)I5BN 0-937073-
45-8 (paper,
The Proceedings of the Fourth West
Coaat Conference on Formal Lin
guiatica (WCCFL 4). ( tii. ss) I5BN
0-937073-45-8(paper,
The Proceedings of the Fifth Weat Coaat
Conference on Formal Linguiatica
(WCCFL 5). ( ti e.ss)I5BN 0-937073-
45-8 (paper,
The Proceedings of the Sith West Coast
Conference on Formal Linguistics
(WCCFL 6). (ti. ss) 5BN 0-93707J-
45-8 (paper,
Hausar Yau Do Kullum: Intermediate
and Advanced Le880n8 in Hausa Lan
guage and Culture. Wilia H. Leben,
Ahmadu Bello Zaria, Shekrau B.
Mak, and Lawan Danladi Yalwa.
( tis. ss) I5BN 0-937073-b8-7(paper,
Hau8ar Yau Do Kullum Workbook.
Wilia H. Leben, Ahmadu Belo
Zaria, Shekarau B. Mak, and
Lawan Danladi Yalwa. ( t. se) I5BN
0-93703-b9-5 (paper,
LtUCtD_ C5
)5tDuCU D Lb
Titles distributed by CSLI may be
ordered directly from CSLI Publica
tions, Ventura ), Stanford Univer
sity, Stanford, California 11c-1I I or
by phone (1I)Iz1-IIIz or (1I)Iz1-
I1. Orders can also be placed by e
mail ([email protected]) or FAX
(1I)Iz1-cI.
All orders must be prepaid by
check, VISA, or MaterCard (include
card name, number, expiration date) .
For shipping and handling add tz. c
for frst book and tc.Ifor each addi
tional book; tI. I for the frst report
and tc.z for each additional report.
California residents add I7sales tax.
For oversea shipping, add t1. c
for frst book and tz. zfor each addi
tiona book; tz.zfor frst report and
tc.I for each additional report. All
payments must be made in US cur
rency.