Di Frisco Et Al. 2022
Di Frisco Et Al. 2022
Di Frisco Et Al. 2022
net/publication/365002477
CITATIONS READS
7 404
3 authors:
Gunter Wagner
Yale University
527 PUBLICATIONS 28,043 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by James DiFrisco on 04 November 2022.
1
Abstract
Given the pervasiveness of gene sharing in evolution and the extent of homology across the tree
of life, why is everything not homologous with everything else? The continuity and overlapping
genetic contributions to diverse traits across lineages seem to imply that no discrete determination
of homology is possible. Although some argue that the widespread overlap in parts and processes
should be acknowledged as “partial” homology, this threatens a broad base of presumed
comparative morphological knowledge accepted by most biologists. Following a long scientific
tradition, we advocate a strategy of “theoretical articulation” that introduces further distinctions to
existing concepts to produce increased contrastive resolution among the labels used to represent
biological phenomena. We pursue this strategy by drawing on successful patterns of reasoning
from serial homology at the level of gene sequences to generate an enriched characterization of
serial homology as a hierarchical, phylogenetic concept. Specifically, we propose that the concept
of serial homology should be applied primarily to repeated but developmentally individualized
body parts, such as cell types, differentiated body segments, or epidermal appendages. For these
characters, a phylogenetic history can be reconstructed, similar to families of paralogous genes,
endowing the notion of serial homology with a hierarchical, phylogenetic interpretation. On this
basis, we propose a five-fold theoretical classification that permits a more fine-grained mapping
of diverse trait-types. This facilitates answering the question of why everything is not homologous
with everything else, as well as how novelty is possible given that any new character possesses
evolutionary precursors. We illustrate the fecundity of our account by reference to debates over
insect wing serial homologues and vertebrate paired appendages.
Keywords: serial homologues, homology, levels of organization, insect wing evolution, paired
appendages
2
1. The Need for Theoretical Articulation
In a recent paper (Ralevski et al., 2022), a striking discovery was reported. A mitochondrial
gene in Arabidopsis that has a highly conserved homologue in mammals appears to play similar
developmental and physiological roles across this yawning phylogenetic gap, including effects on
movement (for mice, locomotion; for plants, hyponasty). Setting aside the question of what is
meant by “homologous functions” (Love, 2007), this discovery harbors two conceptual issues at
(Piatigorsky, 2007) and the nature and extent of homology across the tree of life (Wagner, 2014).
These jointly form a problem that remains unresolved. Given the fact of common descent, why is
everything not homologous with everything else? The composition and developmental formation
of “traits” at different levels of organization across taxa are affected by extensive gene sharing that
make it difficult to discriminate, at the genetic level, one trait from another. As a result, drawing a
sharp contrast between traits that are homologous and others that are not seems to rely on
selectively ignoring some portion of this ubiquitous common inheritance. The continuity and
overlapping genetic and developmental contributions to diverse traits across lineages seem to
This problem is especially acute for hierarchical notions of homology that focus on the
for some time that homologous characters develop from different and often diverse sets of causes
(de Beer, 1971; Spemann, 1915). Empirical studies in evolutionary developmental biology (evo-
devo) have demonstrated that homologues can be induced by different signaling pathways in
different species and can arise from different germ layers and cell populations, sometimes
3
(Haag, 2014; Haag & True, 2021; Hall, 2003). However, it is also the case that key signaling
pathways and cell types are involved in developmental mechanisms that give rise to different traits;
the existence of shared components or genetic networks for characters that are seemingly non-
homologous (e.g., eyes or limbs) suggests “deep homology” (Shubin et al., 1997, 2009). Other
authors, building from this data, argue that the widespread overlap in parts and processes should
be acknowledged as “partial” homology (Abouheif, 1999; Moczek, 2014; Roth, 1984). Since most
characters share some genetic and developmental commonality (i.e., “partial” homology can
always be detected), the distinction between homology and non-homology seems to blur. This
biologists.
The problem is compounded when we turn to inherent difficulties with the concepts of
serial homology and evolutionary novelty. Both have faced criticism within and among
communities of biologists. For serial homology, it is unclear why repeated structures within the
(Fusco, 2022; Schmitt, 2017). For evolutionary novelty, the very idea seems anchored in the
distinction between homology and non-homology (i.e., novelty = non-homology; Müller &
Wagner, 1991). Assuming this distinction, “partial” homology implies that nothing is a novelty.
For any pair of characters, they are only more or less diverged. If this distinction is rejected (i.e.,
novelty does not require non-homology), the ubiquity of “partial” homology implies that
everything is partially novel. And this doesn’t even address the tendency of biologists to label traits
as novel according to diverse and conflicting criteria (Brigandt & Love, 2012).
when biologists are faced with difficulties in conceptualizing complex phenomena, usually
4
because new data arrives rapidly and thereby contributes to the disruption of theoretical categories.
narrowing their original meaning, to produce increased contrastive resolution among the labels
used to represent biological phenomena. Richard Owen famously exemplified this strategy when
he distinguished “general homology,” “special homology,” and “serial homology” (Owen, 1848).
More recent examples include “positional homology” (Minelli, 1998), “organizational homology”
(Müller, 2003), and “deep homology” (Shubin et al., 1997, 2009). We label this strategy
relationships to yield productive theory for doing empirical work. Importantly, this strategy can
fail, evidenced by terms and distinctions that do not catch on (e.g., Lankester’s (1870) “homogeny”
or Sattler’s (1984) “dynamic homology”) or underlying difficulties with the distinctions (e.g., the
connection between “general homology” and a presumed ideal archetype, or the fact that two body
parts can stand in a relation of deep homology while being homoplasies, serial homologues, or not
even candidate homologues [see (DiFrisco et al., 2022)]). And sometimes there is value in
exploring connections across different approaches to theoretical articulation (Novick 2018). Yet a
successful theoretical articulation can enrich biological investigation (e.g., the separation of
orthology and paralogy for gene homology), and eventually undergird much of the basic
We think the time is ripe to undertake new theoretical articulation in relation to serial
homology, and in a way that complements and augments recent work of this kind for evolutionary
novelty and co-option (DiFrisco et al., 2022). Here we adopt a specific tactic to pursue this strategy
that involves examining the successful patterns of reasoning that have coalesced in talking about
homology at the level of gene sequences (orthology, paralogy, gene families). These reasoning
5
patterns are now stable in genomics, population genetics, and protein biology; together they offer
a basis for additional theoretical articulation to address the problem described above. In
combination with important desiderata for the concept of homology, such as the requirement that
homologues form equivalence classes and therefore involve “sameness” (i.e., in contrast to
based on an account of what it means for a part to have identity as a biological character (DiFrisco
et al., 2020) and permits a more fine-grained mapping of diverse trait-types discussed by biologists,
while also answering the question of why everything is not homologous with everything else. We
illustrate the fecundity of our account by reference to standard empirical problems involving serial
homology, such as the evolution of insect wing serial homologues, the vertebral column, and
paired appendages of gnathostomes, which have been active sites of discussion within evo-devo
over the past decade. An advantage of the resulting hierarchical picture of serial homology is that
transformation series, thereby blunting concerns that “new” characters are always in the eye of the
beholder and subject to deflationary interpretations based on future empirical studies. In closing,
we consider the broader significance of how concepts are constructed and used in scientific
inquiry, highlighting domains where the status of theoretical articulation remains an open question
6
kind of continuity that is discovered in an act of tracing. In contemporary biology, the tracing of
genes across species uses sophisticated algorithms to identify the most likely or parsimonious
historical scenario to support the notion that a particular gene a in species A is in fact the same
gene as gene b in species B (i.e., it can be traced to an ancestral gene). This includes an initial
discovery of similarities (sequence alignment) and the reconstruction of the evolutionary history
of the genes across species (phylogenetic inference). Similarly, morphological homologies are
discovered via a process of initial similarity discovery (“primary homology”) (de Pinna, 1991),
which leads to the construction of a historical scenario connecting two characters to a hypothetical
relatively uncontroversial for special homology (i.e., the same character in different species), it is
unclear whether this way of thinking also applies to serial homology (i.e., the relationship between
repeated parts of the same organism, such as ribs in a vertebrate or the legs of a centipede).
The conceptual intricacy of serial homology derives primarily from the fact that serial
cartilage—but also are shared across taxonomic groups. Cervical and thoracic vertebrae are serial
synapomorphy of the tetrapod vertebrates as a clade. This dual aspect of serial homology generates
three possible ways of understanding serial homology: (A) phylogenetically, (B) intra-
(A) Tracing special homologues through phylogeny comes with a well-established framework of
tools and tests from systematics and cladistics, but it is not obvious how to apply these to characters
within the same organism. Some authors have conflated the seeming lack of phylogenetic tests
7
with the lack of any tests for serial homology, concluding that it is a defective concept (e.g.,
Patterson, 1982). The idea is that different parts of the body are not related to each other through
a process of phylogenetic change and lineage splitting; thus, they cannot be accommodated within
and a confusion. Alternatively, serially repeated structures in an organism can be grouped together
can then be investigated as to its phylogenetic relationships, just like non-serial characters such as
the brain or skin (Nixon & Carpenter, 2012). This perspective tends to assimilate serial homology
(B) Serial homology might be understood as applying to structures within an organism that are
relative to major body planes, or that possess the same developmental mechanisms controlling
their identity. The reasoning to establish such homologies might rely on comparative methods to
infer the existence of these mechanisms, but this is nonetheless consistent with serial homology as
(C) The crucial phenomenon missed by both alternatives is that characters—and not just species—
form phylogenetic trees of ancestral and derived identities, and it is often the case that multiple
branches deriving from the same ancestral character coexist within the same organism. The latter
characters are serial homologues. We can express this idea that combines both phylogenetic and
8
Serial homology: Two characters in the same organism are serial homologs if they are
derived by differentiation from a single character or a set of multiple identical characters
in an ancestral species.
The clearest picture can be obtained by starting from gene paralogy. Genes can be orthologous if
the same gene is found in the genomes of two different species and if there is a one-one relationship
between them (i.e., if there is no indication of a gene duplication event in evolutionary history).
However, there are also genes in the same genome that are phylogenetically related to each other,
so-called paralogous genes. These genes originated by duplication and have acquired different
examples include the vertebrate Hox gene clusters, which arose by whole genome duplication at
the base of the vertebrate tree (Gehring, 1998). These are genes in the same genome that are
phylogenetically related to each other and thus can be traced to an unduplicated gene in a
They are clearly homologous but, since they are in the same organism (genome), must be serially
homologous. If the number of paralogous genes is larger than two, then it is useful to think of the
set of paralogous genes as a gene family that has a history of duplication and divergence, which
can be represented by a gene tree. This phylogenetic tree reflects the evolutionary history of the
members of the gene family. Hence, in the case of paralogous genes, we have two or more
characters in the same organism that are phylogenetically related—serial homologues. Can this
way of thinking be applied to morphological characters? To approach this question, let us move
In the last two decades, there has been a growing realization that cell types can be
understood as units of evolutionary change just like genes at the molecular level (Arendt, 2008;
Arendt et al., 2016; Wagner, 2014). Akin to genes or morphological characters, cell types from
9
different species can stand in the relationship of homology. In addition, there are cell types that
are clearly differentiated from one other but more closely related to each other than to other cell
types. For instance, macrophages are cells from the innate immune system of vertebrates and are
Martinez, 2019). However, there are also specialized sub-groups, such as the resident macrophages
of most organs: microglia of the brain, Kupffer cells of the liver, alveolar macrophages of the lung
and uterine macrophages of the endometrium (Okabe & Medzhitov, 2016). Most likely, these are
different cell types specialized for different functions, phylogenetically related to each other and
derived from an ancestral phagocyte of pre-chordate origin. The same is likely true of neurons,
which probably arose once or twice in animal history (Kristan, 2016). There are many neuron types
in the brain and the diversity of cerebral neuron types likely arose from a history of evolutionary
cell type differentiation (Arendt, 2008; Arendt, et al., 2019; Arendt et al., 2016). Cell types from
the same organism appear to form cell type families, where they display different levels of
relatedness based on an evolutionary history of sister cell type differentiation (Arendt et al., 2016).
Thus, cell types in the same body that arose in evolution via differentiation from an ancestral cell
type are examples of serial homology. Again, we see a strong relationship between serial
Next, we can ask whether this pattern of reasoning scales up to morphological characters.
The so-called epidermal appendages (e.g., hair) are an example of characters that occur in the same
organism and are phylogenetically related like cell types (see Figure 1). A mammalian hair is not
just a keratinous shaft growing out of the skin, but a complex organ that consists of a sebaceous
gland, muscles, and the hair shaft proper with a follicle. In comparative anatomy, it is referred to
as a pilo-sebaceous unit (PSU). There is an interesting relationship between the PSU and mammary
10
gland, the latter of which is evolutionarily derived from (and thus related to) the PSU (Blackburn,
1991; Oftedal, 2002). The connection between PSUs and mammary glands is supported by the fact
that the developing mammary glands in marsupials and some eutherian mammals produce hair
that is lost later during development. Hence, the PSU and mammary glands are serial homologues
Realizing that serially homologous cell types and structures are related to each other as
represented in a phylogenetic tree makes it clear that they can have different degrees of relatedness,
just as some species are more closely related to each other than they are to other species (e.g., two
species of mice are more closely related than they are to cows). The same is true for paralogous
genes; HoxA1 and HoxB1 are more closely related to each other than HoxA1 is to HoxA2, which
duplicated earlier than HoxA1 and HoxB1 (Prince & Pickett, 2002). Degrees of relatedness among
cell types reflect the phylogenetic history of differentiation rather than degrees of similarity or
number of shared parts. All members of a cell type family are serially homologous, with their
relatedness determined by the number of branching points separating them on the character tree.
Figure 1. A simplified hypothetical character tree of epidermal appendages. On the right, feathers and scales are
characters that exist in “reptiles” (including birds); feathers are evolutionarily derived from ancestral body scales and
11
thus feathers and scales are more closely related to each other than each is to hair. On the left, three examples of
mammalian skin appendages are shown. As drawn, the tree suggests that different types of body hair have arisen more
recently than mammary glands, but hair (i.e., the “pilo-sebaceous unit” [PSU]) is the ancestral state from which
mammary glands evolved (see main text for references). Note: the hypothesis depicted here requires us to make
assumptions about the body cover of pre-mammary gland mammalian animals.
Importantly, not all iterated structures that are commonly considered serial homologues
form traceable character trees. Some repeated cellular elements are simple developmental copies
of each other or copies of a prototype, such as different cells of the same cell type (e.g., two
neutrophil blood cells), which are different instantiations of the same differentiation program.
They are iterations of the same cell type and have a developmental traceability to a progenitor cell
type (e.g., stem cell) in the life of an organism. However, developmental traceability does not
connect them to the same individual stem cell because different instances of the stem cell can give
rise to the same neutrophil cell type. Thus, cells of the same type in a body do not need to be
There also are repeated elements that are highly similar but more individuated than cells of
the same cell type. A morphological example is the forewing and the hindwing of a bee. Both are
similar blade-like structures composed of two apposed epithelial cell layers and the associated
cuticle. Yet they occur in different locations of the body (mesothorax and metathorax) and differ
in size and shape across insect taxa. Shape differences can become extreme, like that between the
forewing and hindwing of a beetle or that of a dipteran. In beetles, the forewing is transformed into
a protective cover (“elytra”), while the hindwing often (but not always) functions as a wing. In
dipterans, the forewing is (in most cases) a functional wing and the hindwing a haltere (i.e., a club-
shaped sense organ). This example illustrates that these repeated elements can be similar, like in
the case of a honeybee or a mayfly, but in different instantiations show remarkable differentiation,
like in beetles and flies. Similarity of the forewing and hindwing suggest relatedness, but they also
12
are developmentally and evolutionarily individuated; the forewing, as a homologue across
pterygote insect species, has a different evolutionary history of transformation than the hindwing.
The examples of paralogous gene copies, sister cell type families, and iterated
morphological characters demonstrate that our proposed phylogenetic notion of character trees of
units. Traceability of historical relationships does not apply to identical copies of the same element;
at best, we can trace their developmental history in the lifetime of the individual in which they
occur. Cells of the same cell type form ahistorical classes rather than historical individuals and
thus should be distinguished from serial homology. Here the need for further theoretical
articulation is palpable since the terminology of serial homology alone does not provide that
distinction. Before we turn to this task, let us briefly consider instances of duplicated genes that
do not form gene families, as truly paralogous genes do, but behave more like copies of the same
cell type in a phenomenon labeled “concerted evolution” (Ganley & Kobayashi, 2007; Zimmer et
al., 1980).
Ribosomal RNA genes exist in the genome as multiple copies. This is needed to produce
enough ribosomal RNA to form the ribosomes necessary for a high level of protein production
rate. Surprisingly, different copies of the ribosomal RNA genes have a very shallow phylogenetic
signature; there are no one-one orthologues of individual rRNA genes from one species to the next.
These genes get duplicated and lost at a high rate by unequal crossover or become homogenized
with respect to their sequence through gene conversion. The result is that members of the rRNA
cluster do not have individualized gene copies, unlike other gene families (e.g., hemoglobin or
Hox genes). Identical copies or replicas of the same biological unit are a different phenomenon
13
than serial homologues of genes and cell types, which do have a historical phylogenetic
The distinction between copies or replicas and serial homologues is at odds with an earlier
proposal by one of us (Wagner, 2014, Figure 2.13A). In that proposal, replicas were subsumed
under the general notion of serial homology as “homomorphs” and distinguished from
“paramorphs” (i.e., individuated serial homologues). At that time, the notion of evolutionary
traceability as the conceptual core of identity had not been appreciated; here it is considered central
to any form of homology, serial or not. Again, the need for theoretical articulation is pressing;
further distinctions are required, especially to foster an empirically discriminating and fruitful
research program. A hypothesis of serial homology among parts of the same body implies that one
must investigate whether a plausible scenario for the evolutionary history of the putative serial
homologues can be empirically supported. Such a question would be moot for copies traced
developmentally (e.g., different cells of the same terminal branch cell type). Theoretical
articulation of this kind for serial homology takes on added significance when we turn to a variety
A key principle for making sense of serial homology is that homology is a form of sameness
rather than similarity. Homology between two characters means that they are the same kind or type
of character—a leaf, forelimb, or neuron—and that this kind forms a historically traceable
individual like a species (Wagner, 2014). It does not mean that homologous characters are similar
in every respect; they can be highly dissimilar, such as in the well-known transformation of the
14
jaw joint of reptiles into inner ear ossicles of mammals or the transformation of the ancestral
parietal eye in vertebrates to the mammalian pineal gland. This principle applies to special
homology and serial homology alike. One implication of this understanding of sameness is that
judgments of homology are binary or discrete, at least in principle: two characters are either
homologous or not, as opposed to having some degree of homology. Since homologues are the
Parting with the principle of sameness, some influential architects of the Modern Synthesis
(Mayr, 1969; Simpson, 1961) redefined homology as similarity due to descent from a common
ancestor. It is important to appreciate why a graded version of homology stands in conflict with
classes are formed by a relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. Thus, character A is
(symmetric); and if A and B are homologous, and B and C are homologous, then A and C are
homologous (transitive). A theorem of elementary set theory proves that all elements fulfilling
these conditions jointly form a class (i.e., a set that neither overlaps with other such sets nor is a
proper subset). These logical attributes combine with the hierarchical nesting of phylogenetic
descent to give comparative evolutionary reasoning its characteristic form. Within a given clade,
homology of a character applies to the clade as well as every nested sub-clade within it. This is
important for guiding comparative research because only a tiny fraction of species—extant or
extinct—can be studied. When a character is studied in one species in a clade, the results can be
projected across the clade to homologous characters, yielding a rich network of empirical
15
hypotheses with an underlying evolutionary rationale for their likelihood (Harvey & Pagel, 1991).
Work on specific cases should lead to likely inferences applicable to yet unobserved instances
reasoning (which may not always manifest in scientific practice). Unlike sameness, similarity is
This is because things can be similar and dissimilar in different degrees and respects. For example,
profiles between characters A and B, and B and C, but not necessarily between A and C.
homology of a character in a taxonomic group does not necessarily apply across the whole group.
Instead, each potential homologue would have to be compared in a pairwise fashion as to their
similarity or dissimilarity. Carrying out such research would be impractically demanding for
groups with even modest species diversity. It would make comparative research hyper-contextual
and local. It also would stunt empirical hypotheses and block projections that are otherwise enabled
a clade, and thereby reveal underlying biological commonalities between the characters under
comparison, we would have to know in advance all relevant similarities and dissimilarities in order
point of investigation that makes homology a blunt if not useless tool in comparative reasoning. It
is perhaps not surprising that there was a relative absence of homology thinking (Ereshefsky, 2012)
in the evolutionary research associated with the Modern Synthesis (see Nuño de la Rosa, this
issue).
16
Some more nuanced proposals, though not embracing the identification of homology with
mere similarity, likewise counsel abandoning the idea of homology as a binary or discrete relation
in favor of graded notions like “partial homology” (Minelli & Peruffo, 1991; Abouheif, 1999;
Minelli & Fusco, 2013; Moczek, 2014; Roth, 1984; Sattler, 1994; Shubin & Wake, 1996). Partial
homology can be more complex than mere similarity if its assessment is based on multiple
evidential factors—for example, not just similarity, but also phylogenetic relationships,
topological position, and shared developmental mechanisms. The output of such assessments is
homology. It implies that comparative research should be highly contextual and local: “We must
abandon the concept of homology as an all-or-nothing relation. We must rather look, in the
individual cases, for those particular aspects of homology which are recognizable in the context
and at the level of the particular modules we are dealing with” (Minelli, 1998, 344). Although the
rationales for partial homology vary, there are two broad motivations. The first is that evolution is
too contingent and variable for tracing discrete character identities across the vicissitudes of
phylogeny, and therefore binary judgments of homology are unrealistic. The second is that
homologies at different levels of organization can be decoupled from one another. For example,
homologous organs are not necessarily produced only by homologous developmental processes
It is true that differences between homologous characters can always be found, as should
be expected from the long-term evolution of independent lineages. However, the notion of
homology and definition of shared characters abstracts from biological variation and diversity,
picking out what is invariant or conserved across a given taxonomic group. The identification of a
morphological character does not need to include all of its features and components—if it did, it
17
is not clear how comparative generalizations would be possible. The question is whether
abstracting from these details is problematic, or significantly diminishes the realism of our
conceptual frameworks. We think the question cannot be decided a priori, but must be adjudicated
on the basis of the empirical success of research programs that rely on this conceptual strategy
Shifting from categorical to graded notions may seem appealing to manage biological
variation and complexity, but “degrees” still require specification of the properties that living
systems can have degrees of. In practice, criteria of homology can be in tension (e.g., position
versus special quality) and must be weighted appropriately, yet the existence of different degrees
of evidence for homology does not entail degrees of homology itself. The invocation of graded
notions does not present clear advantages in this situation, whereas it introduces the need to make
comparisons. The situation parallels the difficulty that assessing “similarity” requires specification
of which similarities are relevant, a problem that confounded the mathematization of taxonomy
(Sterner & Lidgard, 2014). Principled decisions about which aspects are relevant (and which are
not) would hardly be less demanding than understanding homology as sameness of kind. These
challenges are not insurmountable, but it is not clear that they have been met with a principled
framework of partial homology that is sufficiently articulated to guide the practices of comparative
biology.
As noted, partial homology can be understood as a way of capturing the fact that
homologous characters do not necessarily have all of the same parts or mechanisms. In this sense,
homology is conceived as not “all-or-nothing.” This line of thought presupposes that homologues
18
discrete, and thus deviations from total conservation imply that homology itself must be graded.
This assumption is unwarranted, however. Homologies are defined for characters identified at a
specific level—a level of organization and level of taxonomic inclusion (see below, Section 5)—
without requiring that all the parts of the character are also homologous. If homology and character
identity are level-specific, then deviations from total conservation across levels need not degrade
the concept of homology itself or make it a matter of degrees. At the same time, violations of the
assumption of total conservation do not entail the opposite extreme of a total independence of
levels of homology. For example, in our model, level-specific character identity is underwritten
by developmental mechanisms that are responsible for the developmental individuation of the
structure. Hence, the independence of character identity only applies to compositional and
developmental mechanisms that are not part of the character identity mechanism itself (DiFrisco
Crucially, in our estimation, the idea of partial homology creates difficulties for assessing
how homology at one level of organization influences homology at another level (DiFrisco et al.,
2022). Many of the same genes are reused in different tissues in diverse metazoans. Does this reuse
make all those characters partially homologous? When we consider that key signaling pathways
like Shh and Wnt are involved in many unrelated developmental processes, this would threaten to
make everything partially homologous with everything else. We have returned to our animating
problem: given the pervasiveness of gene sharing in evolution, why is everything not homologous
with everything else? Since Shh signaling is involved in the development of feathers, head midline
partial homologies becomes dizzying, if not empirically intractable. Under this conception, the
19
notion of homology loses contrastive resolution, which reduces its usefulness as a tool for
To situate our perspective on character identity and homology in contrast to accounts based
character that gives substance to notions of character identity and character states. In our approach,
a morphological character is a circumscribed part of an organism that consists of at least one but
usually multiple cells and their products. This organismal part develops under the influence of a
character identity mechanism or ChIM (DiFrisco et al., 2020), which endows that part of the body
(as a unit) with the capacity to manifest distinct developmental states from other parts of the same
body. A ChIM is the mechanistic basis for the developmental and evolutionary individuality of a
independence of an organismal part relative to other such parts. Although there is much more to
the ChIM framework (DiFrisco et al., 2020; DiFrisco et al., 2022; Wagner, 2007, 2014), it is
important to note that a ChIM is necessary for developmental individuality but does not dictate the
particular phenotype or state that a character displays. Character identity and character states (or
the realization of a character) are thus, to some degree, decoupled. This allows character identity
Character state differences can be described in terms of two complementary aspects: (a)
differences in the configuration of sub-parts of the character, and (b) differences of attributes of
the character. A configuration is a set of parts contained within the character that includes their
20
spatial relationships—e.g., zeugopod, stylopod, and autopod arranged along the proximo-distal
individualized characters themselves. Character states can also differ with respect to attributes or
properties of the character or its parts. These attributes include size and shape, as well as physical
configuration, such as the presence or absence of parts, the number of parts, or their spatial and
functional relations. A potential source of ambiguity is that the parts of a character are entities (and
potentially characters themselves), but having such-and-such parts is an attribute of the character.
The same ambiguity exists for whole characters: feathers are biological characters, but the
differences of character state can include differences in any attribute (e.g., size, shape) or
differences in the kinds and numbers of sub-parts as well as their relations (i.e., their
configuration).
vertebrates do not have paired appendages). All paired appendages of gnathostome vertebrates are
homologous and their development is guided by a conserved set of signaling centers, such as the
apical ectodermal ridge and the zone of polarizing activity, as well as dorsally and ventrally
differentiated ectoderm. In teleost fishes, the paired appendages have a different complement of
skeletal parts compared to limbs. Teleost pectoral fins have four radials, a row of small nodular
distal radials, and a series of dermal fin rays. In contrast, a forelimb has, at least ancestrally and
often early in development, a single proximal stylopodial element (humerus), two zeugopodial
elements (radius and ulna), small wrist elements (carpals), palm elements (metacarpals), and digits
(phalanges). The difference between a pectoral fin and a forelimb is thus due to differences in the
complement of their parts (e.g., limbs have no fin rays) and their attributes (e.g., outward shapes).
21
Hence, fins and limbs are two different character states of the pectoral paired appendage character.
To be more precise, fins and limbs are two classes of character states for this morphological
character because both encompass a variety of states collectively described as fins or limbs. None
of these differences affect the identity of the pectoral paired appendages, which are controlled by
the same ChIMs (see below, Section 6). They only differ in their configurations and attributes, and
there is clear evidence for the continued existence of paired appendages in the lineages leading to
extant tetrapods, notwithstanding that limbs have been lost in some lineages (e.g., snakes,
gymnophiones). Importantly, fins and limbs are not very similar but nonetheless homologous;
there is a traceable history of the presence of paired pectoral appendages in gnathostome lineages.
categories within the broad and inclusive phenomenon of serially repeated structures (Table 1). A
key distinction is between morphological attributes and structures. Attributes of a body part—
including features like size, color, curvature, overlap of parts, and number of parts—are essentially
dependent on the body part they are an attribute of, and have no separable existence (i.e., there is
no colored phenotype without a body part to have that color). By contrast, structures are separable
22
Condition of serial feature Term Examples Traceability
Zygomatic arch,
Separable structure of a body Character state transverse and spinous Sometimes
part, no ChIM structure process, peripheral (contextual)
vascular elements
Table 1. Categories differentiating the various phenomena associated with serial homology. “Serial homology” is
often loosely applied to each category from character state structures to paramorphs. In our framework, the key
distinction is between paramorphs and non-paramorphs because only the former include distinct individuated
characters.
as the zygomatic arch (lateral cheekbones), the transverse and spinous processes on vertebrae, and
peripheral vascular elements (Figure 2). These are entities or parts rather than attributes, but they
when these structures are stably represented across generations, they are traceable as serial and
special homologues. Often, this is based on their position relative to individualized structures (e.g.,
the spinous process of the C4 vertebra, or the right transverse processes of the thoracic vertebrae).
This is a form of contextually dependent traceability that does not require developmental
individualization. By contrast, character state attributes do not form traceable units or entities at
all. Although one can compare attributes, such as size or color of body parts, such comparisons
necessarily depend on tracing the body part rather than the attribute itself.
23
Figure 2. Examples of morphological structures that are likely not developmentally individualized: (A) The zygomatic
arch is formed by projections from the temporal and zygomatic bone, with variable relative contributions between
species; (B) vertebral processes on thoracic and lumbar vertebrae; and (C) peripheral veins whose formation is due
more to epigenetic factors like shear stress and pressure differences than regulatory specification.
further distinctions relevant to the issue of serial homology. The primary differentiating factors are
whether the serially repeated characters (cell type, tissue, or organ) have the same ChIM and
whether there are stable positional differences that permit a descriptive indexing of the positions
of their different instances. Characters that have the same ChIM but no positional indexing are
simple copies, which we label replicas. These include cells of the same cell type, mammalian body
hairs, and leaves. Mammalian hair of some specific type (e.g., contour hair) is developmentally
individualized vis-à-vis other skin appendages, such as mammary glands, but single hairs are not
individualized vis-à-vis other instances of the same type of hair and lack positional identifiers.
Without differences in identity mechanisms and without stable positional attributes, it is not
meaningful (and may often be practically impossible) to trace such structures across individuals
and species. Cells are only replicas if they belong to a terminal branch in a cell type tree (e.g.,
erythrocytes rather than blood cells) because instances of a non-terminal type can be further
24
distinguished with respect to other terminal types (i.e., blood cells differentiated as lymphocytes
versus myeloid leukocytes). The same principle applies to tissues and organs.
but possess stable positional differences that allow descriptive indexing: the right or left pectoral
appendage, or digits 2-5 in mammalian pentadactyl limbs. We call these serial structures
homomorphs (Wagner, 2014). The categories of homomorph and replica are morphologically
distinct but mechanistically the same (see Stewart et al. 2019); their instances will vary together
and their capacity for independent variation is limited by the influence of positional factors on
development (e.g., local growth rates or hormonal influences on 2:4 digit ratio).
derived from the same ancestral ChIM are called paramorphs, parallel to gene paralogues
(Wagner, 2014). 1 Paradigmatic examples are forelimbs and hindlimbs of mammals, which in spite
of their obvious homology are developmentally individualized through the action of the paralogous
transcription factors Tbx4 and Tbx5 (see discussion in Section 6). For tissues and organs, the
positional indexing of paramorphs (McKenna et al., 2021). Often, in the absence of mechanistic
knowledge, positional indexing is used as a proxy to name different serial structures and
differentiate them descriptively. Comparisons of variation over a wide taxonomic scope also can
correlated variation. However, it is not possible to confirm the status of some serial structures as
homomorphs or paramorphs without the mechanistic study of their development. For example,
1 Others have introduced the term “paramorph” for similar phenomena (Minelli, 2000, 2002). However, this
introduction of the term “paramorph” does not distinguish phenomena we would label as “homomorphs” and
therefore the reader should be aware of the subtle differences in vocabulary.
25
although mammalian digits 2-5 are homomorphs, digit 1 (thumb) is a paramorph of digits 2-5 and
developmentally individualized from them (Stewart et al., 2019), while also being positionally
paramorph are morphologically the same but mechanistically distinct. Paramorphs are distinct
characters with capacities for independent evolutionary trajectories due to being developmentally
The status of some serial structures as homomorphs versus paramorphs can change over
the course of development when multiple ChIMs operate sequentially in the same regions. For
example, in Drosophila, trunk segments along the antero-posterior axis develop from a
segmentation cascade controlled by the gap gene network, pair-rule network, segment polarity
network, and Hox genes that differentiate segmental identities. Prior to the action of Hox genes,
the trunk segment domains are homomorphs, having the same ChIM—the segment polarity
network (Chipman, 2015; DiFrisco & Wagner, 2022; Lev & Chipman, 2021; Lev et al., 2022;
Wagner, 2014; see Figure 3). 2 They are positionally indexed and traceable only in a weak sense
(e.g., “anteriormost segment”). In comparing myriapods, which have more segments and more
segment number diversity than insects, it might not be meaningful to ask (at this stage) which
segments have been added and which are the same. However, after Hox genes activate cascades
paramorphs (Hughes & Kaufman, 2002). In arthropods generally, segments are serially
homologous as segments, but also have additional identities, such as thoracic segments or a T2
2 Lev and colleagues (2022) have recently used the ChIN/ChIM concept to assess serial homology between
arthropod segments, finding that pre-gnathal segments of the head are not serially homologous to trunk segments
due to their not having the same ChIM (the segment polarity network). This insight is then used to support a novel
hypothesis about the evolutionary origin of head segments.
26
segment. In this case, paramorphs also are positionally indexed and strongly traceable; they can
A feature unique to paramorphs is that they form hierarchies or trees of character identities.
Because of this, it is necessary to specify the “levels” at which the characters are homologous or
from a thoracic segment and a vertebra must be distinguished from a thoracic vertebra. This feature
also has an important implication: evolutionary novelty should also be understood in a hierarchical
are different senses in which this is true. One sense refers to levels of organization: robust part-
whole relationships that capture wide-ranging biological regularities (Brooks et al., 2021). For
morphological characters, the primary levels of anatomical organization are cell types, tissues,
organs, and whole body plans. These different characters have level-specific kinds of character
identity mechanisms (ChIMs). For cell types, these are primarily core regulatory complexes of
transcription factors; tissue ChIMs include extracellular matrix and cell–cell signaling networks
that maintain appropriate distributions of cell types; and organ ChIMs are interdependent signaling
centers that control the distribution of tissues in a region (DiFrisco et al., 2020). Body plan identity
mechanisms, or ChIMs for integrated body plans, are similarly composed of interdependent
signaling centers, but the signals cross embryonic structures that are not developmentally
individualized (DiFrisco & Wagner, 2022). The ChIM model revises and qualifies a common
contention about homology and levels—namely, that homology between characters at one level is
27
often independent of homology at another level. While acknowledging this fact, the central
hypothesis of the ChIM model is that character identity is linked to the identity of specific
underlying (i.e., lower-level) mechanisms, which are subsets of the total developmental
the branching points define different levels of taxonomic inclusion or specification. With special
homology, the branching pattern of characters coincides with the speciation events of the lineages
having those characters. When serial homologues are treated as single phylogenetic characters
(e.g., the vertebral column; see Section 3.2), the situation is the same. However, with paramorphs
the pattern is more intricate because multiple terminal branches of a character tree coexist within
the same organism. Thus, in making a statement about serial homology between paramorphs, it is
necessary to specify the level of inclusion at which that relationship holds. This can be captured in
the language of “levels”: the vertebrae C4 and T3 are serially homologous (paramorphic) at the
level of vertebrae but not cervical vertebrae, whereas C4 and C5 are serially homologous
(homomorphic) at the level of vertebrae and cervical vertebrae. The hierarchical or tree-like
relationship among paramorphs entails that they can be more or less closely related, though this
does not imply that there are continuous degrees of homology (e.g., insect segment T2 is not “X%
determined by the number of (discrete) branches or levels separating them on the relevant character
tree.
paralogous genes to cell type families, tissue paramorphs, and organ paramorphs. At still higher
levels of organization, sexual homologies between male and female genitalia are paramorphic
28
(Pavlicev et al., 2022), as are caste types in insect colonies (Abouheif, 2021). Given that paramorph
hierarchies comprise characters that are developmentally individualized from one another, their
existence implies a corresponding hierarchy for the associated ChIMs. The ChIM for
homomorphic arthropod segments is the segment polarity network (SPN), but the ChIM for the
prothorax includes the SPN plus Sex combs reduced (Scr), which individualizes the T1 segment
(Figure 3). In this ChIM hierarchy, the SPN is at a more basal node, whereas the ChIM that
includes the SPN and Scr is a terminal branch. In the same way, “arthropod segment” is a more
basal character and “prothorax” is one among several terminal branches—a developmentally
characters that are not serially or specially homologous to an existing character (Müller & Wagner,
1991), and paramorphy is a hierarchical relationship, then the status of some paramorph as a
novelty versus a serial homologue is also hierarchical. 3 That is, the difference between novelty
and serial homology is only well-defined relative to particular levels in a paramorph hierarchy.
Thus, when we ask whether the first digit in mammals (the thumb) is a novelty or a serial
homologue, the answer is both—relative to different levels of specification of the digit paramorph
individualized from them, it is also a novel character. By contrast, a supernumerary 6th digit would
be serially homologous (homomorphic) to digits 2–5, but not a novelty if it is not individualized
3 Our conceptualization of serial homology requires a slight modification of the earlier definition of evolutionary
novelty as non-homology (Müller & Wagner, 1991). An evolutionary novelty that arises from duplicated characters
introduces a new level in the hierarchy of serial homologues, but it can be serially homologous with respect to its
components at a deeper level of the hierarchy.
29
Figure 3. A simplified illustration of a character tree for arthropod segments, shown here in Drosophila. The Segment
Polarity Network (SPN) is proposed as the ChIM shared by all trunk segments, with individual segmental identities
differentiating from these under the influence of Hox identity genes (Sex combs reduced for prothorax, Antennapedia
for mesothorax, Ultrabithorax for metathorax, and so on). The segments and the corresponding ChIMs both form a
paramorph hierarchy.
This hierarchical understanding of novelty differs from a common but mistaken assumption
that genuine novelty is absolute and requires non-homology with respect to all existing characters
and their components: “Do new anatomical structures arise de novo, or do they evolve from pre-
existing structures?” (Shubin et al., 2009, 818). Given the pervasiveness of gene co-option and re-
use of existing structures, it is not clear how many multicellular characters would satisfy this strict
understanding of novelty; in other words, we would expect that almost all novelty evolves from
summarized in Table 1 takes into account the hierarchical dimensions of homology and (therefore)
novelty. The question is not whether a novelty evolved from pre-existing structures; new
characters arise from pre-existing structures just as new species evolve from pre-existing species
by descent with modification. The relevant question is how. This mechanistic question involves
not only discerning whether the putatively new character is developmentally individualized at a
particular hierarchical level, but also assessing the status of the pre-existing structures and whether
30
they were replicas, homomorphs, or paramorphs at a particular hierarchical level. And,
importantly, “hierarchical level” needs to be understood in both space and time. The relevant pre-
existing structures from which a novelty evolved might be at a different spatial level of
organization (e.g., gene regulatory networks) or at a different temporal juncture in the ontogenetic
homologous with everything else, then nothing is an evolutionary novelty. Our hierarchical
account of serial homology and novelty escapes these untoward implications, grounds the basic
vocabulary and knowledge base of comparative biology, and facilitates new inquiry by permitting
a more fine-grained mapping of diverse trait-types discussed by biologists. Thus far, our theoretical
articulation has been relatively abstract with a few scattered illustrations from well-known
examples. These ideas about levels of organization, paramorph hierarchies, and evolutionary
novelty can be clarified and elaborated by sustained application to more detailed empirical case
studies.
Wings represent a major innovation of the insect body plan that likely contributed to the
exceptional success and diversity of winged insects (Grimaldi & Engel, 2005). Wings are thought
to be monophyletic, but their evolutionary origin has proved a difficult problem in part because of
the lack of transitional forms in the fossil record between non-winged and winged insects
(Grimaldi & Engel, 2005). This has encouraged studies of potential serial homologues of wings
(e.g., on wingless segments) as a source of clues about wing origins (Clark-Hachtel & Tomoyasu,
2016). It is now known that many genes from the canonical wing gene regulatory network that
31
were revealed from earlier studies of Drosophila—including the “master wing genes” vestigial
(vg), apterous (ap) and wingless (wg)—are expressed in multiple structures along the insect body
wall, including in ancestrally wingless insects, such as the bristletail Pedetontus unimaculatus
(Niwa et al., 2010). The observation of shared key regulators suggests that either the wing
originated by co-option or it possesses some underlying serial homology with other body wall
structures. In the latter case, wings would be derived branches in a paramorph hierarchy that
Historically there have been two competing serial homology hypotheses for wing origins
(Figure 4). The tergal origin hypothesis (also known as the paranotal hypothesis) holds that wings
are lateral extensions of the thoracic tergum, or dorsal body wall. The pleural origin hypothesis
holds that wings originated as outgrowths of the pleuron, or lateral body wall. More recently, some
authors have gathered compelling evidence for a dual origin hypothesis, which holds that wings
arose from fusion of both tergal and pleural source tissues (Clark-Hachtel & Tomoyasu, 2016;
Niwa et al., 2010). These hypotheses have different implications for serial homology between
wings and other body wall structures. If the tergal origin hypothesis is correct, then wings could
be serially homologous to specialized tergal outgrowths, such as beetle horns and the T1 carinated
margin. If the pleural origin hypothesis is correct, then wings would likely be serially homologous
with pleural outgrowths, such as lateral lobes or lateral sclerites. Under the dual origin hypothesis,
however, it is only the tergal source tissues of the wing that would be serially homologous to the
tergal outgrowths, while the pleural source tissues would be serially homologous to pleural
structures. By hypothesis, the tergal source tissues would be responsible for the flat wing blade,
whereas pleural plates with exite outgrowths would have provided a pre-existing articulation
mechanism and muscle attachment for the wing (Clark-Hachtel & Tomoyasu, 2016).
32
Figure 4. A basal wingless insect from the suborder Monura (order Archaeognatha), illustrating proposed source
tissues for wing origins. Modified and redrawn after (Kuklová-Peck, 1987).
This example highlights the need to clearly specify homology relations in terms of the
appropriate level of organization and paramorph hierarchy. If the dual origin hypothesis is right,
the wing is only “partially” serially homologous with tergal structures (and with pleural structures).
This does not mean that the homology relation itself is graded and partial, but rather that part of
one character (wing) is homologous to another character (tergal outgrowth). Likewise, the
conundrum of wing serial homology can be understood as a problem of determining what is the
basal character in the character phylogeny that includes wings. One recent theory combining
elements of pleural and tergal theories holds that insect wings derive from crustacean exites or
lateral lobes extending from proximal leg segments, which were incorporated into the body wall
in insects (Bruce & Patel, 2020). With exites as the basal character in the paramorph hierarchy,
many structures considered wing serial homologues, such as the larval gin trap and lateral lobes,
would be exite paramorphs (Bruce & Patel, 2020). Within that inclusive underlying homology,
however, these structures do not necessarily share more derived and specific character identities—
i.e., they are not wings. Thus, wings could still be novel characters, in the sense of novel
individualized branches in the character tree, relative to their branching from ancestral exite-like
structures, while still being serially homologous with other structures derived from exites.
33
Similarly, a recent dual-origin theory holds that wings and other body wall outgrowths are
patterning of cuticularized bilayered epithelia (Fisher et al., 2021). In this interpretation, the basal
character would be “bilayered epithelial outgrowths” and the associated ChIM would be the
ancestral regulatory network that patterns all such structures. Derived characters such as insect
wings, the diverse gills of crustaceans, mayflies, and chelicerates, treehopper helmets, abdominal
gin traps in beetle pupae, and other marginal outgrowths would be serially homologous (and likely
all paramorphic) as bilayered epithelial outgrowths, but would not necessarily share more derived
character identities (e.g., wings) (Fisher et al., 2021). An important question for evaluating this
(i.e., a character), rather than a character state or structure of some other character (see Section 3.2;
Table 1). A trait description like “bilayered epithelial outgrowth” would need to be traceable to a
monophyletic evolutionary origin. In addition, it is not clear that all wing serial homologues use
this module. Dipteran halteres are paramorphic with forewings but are not bilayered epithelia and
therefore cannot have a ChIM for that structure. In this case, “bilayered epithelial outgrowth”
might not be the most appropriate description for the basal character in the paramorph hierarchy.
These hypotheses illustrate how simple pairwise comparisons of structures will often be
inadequate to resolve serial homology relationships or determine whether the concept of serial
homology is applicable. For example, to determine whether treehopper helmets are novel or
serially homologous to wings (Kudla et al., 2022; Prud'homme et al., 2011), these structures must
be compared at the appropriate organizational level and, if they are homologous, assessed for
is possible that helmets are serially homologous to wings because they belong to an exite-derived
34
character family or the character family of some other basal character without helmets being wings.
Indeed, this seems to be the case (DiFrisco et al., 2022; Fisher et al., 2021). Thus, despite the name
“wing serial homologues,” which is commonly used to describe research in this area, wings are
evidently too derived to serve as the most evolutionarily informative character for defining the
character tree of pleural and tergal outgrowths. The name reflects the order of scientific discovery,
which started with developmental-genetic studies of Drosophila forewings, rather than the order
of evolutionary change. Accordingly, the more informative terminology would refer to the node
in the paramorph hierarchy that connects wings and helmets, if it exists: for instance, exite serial
homologues.
incomplete, as it is with insect wing origins. In this situation, an advantage of the hierarchical view
is that serial homology and novelty between any two structures can be established without a
helmets and wings, and the status of the helmet as a novelty, is consistent with their serial
with any and all existing characters, it would not only be exceedingly rare as a natural category
(see Section 4) but also something that could only be established empirically after the origins and
transformation series are fully known. Our proposed framework not only avoids this discouraging
implication but also connects the status of a character as a novelty or homology to underlying
developmental differences that are informative about the capacities of a character for quasi-
independent variation and evolutionary change. In this way, a hierarchical perspective on serial
homology and novelty is a more useful and inferentially rich framework that maximizes the
35
6. Paired Gnathostome Appendage Serial Homology
In recent years, Rui Diogo and collaborators have mounted a challenge to the concept of
serial homology (e.g., Miyashita & Diogo, 2016). This challenge concentrates on two prominent
hypotheses of serial homology in vertebrate anatomy: the mandibular arch as a serial homologue
of the pharyngeal arches (“gill arches”), and the serial homology of forelimbs and hindlimbs. Of
these two hypotheses, a particular popular scenario has been challenged for the question of the
origin of the mandibular arch. However, this does not affect the concept of serial homology as
such. In contrast, the case of tetrapod forelimbs and hindlimbs has been advanced as a direct
Diogo’s challenge to the serial homology of gnathostome paired appendages has two
aspects, one pertaining to general issues beyond the specific example and another pertaining to the
empirical evidence relevant to claims of serial homology between the pectoral and pelvic paired
appendages. Regarding the first aspect, there are three general issues: the relationship between
homology and similarity, the co-option of molecular mechanisms, and the relativity of homology
claims to a level of organization. We have already discussed the first at length (Section 3.1) and
therefore only reiterate that arguments against serial homology based on a lack of similarity fail
The second issue concerns how to assess the similarity of developmental mechanisms
among parts as evidence for or against serial homology. Miyashita and Diogo (2016) correctly
point out that some of the mechanisms underlying paired appendage bud development are shared
with other body appendages, and these have not been proposed as serial homologues to paired fins
and limbs (e.g., barbs in catfish, medial fins, and the amniote phallus). These mechanisms include
36
the role of Shh from the zone of polarizing activity in causing anterior-posterior polarity and
sustaining appendage bud outgrowth in conjunction with FGFs from the apical ectodermal ridge
(Zeller et al., 2009). The broad distribution of this regulatory module among diverse body parts
suggests it is a generic appendage outgrowth module rather than a ChIM. As we have argued
elsewhere (DiFrisco et al., 2022), mechanistic similarity in the development of different body parts
can occur for several reasons. The similarity could be due to (i) “plesiomorphic” features that
existed in body regions where the new structures are formed, (ii) co-option, or (iii) a transfer of
character identity (e.g., duplication, or homeotic transformation). Co-option refers to the situation
where parts of an existing gene regulatory network are recruited in order to perform a
(DiFrisco et al., 2022). Character duplication happens when the ChIM of one character is recruited
to be expressed in another part of the body and thus re-instantiates the character identity in a novel
location (DiFrisco et al., 2022). The latter would create a serial homologue by character
duplication. Consequently, the question of whether shared molecular mechanisms support the
hypothesis of serial homology between the pectoral and pelvic paired appendages depends on the
Paired appendage development is more complex than the Shh/Gli3/Fgf signaling module.
It also includes interactions between lateral plate mesoderm and both dorsal and ventral
compartments of the ectoderm, which help to endow the appendage bud with dorsal-ventral
polarity (Delgado & Torres, 2017). This does not exist in medial fins. To our knowledge, a putative
ChIM for paired appendage identity that distinguishes paired appendages from other body
outgrowths has not been established. By implication, no ChIM has been shown to be shared
between pectoral and pelvic appendages. Hence, assessing the claim of serial homology for paired
37
appendages in vertebrates is an outstanding research question rather than something already
established.
The third general issue is the relativity of homology claims to a level of organization. Given
that fins and limbs are complex, hierarchically structured body parts, it is necessary to explicitly
state which level or body part an assertion or denial of serial homology refers to. As our theoretical
articulation suggests (Section 4), it is possible that parts of limbs can be serially homologous,
whereas the pelvic and pectoral appendages themselves may not be serially homologous. For
example, body hair on the torso and legs can be the same, even though these body regions are not
serially homologous. This point is crucial to account for the otherwise puzzling fact that, after the
fin-limb transition, the forelimb and the hindlimb became more similar than the corresponding
Another aspect of this issue is whether the autopod (hand or feet) and the mesopodium
(wrist or ankle) of the tetrapod limb are novel. There is some developmental evidence suggesting
that the distal parts of the fin are already distinguished from the rest of the fin, reminiscent of
autopodium development (Letelier et al., 2021; Metscher et al., 2005; Nakamura et al., 2016).
Some interpret this as evidence that the autopod is not novel (Letelier et al., 2021), though there
remain differences that support an interpretation of its novelty (Wagner & Chiu, 2001). If an
autopodial developmental module already exists in pelvic and pectoral fins, then this would
suggest that they are serially homologous and the simultaneous transformation of the two
even if we assume that pectoral and pelvic fins are not serially homologous and the autopod is a
novelty, as Miyashito and Diogo (2016) do, the question remains whether the “autopod” units—
and not the appendage as a whole—are serially homologous. The similarity of gene regulatory
38
networks underlying autopod identity would support such a conclusion (Petit et al., 2017), as well
as the near simultaneous origination of autopodial structures in the forelimbs and hindlimbs of
stem tetrapods (Clack, 2002). Hence, serial homology may apply to some components of the paired
homologous.
The specific historical scenario for the origin of paired appendages remains contested.
There is agreement that the first paired appendages with endoskeleton were found in a group of
ostracoderms within the gnathostome stem lineage ~430 mya (Coates, 2003; Janvier, 1996, 2001;
the oldest group with two paired appendages. At face value, this is compatible with a duplication
event; for example, the pelvic paired appendage of crown-group gnathostomes could be a duplicate
of the pectoral appendage of ostracoderms. The fossil remains of pelvic appendages in basal
placoderms do not show much similarity with fossilized pectoral fins (Coates, 2003). However,
we do not have information about what the pelvic fins looked like shortly after their origin. Thus,
we do not know whether the morphological differences between pectoral and pelvic fins observed
in fossil remains are due to adaptive divergence or independent origin (i.e., non-homology).
However, we do know that the pelvic fin was initially much smaller than the pectoral fin and also
was repeatedly lost, as evidenced in specimens that lack pelvic fins but still have a pelvic girdle
(Zhu et al., 2012). It is thus not clear whether the pelvic fin performed an important function or
was just a rudimentary organ, one that may not have had a specific function immediately after
origination. We therefore conclude that existing paleontological evidence cannot resolve the issue
39
Despite the inability of paleontological evidence to decide the question of the origin of
pectoral and pelvic paired appendages, existing developmental evidence provides a plausible
scenario that supports serial homology of pectoral and pelvic fins. There are two developmental
differences that distinguish the body wall of lamprey, a cyclostome which never had paired
appendages, and extant gnathostomes with two pairs of fins or limbs. First, the posterior lateral
plate mesoderm of lamprey is not differentiated into splanchnic (visceral) and somatic (body wall)
layers, and the dorso-ventral compartment boundary in the ectoderm is located dorsally of the
lateral plate mesoderm (i.e., it faces the somites and not the lateral plate) (Tanaka & Onimaru,
2012). In contrast, the gnathostome paired fins and limbs derive from the somatic layer of the
lateral plate mesoderm and the identity of the somatic layer is considered essential for the
development of paired appendage bud mesoderm. Also, the appendage bud develops at the place
where the dorso-ventral compartment boundary is opposite the lateral plate. This boundary
becomes the apical ectodermal ridge, an essential signaling center for appendage bud development
and outgrowth. These facts and the plausible assumption that the differentiation of the lateral plate
mesoderm in stem gnathostomes proceeded from anterior to posterior is consistent with the fact
that paired appendages first appeared in the pectoral region and only later on the posterior body.
Importantly, this scenario does not address the question of why there are only two pairs of
appendages in gnathostomes.
Another interesting observation related to paired appendages is that the pectoral and the
pelvic appendages became more similar during the fin-limb transition than they were as fins
(Miyashita & Diogo, 2016; Roth, 1988). The distal parts of the limb (i.e., elements of the autopod)
are anatomically more similar between forelimb and hindlimb than the corresponding parts of the
pectoral and pelvic fins (Miyashita & Diogo, 2016). Additionally, the gene regulatory networks in
40
the distal parts of both forelimb and hindlimb are more similar to each other than what is found in
their proximal parts (Petit et al., 2017). Miyashito and Diogo (2016) interpret these facts as
showing that the forelimb and hindlimb are similar due to evolutionary convergence and therefore
should not be considered serial homologues. However, this conclusion is questionable for two
reasons. First, it depends on the notion that serial homology is similarity due to derivation from an
similarity but rather identity—in spite of differences in form and function. Second, the finding that
serially homologous characters can become more similar over evolutionary time relative to their
initial appearance should not be surprising. This would be expected if the characters are under
selection for a common function, such as locomotion. Moreover, if serial homologues possess
do not exhibit an evolutionary trend of initial similarity followed by later divergence, as Siomava
and colleagues (2020) show, the precise pattern of these trajectories does not establish or
undermine their status as serial homologues. In fact, most of the traits used to measure similarity
in this study are character states—shapes, sizes, and numbers of parts—rather than character
identities. The expectation that serial homologues should conform to a particular evolutionary
pattern (e.g., ancestral similarity [isomerism], derived dissimilarity [anisomerism]) only makes
sense if homology is understood as similarity due to common descent (Mayr, 1969, see above,
41
7. The Value of Theoretical Articulation: Beyond Serial Homology
Toward the end of the 19th century, Ray Lankester reflected on the impact of Owen’s
It is not easy to exaggerate the service rendered by Owen to the study of zoology by the introduction
of this apparently small piece of verbal mechanism; …And, though the conceptions of “archetypal
morphology,” to which it had reference, are now abandoned in favour of a genetic morphology, yet
we should remember, in estimating the value of this and of other speculations which have given
place to new views in the history of science” (Lankester, 1888, 808).
The ability to simultaneously recognize Owen’s achievement in the midst of his error is significant.
This tells us something important about good working concepts in the sciences. One of their chief
assets is fruitfulness, the capacity to engender new forms of scientific inference or research,
especially in the context of new empirical discoveries that disrupt current biological understanding.
Concepts can accomplish this despite not being fully adequate or having aspects that require
further modification. Owen’s categories of special, serial, and general homology exemplify this
biology.
The pervasiveness of gene sharing in evolution (Piatigorsky, 2007) and the increasing
discovery of so-called deep homology across the tree of life (Shubin et al., 1997) disrupted
The remarkable similarity of the genetic regulation of development in distant organisms has
heralded a new conception of evolution. It was a big surprise when evolutionary conservation of
the Krebs cycle, the genetic code, and classes of structural proteins was extended to regulation of
development. The diversity of organisms had fooled everyone into thinking that the evolution of
completely different regulatory processes, or at least completely different uses of the same genes,
was likely to be responsible for evolutionary change (Scott, 2000, 33).
This disruption generates an unresolved conceptual problem: Given the fact of common descent,
why is everything not homologous with everything else? Since most characters exhibit genetic and
42
between homology and non-homology seems threatened. This threat calls into question a large
range of comparative morphological knowledge and makes it difficult to ascertain the origin of
quickly see the difficulty (Section 3). It is a stopping point of inquiry; it does not enable further
biological realism, also diminishes the fruitfulness of general comparative reasoning and
hypothesis-generation based on homology. To address the problem that arises from the conceptual
form of theoretical articulation is necessary. Herein we used successful patterns of reasoning that
have coalesced in talking about homology at the level of gene sequence in combination with
important desiderata (e.g., homologues must form equivalence classes and therefore involve
a five-fold theoretical classification (Section 3.3, Table 1). Our proposal was grounded in earlier
work that elucidates what it means for a part to have identity as a biological character (DiFrisco et
al., 2020) and is amply illustrated by findings over the past decade in studies of the origin and
evolution of cell types (Arendt et al., 2016). This theoretical elaboration meets the criterion of
fruitfulness and offers biologists a richer and more precise vocabulary, opening new avenues of
inquiry on recalcitrant questions about insect wing serial homologues and vertebrate paired
appendages. More generally, it is especially helpful for comparative analyses focused on the origin
the identification of novelty as such does not demand a complete knowledge of precursors or a
43
step-by-step transformation series. Thus, this understanding of novelty can fruitfully guide
research as it proceeds rather than being only applicable when empirical matters are fully resolved.
questions where further empirical and conceptual work are needed. For example, the concept of a
“character swarm” picks out a phenomenon that appears to fall between homomorphs and
features that are sufficiently individualized to take on distinct identities and functions in the head,
wing, and tail locations on birds. However, they retain a tendency to vary as a unit independent of
their positional indexing and thereby evolve in concert, which seems to clash with their purported
one feather tract, such as coloration in wing feathers used in mating displays, also appears in low
frequency in other feather tracts where this function is irrelevant. Feather tracts appear to hover
between distinct, individualized character identities and a single, globally coordinated character
proposed theoretical articulation surrounding serial homology offered here. As we have argued
engineering (Brigandt, 2011; Wilson, 2018; Wimsatt, 2007), which is applied to evolved, complex
systems whose history is often inaccessible. Therefore, variation and exceptions are expected. To
understand these systems, scientists must adopt strategies and heuristics that yield partial models
the goal of generating theoretical understanding that exhibits fruitfulness for future research. Our
proposed re-engineering of serial homology works toward this goal by accounting for why
44
everything is not homologous to everything else and why there is no contradiction in saying that
genuine novelty has evolved at different levels of organization out of a variety of precursors in the
history of life.
45
Bibliography
Abouheif, E. (1999). Establishing homology criteria for regulatory gene networks: prospects and
challenges. In G. R. Bock & G. Cardew (Eds.), Homology (pp. 207–225). Chichester: John
Wiley & Sons.
Abouheif, E. (2021). Ant caste evo-devo: it’s not all about size. Trends in Ecology & Evolution,
36, 668–670.
Arendt, D. (2008). The evolution of cell types in animals: emerging principles from molecular
studies. Nature Reviews Genetics, 9, 868–882.
Arendt, D., Bertucci, P. Y., Achim, K., & Musser, J. M. (2019). Evolution of neuronal types and
families. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 56, 144–152.
Arendt, D., Musser, J. M., Baker, C. V. H., Bergman, A., Cepko, C., Erwin, D. H., . . . Wagner, G.
P. (2016). The origin and evolution of cell types. Nature Reviews Genetics, 17, 744–757.
Blackburn, D. G. (1991). Evolutionary origins of the mammary gland. Mammal Review, 21, 81–
96.
Brigandt, I. (2011). Natural kinds and concepts: A pragmatist and methodologically naturalistic
account. In J. Knowles & H. Rydenfelt (Eds.), Pragmatism, Science and Naturalism (pp.
171–196). Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Brigandt, I., & Love, A. C. (2012). Conceptualizing evolutionary novelty: Moving beyond
definitional debates. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol Dev Evol), 318B, 417–427.
Brooks, D. S., DiFrisco, J., & Wimsatt, W. C. (Eds.). (2021). Levels of Organization in the
Biological Sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Bruce, H. S., & Patel, N. H. (2020). Knockout of crustacean leg patterning genes suggests that
insect wings and body walls evolved from ancient leg segments. Nature Ecology &
Evolution, 4, 1703–1712.
Buchmann, K. (2014). Evolution of Innate Immunity: Clues from Invertebrates via Fish to
Mammals. Front Immunol, 5, 459.
Clack, J. A. (2002). Gaining Ground: The Origin and Evolution of Tetrapods. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Clark-Hachtel, C. M., & Tomoyasu, Y. (2016). Exploring the origin of insect wings from an evo-
devo perspective. Current Opinion in Insect Science, 13, 77–85.
46
Coates, M. I. (2003). The Evolution of Paired Fins. Theory in Biosciences, 122, 266–287.
de Pinna, M. C. C. (1991). Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics,
7, 367–394.
Delgado, I., & Torres, M. (2017). Coordination of limb development by crosstalk among axial
patterning pathways. Developmental Biology, 429, 382–386.
DiFrisco, J., Love, A. C., & Wagner, G. P. (2020). Character identity mechanisms: a conceptual
model for comparative-mechanistic biology. Biology & Philosophy, 35, 44.
DiFrisco, J., & Wagner, G. P. (2022). Body Plan Identity: A Mechanistic Model. Evolutionary
Biology, 49, 123–141.
DiFrisco, J., Wagner, G. P., & Love, A. C. (2022). Reframing research on evolutionary novelty
and co-option: character identity mechanisms versus deep homology. Seminars in Cell &
Developmental Biology.
Fisher, C. R., Kratovil, J. D., Angelini, D. R., & Jockusch, E. L. (2021). Out from under the wing:
reconceptualizing the insect wing gene regulatory network as a versatile, general module
for body-wall lobes in arthropods. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences,
288, 20211808.
Ganley, A. R. D., & Kobayashi, T. (2007). Highly efficient concerted evolution in the ribosomal
DNA repeats: Total rDNA repeat variation revealed by whole-genome shotgun sequence
data. Genome Research, 17, 184–191.
Gehring, W. J. (1998). Master Control Genes in Development and Evolution: The Homeobox
Story. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Grimaldi, D., & Engel, M. S. (2005). Evolution of the Insects. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Haag, E. S. (2014). The same but different: worms reveal the pervasiveness of developmental
system drift. PLoS Genet, 10, e1004150.
47
Haag, E. S., & True, J. R. (2021). Developmental system drift. In L. Nuño de la Rosa & G. B.
Müller (Eds.), Evolutionary Developmental Biology: A Reference Guide (pp. 99–110).
Cham: Springer International Publishing.
Hall, B. K. (2003). Descent with modification: the unity underlying homology and homoplasy as
seen through an analysis of development and evolution. Biological Reviews of the
Cambridge Philosophical Society, 78, 409–433.
Hall, B. K. (Ed.) (1994). Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative Biology: Academic
Press.
Hartenstein, V., & Martinez, P. (2019). Phagocytosis in cellular defense and nutrition: a food-
centered approach to the evolution of macrophages. Cell and Tissue Research, 377, 527–
547.
Harvey, P. H., & Pagel, M. D. (1991). The Comparative Method in Evolutionary Biology. Oxford
& NY: Oxford University Press.
Hughes, C. L., & Kaufman, T. C. (2002). Exploring the myriapod body plan: expression patterns
of the ten Hox genes in a centipede. Development, 129, 1225–1238.
Janvier, P. (2001). Ostracoderms and the shaping of the gnathostome characters. In P. E. Ahlberg
(Ed.), Major Events in Early Vertebrate Evolution: Palaeontology, Phylogeny, Genetics
and Development (pp. 172–186). London and New York: Taylor and Francis.
Kudla, A. M., Miranda, X., & Nijhout, H. F. (2022). The roles of growth regulation and appendage
patterning genes in the morphogenesis of treehopper pronota. Proceedings of the Royal
Society B: Biological Sciences, 289, 20212682.
Kuklová-Peck, J. (1987). New Carboniferous Diplura, Monura, and Thysanura, the hexapod
ground plan, and the role of thoracic side lobes in the origin of wings (Insecta). Canadian
Journal of Zoology, 65, 2327–2345.
Lankester, E. R. (1870). On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction
between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Annals and Magazine of Natural
History, 6, 34–43.
Letelier, J., Naranjo, S., Sospedra-Arrufat, I., Martinez-Morales, J. R., Lopez-Rios, J., Shubin, N.,
& Gómez-Skarmeta, J. L. (2021). The Shh/Gli3 gene regulatory network precedes the
origin of paired fins and reveals the deep homology between distal fins and digits.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 118, e2100575118.
48
Lev, O., & Chipman, A. D. (2021). Development of the pre-gnathal segments in the milkweed bug
Oncopeltus fasciatus suggests they are not serial homologs of trunk segments. Frontiers in
Cell and Developmental Biology, 9, 695135.
Lev, O., Edgecombe, G. D., & Chipman, A. D. (2022). Serial Homology and Segment Identity in
the Arthropod Head. Integrative Organismal Biology, 4, obac015.
Love, A. C. (2006). Evolutionary morphology and evo-devo: Hierarchy and novelty. Theory in
Biosciences, 124, 317–333.
Love, A. C. (2007). Functional homology and homology of function: biological concepts and
philosophical consequences. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 691–708.
Metscher, B. D., Takahashi, K., Crow, K., Amemiya, C., Nonaka, D. F., & Wagner, G. P. (2005).
Expression of Hoxa-11 and Hoxa-13 in the pectoral fin of a basal ray-finned fish, Polyodon
spathula: implications for the origin of tetrapod limbs. Evolution & Development, 7, 186–
195.
Minelli, A. (2000). Limbs and tail as evolutionarily diverging duplicates of the main body axis.
Evolution & Development, 2, 157–165.
Minelli, A. (2002). Homology, limbs, and genitalia. Evolution & Development, 4, 127–132.
Minelli, A., & Fusco, G. (2013). Homology. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The Philosophy of Biology:
A Companion for Educators (pp. 289–322). Dordrecht: Springer.
Minelli, A., & Perfuffo, B. (1991). Developmental pathways, homology and homonomy in
metameric animals. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 3, 429–445.
Miyashita, T., & Diogo, R. (2016). Evolution of serial patterns in the vertebrate pharyngeal
apparatus and paired appendages via assimilation of dissimilar units. Frontiers in Ecology
and Evolution, 4.
49
Müller, G. B. (2003). Homology: The evolution of morphological organization. In G. B. Müller &
S. A. Newman (Eds.), Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in
Developmental and Evolutionary Biology (pp. 51–69). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Müller, G. B., & Wagner, G. P. (1991). Novelty in evolution: restructuring the concept. Annual
Review of Ecology and Systematics, 22, 229–256.
Nakamura, T., Gehrke, A. R., Lemberg, J., Szymaszek, J., & Shubin, N. H. (2016). Digits and fin
rays share common developmental histories. Nature, 537, 225–228.
Niwa, N., Akimoto-Kato, A., Niimi, T., Tojo, K., Machida, R., & Hayashi, S. (2010). Evolutionary
origin of the insect wing via integration of two developmental modules. Evolution &
Development, 12, 168–176.
Novick, A. (2018). The fine structure of ‘homology’. Biology & Philosophy, 33, 6.
Oftedal, O. T. (2002). The mammary gland and its origin during synapsid evolution. Journal of
Mammary Gland Biology and Neoplasia, 7(3), 225–252.
Okabe, Y., & Medzhitov, R. (2016). Tissue biology perspective on macrophages. Nature
Immunology, 17, 9–17.
Owen, R. (1843). Lectures on the Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Invertebrate
Animals. London: Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans.
Owen, R. (1848). On the Archetype and Homologies of the Vertebrate Skeleton. London: John van
Voorst.
Patterson, C. (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: K. A. Joysey & A. E. Friday
(Eds.), Problems in Phylogenetic Reconstruction (pp. 21-74). London: Academic Press.
Pavlicev, M., Herdina, A. N., & Wagner, G. (2022). Female genital variation far exceeds that of
male genitalia: a review of comparative anatomy of clitoris and the female lower
reproductive tract in Theria. Integrative and Comparative Biology, icac026.
Petit, F., Sears, K. E., & Ahituv, N. (2017). Limb development: a paradigm of gene regulation.
Nat Rev Genet, 18, 245–258.
Piatigorsky, J. (2007). Gene Sharing and Evolution: The Diversity of Protein Functions.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Prince, V. E., & Pickett, F. B. (2002). Splitting pairs: the diverging fates of duplicated genes.
Nature Reviews Genetics, 3, 827–837.
50
Prud'homme, B., Minervino, C., Hocine, M., Cande, J. D., Aouane, A., Dufour, H. D., . . . Gompel,
N. (2011). Body plan innovation in treehoppers through the evolution of an extra wing-like
appendage. Nature, 473, 83–86.
Ralevski, A., Apelt, F., Olas, J. J., Mueller-Roeber, B., Rugarli, E. I., Kragler, F., & Horvath, T.
L. (2022). Plant mitochondrial FMT and its mammalian homolog CLUH controls
development and behavior in Arabidopsis and locomotion in mice. Cellular and Molecular
Life Sciences, 79, 334.
Roth, V. L. (1984). On homology. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 22, 13–29.
Roth, V. L. (1988). The biological basis of homology. In C. J. Humphries (Ed.), Ontogeny and
Systematics (pp. 1–26). New York: Columbia University Press.
Sattler, R. (1994). Homology, homeosis and process morphology in plants. In Homology: The
Hierachical Basis of Comparative Biology. B.K Hall (ed) Academic Press (pp. 423–475).
Schmitt, S. (2017). Serial homology as a challenge to evolutionary theory — the repeated parts of
organisms from idealistic morphology to evodevo. In P. Huneman & D. M. Walsh (Eds.),
Challenging the Modern Synthesis (pp. 317–347). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Scott, M. P. (2000). Development: the natural history of genes. Cell, 100, 27–40.
Shubin, N., Tabin, C., & Carroll, S. B. (2009). Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary
novelty. Nature, 457, 818–823.
Shubin, N., Tabin, C., & Carroll, S. B. (1997). Fossils, Genes and the Evolution of Animal Limbs.
Nature, 388, 639–648.
Shubin, N., & Wake, D. (1996). Phylogeny, variation, and morphological integration. American
Zoologist, 36, 51–60.
Simpson, G. G. (1961). Principles of Animal Taxonomy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Siomava, N., Fuentes, J. S. M., & Diogo, R. (2020). Deconstructing the long-standing a priori
assumption that serial homology generally involves ancestral similarity followed by
anatomical divergence. Journal of Morphology, 281, 1110–1132.
Spemann, H. (1915). Zur Geschichte und Kritik des Begriffs der Homologie. In C. Chun & W.
Johannsen (Eds.), Allgemeine Biologie (Vol. 3.4, pp. 163–185). Leipzig und Berlin: B.G.
Teubner.
Sterner, B., & Lidgard, S. (2014). The normative structure of mathematization in systematic
biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 46, 44–
54.
51
Stewart, T. A., Liang, C., Cotney, J. L., Noonan, J. P., Sanger, T. J., & Wagner, G. P. (2019).
Evidence against tetrapod-wide digit identities and for a limited frame shift in bird wings.
Nature Communications, 10, 3244.
Tanaka, M., & Onimaru, K. (2012). Acquisition of the paired fins: a view from the sequential
evolution of the lateral plate mesoderm. Evolution & Development, 14, 412–420.
Wagner, G. P. (2007). The developmental genetics of homology. Nat Rev Genet, 8, 473–479.
Wagner, G. P. (2014). Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Wagner, G. P., & Chiu, C. H. (2001). The tetrapod limb: A hypothesis on its origin. Journal of
Experimental Zoology, 291, 226–240.
Wilson, M. (2018). Physics Avoidance: Essays in Conceptual Strategy. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Wilson, M. V. H., Hanke, G. F., & Märss, T. (2007). Paired fins of jawless vertebrates and their
homologies across the agnathan–gnathostome transition. In J. S. Anderson & H. D. Sues
(Eds.), Major Transitions in Vertebrate Evolution (pp. 122–149). Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Zeller, R., Lopez-Rios, J., & Zuniga, A. (2009). Vertebrate limb bud development: moving
towards integrative analysis of organogenesis. Nature Reviews Genetics, 10, 845–858.
Zhu, M., Yu, X., Choo, B., Wang, J., & Jia, L. (2012). An antiarch placoderm shows that pelvic
girdles arose at the root of jawed vertebrates. Biology Letters, 8, 453–456.
Zimmer, E. A., Martin, S. L., Beverley, S. M., Kan, Y. W., & Wilson, A. C. (1980). Rapid
duplication and loss of genes coding for the alpha chains of hemoglobin. Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences USA, 77, 2158–2162.
52