Hannah Arendt S Book On Totalitarianism Within The Context of The Contemporary Debate
Hannah Arendt S Book On Totalitarianism Within The Context of The Contemporary Debate
Hannah Arendt S Book On Totalitarianism Within The Context of The Contemporary Debate
The fact that Hannah Arendt´s “The Origins of Totalitarianism” – thus the title
of the first publication of 19511 - constitutes one of the most influential
intellectual products of the early twenty-first century hardly needs proof. Is
there any other academic work able to provoke a whole series of conferences
on the occasion of its fiftieth birthday?2 Furthermore, it is not to be expected
that the wave of works and debates on Hannah Arendt, that has more or less
swept over the Western democracies since the break-down of the Communist
empire, will come to a standstill. Neither have the problems of transition been
solved, which the post-Communist states are facing and which form the actual
“kairos” (Karl Jaspers) of the revived interest in Hannah Arendt, nor will they
decrease due to the fact that these states will soon become members of the
European Union.
If, thus, a book by no means easy to read has not only remained in the fore,
despite having had to pass several rather steep cliffs of both political and
scientific critique, but has even become quite popular, then a renewed reading
is facing the reverse danger: i.e. the threat that it will reproduce merely that
which is already well known, a clichee ossified in the history of the work´s
reception and impact.
A curiositiy sprung from the modern twilight of science and politics, it has
become a unique specimen: a “modern classic of political thought”. The
ambivalent consequences of this canonization are evident in the astonishing
revitalization of the debate on totalitarianism after 1989. Hannah Arendt is
present throughout the entire debate, but while she hardly intervenes in the
primarily technical argumentation in Germany, we find the opposite trend in
France; there, the discourse on totalitarianism appears to be almost
1
...
2
From the point of view of its impact, it has probably outrun the „other“ philosophical classic of emigration
(Horkheimer/Adorno 1947).
2
4
The results of research on emigration are presented in a concise summary in Krohn (1998).
4
This list of authors will hardly meet with objection if one admits to its need for
completion and to the special position of Carl J. Friedrich. Doubtless, these
books represent milestones not only of political-scientific emigration, but also
of the historical sequence of both fields of discourse we are concerned with:
the early theory of National Socialism and fascism, on the one hand, and the
later culminating theory of totalitarianism, on the other. A second objection
referring to the factual context and the communicative density of the context
5
This finding is remarkable. Yet, first of all it only shows that there existed a
normal scientific community among the emigrants, too; i.e., the reciprocal
perception was also determined by theoretical differences, political barriers,
and even by personal animosities. If one assumes the reverse, however, and
there are good reasons for doing so, namely that the pressure caused by the
need for acculturation and for survival resulted in a particularly high degree
of political self-stylization or theoretical obstinacy, then one shouldn´t be
astonished by the remarkable communalities which existed despite
communication barriers.
So, how can the position and the importance of Hannah Arendt´s book on
totalitarianism, which overnight made a celebrity of her, be sketched within
the framework of the often critical, sometimes taciturn, yet all in all
6
tableau from which the heroine of that modern age, the “female genius”, rises
(thus in Kristeva 2001: 167-270).
5
Typical of this genre is the form of the political pamphlet, books are rather the exception: for the social-democratic
left cf. e.g. Heller (1929). At the other end of the democratic spectrum we often find sympathy with the new regimes
(cf. e.g. Leibholz 1933).
8
Perhaps it would be easiest to graps the characteristic traits of that book which
was published in the United States in 1941 under the title of “The Dual State”
by calling to mind the highly memorable history of its emergence: Ernst
Fraenkel, who had worked as union jurist, had collected the material while
still working as lawyer (although that work was already severely impeded)
and had had to smuggle the manuscript out of Germany before he himself
managed to flee from the Nazi henchmen in 1938.7
This finds more or less direct expression in the theoretical construction of the
“Dual State”: Fraenkel concentrates on the changes of the juridical theory and
practice since 1933 and posits the thesis that the development in Nazi-
Germany was characterized by the coexistence of two contradictory legal
systems: the “measure state” on the one hand, which dissolves step by step the
old legal structures and guarantees, and the “norm state” on the other, which
is on the retreat and the function of which is finally reduced to keeping up the
capitalist production and to orientate it towards arms production.8 The
National Socialist movement has consolidated itself and is firmly in the saddle
of political power, because it has successfully removed constitutional and legal
barriers limiting police power and other institutional power and has brought
jurisdiction under its control. It has rid itself of its enemies by means of direct
force, shattered the autonomy of the social groups and enforced the
gleichschaltung of society; furthermore, it has used the perversion of the legal
and administrative guarantees for turning rascist propaganda into reality, i.e.
for robbing the minorities discriminated against, especially the Jews, of their
legal and social position (cf. esp. Fraenkel 1999b:53-155).
6
Other examples from the same period, which can however not be analyzed here, are: Loewenstein (1939) and
Ebenstein (1943). Almost every emigré political scientist has at one stage written at least one essay against Hitler!
7
The emergence of the dual state is now documented in detail (by Brünneck 1999:7-32).
8
While this thesis of political science is itself retained, its class-theoretical foundation is weakened on the way from
the German „primary dual state“ (Fraenkel 1999a) to the American „Dual State“ (Fraenkel 1941).
9
The most humiliating aspect of this analysis, however, was that proof which,
for a university-educated and committed jurist, must have been the most
painful,- a proof for which Fraenkel, however, gave minute evidence: namely,
that quite a large number of the juridical elites and authorities who had been
brought up in the tradition of positivism and who had practiced their belief in
legality during the Weimar Republic, worked in the service of the state of
injustice or had even before been active as anti-democratic writers and had
used jurisprudence to delegitimize the democratic order.
The prime example for this is the constitutional jurist Carl Schmitt, who is
presented by Fraenkel as one of those who helped the National Socialists to
come to power and, at the same time, as the most astute mentor of the
National Socialist conception of politics. The anti-Semitic racial policy of the
national state, thus Fraenkel summarizes his line of reasoning, is nothing but
the translation into practice of Schmitt´s theory of the political enemy. All
these perversions, however, were only made possible by the long effective loss
of the tradition of rational natural law, of the legal guarantees and of the
corresponding concepts of the inalienable rights of man – the programmatic
anti-liberalism of the National Socialist ideologists was, from this point of
view, merely a final, gruesome disillusionment.9
Institute of Social Research, which had had to emigrate too, and within the
framework of the research carried out there, he managed to strengthen a
modified Marxism.
While these were the decisive factors as regards the history of science, the
publication of the “Behemoth” was also an important event from the political
point of view because it analyzed the inner structure of National Socialism at a
time when the United States decided to enter the war against the Axis powers
and when everything depended upon revealing in its entirety the aggressive
dynamism and the destructive potential of the enemy they had to overcome.
Starting from an intensive and self-critical depiction of the Weimar Republic,
Neumann was so convincing in his attempt that, even today, the “Behemoth”
is still considered the first comprehensive interpretation of National Socialism,
which, since then, quite a large number of researchers on contemporary
history have taken as benchmark for their own work.10 Three large
argumentative steps have to be differentiated:
10
I quote from the German translation of the second edition of 1944 (Neumann 1977). On the origins/emergence of the
Behemoth cf. Gert Schäfer (1977: 633-776).
11
11
The pertinent chapters III-VI of the first part (Neumann 1977:114-268) have long been overlooked in the economist
interpretation of the Behemoth.
12
Accordingly, the two chapters on monopoly economy (Neumann 1977: 307-347) and command economy (Neumann
1977: 348-422) remain integral parts of the overall thesis of „totalitarian monopoly capitalism“.
12
The third part of the “Behemoth” spells out what this means sociologically
and, to this end, develops a combined theory of classes and elites, which later
became known as the “polycratic theory”: according to Neumann, a new and
sharply defined structure of power has emerged in Germany, which was
pushed through by direct violence and could only be maintained by
aggressive means, by using terror and propaganda. Still, the ruling class
appears not so much as a unified formation but, rather, as a wild
conglomeration of political, social, and economic “lumps of power”, whose
interest-related rivalry is hardly concealed by the national ideology, which in
turn is without concrete shape, – the ruling powers concur only in their
relentless use of violence both inwards and outwards (Neumann 1977: 423-
463).
The mass of the population is powerless and helpless in the face of the four
organizational pillars of the National Socialist regime: Neumann differentiates
between party, ministerial beaurocracy, army, and economic leadership. Just
as the suppression of the democratic institutions lead to the destruction of
autonomous social milieus in Germany, thus the working class, which had still
13
been the strongest political force in the Weimar Republic, now is at the mercy
of the direct dictate of the capital and of the authoritarian state beaurocracy,–
compulsory organizations such as the “Deutsche Arbeiterfront” (the German
workers´ front), which had been newly created by National Socialism, are
merely a glistening faade behind which reductions in wage levels and slavery
take place.13
In the following sketch of the theory of totalitarianism I will commit a faux pas
a historian could normally not afford. I will try to characterize the well-known
concept of totalitarianism by reversing to some degree the diachronic principle
and by questioning the canonical finalization of the theoretical development.
While it is a commonplace in the history of the concept of totalitarianism that
its both temporal and factual point of culmination lies in the 1950s and that its
13
Being a former union lawyer, this aspect was of special interest to Neumann (cf. esp. Neumann 1977:464-530).
14
Contrary to the debate on fascism, we are relatively well informed about the
history of the emergence of the conept of totalitarianism, which extends from
the liberal opponents of Mussolini-fascism in the 1920s to a small number of
mostly conservative emigrants such as Waldemar Gurian and Eric Voegelin in
the 1930s and which, in the first years of the Second World War, became a
topos also of the leftist liberal and social democratic emigration. Characteristic
of the latter group are, for instance, the publications of the former Communist
Franz Borkenau, who, however, hardly gets beyond a crude, mainly politically
intended equation of “red fascism” and “Nazi Bolshevism”.14
14
Franz Borkenau has written a number of books in exile in England. The best known is: The Totalitarian Enemy
(1940). The social democratic context is conprehensively analyzed by William David Jones (1999).
15
It is interesting that a description such as the one by Abbot Gleason (1995), which is not interested in the history of
theory, remains free of this finalization.
15
It is only on the basis of three case studies illustrating the different starting
positions, that he develops in a second step - which could by called historical-
inductive - a set of five problem areas to which totalitarian regimes react with
16
In the following, I quote from the second edition edited by Hans Krohn (Neumann 1965), which contains an
extended bibliography.
16
Still, at the end it is the common factors which culminate,as it were, and the
careful synthesis of which gives a clear outline to the concept of totalitarian
regime. In this respect it is noteworthy that Neumann does not restrict himself
to the three contemporary totalitarianism “candidates”, to Italy, Germany, and
Russia, but that he also includes the Western democracies in his comparison –
a specific method which he calls “definition by contrast” (Neumann 1965: 44-
45). For the inner structure of totalitarian regimes the following aspects are of
outstanding importance: the installation of the leadership principle, which,
however, is not conceived as purely monocratic but, rather, implies the strong
participation of a group executing power which Neumann refers to as
“political lieutenants”. These are facing a more or less amorphous mass which
is a daughter product of the dissolving bourgeois society and is socio-
psychologically described as “mob” (cf. Neumann 1965: 73-95).
The institutional centre of the totalitarian regime is the “One Party State”,
which, on the one hand, produces the political elite and, on the other, educates
and controls the masses, thus establishing the communication between state
and society (Neumann 1965: 118-141). While the institutional maintenance of
rule also uses thoroughly conventional means such as plebiscitarian will
formation and bureaucratization, as well as militarization and state control
over education, the specific quality of the technique of totalitarian leadership
lies in the use of “fear as political weapon”, including the increasingly effective
17
The curve described by this analysis closes in view of the war of aggression
started by Hitler and initially tolerated by Stalin, but only up to the point
when the Soviet Union joined the other side and became itself a hostile war
party. This movement, meant to be of duration, - the “permanent revolution” -
was in a regime-specific state of tension which would lead with inner necessity
to an “international total war”, as is shown by Neumann in the final chapter
(Neumann 1965: 230-310) – in the year 1942, mark you. This contemporary
signal ought to be be the starting point for a comprehensive reflection on the
contradictions and anachronisms of which political emigration abounds.
If one risks jumping from here right into the middle of the 1950s, looking at
Friedrich´s and Brzeszinski´s book on totalitarianism (Friedrich/Brzezinski
1956)17 from the perspective of the crunch question of the analysis of
totalitarianism, so vividly formulated by Sigmund Neumann, i.e. the question
of the methodological feasability of a systems comparison, the question is
raised which changes reveal themselves and how they are linked to the
pretension of “scientification” radiating from political science, in particular, to
17
I here quote from the German translation, for which Friedrich alone signed responsible (Friedrich 1957).
18
The answer to these questions is rather obvious; one simply has to look at the
much greater amount of historical and empirical material on which the
authors of the mid-1950s could draw. This does not only refer to the largely
increased flood of sources, documents, and analyses of National Socialism, but
even more so to the greater distance which it was possible to keep to the
developments in the Soviet bloc after Stalin´s death and following the
disclosures of the twentieth party convention. To this must be added the fact
that Brzezinski was an expert on Russian dominated societies, a renowned
Sovietologist. Yet, can the same positive assessment simply be transferred to
the subtlety of the theoretical construction and to the methodological
procedure of the analysis of totalitarianism?
I cannot answer this question in detail, here18, but I would like to at least
scratch at the smooth surface of this classic of political science by sketching the
following three reflections:
The first of these considerations refers to the status of the six “general
characteristics” of totalitarian regimes which, as is well known, are listed
bright and cheerfully right at the beginning of the book, in its introduction
(Friedrich 1957:13-23), but which do not really explain how they can form the
basis for the type of totalitarian dictatorship, also because, simultaneously, the
thesis is supported that the totalitarian form of rule is a regime type sui
generis and represents a true historical novelty.
The second consideration is linked to the first, but refers more to the
theoretical and empirical justification of the assumption of monopolization as
it is evident, first, in the leading role of the united party, later becoming over-
dominant in the final three systems characteristics (communications
18
A comprehensive answer is given in the historical work by Hans J. Lietzmann (1999).
19
19
It is no accident that the momentous updatings of the concept of totalitarianism are connected with the withdrawal of
the technicist ideal of knowledge. Thus in Hans Maier (1996/7; cf. also Siegel 1997).
20
surprise coup which compels one to draw conclusions about the author and
the subject!20
Thus, the dry scenario of the history of science and of political theory would
have to be dramaturgically rebuilt, e.g., as follows: what is being played is a
scene from American intellectual life of the early 1950s; the scenery consists,
on the one side, of the huge massif composed of the theories of fascism and
National Socialism, which had progressed from juridical analysis to social
theory and in which the totalitarian system of rule appeared as a functional
component of a machine, orientated to war and destruction, which could only
be overpowered by military means. On the other side, we have the open plain
of the debate on totalitarianism, to which new political life had been brought
by the ideological needs of the Cold War, but which was tied to the
imperatives of scientification by both the comparative perspective and the
integration into the development of political science as a discipline.21
In what consisted the shock effects when, suddenly, a more or less unknown
New York essayist entered the scene with a book which joined – as it were,
from the ambush of far-away socio-historical studies on Europe during the 19th
century – a debate which was politically just as explosive as it was
theoretically undecided? I would like to distinguish three of these shock
effects:
20
That insight has to do with the “breaking up of the historical continuum” was one of the basic maxims of Walter
Benjamin, with whom Hannah Arendt was well acquainted in Paris during the 1930s.
21
On the rank of the theory of totalitarianism in the context of the Cold War cf. Abbott (1995); on the development of
the discipline of American political science cf. Raymond Seidelman (1985).
22
E.g. by the historian Carlton J.H. Hayes (1940) at the conference “The Novelty of Totalitariansim in the History of
Western Civilization (1939), Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society (82).
21
for – given extraordinary sharpness and pith to this assertion, thus necessarily
attracting attention: in her argumentation, totalitarianism appeared as
something “completely new” in the history of mankind, even as an outrageous
and shocking phenomenon which did by no means allow for historical or
scientific detachment. However, her thesis was turned into a downright
provocation only through two complications, which were connected with the
peculiar construction of the book itself and which unexpectedly turned a
gesture of disarming naivety into an attack on the foundations of the
established historical and social sciences.
23
An attempt in that direction is made by Seyla Benhabib (1998; 111ff); a critical position is now taken by Richard
Wolin (2001: 31-69).
22
that investigation would be the text ”Ideologie und Terror” (“Ideology and
Terror”), written in 1953 for the Jasper-festschrift, which later replaced the
final chapter of the first American edition. This most frequently quoted text,
however, also reveals a reverse movement, suggesting that Hannah Arendt
wanted to dam again and re-integrate into the history of ideas the
unprecedented fright she had caused with her book.
Thus, this text features formulations such as: “Das Entsetzen gilt nicht dem
neuen schlechthin, sondern der Tatsache, dass dies Neue den
Kontinuitätszusammenhang unserer Geschichte und die Begriffe und Kategorien
unseres politischen Denkens sprengt. Wenn wir sagen: Dies hätte nicht geschehen
dürfen, so meinen wir, dass wir dieser Ereignisse mit den großen und durch große
Tradition geheiligten Mitteln unserer Vergangenheit weder im politischen Handeln
noch im geschichtlich-politischen Denken Herr werden können..” (Arendt 1991: 705)
On the other hand, directly following this passage, she tries to place the
phenomenon of totalitarianism into the framework of the traditional doctrine
of types of state, in this case Montesquieu´s typology of political ethics,- thus
coming to the well-known conclusion that the ”actual novelty” of totalitarian
rule resides not so much in the quantitative increase, but, rather, in a new
quality of ideology and terror, in its elevation to the level of the central
constituents of political control as such.24
24
The famous passages (Arendt 1991: 711-724) show a new intensity in the formulations, too, compared to the
previous chapters on the secret police and the concentration camps!
23
for the topicalization of the inner cohesion and the functional differentiation of
totalitarian regimes, be it in the form of the Marxist social doctrine or in the
form of humanistic structural sociology, in which Sigmund Neumann had his
roots, as is well known. She furthermore neglected the arsenal of methods of
comparative social and political research, which pushed for relativization and
detachment,- a line of research which, at the end of the 1940s, was certainly
only in an embryonic stage, but which, from today´s point of view, constitutes
an indispensable basis for every approach to the theory of totalitarianism.25
That her specific way of arguing and her literary elegance had to do with a
pronounced philosophical talent was already evident during the early 1950s.
However, where this remarkable gift stemmed from and what the preparation,
the philosophical fine-tuning of the applied instruments of interpetation
consisted in we know in detail only now, due to the intensive biographical
research Hannah Arendt has attracted in recent years. She distinguishes
herself through her individualization not only from the broad, collective-
25
That is the irrevocable conviction of all updatings of the totalitarianism debate, of the more sceptical, because socio-
scientifically oriented, one as well as of the hunanistic one, which tunes positively into the philosophical tenor. With
regard to the first cf. esp. Juan J. Linz (2000); with regard to the second cf. Hans Maier (1996/7).
24
biographical research on exile and emigration; she also has turned a small
scientific wonder into a great fashion with an international aura, which does
not shy away from scandalization.26
Regardless of how one judges this literature in its endearing glorification – the
parallel historio-philosophical approach has shown in an entirely convincing
manner that the remarkable dynamism which had driven Hannah Arendt´s
political thinking since the 1950s is in fact best understood if one recognizes
that here basic concepts are at work which had obviously been adapted
straight from the German existentialist philosophy of the Weimar Republic, in
concrete terms, from Martin Heidegger and – somewhat toned down – from
Karl Jaspers. Of course, one has to add immediately that this adaptation
amounted, from the very beginning, to a transformation of these basic
concepts; this was, on the one hand, due to Hannah Arendt´s specific personal
history of learning and, on the other, was the result of drawing a serious
philosophical lesson from the totalitarianist experience. Her book on
totalitarianism is nothing less than the first distressing monument on this
difficult path.27
The description of totalitarian rule in the narrow sense then sort of pushes
aside the traditional institutions of the monopoly of power – the apparatus of
state and the military -, in order to illustrate, with the secret police, the actual
totalitarian instruments of rule: ideology as the total destruction of reality and
terror as the practical translation of the same principle. In the concentration
and extermination camps, finally, Hannah Arendt detects “die eigentliche
zentrale Institution des totalen Macht- und Organisationsapparates” (“the actual
central institution of the totalitarian apparatus of power and organization”)
(Arendt 1991: 677) and, thus, the core of the essence of totaliatrian rule, which
eludes functional analysis because what is practiced here is neither violent
sadism nor annihilation of the enemy, but, rather, a demonstration of the
“Überflüssigkeit des Menschen “ (“superfluousness of man”) (Arendt 1991: 688-
9).
Stalinism as totalitarian regimes in the strict sense (and not Italian fascism, nor
the Socialist regimes after Stalin), did not have sufficient knowledge of the
Soviet development or that she had not paid enough attention to the inner
structures of National Socialism, to the role of the economy, in particular.
Yet, this same train of thought, which feeds on the mistrust between
philosophy and science, could well be reversed and it could be asked whether
it had not in fact been the “philosophical exaggerations” to which research –
then just as much as nowadays – owes important insights into the inner logic
of totalitarianism of both fascist and Bolshevik style. With regard to our
context, it is of special interest to ask whether Hannah Arendt´s philosophical
approach had supported or, rather, impeded the factual, i.e. the historical and
the socio-scientific research on totalitarian societies. In the weighing of this
question I suspect the third shock effect, which Hannah Asrendt´s book on
totalitarianism triggered perhaps not so much at the time of its appearance,
but rather from today´s point of view.
that the actual aggravation of terror did not come first and was not
directed so much against the political opponents, but rather, that it
started only after the regimes had established themselves and was
therefore directed “potentially against everyone”.
d) As regards the key role of the secret police in securing political
power, Friedrich/Brzezinski have not only felt themselves to be
inspired by Hannah Arendt, but even had to accept being corrected
by her (in greater detail in Lietzmann 1999: 131-141).
e) What remains is the large complex of mass extermination, which has
since then increasingly become the focus of attention of politics and
science, in concrete terms: the gulag and the Jewish genocide. In this
respect, Hannah Arendt´s place in the history of science seems to be
characterized by a certain ambivalence. On the one hand, her book
on totalitarianism has turned this aspect, through its powerful
existentialist interpretation, into something that can clearly not be
overlooked or neglected by research, not least because of the
pugnacious – and up this day controversial – thesis of the total
economic anti-rationality of the holocaust, in particular. On the other
hand, it is obvious that the consequent, i.e. the historically detailed
and sociologically momentous study of the holocaust was not
primarily inspired by Hannah Arendt, but, as is shown by the work
of Raul Hilber, in particular, rather by the structural theory of Franz
Neumann (cf. Hilberg/Söllner 1988: 175-200).
mixing of politics and science, and would she have done so by means of just
that obstinacy of philosophical reflection in face of a retrogressive public, in
which critique and public morals become indistinguishable, which was to
become so important in her entire future work?