Character
Character
Character
Murray Smith
O
n 2 January 2011, Nigel Pargetter slipped while working on
the roof of his home, Lower Loxley Hall in Ambridge, falling to
his death. That evening, Nigel had been hosting a New Year’s
Eve party for the local community. The party was disrupted when a close
friend of Nigel and his wife Elizabeth—Helen Archer—was taken to
hospital with suspected pre-eclampsia. The party having in effect come
to end, Nigel was persuaded by his friend (and Helen’s cousin) David
Archer to help him remove the celebratory banner on top of the house,
placed there to announce the New Year’s party. Underestimating the
strength of the wind, Pargetter lost his footing while loosening a knot
and plunged to the ground. A well-known and well-liked national figure,
many expressed their shock and sorrow at his untimely death. Pargetter
was a “kind, positive, adoring husband, [a] family man, [a] funny, mildly
eccentric minor aristocrat,” read one typical tribute.1
Readers resident in Britain may well recognize these events as those
constituting the main storyline of the sixtieth-anniversary episode of
the BBC radio drama The Archers (now the longest running serial drama
in any medium).2 Nothing in the description I offer above, however,
distinguishes it from a description of actual events and people; these
fictional characters are, it seems—beyond the fact that they don’t exist
as actual persons—just like actual people. We speak in terms of their
desires, values, and temperaments; of their lives as ones lived through
families, the local community, and various larger social structures; as
subject to the same medical conditions and physical laws that hold in
our world. Still more strikingly, we can and do respond to such char-
acters in ways that parallel our responses to real individuals, liking and
disliking them, evaluating them, expressing pleasure and dismay at
what befalls them.3 Many fans of The Archers were said to be “shaken”
by the events of the anniversary episode, some speaking of their “grief”
for Nigel Pargetter; at least one eulogy—from which the quotation at
the end of my first paragraph is taken—was written in his memory.4
In all of these ways, The Archers represents its events and characters
in a manner prototypical for a certain type of realist fiction, one that
And yet, even for realist fiction of this type, fiction that seems to
invite a mimetic attitude towards its characters, that attitude is—so to
speak—only half of the story. Or, more precisely, the attitude itself is only
half-described if we accept the sketch I have offered. In the extensive
fan discussions of The Archers following the death of Nigel Pargetter, at
least as much emotion—usually in the form of upset, annoyance, and
anger—was expressed towards the show and its creators as towards
the characters. Throughout these debates, listeners of the show reveal
themselves to be sophisticated dramaturges, highly aware of the show’s
artifice. Their willingness and ability to respond to The Archers’ charac-
ters as if they were real is matched by a thorough understanding of the
characters’ irreality. Thus we need to probe our stance towards fictional
characters more deeply; to aid that task, I draw upon Richard Wollheim’s
notion of twofoldness.6
II
Even Goya’s use of paint shapes our visual and cognitive responses. If we look
closely we see the roughly treated surface, the lightning stripe of the soldier’s
sword sheath in the foreground, the scraped, coagulated, dark splotches of
crimson blood and the smeared facial features of the foremost prostrate figure,
his individuality blotted out.8
the expense of the other.” Thus, on the one hand, I can focus my atten-
tion on the marked surface, scrutinizing the canvas, the brushstrokes, or
(in the case of film) the grain of the image, to the point where I “lose
all but a shadowy awareness” of whatever is depicted by the image.9 On
the other hand, I can focus on what I see in the image, marveling at the
pristine, clean-cut appearance of Roger Thornhill, retaining only the
“vaguest sense” of the surface of the image that allows me to see Roger
Thornhill in it. And at the extremes, according to Wollheim, twofold-
ness can “evaporate” altogether, so that we find ourselves either seeing
the marked surface “face-to-face,” that is, simply as a textured surface in
which we see nothing depicted, or (at the other extreme) drifting into
a mode of visualizing “in the mind’s eye” the contents of the depiction
(47). In this latter state, while the picture has clearly been vital in getting
this process of private visualizing off the ground, once in it we cease to
engage with the picture as a picture. Wollheim also notes that, as a mat-
ter of fact, neither of these extreme states are likely to be stable when
we are engaged with a depiction: the marked surface draws us back to
the twofold nature of seeing-in. So while Wollheim’s theory accommo-
dates the intuition that it is possible to lose awareness of the artifactual
status of a depiction, or to lose awareness of the depictive function of a
marked surface, he underlines both the natural and the normative force
of twofoldness. Looking at a marked surface that has been successfully
designed to trigger seeing-in, we find it difficult to resist that invitation;
and it is a norm for the proper appreciation of such depictions that our
perceptual engagement with them should involve an interplay between
their recognitional and configurational aspects—between attention to
the design and to the depicted content (see also Wollheim 166, and my
discussion in section V below). Thus, in the passage of critical analysis
on Goya’s The Third of May quoted above, Kieran praises the way in
which the configurational aspects of the painting expressively shape
our experience and understanding of its recognitional elements, that
is, what the painting depicts.
In speaking of the “interplay” of the two aspects of twofoldness, it is
important to contrast the position I argue for here with the rival theory
of depiction propounded by E. H. Gombrich. Gombrich—with whom
Wollheim sustained a dialogue over many years—also recognized that our
perception of both the marked surface and the depicted object figure
in our experience of engaging with depictions. But Gombrich’s theory
was based on a notion of illusion: when we perceive what a depiction
represents, we are subject to an illusion that we are seeing that object
face-to-face.10 Gombrich likens our experience of depictions to our expe-
rience of Robert Jastrow’s duck-rabbit illusion, made famous by Ludwig
282 new literary history
III
thus the impact this has on the presumed transparency of the film image.
To this we may add the second point: even if we grant that there is some
general and important contrast between painted and filmed depictions
in respect of their degree of transparency, we should not conceive of
the viewer’s attention or experience in terms of an “oscillation” between
the fictional world depicted, and the “configurational” features of the
image through which the depiction is achieved. The model of multiple
and variable levels of attention developed above, in which our “twofold”
awareness of the image as both designed surface and depiction is the
norm, furnishes us with a more plausible and supple account of both
painted and filmed depiction.
IV
focus of the camera lens. Objects in a black and white film are not to
be understood as lacking colour in the fictional world; rather, they ap-
pear to us in that form as a consequence of the film stock used by the
filmmakers (58). In all these ways, our appreciation of films that strive
for transparency show that awareness of configuration does and must
accompany proper attention to and understanding of the elements
comprising the fictional world.
In order to show how the theory here extends to include characters
in literary and other media, however, we need to detail other ways in
which our awareness of the formal aspect of character may be manifest.
Narrative structure and generic form are perhaps the most significant
of these. We have already encountered some basic examples of formal
claims about characters bearing upon narrative structure: the statements
that North by Northwest features a character called Roger Thornhill, and
that Charlie is the protagonist of Modern Times. In a similar spirit, we
might say that the subplot concerning Don Draper’s half-brother Adam
(Jay Paulson), in Mad Men, reaches its climax when Don discovers that
Adam has committed suicide. We might claim that the narrative arc of
the first season of the show as a whole completes itself with Draper’s
presentation of his proposed ad campaign for the Kodak slide carousel
(based on its role as an engine of nostalgia). Or we might speak of
the final scene in The Silence of the Lambs (Jonathan Demme, 1991), in
which Hannibal Lecter (Anthony Hopkins) phones Clarice Starling
(Jodie Foster) from a Caribbean island, as a blackly humorous coda to
the main action of the film. Whenever we think in such terms about
characters—pondering their degree of significance within the narrative,
or the way in which they figure in the “parts” constituting the narrative
whole—we are thinking formally about the fiction. And if we go on to
think about the types of character and narrative that the fiction embod-
ies—recognizing the figure of the little tramp from other Chaplin movies,
and wondering if this fiction will unfold in the same direction as those
other works by Chaplin; recognizing a character as a hero, an antihero,
an antagonist, a bounder, or a femme fatale—we are also responding to
the formal dimensions of character, now in a way that brings in generic
considerations alongside those specific to the particular fiction in hand.
Greg Currie marks out a similar contrast to that between the recogni-
tional/referential and the configurational/formal aspects of character,
speaking of the “external” and “internal” facets of narrative and character.
In a related discussion, he notes that
on the twofoldness of character 289
when we learn something about a fictional character because the work itself tells
or suggests it, this is not at all like learning something about someone in the
real world by casual observation. For what the fiction tells us comes labeled as
having a special evidential relevance; we are told this for a reason . . . Thus the
world of a fiction is not one that we engage with by applying ordinary standards
of evidence and probability; what is evidence is inseperable from what is a sign
of authorial intention. And so we may rightly draw conclusions about motive
or behavior that would be unwarranted on the same purely evidential basis in
real world situations.19
depiction is that they assume that the naturalistic effect arises from some
form of suppression of the configurational aspect of a depiction, so as to
allow for an especially fluid or fast uptake of the recognitional content
of the depiction. But, Wollheim insists, it is the reciprocal interplay be-
tween awareness of the marked surface, and of what we see in a picture,
that creates the naturalistic effect. And naturalism is something that is
continually reinvented in the context of new materials and new types of
subject matter; that is why there is no single style of depiction which can
lay claim to being the naturalistic style (73–74). Further on in Wollheim’s
discussion, the normative aspect of twofoldness—that is, the sense in
which it is not only something that usually characterizes our experience of
pictures, but something that should be part of that experience—surfaces
again. Any picture that seeks to maximize our absorption in the action
depicted must, reciprocally, find a way of returning the spectator “from
imagination to perception: twofoldness must be reactivated” (166). So
again we see that twofoldness is a quality of our experience that typically
is and should be prompted not only by the varieties of nonnaturalistic
depiction—caricatural, expressionistic, reflexive, and so forth—but by
prototypically realist and naturalist pictures as well. Judging a depiction
to be realistic is not at all like mistaking it for a real scene, because our
awareness of the differentiated surface runs alongside—is a part of the
same experience as—our awareness of what is depicted.
The same holds, once more, for nondepictive forms of representa-
tion. An integral part of appreciating the realism of a novel or a stage
performance is an awareness of the configurational features of the
object of our attention, of its status as an artifact, a product of design.
So we return finally to the central claim of this essay: that the property
of twofoldness characterizes not only our experience of depictions, but
our experience of representations—and the characters that loom large
within them—in general. Understanding and appreciating fictional
characters in any medium involves “a complicated blend of imagina-
tive engagement and metafictional reflection.”21 We may talk freely of
fictional characters as if they literally inhabited our own world, but in so
doing we do not lose sight of their invented status. Far from suggesting
naïveté, such talk betrays the ease, sophistication, and naturalness with
which we handle fictional characters.
University of Kent
Notes
1 The comment is contained within the eulogy to Pargetter posted at: http://onelifecer-
emonies.co.uk/funeral-blog/index.php/2011/01/nigel-pargetter-the-archers-a-eulogy/
292 new literary history
2 The pilot series for the show began in May 1950; the confirmed series in January
1951, with five fifteen minute episodes broadcast each week since then.
3 Whether such affective responses are genuine emotions has been actively debated
over the past thirty years or more. In a well-known paper, Kendall Walton argued that such
responses are “quasi-emotions”; others have defended the idea that our affective responses
to fictional characters are authentic emotions. See Kendall L. Walton, “Fearing Fictions,”
Journal of Philosophy 75, no. 1 (1978): 5–27, and Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations
of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1990), 241–55.
4 See note 1 for the link to the eulogy for Pargetter. The actor who had played Pargetter
for 30 years, Graham Seed, also spoke of his grieving over the death of the character. Given
the extended nature of his imaginative inhabitation of the character, one might think of
Seed’s situation and response as qualitatively different from that of committed listeners
of The Archers. I would be more inclined to think of his response as on a continuum with
similar responses from such listeners, though I will not pursue that claim here.
5 A four-part series broadcast on BBC Two, February–March 2011; Faulks makes this
claim in the introduction to the first episode, The Hero. Recently a debate has emerged on
the implications of research in social psychology, most famously associated with Stanley
Milgram, concerning the power of situations—rather than character traits—in the deter-
mination of action of actual persons. On one interpretation, experimental work in this
tradition shows that human individuals do not possess the kind of stable clusters of traits
embodied in the idea of “character.” If real individuals lack character in this sense—a
substantial degree of trait consistency over time—then it follows, on this view, that fictional
characters possessing such consistency cannot give us insight into actual human psychol-
ogy in the way that Faulks, for example, assumes. I think this worry is overstated, but in
any event, note that Faulks’s claim bears on the movement from fictional characters to
actual persons—on the role that fictional characters play in our own real lives, on what
we may learn from such characters. By contrast, the focus of my argument here is on the
movement from actual persons to fictional characters—on, that is, our readiness to think
and speak about fictional characters using the same cognitive and linguistic tools that we
deploy in relation to real persons.
6 Richard Wollheim, Painting as an Art (London: Thames and Hudson, 1987) (hereaf-
ter cited in text); the notion of “twofoldness” is introduced on page 21. Although I draw
upon Wollheim in this essay, the seeds of the idea that our apprehension of characters
is marked by “twofoldness” are in my Engaging Characters: Fiction, Emotion, and the Cinema
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1995), 42–44, 138, and “Engaging Characters : Further Reflections,”
in Characters in Fictional Worlds: Understanding Imaginary Beings in Literature, Film and Other
Media, ed. Jens Eder, Fotis Jannidis, and Ralf Schneider (Berlin: DeGruyter, 2010), 237.
7 The first example is my own; the second two examples are inspired by two photographs
used by Wollheim to illustrate seeing-in: Cumulus Cloud, Mushrooming Head (1930s), by E.
E. Barnard, and Empty Head, Frost on Window, Rochester, New York (1962) by Minor White.
Painting as an Art, 46–47.
8 Matthew Kieran, Revealing Art (London: Routledge, 2005), 59.
9 Wollheim, Painting, 47. Dominic Lopes makes a further distinction, related to this
point in Wollheim’s discussion, between “design-seeing” (seeing the marks on the surface
as parts of a representational or abstract design) and “surface-seeing” (seeing the marks
on the surface simply as marks). See his Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures (Oxford:
Oxford Univ. Press, 2005), chap. 1.
10 Gombrich’s arguments were originally laid out in his classic Art and Illusion: A Study
in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation, rev. ed. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press,
1969), first published in 1960. Wollheim’s review of that work initiated a dialogue be-
tween them, the comments in Painting as an Art representing a much later moment in
on the twofoldness of character 293
that conversation. It is also worth mentioning at this juncture that another major player
in these debates over the nature of depiction, the perceptual psychologist J. J. Gibson,
argued that our apprehension of still and moving pictures involves a dual, simultaneous
perception of the two-dimensional surfaces of images, and the three-dimensional spaces
represented by them. Gibson’s position is thus (in this respect, at least) remarkably similar
to Wollheim’s. See Gibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1979), 276.
11 For more on consciousness and our experience of film, see my “Film and Conscious-
ness,” in The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Film, ed. Paisley Livingston and Carl
Plantinga (London: Routledge, 2009), 39–51.
12 On the phenomenon of “ontological self-subsistence,” and its relationship with filmic
transparency, see George Wilson, “The Transfiguration of Classical Hollywood Norms: On
Von Sternberg’s Last Films with Dietrich,” in The Creation of Art: New Essays in Philosophi-
cal Aesthetics, ed. Berys Gaut and Paisley Livingston (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press,
2003), 270–71.
13 George M. Wilson, “Coherence and Transparency in Classical Narrative Film,” in
Narration in Light: Studies in Cinematic Point of View (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press,
1986), 56–57 (hereafter cited in text). In a later essay, Wilson restates this argument:
Because motion picture images are formed on a fixed screen by means of the projection of
light, they, unlike paintings, do not exhibit the sort of worked surface produced, for example,
by strokes of paint on canvas. As a consequence, film images do not have the same potential for
eliciting the experience of seeing the drawn or painted scene as arising out of the fine-grained
configurations of material on the displayed surface—an aspect of our total experience of paint-
ing whose aesthetic importance Richard Wollheim has done so much to elucidate. The absence
in film images of this property, foundational for representational painting, both enhances our
impression of the “immediacy” of their depictive power and denies to them the special artistic
possibilities of well-crafted facture.
Wilson, “Le Grand Imagier Steps Out: The Primitive Basis of Film Narration,” Philosophical
Topics 25, no. 1 (1997): 313.
14 Note also that Wilson’s account diverges here from Walton’s account of photographic
transparency, to which Wilson alludes. Walton argues that in looking at a photograph,
we see both the photograph and the object that it depicts. As Wilson notes (212, note
13), however, Walton’s argument is directed at documentary photographs and films in
the first instance, while Wilson’s is concerned with the transparency characteristic of cin-
ematographic fiction films. See Kendall L. Walton, “Transparent Pictures,” Critical Inquiry
11, no. 2 (1984): 246–77.
15 André Bazin, “The Ontology of the Photographic Image,” trans. Hugh Gray, in What
is Cinema? vol. 1 (Berkeley and Los Angeles: Univ. of California Press, 1967), 1:14.
16 Of course, in many animated films and some films using CGI, the filmmaker does cre-
ate every part of the image. But these special cases leave standing the more general points
regarding the differences between painting on the one hand, and film and photography
on the other, that I discuss here.
17 Francis Dauer, “The Nature of Fictional Characters and the Referential Fallacy,” Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53, no. 1 (1995): 36.
18 It is also, of course, reminiscent of the classical structuralist distinction between the récit
and discours of a text, as elaborated in the work of Gérard Genette and Seymour Chatman,
for example; and of the distinction in theories of emotional response to fictions between
“fiction emotions” (responses to events in a fiction) and “artifact emotions” (responses to
the work representing the fiction). On the latter distinction, see Ed S. Tan, Emotion and
the Structure of Narrative Film: Film as an Emotion Machine, trans. Barbara Fasting (Mahwah,
NJ: Erlbaum, 1996).
294 new literary history
19 Gregory Currie, “The Capacities that Enable Us to Produce and Consume Art,” in
Matthew Kieran and Dominic McIver Lopes, Imagination, Philosophy and the Arts (London:
Routledge, 2003), 296–97; the related discussion of the “external” and “internal” facets of
narrative is to be found in “Narrative Representation of Causes,” The Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism 64, no. 3 (2006): 312.
20 Kendall L. Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational
Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1990), 175–76 (hereafter cited in text).
21 Paisley Livingston and Andrea Sauchelli, “Philosophical Perspectives on Fictional
Characters,” this volume, 355.
CONTRIBUTORS
Catherine Gallagher is the Ida May and William J. Eggers Professor of English
at the University of California–Berkeley. She has published several books on
the British novel and is currently writing on narratives of counterfactual history.
Julian Murphet is Professor in Modern Film and English and Director of the
Centre for Modernism Studies in Australia at the University of New South Wales.
He is the author of Literature and Race in Los Angeles (2001) and Multimedia
Modernism (2009) and is writing a book on William Faulkner’s relations with
the modern media ecology.