Lecture 6 Summary
Lecture 6 Summary
Lecture 6 Summary
- This mean that all valid arguments have the same form, and all invalid arguments have the
same form.
- Therefore, argument form illustrates the argument’s internal structure or pattern of
reasoning.
For example:
All A are B
A
All C are A
All C are B B C
- If A, B and C represent groups of things, it’s easy to see that this is a valid form. Assumed by
the second premise that the C’s are included in the A’s and by the first premise that the A’s
are included in the B’s. Then it necessarily follows that the C’s are included in the B’s.
- Hence: an argument form is an arrangement of letters and words such that the uniform
substitution of words of phrases in the place of the letters results in an argument. For this
form, the words or phrases being substituted must refer to groups of things (within the
argument).
For example:
- If we substitute “sporting events”, “engaging pastimes”, and “baseball games” in the place of
A, B, and C, respectively in the argument form (left above), we obtain the following argument
(right above). This instance is called a substitution instance of the argument form. Any
substitution instance of a valid argument form is a valid argument.
- Let’s consider invalid argument form:
All A are B
A
All C are B C
All A are C B
- In this argument form, if we assume that the A’s are in the B’s and that the C’s are in the B’s,
it does not necessarily follow that the A’s are in the C’s. It would not follow if the A’s were in
one part of the B’s and the C’s were in another as the diagram illustrates above.
- The diagram suggest that we can prove the form of the argument invalid if we can find a
substitution instance having actually true premises and a false conclusion.
- For example: if we substitute “cats” for A, “animals” for B and “dogs” for C, we have such a
substitution instance:
- The substitution
case where the As are in the Bs and the Cs are in the Bs but the As are not in the Cs.
- Not every substitution instance for an invalid form Is in an invalid argument. The reason is
that some substitution instances of invalid forms are also substitution instances of valid
forms. However, we can say that any substitution instance of an invalid form is an invalid
argument provided that it is not a substitution instance of any valid form. Hence, we can say
that an argument actually has an invalid form if it is a substitution instance of that form and
is not a substitution instance of any valid form.
- For example: the following valid argument is a substitution instance of the invalid form we
have been discussing:
- However, because “bachelors” are equivalent in meaning to “unmarried men” the argument
is also a substitution instance of this valid form.
- Counterexample Method
- The counterexample method can be used to prove the invalidity of any invalid argument but,
it cannot prove the validity of any valid argument. Therefore, before the method is applied to
an argument, the argument must be known or suspected to be invalid in the first place.
- For example, let’s apply the counterexample method to the following categorical syllogism:
- Since some employees are not social climbers and all vice presidents are employees, we may
conclude that some vice presidents are not social climbers.
This argument is invalid because the employees who are not social climbers might not be
vice presidents. Accordingly, we can prove the argument invalid by constructing a
substitution instance having true premises and a false conclusion. We begin by isolating the
form of the argument.
Some E are not S
All V are E
Some V are not S
Next we select three terms to substitute in place of the letters that will make the premises
true and the conclusion false:
E= Animals
S= Mammals
V=Dogs
The substitution instance has true premises and a false conclusion and is therefore, by
definition invalid. Because the substation instance is invalid, the form is invalid and therefore,
the original argument is invalid.