Science and Scientific Method
Science and Scientific Method
Science and Scientific Method
net/publication/359985426
CITATIONS READS
4 8,406
1 author:
J.G.C. da Silva
Universidade Federal de Pelotas (retired).
84 PUBLICATIONS 145 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by J.G.C. da Silva on 15 April 2022.
Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Federal University of Pelotas (retired). Pelotas, RS, Brazil.
Orcid ID 0000-0003-2985-0925.
E-mail: [email protected].
Abstract. The roots of science go back to the contributions of Greek philosophers some 2,500 years ago. However, science as it is
known today and its great power and remarkable influence over humanity emerged in the 16th century as a consequence of the
Renaissance revolution that radically transformed the objects, methods and objectives of knowledge of nature. Objects became
natural phenomena; the methods, disciplined cooperative research, and a set of objective, systematic, rational, and critical
procedures that have been generically called the "scientific method"; and the objectives, the construction of a factual, verifiable
and explanatory body of knowledge. What essentially characterizes science as a rationally and critically grounded body of
knowledge is the method by which that knowledge is constructed. This article reviews the foundations of the scientific approach to
knowledge generation and characterizes the scientific method.
1. Introduction
The common person can acquire knowledge in different ways. The farmer, for example, is aware of the plants he cultivates, the time
of sowing and planting, the way to treat the land, the means of protection against insects and pests. This knowledge comes from
imitation, information transmitted by predecessors, family members and formal education, and personal experience. This person
may also possess knowledge generated by research carried out by scientific institutions that is transmitted to him by means of
communication and training. Scientific knowledge can also be acquired more rationally through formal higher education, and
enhanced with specialization in postgraduate courses.
The discovery that nature is governed by an intelligible scheme originated in Greece. Greek theory discovered the universe of ideas
and forms, ordered by the rules of geometry, and the universe of nature, consisting of logically ordered movements. All Greek theory
is dedicated to the description of these two orders, embodied in Euclid's Geometry, in Aristotle's Physics and in Plato's Theory of
Ideas. Only at the beginning of the 17th century did modern science originate.
Science is a logical process of investigation for solving problems and seeking answers to questions regarding natural phenomena.
Through the scientific method, scientists attempt to generate a body of knowledge free from personal beliefs, perceptions, values,
attitudes and emotions. This is achieved by the empirical verification of ideas and beliefs through a procedure open to public
inspection. The reliability of scientific knowledge derives from its evidence base provided by objective observation.
Scientific knowledge is not absolute and definitive knowledge. On the contrary, it tends to improve itself and, as a result, lead, for
example, to the creation of new more adequate and convenient methods, techniques and procedures. This progress is achieved by
the permanent activity of inquiry to which researchers are dedicated. Thus, science is a source of knowledge generation that renews
itself to solve problems, answer questions, and develop more effective procedures to solve problems and answer questions.
This article reviews the origins, evolution and characteristics of the scientific approach to knowledge generation. This review is
based mainly in the contributions of Descartes [1], Madden [2], Lastrucci [3], Bunge [4], Heath [5], Cervo & Bervian [6], Wilson
[7], Hinkelmann & Kempthorne [8], Johann [9], Christensen [10], Carey [11], Gottschall [12], Silva [13].
2. Sources of Knowledge
The search for knowledge of nature was already a characteristic of prehistoric man. Man's first contacts with nature generated
eminently sensitive knowledge. Limited resources allowed the perception of phenomena only through the senses and superficial
explanations. Seeking to unravel the universe, man adheres to the cult of the forces of nature as a form of knowledge. In the passage
from primitive times to antiquity, man expands the limits of his knowledge, going from mythological explanations of the universe
to explanations of a religious nature. The next step is interpretation by way of reason. With the rise of philosophy, the explanation
of nature becomes eminently rational. The incessant search for truth leads to the passage from philosophy to science, that is, to the
interaction of reasoning with the empirical approach to explaining the causal relationships between phenomena, through rigorous
analytical and rational procedures.
Empirical knowledge. The most remote and ordinary way for man to create his representations and interpretations of reality is
through everyday experience and common sense. The knowledge constituted by these representations arises from the need to solve
immediate problems. This empirical knowledge is a spontaneous and unsystematic way of representing reality, without an
appropriate method to deepen its foundations. This is the knowledge of the common person, without training, generated by his
relationship with the material world. It originates from individual and collective experiences and beliefs. This knowledge is
developed, used to predict future events and transmitted from one generation to the next.
Common sense implies a certain degree of abstraction. However, it proceeds to a simple junction of ideas, notions and concepts and
does not reach a level of elaboration that originates the creation or use of concepts whose meanings deepen the understanding of
reality. This limitation generates knowledge of facts based on their appearance, without concern for their explanation through
analysis to characterize their origins. The knowledge generated is constituted by an agglomeration of elements, without unity and
coherence. Besides, it is not subjected to a level of criticism necessary to understand reality beyond what is experienced. This can
lead to fatalistic interpretations of the situations that present themselves, which attribute to destiny defined by a superior being
responsible for the events of life.
Mythical knowledge. Without using writing, primitive man sought to explain, narrate and announce phenomena through symbols
and allegories, thus creating myths. Reality then began to be interpreted based on these myths. Mythical knowledge is a product of
the oral transmission of empirical knowledge from generation to generation. Myths were rooted in the culture and tradition of ancient
peoples and represented much more than an attempt to explain reality. Myth constituted the historical foundation of civilizations,
explaining the past and the origin of the present. It was a representation of the real world, recreated from the subjective elaboration
of man's experiences. The origins of inexplicable phenomena were attributed to immanent powers and forces existing within objects,
animals and people. Ancient peoples worshiped the Sun and the Moon; the Hindus, the cow; the Mayans, the Incas, the Aztecs and
other peoples, the totems and amulets, monuments and objects that they built themselves. These peoples believed that these entities
and objects had the strength and powers to do good and evil, and created their interpreters or interlocutors, such as witches, sorcerers,
priests, shamans.
At a later stage, these mysterious forces are transferred to fictitious beings with human forms. These beings were invisible,
represented by statues, to which, mainly the Greeks, Romans and Egyptians, rendered cults. The interventions of these superior
beings, called gods, would be the origin of all natural phenomena. It is the phase of polytheism. The cause of a set of phenomena in
a particular sector of nature was attributed to a particular god. Polytheism predominated in Greece and ancient Rome. Thus, for
example, Diana was the goddess of the hunt, Eolo the god of the wind, Neptune the god of the sea, Ceres the goddess of the harvest.
Theological knowledge. Religious experience is as old as civilized man is. Religious or theological knowledge is aimed at
understanding the totality of reality. Its purpose is the explanation of a unique origin and end concerning the genesis and existence
of the universe. It attributes the cause of all phenomena to a single superior being: God. In the Judeo-Christian religion, God is the
only creator of all that exists. The creation of the universe and natural phenomena are attributed to him, in particular the creation of
man and animals, their existence, transformations and purposes.
From a theological point of view, the divine existence is evident and evidence needs no proof. Based on this principle, it seeks to
find explanations for everything that has happened and happens to human beings, and seeks to study issues relating to knowledge
of the deities, their attributes and relationships with the world and with men. Religion has its foundations in dogmas and rites, which
are accepted by faith and cannot be proved or criticized, because it is the only source of truth. The sources of theological knowledge
are the holy books – Koran for Muslims, Veda for Hindus, Talmud for Jews and Bible for Christians. The interlocutors between
man and God are priests, rabbis, pastors and other interpreters.
Philosophical knowledge. Philosophical knowledge began with man's first attempts to understand the world by associating
reasoning with observation. Philosophy developed in Persia, China, India, and elsewhere in the Orient. Western philosophy
originated six centuries before Christ, from the teachings mainly of Greek philosophers such as Pythagoras (580-500 BC), Socrates
(470-399 BC), Plato (428-348 BC) and Aristotle (384- 322 BC), and the first ones who sought to interpret nature by observation
and logic, without necessarily supernatural interpretation.
Philosophy seeks knowledge of first causes or principles. It has no particular object, but assumes the guiding role of science itself
in the solution of universal problems. Thus, philosophy is the expression of the universality of human knowledge, that is, the source
of all areas of human knowledge. In this context, science not only depends on philosophy but also includes itself.
Philosophical knowledge developed from ideas and theories formulated by great philosophers, such as the aforementioned Greek
philosophers, and Saint Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274), Francis Bacon (1561-1626), René Descartes (1596-1650) , John Locke
(1632-1704), Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778), Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), Georg Hegel (1770-1831), Karl Marx (1818-1883)
and, in recent times, Bertrand Russell ( 1872-1970), Ernest Nagel (1901-1985), Karl Popper (1902-1994) and Carl Gustav Hempel
(1905-1997).
Philosophy rests on reflection on experience. Reflection provides interpretation variations on impressions, images and opinions.
However, philosophy is not reduced to a search for reflexive and conceptual originality. Above all, philosophy aims to understand
reality and provide reflective and logical content to change and transform reality. Philosophy has the task of elaborating
presuppositions and guiding principles of human actions. Philosophy is also a critical reflection of society, politics, law, education.
For this reason, philosophical knowledge evolves according to the historical context.
Scientific knowledge. Science originated from philosophy. From 5,000 years before Christ, Babylonians and Egyptians developed
important knowledge mainly in mathematics and astronomy. However, the Greek philosophers were the main responsible for the
combination of knowledge in these two areas, which constituted the starting point of science.
The task of science is the explanation of natural processes and phenomena. No system of theoretical ideas, technical terms, and
mathematical procedures can be regarded as scientific unless it relates to these empirical facts at some point and in some way, and
helps to make them more intelligible. Scientific knowledge is a system of methodical knowledge about nature. It differs from other
forms of knowledge in that it requires objective empirical verification of all explanations regarding phenomena, which allows an
understanding of their nature and causes, free from the observer's influences, desires and prejudices. Scientists seek knowledge of
the relationships between phenomena, that is, of natural laws. It relies on logical reasoning to deduce new knowledge from general
laws or concepts.
The special character of science can be explained by the circumstances in which scientists work in their respective fields. These
circumstances include the basic principle of knowing the natural world through demonstrative arguments. Thus, a representation or
interpretation of a phenomenon or process is only scientific knowledge if it has been verified or empirically demonstrated.
The search for scientific knowledge stems from the perception that the available body of knowledge is insufficient to understand
some phenomenon or natural event. Part of the available knowledge is common or ordinary knowledge, that is, non-scientific, and
part is scientific knowledge, that is, knowledge derived through the method of science. This knowledge can be put back to the test,
perfected or surpassed, through this same method. As the scientific process progresses, portions of the ordinary body of knowledge
are corrected or rejected, and the body of scientific knowledge is increased. Thus, science grows from common knowledge and
surpasses it with its growth. In fact, scientific work begins at the point where experience and common knowledge fail to provide
solutions to problems related to phenomena of interest, or even to formulate them. However, scientific knowledge is not a mere
refinement and extension of common knowledge. It is knowledge of a special nature. Science also deals with unobservable
phenomena not considered by the common person, raises conjectures that go beyond common knowledge, and puts these conjectures
to the test on the basis of its theories and with the help of special techniques. On the other hand, science is unable to develop
knowledge from unnatural explanations.
Thus, scientific knowledge is radically distinguished from common knowledge in many respects, particularly in terms of method.
However, these two sources of knowledge have some similarity, at least if consideration is limited to the ordinary knowledge
generated by common sense. In fact, common sense, like science, aspires to be rational and objective. However, the ideal of
rationality, that is, the coherent systematization of knowledge is only achieved through theories, which constitute the core of science,
while common knowledge is constituted by the accumulation of unrelated pieces of information. Besides, ideal objectivity, that is,
the construction of impersonal representations of reality, cannot be achieved without overcoming the narrow limits of everyday life
and personal experience. It demands the formulation of conjectures about the existence of physical objects in addition to precarious
sensory impressions, and the verification of such conjectures through objective experience, planned and interpreted with the aid of
theories. Common sense can achieve only limited objectivity because it is closely linked to perception and action.
In short, scientific knowledge is rational and objective like that which comes from common sense, but much more rational and
objective than that. The peculiarity of the scientific approach that distinguishes it from common sense is the way it operates, that is,
the scientific method, and the purpose for which this method is applied.
5. Scientific Method
Science is often defined as an accumulation of systematic knowledge . This definition includes three basic terms for the
characterization of science. Yet it is inadequate, like other definitions that emphasize the content of science rather than its
fundamental characteristic: its method of operation. This is inconvenient as the content of science is constantly changing, given that
knowledge considered scientific today may become unscientific tomorrow. Furthermore, the demarcation between science and non-
science is not obvious. Indeed, it is not a sharp line, but a mobile and debated area.
Science aims at understanding the world in which man lives, knowledge of reality. Thus, it is fundamentally a method of approaching
the empirical world, that is, the world susceptible of experience by man. The consensus regarding the essential attributes and
processes of the method of science allows for a functional conceptualization of science through its method, as follows:
- Science is an objective, logical and systematic method of analyzing phenomena created to allow the accumulation of
trustworthy knowledge.
For a better understanding of this definition of science, it is convenient to explain its key terms:
Method. A controversy often arises over the uniqueness of the scientific method. It can be argued that this is not a conceptual issue,
but a mainly semantic problem that arises from the various meanings attributed to the word “method”. Indeed, although the various
fields of science differ in content and techniques, an examination of all highly developed science reveals a common basis of inquiry
procedures, which constitutes the general method of science. The implementation of this method in particular areas of science
usually requires specific techniques and procedures, which constitute the particular methods of science.
Objectve. Objectivity in science refers to attitudes devoid of personal whim, bias, and prejudgment, to methods for discovering
publicly demonstrable qualities of a phenomenon, and to the principle that the last resort of a speculative argument is the objective
phenomenon, that is, an observation or experience that can be publicly verified by trained observers. Evidence in science is factual,
not conjectural, and the “truth” is obtained by empirical demonstration. Although science is practiced by individuals, the scientific
method inspires a rigorous and impersonal way of proceeding, dictated by the demands of logical and objective procedures.
Scientists constantly seek this way of proceeding through training and the use of objectification instruments that allow them to look
at their data with as little bias as possible.
Logical. To say that science is a logical method means that the scientist is constantly guided by acceptable rules of reasoning
standardized by reputable logicians. Competence in science requires competence in logical analysis. Rules of definition, forms of
deductive and inductive inference, probability theory, calculus, etc., are fundamental to any reputable science. Science is a
systematic arrangement of facts, theories, instruments and processes, interrelated by reasoning principles. While one can act in
applied areas by apprehending and applying formulas, acting as a scientist requires a thorough grounding in logical analysis as well
as specific factual proficiency and knowledge.
Systematic. Science is a systematic form of analysis. Science proceeds in an orderly manner, both in the organization of a problem
and in the methods of operation. This is one of the essential features that distinguishes the scientific approach. The systematic
procedure inherent in the scientific approach takes the form of a sequence of tightly interconnected and logically arranged steps that
allows for few deviations. Verification in science is a systematic process of logical inference that requires that premises, facts, and
conclusions be neatly arranged.
The systematic character of science also implies internal consistency. In a well-developed science, the various theories and laws are
interrelated and corroborative. They are mutually supportive or at least not contradicting each other. An immature science is
characterized by internal disagreements between theories, laws, propositions, principles and even methods. It should be noted,
however, that complete and final consistency is never achieved, even in the most advanced sciences. New discoveries suggest new
laws, principles and theories, which, in turn, require the modification of established notions of reality.
Phenomena. The scientific method is applicable to any phenomenon, that is, to any event or behavior that has objectively
demonstrable attributes or consequences. If an event is presumed to be inherently subjective (for example, an idea, a feeling, a
dream), then it is not treatable by scientific analysis unless its presence can be demonstrated through objective attributes or
consequences. Although the phenomena studied by science are publicly verifiable, it should not be understood that such research
objects are the only interest of science. The scientific method is built on a foundation of ideal abstractions (for example, notions,
ideas, theories, laws, principles, etc.) designed to relate and explain observable objects and events. Much of the content of science
consists of intellectual notions about things and events. However, the object of all such thoughts is the particular phenomenon under
study.
Created. Science is a system made up of diverse factual knowledge synthesized in an interrelated and logical set created by human
ingenuity. In turn, the scientific method is a creation to serve a particular purpose: the development and orderly arrangement of that
knowledge and ideas concerning reality in the form that seems most fruitful for the ends to be served. It should be noted that man
arranges his thinking concerning the world in which he lives according to various preferences, and the scientific method is the
arrangement that has so far proved most fruitful for the explanation of objective phenomena..
Accumulation. Science is an accumulative and integrated system, built in an orderly way, where every fact, law, theory, principle,
etc. support other facts, laws, theories, etc. However, science is not a mere accumulation of knowledge. Scientific knowledge is
dynamic. Science always looks for additional knowledge, in the belief that knowledge is never complete. The “truth” in science is
always relative and temporal, never absolute and final. In contrast to many closed philosophical and ideological systems, science is
characterized as an open system of ideas. Therefore, it is constantly growing, discarding erroneous or useless notions and replacing
them with more correct and useful ones in the light of new evidence.
The accumulative attribute of science must not mean that it grows by simple addition. The history of science shows that complex
explanations and designations are constantly being replaced by scientifically simpler and more accurate explanations and
terminology. This principle of parsimony of science determines that the scientist must constantly strive to obtain explanations that
involve as few terms, attributes, concepts and formulas as possible. The accumulative attribute and the principle of parsimon y are
closely intertwined. Indeed, science constantly strives to predict the behavior of as-yet-unobserved phenomena on the basis of the
commonly known qualities they possess as members of a class of phenomena. Together, accumulation, ordering and parsimony
allow a large number of specific predictions to be made from a few basic and general laws.
The term “reductionism” has been used in discussions of this broad principle of parsimony. Reductionism refers to the general
practice of seeking to encompass as many sub-theories as possible in broader and more inclusive categories of "grand theories”.
Although much of the scientific knowledge at any given time is temporarily unrelated or uncoordinated, the scientist constantly
strives to relate isolated facts into meaningful sets or models. The history of science shows that over time such models become
integrated into broader systems of facts and ideas (“theories”) that allow for a greater range of explanations than would be possible
if segmented facts were used in isolation.
Trustworthy knowledge. In the current context, it is referred to trustworthy knowledge for prediction. In this sense, trustworthy
knowledge means correct knowledge. Science constantly strives for precision and accuracy. In fact, science progresses as its
measurements and calculations become more refined. Note, however, that precision and accuracy is not an end in itself. They are
only related to the purposes they serve, that is, the promotion of more specific descriptions that allow for reliable prediction or
control.
The function of the scientific method is to understand phenomena in such a way that the reason and range of accurate predictions
can be constantly increased. Presumably, it is only through a valid and organized system of knowledge, such as science, that
predictions can be effectively extended beyond the limited experience of a particular and simple group of individuals.
Through the scientific method, scientists attempt to generate a body of reliable knowledge. This is achieved by empirical verification
of ideas and beliefs through objective observation.
9. Bases of Science
Interpretations (descriptions or explanations) of phenomena are usually based on some presumed prior knowledge. Since some facts
are required to prove other facts, all knowledge systems are compelled to prove basic facts. As these basic facts cannot be proved,
they must be admitted as fundamental conventions, necessary to any logical or epistemological system. These fundamental facts are
often accepted as indisputable (dogmas) or self-evident. This kind of evidence is, however, a dubious and often unrealistic basis for
establishing valid knowledge. Science rests on basic assumptions supported by logical consistency with experience, which scientists
employ to interpret the evidence needed to produce verified facts, that is, to derive scientific knowledge.
These basic assumptions are the postulates of science. These postulates should not be confused with scientific discoveries.. They
are just functional tools useful for their purposes, while scientific discoveries are confirmed by objective empirical evidence. The
postulates can be changed over time, if the evolution of scientific knowledge demands new forms of reference, as new knowledge
frequently changes the state of previous scientific discoveries.
An examination of the literature reveals that there is no agreement regarding the number and designation of postulates, as there is
still no uniform or typical treatment of the scientific method. The list of eight postulates that follows is just an attempt to concretize
and add what seems to be generally accepted by competent authorities as essential presuppositions of the scientific method.
1) Every event has a natural antecedent ("cause"). Explanations of events must be sought in natural causes or antecedents, that
is, objectively and empirically demonstrable phenomena. This postulate is employed in science in the analysis of causality. Its main
function is to direct the search to explain phenomena to the regularities they apparently obey.
2) Nature is orderly, regular and uniform. The belief that the universe operates according to certain rules of regularity ("natural
laws") is inherent in the scientific analysis of natural phenomena. In practice this belief takes the form of explanations expressed in
terms of inferred probabilities from the particular to the general, or from past experience to the present and hence to the future.
According to this postulate, every phenomenon has an antecedent, and while many phenomena may appear to be unique (for
example, no two storms have identical characteristics), underlying such unique or inexplicable events are certain models of forces
that, when understood, will allow for better prediction than would be possible by mere guesswork. Therefore, direct attention must
be given to the search for qualitative and quantitative relationships that apparently exist between natural phenomena.
This postulate also expresses the apparent fact that nature is not infinitely complex. Thus, the ordering of scientific knowl edge
allows the scientist to develop theories regarding the interrelationships of phenomena and then proceed to a broader analysis of the
universe as a whole.
The implications of this postulate form the basis of scientific logic applied to natural phenomena. It allows for generalizations and
classifications regarding phenomena and supports the probabilistic basis of inference in science; particularly it is indispensable for
sampling. It also suggests the possibility of ever-increasing scope for a more highly integrated general theory, which is the main
aim of all scientific endeavor.
3) Nature is permanent. Although apparently everything changes over time, many phenomena change slowly enough to allow a
reliable body of knowledge to build up. This postulate supports the cumulative attribute of science. It implies the belief that an event
studied today, though perhaps indeterminately altered tomorrow, will nevertheless be sufficiently similar to allow valid
generalizations to be derived about it that remain reliable for a period of time.
4) Every objective phenomenon is knowable. That is, given enough time and effort, no objective problem is unsolvable. This
postulate stems from two related convictions: a) man's intelligence is capable of unraveling the mysteries of the universe; b) man's
search in the mysteries of objective phenomena has been so fruitful that apparently no door to knowledge is immutably closed to
the continued efforts of scientific research.
5) Nothing is self-evident. That is, reality must be objectively demonstrated. This postulate asserts that no reliance should be placed
on so-called "common sense", on tradition, on popular authority, or on any of the customary interpretations of phenomena. Historical
examples reveal that apparent veracity is often very different from objective empirical verification.
6) Truth is relative (to the existing state of knowledge). Evidence in science is always relative - to the state of scientific knowledge,
to the data, to the methods, to the instruments used, to the frames of reference and, therefore, to interpretation. Therefore, the "truth"
in science is simply an expression of the best demonstrable professional judgments at any given time. This postulate does not imply
that stable knowledge cannot be acquired; but it recognizes that knowledge is dynamic and that, as knowledge grows in quality (that
is, it becomes more highly verified) and in quantity, reinterpretations and new conclusions about phenomena become imperative.
This attribute has encouraged the constant re-evaluation of ideas both old and new and has allowed for the extraordinary growth of
science.
7) All perceptions are acquired by the senses. That is, all knowledge is acquired from sensory impressions. The elements and
instruments of reasoning (that is, ideas, concepts, constructions, images, etc.) are shaped by the impressions received by the senses.
This postulate also ensures that the only reliable knowledge is that which is objectively and empirically verifiable.
This postulate originated from the influence of Galileo regarding the demonstrability of theoretical predictions. The empirical
demonstration became the essential test of the validity of all theoretical speculation concerning phenomena and resulting predictions.
8) Man can believe in his perceptions, memory and reason as a means of acquiring facts. This postulate supports the entire
rational and empirical basis of scientific knowledge. It does not imply that any or all perceptions, memories and reasons are
trustworthy. What this postulate asserts is that the final resolution of any dispute over phenomena must be based on accepted rules
of reasoning and on sense-perceived data; not about mere notions and ideas. The ultimate belief in the analysis of phenomena must
be based on empirical evidence interpreted according to rules of logical reasoning.
10. Bibliography
1. Descartes, R. Discurso del método. Barcelona: Altaya, 1993. Spanish.
2. Madden, E.H. (ed.) The structure of scientific thought, an introduction to philosophy of science. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1960.
3. Lastrucci, C.L. The scientific approach, basic principles of the scientific method. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Schenkman, 1963.
4. Bunge, M. La investigación científica, su estrategia y su filosofía. 4. ed. Barcelona: Ariel, 1975. Spanish.
5. Heath, O.V.S.A. Estatística na pesquisa científica. São Paulo: Universidade de São Paulo, 1981. Portuguese.
6. Cervo, A.L.; Bervian, P.A. Metodologia científica. 3. ed. São Paulo: McGraw-Hill, 1983. Portuguese.
7. Wilson, E.B. An introduction to scientific research. New York: Dover, 1990.
8. Hinkelmann, K.; Kempthorne, O. Design and analysis of experiments. New York: John Wiley, 1994.
9. Johann, J.R. Introdução ao método científico; conteúdo e forma do conhecimento. 2. ed. Canoas: Universidade Luterana do Brasil,
1997. Portuguese.
10. Christensen, L.B. Experimental methodology. 7.ed. Boston: Allyn and Bacon, 1997.
11. Carey, S.S. A beginner's guide to scientific method. 2. ed. Belmont, California: Wadsworth, 1998.
12. Gottschall, C.A.M. Do mito ao pensamento científico: A busca da realidade, de Tales a Einstein. São Paulo: Ateneu, 2003.
Portuguese.
13. Silva, J.G.C. Ciência e método científico. Boletim Técnico 6. Instituto de Matemática e Estatística. Pelotas: Universidade Federal
de Pelotas. 2005. Portuguese. Accessed 11 April 2022. Available:
https://www.academia.edu/3068751/Science_and_scientific_method.