Åkervall 2021 A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect
Åkervall 2021 A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect
Åkervall 2021 A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect
Abstract
This essay offers a critical rejoinder to affect theories prevalent in the
humanities since the 1990s. In film and media studies, affect theories
display an opposition to ‘screen’ and apparatus theory of the 1970s
and 1980s alleged to have marginalised the spectator’s body and affects
and privileged cognition over affection. Yet film and media studies’
turn to affect came with its own set of problems: in emphasising the
affective over the cognitive aspects of cinematic experience, theories of
the affective turn invert and reproduce the dichotomies (e.g. body/mind,
affect/thought) they seek to contest. Critically reconsidering the turn to
affect and its place within film and media studies, this article challenges
the relation of affect theories to Gilles Deleuze’s concept of affect,
highlighting these theories’ failure to account for Deleuze’s indebtedness
to Immanuel Kant’s aesthetics and his theory of the faculties. Suggesting
a conception of cinematic affect beyond dichotomies of body and mind,
affect and thought, this essay instead shows how cinematic experience
instigates transformations in spectators that are simultaneously affective
and cognitive.
Jordan Peele’s 2017 horror film Get Out tells the story of Chris
Washington, a young African American photographer who finds himself
caught in a tale of racialised body snatching. While spending the
weekend at the country home of his white girlfriend Rose Armitage’s
the stand-in for the viewers, who collectively learn to see what has been
there all along.
In Get Out, visual media are tools for learning to see. The coordinates
of affect, thought and vision sketched out in this process elaborate a
frame of analysis discerned by Gilles Deleuze in Cinema 2: The Time-
Image as ‘becoming-visionary’. Rejecting the at-the-time popular view
of cinema as a mere apparatus of ideological capture, holding the body
in place to seduce the mind with images, Deleuze suggested an account of
574 Lisa Åkervall
spectator’s body and affects, on the one hand, and privileging cognition,
on the other. Proponents of affective theory criticised screen theory’s
conception of an active and controlling spectator-subject, as well as
screen theory’s fear that the cinematic apparatus induced an artificial
state of regression in the audience. Affect theorists also rejected screen
theory’s marginalisation of the spectator’s body. Within this conceptual
framework, affect served as the neglected flipside of screen theory,
leading affect theorists to foreground and emphasise the affective and
bodily dimensions over and against cognitive aspects of cinematic
experience. As a result, affect theorists tended to duplicate and invert
the dichotomies (e.g. body/mind, affect/thought) they set out to contest
in screen and apparatus theory. These theorists ended up insisting on
the immediacy and purity of an affect divided from thought and thereby
maintaining a one-sided conception of affect that failed to account for
the nuances of Deleuze’s philosophy, which many invoked in support of
their analysis.
In the turn towards affect in film and media studies, Deleuzian and
phenomenological approaches constituted the two major theoretical
camps.2 As an influential example of the former, Steven Shaviro
polemically criticised screen theory in his book The Cinematic Body,
outlining a theory of cinematic experience that foregrounds its affective
dimensions and the spectator’s body, in particular. In this context, he
speaks of a ‘visceral immediacy of cinematic experience’ and ‘primordial
forms of raw sensation’ (Shaviro 1993: 37, 26). Shaviro insists on a
psychophysiology of cinematic experience, by which he means ‘the ways
in which film . . . short-circuits reflection and directly stimulates the
nervous system’ (Shaviro 1993: 53). The Cinematic Body has become
one of the key references for thinking about affect in film theory and
shares a number of assumptions with Brian Massumi’s Parables for the
Virtual. In this book, Massumi distinguishes affect from emotion and
insists on what he calls the ‘autonomy of affect’ (Massumi 2002). The
expression ‘autonomy of affect’ stands in for a concept of affect that
exists independent of thought and thus stands on its own. Massumi’s
differentiation between affect and emotion has led to a number of
misunderstandings in film and media studies concerning the Deleuzian
notion of affect, stemming from the conflation of the relation between
affect and emotion with the relation between body and mind. While
emotions are conceived of as something that we reflect upon and that
we experience consciously, affects are conceived of as ‘prior’ to our
consciousness or even as mere bodily reactions or sensations. Many of
these misunderstandings can be related to rather idiosyncratic readings
A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect 577
It is because what happens to them does not belong to them and only half
concerns them, because they know how to extract from the event the part
that cannot be reduced to what happens: that part of inexhaustible possibility
that constitutes the unbearable, the intolerable, the visionary’s part. (Deleuze
[1985] 1989: 19–20)
Take, for instance, Rossellini’s Europe ’51. The film opens with the
traumatic suicide of a 10-year-old boy, Irene Girard’s son Michael. As
was the case with Chris in Get Out, this event seems at first to render our
protagonist incapable of action, until it gives rise to a new set of agencies
hybridising the affective and the cognitive. From that inaugural event,
the film traces the protagonist Irene’s transformation from a bourgeois
American housewife and member of Rome’s upper-class society to
what Deleuze calls a ‘visionary’ (Deleuze [1985] 1989: 21). Irene is
exemplary of all the other visionaries that populate the cinema books,
and her process of becoming-visionary is paradigmatic of how Deleuze
conceptualises cinematic affect. It thus also exemplifies the concept of
affect sketched out in this article, including the new connection between
affect and thought introduced here.4 Irene’s mutation is at first closely
linked to her personal life: After her son’s suicide her relation to the
world of the Roman bourgeoisie breaks down successively.5
Inspired by her cousin Andrea, a communist journalist, Irene starts to
explore a world hitherto foreign to her: the world of the proletarian
inhabitants of Rome’s suburbs. The inhumanity of these suburbs
overwhelms her. Shocked by what she has seen, Irene decides to take care
of a sick prostitute and to help a single mother with six children get a job
at a newspaper factory.6 As a female version of Francis of Assisi, she is
completely immersed in her helping role.7 At the same time, she becomes
more and more displaced from her role as upper class housewife, from
A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect 581
tells Chris that race was never his concern; instead, he declares, ‘I want
your eyes, man, I want these things you see through’. He wants to see
with Chris’s eyes, to possess Chris’s vision, which in this case is nearly
the same as dispossessing Chris of his vision, rendering him a prisoner in
his own body. In this overwhelming moment, Chris becomes visionary.
He sees the truth of his present, the truth of a contemporary American
racism embodied in educated liberal envy to occupy the position of
A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect 583
the black body without being subject to its constraints; to inhabit its
eye while still commanding white privilege. Becoming-visionary involves
a confrontation with the varieties of forms of bondage, physical and
psychic, that afflict the characters in these films, from the truth of
capitalism in Europe ’51 to that of racism in Get Out, including
carceral capitalism, and its preoccupation with the dispossession of
bodily liberties, and contemporary neoliberal dreams rooted in self-
posing individualism. However, Get Out takes the visionary experience
a step further in making it the reality of its narrative. Whereas Irene in
Europe ’51 is admitted to a closed mental institution for her visions, in
Get Out Chris’s visions entirely coincide with reality itself: the reality of
contemporary America inescapably possessed with the desire to imprison
and inhabit the black body.
experience that always leads from affect to thought, from the sentiendum
to the cogitandum.
As discussed above, the disharmony of the faculties and the encounter
reappear in the processes of becoming-visionary in the cinema of the
time-image (Deleuze [1985] 1989). There are, however, key differences
in how Deleuze presents this differential theory of the faculties in
the context of cinema. More precisely, the confrontation with cinema
inspires Deleuze to develop his differential theory of the faculties into a
differential theory of cinematic affect. Deleuze’s analysis in the cinema
books rests on a distinction between two different uses of vision: the
empirical use of ordinary vision and its transcendental use as visionary
vision. Becoming-visionary means that ordinary vision reaches its limits
and vision assumes its transcendental use. Whereas in a differential
theory of the faculties the encounter unleashes the transcendental
use of the faculties, in a differential theory of cinematic affect the
encounter leads its characters to see differently, to become visionary. The
visionaries encounter situations to which they cannot adequately react.
For example, Irene’s encounter with the factory in Europe ’51 is such a
situation that unleashes a process of becoming-visionary. The encounter
with the reality of the factory has a double function, as it makes it
impossible for Irene to see the factory in a context of sense and purpose.
Instead, in Irene’s gaze the factory transforms into a prison. In this way,
Irene is led to a visionary vision that implies a change of perspective.
The same could be said for Chris’s encounter with the truth of racism
in Get Out. Chris is led to a visionary vision that implies a change of
perspective, showing him the truth about his girlfriend Rose and the
Armitage family as body snatchers, who seek to occupy and possess
his black body. In the concepts of a differential theory of cinematic
affect, we could say that such encounters force to think. They lead to
a disharmony of the faculties and a breakdown of their empirical use.
Vision is forced to assume its transcendental use and becomes visionary.
In that way, the encounter is a starting point for a new, ‘visionary’
kind of vision, as when Irene sees the factory as prison and the
factory workers as convicts, or when Chris sees the white liberals as
body snatchers. Irene and Chris at once grasp the concrete empirical
circumstances and are overwhelmed by them. This confrontation with
perceptual limits triggers a series of affective transformations that
rearrange perceptions. In this account, affect and thought collaborate
in a mode irreducible to either, depending on the constant affective
dislocation of any boundary between them. Ultimately, this triggering
also dislocates the line between character and spectator: the viewers of
588 Lisa Åkervall
Europe ’51 and Get Out undergo parallel redistributions of affect and
thought, none of which may be reduced to affect or cognition alone.
both the affective turn and the new materialism. Canonical expressions
of affect theory and the new materialism agree in their effort to
revise a disproportionate emphasis on the subject and cognition in
the work of Kant and the thinking that comes after it. This has
often led both affect theorists and new materialists to adapt blinkered
conceptual positions based on the premise that overcoming Kant
involves rejecting his philosophy altogether. Yet, the case of becoming-
visionary suggests something different: rather than simply overturning or
rejecting Kant, Deleuze’s intervention offers a possibility of resituating
him – an endeavour that also involves a reconceptualisation of affect.
Deleuze turns Kant’s doctrine of the faculties against itself, resulting
in a differential theory of cinematic affect: a theory of affective
transformation that elides the limits of the traditionally imposed
boundaries between body and mind, affect and thought.
Notes
1. It is notable, in this regard, that his seemingly more working-class African
American friend Rod, who seems less steeped in the gestures of white political
correctness, insistently cautions Chris against the peculiarities of white people,
and Rose’s family in particular, explaining, ‘look bruh, all I’m doin’ is connectin’
the dots, I’m taking what you presented to me’ – admonishments Chris ignores.
2. The affective turn can be discerned not only in Deleuzian film and media
theories, but also in other areas of inquiry, such as feminist or queer film and
media theories.
3. See also del Río’s more satisfactory account of these issues in del Río 2008.
4. For a broader concept of becoming-visionary, see Peretz 2008; an earlier version
of these ideas may be found in Åkervall 2008. See also Åkervall 2018.
5. In his analysis of Europe ’51, Jacques Rancière has shown that Irene’s role
as an outsider is central for the transformations that take place on the level
of the film’s images (Rancière [1990] 2003: 105–34). Gilberto Perez has also
emphasised the way the outsider position is important in Rossellini’s films (Perez
1998: 367–416).
6. This is the context in which we can understand the commentary Angelo Restivo
makes regarding Viaggio in Italia (Roberto Rossellini, Italy 1954) and in relation
to Europe ’51: ‘It is as if the very form of the film is itself exhibiting a breakdown’
(Restivo 2002: 98).
7. Rossellini points out that he conceptualised Europe ’51 – which he made right
after Francesco, Giullare di Dio (Italy 1950) – as a story of a female Francis of
Assisi.
8. On the fear of the hypnotic power of film, see Andriopoulus 2008; for an
affirmative theory of film and hypnosis, see Bellour 2009.
9. For an important work on the presence of Kant’s philosophy in Deleuze’s cinema
books, see Zabunyan 2008.
10. For a more detailed account of Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism and its
indebtedness to Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, see Rölli 2018.
In this context, Rölli also mentions the presence of David Hume’s empiricist
philosophy in Deleuze’s writings. Rölli sees Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism
590 Lisa Åkervall
References
Åkervall, Lisa (2008) ‘Cinema, Affect, Vision’, Rhizomes: Cultural Studies in
Emerging Knowledge, no. 16, available at http://www.rhizomes.net/issue16/
akervall.html (accessed 28 February 2020).
Åkervall, Lisa (2018) Kinematographische Affekte: Die Transformation der
Kinoerfahrung, Paderborn: Fink.
Altieri, Charles (2012) ‘Affect, Intentionality, and Cognition’, Critical Inquiry, 38:4,
pp. 878–81.
Andriopoulus, Stefan ([2000] 2008) Possessed: Hypnotic Crimes, Corporate Fiction,
and the Invention of Cinema, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Balke, Friedrich and Joseph Vogl (1996) ‘Einleitung: Fluchtlinien der Philosophie’,
in Friedrich Balke and Joseph Vogl, Gilles Deleuze: Fluchtlinien der Philosophie,
Munich: Fink, pp. 5–28.
Barad, Karen (2003) ‘Agential Realism’, Signs, 28:3, pp. 803–31.
Barad, Karen (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the
Entanglement of Matter and Meaning, Durham, NC and London: Duke University
Press.
Barker, Jennifer (2009) The Tactile Eye: Touch and the Cinematic Experience,
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Bellour, Raymond (2009) Le Corps du Cinéma: Hypnoses, Émotions, Animalités,
Paris: POL.
Bennett, Jane (2004) ‘The Force of Things: Steps toward an Ecology of Matter’,
Political Theory, 32:3, pp. 347–72, doi: 10.1177/0090591703260853.
Bennett, Jane (2010) Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things, Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Braidotti, Rosi (2006) ‘Posthuman, All Too Human: Towards a New
Process Ontology’, Theory, Culture & Society, 23:7–8, pp. 197–208, doi:
10.1177/0263276406069232.
Brinkema, Eugenie (2014) The Forms of the Affects, Durham, NC: Duke University
Press.
Brown, Bill (2001) ‘Thing Theory’, Critical Inquiry, 28:1, pp. 1–16.
Bruno, Giuliana (2002) Atlas of Emotion: Journeys in Art, Architecture, and Film,
London: Verso.
Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman (eds) (2011) The Speculative Turn:
Continental Materialism and Realism, Melbourne: re.press.
Campbell, Norah, Stephen Dunne and Paul Ennis (2019) ‘Graham Harman,
Immaterialism: Objects and Social Theory’, Theory, Culture & Society, 36:3,
pp. 121–37, doi: 10.1177/0263276418824638.
Deleuze, Gilles ([1963] 1984) Kant’s Critical Philosophy: The Doctrine of the
Faculties, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, London: Athlone
Press.
A Differential Theory of Cinematic Affect 591
Deleuze, Gilles ([1968] 1994) Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New
York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles ([1969] 1990) Logic of Sense, ed. Constantin Boundas, trans. Mark
Lester with Charles Stivale, London: Athlone Press.
Deleuze, Gilles ([1983] 1986) Cinema 1: The Movement-Image, trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, London: Athlone Press.
Deleuze, Gilles ([1985] 1989) Cinema 2: The Time-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson
and Robert Galeta, London: Athlone Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari ([1991] 1994) What is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Graham Burchell, London: Blackwell.
del Río, Elena (2008) Deleuze and the Cinemas of Performance: Powers of Affection,
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Duncan, Pansy (2015) The Emotional Life of Postmodern Film: Affect Theory’s
Other, London: Routledge.
Frank, Adam and Elisabeth A. Wilson (2012) ‘Like Minded’, Critical Inquiry, 38:4,
pp. 870–7.
Gregg, Melissa and Gregory Seigworth (eds) (2010) The Affect Theory Reader,
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Hansen, Mark B. N. (2000) Embodying Technesis: Technology Beyond Writing, Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Hansen, Mark B. N. (2004) New Philosophy for New Media, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Hansen, Mark B. N. (2015) Feed Forward: On the Future of Twenty-First-Century
Media, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hardt, Michael (2007) ‘Foreword: What Affects Are Good For’, in Patricia Ticineto
Clough and Jean Halley (eds), The Affective Turn: Theorizing the Social, Durham,
NC: Duke University Press, pp. ix–xiii.
Harman, Graham (2005) ‘Heidegger on Objects and Things’, in Bruno Latour
and Peter Weibel (eds), Making Things Public: Atmospheres of Democracy,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 268–71.
Harman, Graham (2018) Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything,
London: Pelican.
Ivakhiv, Adrian J. (2013) Ecologies of the Moving Image: Cinema, Affect, Nature,
Waterloo, ON: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.
Jameson, Fredric (1991) Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Kant, Immanuel ([1781 (A), 1787 (B)] 1999) Critique of Pure Reason, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kant, Immanuel ([1785 and 1786] 1997) Critique of Practical Reason, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kant, Immanuel ([1790 and 1793] 2001) Critique of the Power of Judgement,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Laine, Tarja (2011) Feeling Cinema: Emotional Dynamics in Film Studies, London:
Continuum.
Latour, Bruno (2005) ‘From Realpolitik to Dingpolitik, or How to Make Things
Public’, in Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel (eds), Making Things Public:
Atmospheres of Democracy, pp. 4–31. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Leys, Ruth (2011) ‘The Turn to Affect’, Critical Inquiry, 37:3, pp. 434–72.
Leys, Ruth (2012) ‘Facts and Moods: Reply to my Critics’, Critical Inquiry, 38:4,
pp. 882–91.
Massumi, Brian (2002) Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation,
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
592 Lisa Åkervall