Social Benefits of ADR

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 28

THE SOCIAL BENEFITS OF ENHANCING THE

USE OF ALTERNATIVE DISPUTE RESOLUTION


MECHANISMS: AN INTRODUCTORY
ECONOMIC APPROACH

Orlando da Silva Neto

Elton Bonmann

Abstract: The first part of this paper shows that solving social
conflicts through Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR) makes
society economically and socially better-off than solving prob-
lems through the judicial system. The second part of this work
shows how the Rule of Law can be enhanced by the use of ADR
and how these two institutions interact and reciprocally enhance
each other. The effects of the reciprocal relationship between
rule of law and ADR are analyzed through an economic ap-
proach. The research was done using deductive methodology
and bibliographic exploration.

Keywords: Alternative Dispute Resolution; Economic Growth;


Rule of Law; Economic Analysis of Law.

OS BENEFÍCIOS SOCIAIS DO USO DE MÉTODOS ADE-


QUADOS DE SOLUÇÃO DE DISPUTAS: UMA ABORDA-
GEM ECONÔMICA INTRODUTÓRIA

Resumo: A primeira parte deste artigo busca mostrar que a reso-


lução de conflitos por meios de Soluções Alternativas de Dispu-
tas (ADR) torna a sociedade economicamente e socialmente me-
lhor do que a resolução desses mesmos problemas por meio do
sistema judicial. Na segunda parte do trabalho é introduzida a
ideia da rule of law e os meios pelo qual esta instituição pode ser

Ano 6 (2020), nº 4, 2241-2268


_2242________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

melhorada com um aumento do uso de ADR, bem como a natu-


reza da melhora recíproca causada pela interação dessas duas
instituições. Por fim, os efeitos da interação entre rule of law e
ADR são analisados por uma abordagem econômica. A pesquisa
foi realizada utilizando método dedutivo e exploração bibliográ-
fica.

Keywords: Soluções Alternativas de controvérsias; Crescimento


Econômico; Rule of Law; Análise Econômica.

INTRODUCTION

E
xcess or excessive judicial litigation has been con-
sidered an issue of general concern to mostly
every nation in recent decades. This problem is
more significant for some nations than for others,
and sometimes the biggest problems are in places
one would not expect.
Take Japan as an example. The ‘land of the rising sun’ is
well known as a country “that does not litigate”1, but in 2008
2,372.84 new civil and family suits per 100,000 population were
filed2. England and Wales courts received, in 2009, 3,889.05
new civil and family suits also per 100,000 population. On the
same trend, in 2009, 2,271.10 proceedings per 100,000 popula-
tion were filed in Canada. France’s courts received, in 2006,
3,100.57 new lawsuits per 100,000 population. In the United
States, in 2007, were filed 7,925.63 per 100,000 population. And
finally, in Brazil, the litigation champion of this list, in 2009
9,974.60 new civil and family suits per 100,000 population3

1
See: Haley, John (1978). The Myth of the Reluctant Litigant. 4 J. JAPANESE STUD.
359, 389. ("Few misconceptions about Japan have been more widespread or as perni-
cious as the myth of the special reluctance of the Japanese to litigate.").
2
We present statistics related to population rather than absolute numbers, because we
believe this kind of comparison better represents the level of litigation.
3
The methodology, and even some data, used to achieve these rates were similar to
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2243_

were filed.
This growth in litigation represents an increase of
government expenses (as well as an increase in court backlog)
and, as a response to that problem, policy makers from countries
with high rates of litigation have in the last decades created pol-
icies and laws intended at controlling or at least decreasing rates
of judicial litigation.
A not so recent idea is that this problem (the increase in
litigation and associated increase in expenses and backlog) can
be solved through the use of Alternative Dispute Resolution
(ADR) mechanisms, which, put in a simple way, can be thought
of as ways of solving social disputes other than the use of the
Judicial system.
While the idea that ADR may solve the problem of over-
burdened courts is generally accepted by most people, some
scholars claim the use of Alternative Dispute Resolution should
not be a public policy goal, because these alternative ways of
solving conflicts could create “social unfairness” or even in-
crease the rates of litigation in long term4.
On the other hand, other authors, favorable to ADR, af-
firm that to increase the usage rates of these alternative ways of
solving conflicts it is necessary to change the “litigation cul-
ture”5 of a country. There is also extensive literature that

those used by Ramseyer and Rasmusen (2010). However, here the rates of litigation
were based in all the commenced civil and family law cases, not just civil cases. For
the United States data it was considered civil litigation at Federal level. For England
and Wales we considered the data from private law suits involving children, dissolu-
tion of marriage, nullity of marriage and judicial separation. For Brazil, which has a
classification of jurisdiction similar to France, labor issues were considered as civil
cases, like everywhere else. The annex I shows in more detail the data and sources
from which we extracted data.
4
These two ideas are well approached by Owen Fiss (1984) in his classical article
“Against settlement”. Also, Wayne Brazil (1998) express the same concern to ADR:
“Some judges and judicial administrators, for example, might be attracted to ADR
only or primarily as docket reduction tool, posing serious threats to fairness or other
values that ADR should be promoting”.
5
Or even the way how law has been taught at law schools. See Alex Zamboni´s
_2244________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

prescribes the necessity of clear rules and incentives to parties in


order to make them settle outside the Court system6.
The causes to excessive litigation are of a varied nature.
In Brazil, for example, if a person can meet a light burden of
proof that her income is low, she´ll be able to file a suit without
paying any fees or costs7. Furthermore, the State may provide
legal assistance - sometimes the claimant won´t even need to be
represented by a lawyer (small claims can be filed without the
assistance of a lawyer)8. Some of the questions this set-up of
rules arise are related to the incentives generated toward the will-
ingness of the party (who will not bear any judicial costs) to file
a lawsuit and at a later moment settle (or not) a judicial case. Is
this policy/law creating incentives for the party to settle or to
litigate and to what extent9?
The answer seems obvious but deserves some refine-
ment, to be done in this paper, which will also show that Alter-
native Dispute Resolution (ADR) are socially and economically
better than litigation for solving disputes, and that the use of the
former can be enhanced when components of the rule of law are
well-defined.
To do so, in the first part of this work it will be shown
that any controversy that cannot be solved by the parties and
analysis of Brazilian pilot laws regarding to ADR and its inefficacy, since the culture
of litigation were still being taught at the law schools and to lawyers.
6
The classical view of Law and Economics claims that people will change their be-
haviors if there is a concrete incentive toward that.
7
Court fees are suspended and can be recovered by the state up to 5 years after the
sentence is rendered if the assisted party is condemned, but only if a change on the
financial situation of the party happens (this practically never occurs).
8
Art. 9 of the law n. 9.099/1996.
9
Steven Shavell (The Fundamental Divergence Between the Private and the Social
Motive to Use the Legal System. The Journal of Legal Studies, 26(S2), 575-612.
doi:10.1086/468008) reminds us that “The legal system is an expensive social institu-
tion” and that the amount of litigation then happening was not ‘socially appropriate’
because there were “fundamental differences between private and social incentives to
use the legal systems”. He claims that this is because a party “does not take into con-
sideration the legal costs that he induces others to incur” nor “recognize associated
effects on deterrence and certain social benefits”.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2245_

requires third party intervention constitutes a transaction cost 10


and that the use of ADR usually presents a better cost-benefit
alternative (and almost always a faster one, even if more expen-
sive). We will also demonstrate that the wealth saved by the shift
from the judicial system to ADR benefits not only the parties but
also society, as the new uses of this saved wealth can boost eco-
nomic growth and society’s quality of life.
The second part of this paper will deal with the question
of how a well-defined set of rules enhance the use and benefits
of ADR – more so than the Judiciary. To do so, we will introduce
some ideas developed in the “optimistic model of litigation” de-
signed by Robert Cooter11 and then demonstrate how the appli-
cation of these ideas can enhance the use of ADR, the effective-
ness and application of the rule of the law and why this is a good
thing.

PART I – WHY ENHANCE THE USE OF ALTERNATIVE


DISPUTE RESOLUTION MECHANISMS?

It is well accepted that Alternative Dispute Resolution


(ADR) mechanisms, if compared to the judicial system, are
(sometimes) cheaper, (sometimes) faster, more technically pre-
cise and allow more tailored options for parties to solve dis-
putes12, being considered (in The United States and elsewhere)
as the most efficient and important way to solve social

10
If the controversy arises out of a voluntary transaction, then it is a transaction cost;
if it arises out of a non-voluntary issue, such as a tort, it is then a cost of other nature,
but nevertheless a cost.
11
On the classic article “Bargain in the Shadow of Law”.
12
Taking apart arbitration, which can be thought of as “litigation with specialized
judges and with a faster procedure”, and though it is defended that arbitration presents
a better cost-benefit than litigation in the long term, the other forms of ADR disregard
discovery, which is, indeed, the most expensive part of any judicial dispute (see all
this idea at: Folberg; Golann; Stipanowich; Kloppenberg (2016). Resolving Disputes:
Theory, Practice, and Law. 3th Ed. Aspen Publisher. p. 547-552) and Timm (2017).
_2246________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

disputes13.
However, the literature supporting the advantages of
ADR usually analyzes only the advantages for the parties on the
dispute. Very few of the works we consulted were concerned
with demonstrating and measuring whether society would be
economically and socially better-off using ADR in comparison
to judicial litigation14. It is fair to assume that parties to the con-
troversy benefit from the use of ADR, but the question if society
also benefits from the use of ADR has not been fully answered.
For example: If a party to the conflict (or parties, if there
is settlement) decide(s), after the resolution of a dispute, to go
out to celebrate its/their “victory” and purchase a car that costs
$50.000,00, is society benefiting15? Apparently not, because if
the parties had solved their dispute through litigation, there
would still be money for new cars purchases – this time by the
lawyers16 instead of the parties themselves. Intuitively, one
could think that the use of ADR would be neutral to society, a
‘zero-sum game’. Society would not be any better or worse-off
with either the use of ADR or of the Judicial system.
We believe that this conclusion is wrong. Even though
the example above may reasonably create the idea that the out-
come would be socially neutral, ADR actually makes society
better-off, because if we consider that the judicial system

13
To know more about the enhancement of ADR in U.S., see: Galanter, Marc (2004).
The Vanishing Trial: An Examination of Trials and Related Matters in Federal and
State Courts. Journal of Empirical Studies. V. 1. Issue 3. See also: Judicial Council
of California/Administrative Office of the Courts (2004). Evaluation of the Early Me-
diation Pilot Programs.
14
See the question, “would society be better-off or worse-off through ADR?” at: Fol-
berg; Golann; Stipanowich; Kloppenberg (2016). op. cit. p. 14.
15
Assume that the joint benefit (compared to litigation) is $ 50.000,00.
16
In real world the trial expenses are shared with agents of justice and others, such as
experts brought in trial, for example. In the example above, we opted to use only the
attorneys to simplify the idea that expenses incurred by someone in trial are just a
typical ‘opportunity cost’, in a sense that they are being paid to these agents of Justice
and not used elsewhere (the opportunity). In the example lawyers’ fee in litigation are
the exact same value saved by the use of ADR.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2247_

represents a high transaction cost, the shift from the judicial lit-
igation to ADR would lower the opportunity cost of solving dis-
putes17. This means a twofold benefit. First, ADR use is better
because ADR adjudicators are better prepared to do their jobs
(more technical in arbitration, more skilled in other techniques)
and are not (in most cases) bound by the rules of federal civil
procedure. Judiciary cannot compete or improve (at least in Bra-
zil), because judges are bound to current rules of civil procedure,
but also due to the generalistic nature of their progression in the
career – it is hard to find specialization – and due to the current
process of admission of new judges.
Second, if the wealth saved remains with the parties, es-
pecially if they’re business entities, their use of the savings will
probably be more efficient that if the corresponding amount was
attributed to the state (court fees) or to agents of the court (liti-
gation expenses).These savings can be put to productive uses
that lead to creation of new products and improvement of exist-
ing ones. In other words, economic growth and society’s quality
of life would be increased.
To understand this statement, the reader needs to have a
general idea of what constitutes the wealth of a society. Because
the wealth of a society could be measured in diverse ways, we
opted to use a simple measure - Gross Domestic Production
(GDP)18. We will demonstrate what composes GDP, how it is
increased by the creation of new and diverse products 19, what is
17
See Luciano Benetti Timm. Análise econômica da arbitragem.
https://lawle2014.files.wordpress.com/2017/10/timm-10042016-aed-da-arbitragem-
livro-tarcicc81sio-lmj.pdf
18
To know more about GDP, see: Kuznets, Simon (1934). National Income, 1929-32.
National Bureau of Economic Research. Strictly defined, GDP is the sum of market
values of all goods and services consumed and invested in an economy during a period
of time.
19
For a deeper analysis about the enhancement of economic growth through new
products creation, see: Jorgenson, Dale; Ho, Mun; Samuels, Jon (2014). Long-Term
Estimates of U.S. Productivity and Growth. See also: Ayres Robert (1989). Techno-
logical Transformation and Long Waves. International Institute for Applied Systems
Analysis.
_2248________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

quality of life (and also how to enhance and diminish it), what
are the transaction costs20 that lower GDP and how judicial liti-
gation and ADR are related to all these subjects. We opted to
demonstrate these concepts with the use of some simple exam-
ples.
We start by explaining Gross Domestic Production
(GDP) and how it increases or decreases. We use a very closed
and small economy to make the example easier. Suppose a na-
tion (x) has a total of 4 people that only grow and produce pota-
toes and each person consumes only 1 potato in a time (y) (as-
sume they could consume more things if those were different
from potatoes21), but produces 2 potatoes on this nation at the
same time (y). The total production of this nation is 8 potatoes,
of which 4 would be consumed and other 4 would be stocked.
GDP is generally thought of as the sum of everything
produced by a nation, but that is not fully correct. GDP is actu-
ally measured by the sum of all things consumed and invested22
by national and international players, including government23.
Therefore, because the example here is related to a closed nation
and the potatoes stocked cannot be consumed or invested (no
one in this country wants to consume more potatoes), the GDP
of the nation (x) would be only 4 potatoes.
GDP also increases when new products are created and
offered in the market. Suppose now that instead of having 4 per-
sons producing only potatoes (2 potatoes each), one of these
20
See the general idea of transaction costs at: Coase, Ronald (1960). The problem of
Social Costs. The Journal of Law and Economics.
21
The idea of “the more you have regarding to something, the less you want it, and
the less you have regarding to something, the more you want it”, well illustrated in
the example by a person that is saturated with potatoes, but could consume other
things, is in accordance with utilitarian theory. See: Fishburn, Peter (1970). Utility
Theory for Decision Making. John Wiley & Sons. Inc.
22
Since it is the consumption of things to create and upkeep capital goods or income
producing properties.
23
See the summary of the GDP formula at: Encyclopedia Britannica: https://www.bri-
tannica.com/topic/gross-domestic-product. Retrieved on 28th June. And the original
formula at the report cited above: Simon (1934).
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2249_

persons gets tired of producing potatoes and obtains the


knowledge to start producing wheat and making bread (new
product) out of the wheat. Assume that this different player pro-
duces 2 loafs of bread and that his personal consumption is only
1 bread (but he could consume more food, just like the potato
producers, if there was the opportunity to consume things other
than bread24). In this new setting, this nation would have pro-
duced 8 units of product - 6 potatoes and 2 breads, just like the
first example. However, the GDP of this nation would be higher
because the bread producer can trade with the potato producer
one stocked bread for one stocked potato. If that was the case,
GDP would increase to 4 potatoes and 2 loafs of bread, 6 items
(the trade would result in the consumption of one extra bread
and one extra potato). Given our assumption that the price of a
potato is equal to the price of bread, this new situation would
increase the GDP of the nation (x) by 50% simply by changing
the production of potato to bread (a new product). Diversity
matters.
Let’s now add a new component of complexity:
the idea of quality of life. Quality of life has multiple definitions
and measures, subjective ones (such as happiness 25) and objec-
tive ones (a person with ownership and rights of use to a boat, a
car, a house, food, access to health services and no debts has –
or at least is usually thought of having - a better quality of life
than a person without a similar house, no food, no access to
health services and debts, at least from a majoritarian perspec-
tive)26. Since the subjective standard for quality of life tends to
be a moralistic and abstract proxy, it will not be of concern to

24
Same as the idea discussed on the footnote 16.
25
Examples of abstract definitions for quality of life are: Human Development Index
and World Happiness Report. See those respectively at: United Nation Development
Program and Helliwell, Layard, & Sachs (2018).
26
The objective definition of quality of life is related to the quantity of GDP per capital
of a nation, in other words, the quantity and quality of things consumed. The more
you consume, better your quality of life is.
_2250________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

this work, but having an objective standard to measure quality


of life is an important part of our argument.
Analyzing the situations related to the examples above,
it can be agreed that the society with the bigger GDP also has
the better quality of life, and that is not just because of the higher
GDP, but because on the second nation there were two, of the
four people, who consumed not just potatoes, but also bread, re-
sulting in more quality of life/more utility27. Again, diversity
(access to different options) matters.
Next, there is the idea of transaction costs. To understand
the concept, a little bit of complexity must be added to the ex-
ample. Suppose now that nation (x) has two potato producers
(and each one produces now 3 potatoes), a ‘for hire’ peacekeeper
(his activity is to compel people to keep the order – or restore it,
once broken) and a thief. Initially, the GDP of this society is 2
potatoes, while 4 potatoes are stocked and not part of GDP
(while 6 are produced, only 2 are consumed). Imagine now that
the thief, knowing about the stock of potatoes, steals 2 potatoes
from one of the potatoes’ owners. Before the thief can eat one of
the potatoes, the stolen potato owner hires the peacekeeper (for
the cost of one potato) to catch the thief. The peacekeeper exe-
cutes his service perfectly, getting one potato back to its rightful
owner and maintaining one to himself (his payment).
In this setting, production is now 6 potatoes and 1 peace-
keeper service, while GDP is 3 potatoes and 1 service of the
peacekeeper. Looks like the total outcome on this third example
is better than the initial situation (without the action of the thief),
mainly because GDP increased from 2 potatoes to 3 potatoes and
1 service, a 100% enhancement on the GDP (assuming, for sim-
plicity purposes, the service of the peacekeeper has the price of
a potato).
However, the potato owner’s consumption of the peace-
keeper services did not mean an increase on his wealth or utility

27
The notion of utility used in this work does not refer to the utilitarian approach.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2251_

(if compared to the initial situation). Even though he voluntarily


consumed the peacekeeper services, this service is a typical
transaction cost, because its only purpose was to get back the
two potatoes stolen by the thief28. In substance, the transaction
with the peacekeeper was analogous to a (unwilling) “donation”
of one potato, that is to say, the potato’s owner did not have an
additional gain (he just avoided a loss).
In addition, in this last example society would be actually
economically and socially better if the thief and the peacekeeper,
instead of robbing and combating crime, had produced, for ex-
ample, 2 loafs of bread the first and 2 bushels of corns the second
(assuming also that each would consume one corn and one bread
and exchange the remaining with the others29). This new setting
would account for the “best” social scenario among all the ones
seen so far, because the people would have consumed everything
produced in this nation, resulting in a GDP of 4 potatoes 30, 2
breads and 2 corns (8 items produced and consumed), a 100%
increase when in comparison to example 1 (where 4 potatoes’
producers grew 2 potatoes each and only 4 potatoes were con-
sumed). Perhaps even more importantly, every person in this
new situation would have eaten more than one item (For exam-
ple: 1. potato-bread; 2. potato-corn; 3. corn-potato; 4. bread-po-
tato) which presumably means an increase in quality of life and
not only an increase in economic terms.
However, to arrive at this best situation, thieves should
not exist, and in their absence, there would be no need for

28
Though it was considered here that the peacekeeper service is a transaction cost,
some authors from economics claims that this type of work could be also considered
a rent-seeking activity. See for example: Murphy, Kevin; Shleifer, Andrei; Vishny,
Robert (1991). The allocation of Talent: Implications for Growth. The Quarterly Jour-
nal of Economics. V. 106. N. 2. And a general discussion on rent-seeking activities
and transaction costs at: Murshed, S. (2001). Transaction Costs Politics, Institution
for commitment of Rent-Seeking. UNU World Institute for Development Economics
Research (UNU/WIDER).
29
Just like the potato producers.
30
Assume that each potato producer has produced only 2 potatoes.
_2252________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

peacekeepers, and both the former thief and the former peace-
keeper would be free (and need) to produce something of value.
The production surplus, if existing, could be exchanged with
others that also had resources stocked.
Likewise, if a person spends more and more his “stocks”
(his savings) on things of a nature similar to a peacekeeper’s ser-
vices (transaction costs), society will see a reduction on eco-
nomic growth and quality of life. A nation with a high number
of people offering services similar to the “peacekeeper” is
worse-off than one that does not have the need for such ser-
vices31, not only because of the negative aspects of the thief’s
‘products’, but because neither thief nor peacekeeper are actu-
ally producing things that maximize the wealth of society 32.
What does all of the above have to do with ADR? A lot,
and we can now draw a parallel toward the judicial system and
explain our thesis regarding ADR and its social benefits.
First, we can draw an analogy: peacekeeper services are
of a similar nature to services offered by lawyers, prosecutors,
clerks, judges, etc. (the judicial system), services that depend on
the existence of ‘wrongdoers’33. Because agents of justice only
work to compensate harm to others, enforce breached contracts
and things of the like, they are not adding wealth to society (in
fairness, they are preventing wealth loss, but that is second best
to adding wealth).
Second, if it is possible to reduce the costs (not only fi-
nancial ones) of using the judicial system by solving disputes in
a less bureaucratic and efficient way (ADR), society will actu-
ally be “better-off”, because the decrease on money spent

31
And not only because of the absolute number, but because of the need for the ser-
vices provided.
32
They are just taking part of the production of others, whether voluntarily (peace-
keeper) or not (thief).
33
The idea of wrongdoer applies not only to persons that committed crimes, but, also
include ones that have not fulfilled its contractual obligations or others that violate
third party’s rights and privacy.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2253_

(and/or gain on time) with judicial litigation would mean not


only a gain to the parties involved, which can put this gain to
good use, but also a shift in people offering this service34 to more
productive uses of their time and capabilities. In other words, a
consequent allocation of human capital to areas that ‘produce
new products’35 and generate social wealth.
Besides, even if the shift in the expenses from the judicial
system to ADR36 does not change the number of people working
on dispute resolution (an unrealistic assumption), ADR repre-
sents a ‘better cost-benefit’ “transaction cost”37 (or in other
words, a lesser transaction cost) than the judicial system, which
means that the use of ADR will save more wealth than judicial
litigation, wealth that could be allocated to other economically
productive areas. That’s why we make a claim that the use of
ADR will generally make society economically and socially bet-
ter-off than the use of the judicial system. Of course, this claim
assumes that ADR represents a more cost-benefit effective alter-
native than the use of Judiciary.

PART II – ENHANCING ALTERNATIVE DISPUTE RESO-


LUTION THROUGH THE OBSERVANCE OF A STABLE
AND PREDICTABLE SET OF RULES (THE RULE OF
LAW).

In this part we will deal with the relationship between


34
Supply and demand (Say’s law). See: Jean Baptiste-Say (1803). A Treatise on Po-
litical Economy: production, distribution and consumption of wealth. Augustus M.
Kelley Publishers.
35
In United States, for example, it can be assumed that someone that can be educated
to be a lawyer could also choose to be an engineer or open a business and create new
products.
36
Notice either that no emphasis was given regarding the differences of outcome (re-
covery) through the litigation system or through settlements by ADR. It is assumed
that the plaintiff will receive the same amount through both systems, which may not
be a realistic assumption is some cases.
37
Litigation and ADR are both transaction costs because both are means for solving
conflict between parties.
_2254________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

ADR enhancement and the improvement of the rule of law. We


first introduce some ideas developed by Robert Cooter (and oth-
ers) when they developed the “optimistic model of litigation” on
the classic article “Bargaining in the Shadow of Law”38. Focus-
ing on a specific idea developed at that paper, we will analyze
that relationship with examples about the application of the rule
of the law, using an economic approach we believe to bring rel-
evant insights.
In his famous article, Robert Cooter analyzes some
causes that influence parties’ decision (variables) to litigate in-
stead of bargaining/settling. The author divided the variables in
two groups: (i) those that subjectively influence settlement rates
(psychological variables that depend on the emotions of the par-
ties) and (ii) legal institutions (variables controlled by law) that
influence the “game players” in their decision to settle or to pur-
sue a trial judgment.
Initially, there are variables that increase or decrease the
likelihood of settlement39, as follow: a) urgency for a solution
by the parties (it increases the likelihood of settlement); b) im-
proved value of trial for one litigant (trial’s expected outcomes
are different for the parties, what decreases likelihood of settle-
ment); c) increase in transaction costs of negotiation, which en-
hances the urgency to solve the dispute (increases likelihood of
settlement); d) increase of transaction costs on trials (increases
likelihood of settlement); e) increase in earnings per period con-
tingent on no resolution of the dispute (decreases likelihood of
settlement); f) increase in spitefulness toward opponent (de-
crease settlement); g) less risk aversion by one or both parties
(decrease settlement); h) increase in the familiarity of oppo-
nents, in case of repetitive disputes with the same parties (in-
crease settlement).
38
See: Cooter, Robert (1982). Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable
Model of Strategic Behavior. Berkeley Law.
39
See all the predictions and legal institutions at: Cooter, Robert (1982). op.cit. p.
238-240 and p. 242-243.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2255_

The article then describes the legal institutions that affect


the rates of settlement, such as: a) increase on the use of govern-
ments’ institutions, the judiciary, when the external bargain
costs (transaction costs) are high; b) increase of settlement by
the insertion/existence of Rule 998 of the California Code of
Civil Procedure (or the rule 68 of the United States Rules of
Civil Procedure40), which creates incentives to the parties to bid
for settlement in good faith, and; c) pessimistic parties are more
attracted to litigate in the American Judicial system than the
British judicial system (and also the European civil law system),
because the loser on the British system bears the costs of litiga-
tion incurred by the winning party.
It is easy to realize that subjective variables are very de-
pendent on circumstances of the parties involved. The policy-
maker cannot control plaintiff’s expected behavior in the next
dispute, and neither can he foresee (or influence) if the party will

40
At the time Cooter wrote his paper, the rule 68 of the United States Federal Rules
of Civil Procedure, which is a copy of the alluded rule from California, was not en-
acted yet. That rule states as follows (https://www.federalrulesofcivilproce-
dure.org/frcp/title-viii-provisional-and-final-remedies/rule-68-offer-of-judgment/,
access in 14/11/2019):
Rule 68 – Offer of Judgment
(a) Making an Offer; Judgment on an Accepted Offer. At least 14 days before the date
set for trial, a party defending against a claim may serve on an opposing party an offer
to allow judgment on specified terms, with the costs then accrued. If, within 14 days
after being served, the opposing party serves written notice accepting the offer, either
party may then file the offer and notice of acceptance, plus proof of service. The clerk
must then enter judgment.
(b) Unaccepted Offer. An unaccepted offer is considered withdrawn, but it does not
preclude a later offer. Evidence of an unaccepted offer is not admissible except in a
proceeding to determine costs.
(c) Offer After Liability is Determined. When one party’s liability to another has been
determined but the extent of liability remains to be determined by further proceedings,
the party held liable may make an offer of judgment. It must be served within a rea-
sonable time—but at least 14 days—before the date set for a hearing to determine the
extent of liability.
(d) Paying Costs After an Unaccepted Offer. If the judgment that the offeree finally
obtains is not more favorable than the unaccepted offer, the offeree must pay the costs
incurred after the offer was made.
_2256________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

be willing to solve the controversy quickly, if he is risk averse


or not. These variables are just some proxies that influence the
decision-making process leading to settlement or litigation but
can’t be used by lawmakers and institutions to design structures
applicable to all cases in order to increase settlement rates. Legal
institutions, however, can be objectively designed to increase
settlement rates. In other words, they can be controlled and de-
signed to achieve a specific public policy goal.
For example, Rule 998 of the California Code of Civil
Procedure (or the rule 68 of the United States Rules of Civil Pro-
cedure) works as a settlement inductor. Through this rule, if a
defendant makes a formal settlement offer to the plaintiff, the
plaintiff must pay the cost incurred by the defendant after the
offer is made, unless (assuming the case is tried to verdict) the
awarded compensation exceeds the amount of the offer41. The
application of this rule does not depend on personal characteris-
tics of the parties and it can therefore be used in any situation
where a settlement offer has been made before (or even during)
trial.
Rule of Law is (can also be thought of) a legal institution
that influences the decision to settle or litigate. Rule of Law does
not have a precise definition, so for this paper we will consider
it as the simple idea/rule that emanates from the judicial system
through the combined application of statutory law and jurispru-
dence. In order that the rules of the game be predictable, the rule
of law requires a fair and stable Judiciary.
There is already some literature that asserts that a well-
defined rule of law can increase settlement rates. Most scholars 42
41
One of the authors has presented a draft idea similar to Rule 68 of the USFRCP, to
be used in Brazil. For details, see Silva Neto, Orlando. Responsabilidade civil pela
perda do tempo útil: tempo é um ativo indenizável. (in English, Is time spent in pursuit
of compensation a indemnifiable asset?) In. Rodrigues Jr., Otávio (org). Revista de
Direito Civil Contemporâneo, N. 2. V. 4, Ju/Sept. 2015, p. 139-162.
42
Somehow contrary to this “main conception”, Dan Foote (1995) showed that when
Japan courts started publishing “the rule of thumb” for traffic accidents (which equal-
ized the Rule of Law toward this matter and even increased the potential damages
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2257_

are already aware and agree with the notion that when the rule
of law is well established, reasonably stable and clear 43, parties
will know (or are more likely to know) the expected outcome of
the controversy and will bargain to a solution close to the one
predicted by the rule. However, if the rule of law is not clear, the
variance in rules will mean a variance in the likely outcomes,
which, when framed by human biases (such as I -plaintiff- will
receive more and I – defendant - will pay less: Overconfi-
dence44), will make the parties more likely to pursue a trial rather
than settlement45.
For example: assume that for a given labor accident type
(x) with the same (or very similar) consequences to the injured
party courts of the country award compensation for actual loss
of income equally but damages related to pain vary from
$10.000 to $60.000. In this case, the plaintiff will pursue com-
pensation and damages related to pain in a value close to

recovered by plaintiffs), the number of complaints one year after its publication (1968-
1969) spiked from 5,514 to 10,416. An interesting fact is that after this abrupt increase,
in 1970, the number of deaths by traffic accidents and complaints filed, which were
constantly increasing since 1964, started to decrease. Deaths from traffic accidents
dropped from 21,535 in 1970 to approximately 12,000 in 1978 and kept constant until
1983 (where the data of his research ends). On the other hand, the number of com-
plaints, which reached its peak at 11,620 in 1970, dropped every year to its lower level
in 1983 with 3,235. In addition, the author of that work still compares this situation to
other kinds of civil suits, showing that the decrease in traffic accident litigation was
way bigger than any other sphere of civil litigation.
43
Classical authors that made such claim include Landes (1971) and Posner (1973).
Also, for a more specific discussion on the idea that the clearer is the rule of law, the
bigger is the rates of settlement, see: Albiston, Catherine (1991). The rule of law and
the Litigation Process: The paradox of Losing by Winning. Berkeley Law Scholarship
Repository. Also, the relative influence of any legal outcome and its dependence to
the effective communication of the result and its meaning (Galanter 1983). And the
difference in settlement rates when a matter is approached through written judicial
opinion or by confidentiality agreements and the dearth of information (Erlanger et
al. 1987). A discussion of this idea in Brazil, see Gico Jr. (2014).
44
See this cognitive bias at: Samson, A. (Ed.)(2017). The Behavioral Economics
Guide 2017 (with an introduction by Cass Sunstein). Retrieved from:
http://www.behavioraleconomics.com. p. 95.
45
See Bianca Bez Goulart, Análise econômica do litígio, Editora Jus Podium, 2019.
_2258________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

$60.000. The defendant will evaluate the amount that he will


probably pay related to pain close to $10.000. The farther these
amounts are from each other, the lesser the probability of settle-
ment. On the contrary, if jurisprudence was well established and
uniform, stating a rule like, “the plaintiff will receive 3x the
value of the actual injury” or “high pain is equal to $60.000”,
both parties would be aware of the probable outcome and would
settle for a value close or equal to the value of the court ordered
decision46 (all other relevant variables equal). This is an idea
most scholars agree with and is sort of a fundamental pillar of
economic analysis of litigation.
This paper intends to analyze the question from a differ-
ent perspective. We bring two concrete examples of how the rule
of law should be molded to increase ADR rates. These examples
are valid for both Common and Civil law.
First, there are interventions that can be done through
statutory law, reducing judicial discretion. Statutory law should
avoid general clauses or gaps which the judge can fill out ac-
cording to his discretion. The role of the judge in litigation
should only be to consider the facts and circumstances and apply
the law, not create the law. Even questions about burden of proof
shouldn’t be defined by judges, but by statute. If that is not the
case, settlement rates will be low.
To illustrate the concept, let’s examine the differences
between the application of law regarding drug possession in the
state of New York and Brazil.
As per article 42 of the Brazilian federal antidrug law n.
11.343/200647, the punishment for drug possession depends of
various factors mentioned in article 59 of the Brazilian penal

46
Assuming there are no more attractive alternatives for the defendant – like using his
money in an investment that will bring better results than the interest to be paid in
case of a court judgement.
47
BRASIL. LEI Nº 11.343, DE 23 DE AGOSTO DE 2006. Retrieved from:<
http://www.planalto.gov.br/ccivil_03/_ato2004-2006/2006/lei/l11343.htm>
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2259_

code48, as well as others, such as the quantity of drugs seized and


the type of drug. The problem of using these factors is that they
do not objectively specify the proportion of punishment regard-
ing the quantity of drugs or which drugs are more “harmful” than
others. The consequence is discretionary sentencing by judges.
For example, one judge can find that 10 grams of some drug (x)
is a relevant amount and profer a harsh sentence. Another judge
can decide that this same quantity is insignificant and conclude
that the possession by the offender is not a serious criminal of-
fense, therefore disqualifying the conduct to possession for
one’s own use, a much lesser offense.
Now let´s look at the NY penal code49, section 220 and
on. The Code states punishment for possession of drugs is based
in seven degrees of quantity and type of drugs. Differently from
the Brazilian criminal law, the NY penal code reduces judge’s
discretion to determine the punishment depending on the quan-
tity and type of drugs. These two different laws create different
incentives. In Brazil, both defendant and prosecution have more
incentives to appeal because of the likelihood that there will be
a precedent in favor of both parties in dispute. In New York,
there is less uncertainty and, in consequence, more of an incen-
tive to engage into settlement.
On the other hand, the behavior of judges and courts also
influence the formation of the rule of Law and impact settlement
rates. Courts with the highest hierarchy should define leading
cases for each matter of law, decisions that should be followed
by lower courts (the ‘stare decisis’ conception50). These deci-
sions have to be followed by these primary courts and judges
(precedent should always be acknowledged in the judgement,

48
BRASIL. DECRETO-LEI No 2.848, DE 7 DE DEZEMBRO DE 1940. Retrieved
from:< http://www.planalto.gov.br/ccivil_03/decreto-lei/del2848compilado.htm>
49
STATE OF NEW YORK. New York Consolidated Laws, Penal Law – PEN. Re-
trieved from:< http://ypdcrime.com/penal.law/article220.htm>
50
See a critical discussion over the stare decision at: Collier, Charles (1988). Prece-
dent and Legal Authority: A Critical History. UF Law School Repository.
_2260________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

even if the judge concludes, for any reason, differently to the


precedent established by the higher court).
The observance of precedent is one of the factors that
have made common law systems more predictable than civil law
systems. Willian Tetley51 affirms that one of the main differ-
ences is that decisions in common law are generally based on
judgements of the superior courts while the decisions in civil law
systems are mainly based in doctrinal appointments. Based on
that, the common law system developed to be more secure and
predictable (giving parties incentives to settle instead of litigat-
ing) than the civil law system. This happens because when civil
law systems base its judgments in doctrine, any decision can be
justified. Judges can simply pick and choose the commentator
they like best.
One possible solution to curb court discretion is a return
to legal positivism.52 Positivism is somewhat opposed and in-
compatible with mainstream movements like neo-constitution-
alism, widely accepted and applied in Europe and Latin Amer-
ica53, but it is also different from legal realism and from the eco-
nomic approach chiefly applied in United States54.
Legal positivism could work alongside legal realism and
the economic approach to boost ADR because these approaches
will lead to predictable decisions. Judges will have very little
discretionary power and judgment outcomes will be foreseeable.
This predictability also increases the likelihood of settlement in
the Judiciary, but has an even bigger effect in ADR. If the out-
comes are more predictable, why not get there using the

51
Tetley, William (2000). Mixed Jurisdictions: Common Law v. Civil Law (Codified
and Uncodified). Louisiana Law Review. Volume 60. Number 3.
52
See: H. L. A. Hart, (1958). Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals.
71 Harvard Law Review 593, 601-2.
53
See: Tim, Luciano (2014). Direito e Economia no Brasil. Atlas. 2 ed. p. 7.
54
See: William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner (1992). The Influence of Economics
on Law: A Quantitative Study. Chicago Unbound. An also: Kendall, Keith (2011).
The Use of Economic Analysis in Court Judgments: A Comparison between the
United States, Australia and New Zealand. Pacific Basin Law Journal, 28(2).
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2261_

alternatives that present better cost-benefit?


However, legal positivism, when twisted by the neo-con-
stitutionalism approach (as it happens in Brazil), would probably
decrease ADR and settlement rates. This would happen because
the tools which judges use when they apply the law under a neo-
constitutionalism view are open concepts, like human rights55,
social function (of contract; of property), ethics and moral,
which, in fact, are hugely vague and allow for great variance of
decisions from judge to judge, court to court, etc (discretionary).
Based on the above, it is easy to conclude that socially
(in terms of net benefits to society) we have the following scale
of combinations: 1) ADR + stable/predictable rules; 2) Judiciary
+ stable/predictable rules; 3) ADR under uncertain/unpredicta-
ble rules; and 4) Judiciary under uncertain/unpredictable rules.
Finally, but not less important, the importance of prece-
dent, legal certainty and stability can also be perceived through
the lens of economics, specifically when the classic “economic
model of litigation” is applied to concrete situations.
The “economic model of litigation” (considering now the
rule of law as a variable) highlights the importance of ADR
when one correctly understands the equation below56:

R = [D + P(D)]

Va = (1-(1/da)).R – [Ca + (pa.da)]

Vb = (1/db).R + [Cb + (pb.db)]

In the formula, “R” represents the rule of law (statutory


and jurisprudence prescription). “D” represents the value of the
‘monetarily quantifiable’ damages suffered by the plaintiff from
55
Tim, Luciano (2014). op cit. p. 8.
56
This mathematic model is an adaptation of the classical model of litigation. See the
classical model at: Spurr, Stephen (2010). Economic Foundations of the Law. 2. ed.
Routledge. p. 174-175.
_2262________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

the defendant’s act. “P” is the proportion of the court amount


regarding to the concrete damages that the defendant caused to-
wards the plaintiff (not always applicable, because sometimes
these damages are not related to monetarily quantifiable dam-
ages). “P(D)” is the value given by the court to the plaintiff as
financial compensation for non-promptly measurable damages,
such as punitive damages, pain and suffering damages, etc.
“Va” represents the expected amount that the plaintiff
thinks he will recover from the dispute. “Vb” is the expected
amount that the defendant thinks he will pay for the plaintiff.
“da” and “db” (“dx”) represent the amount of discovery that the
parties are willing to pursue relative to expected recovery or pay-
ment, a value higher than 1. “pa” and “pd” (“px”) represent the
costs with discovery, which are specific to each case but pre-
sumably cheaper for the party acting in good faith (because it
will be easier for her to raise evidences in her favor). And, fi-
nally, “Cx” (a or b) represents attorney expenses occurred on
trial.
Notice that “Cx” and “pxdx” are all transaction costs in-
curred by parties to solve this dispute through litigation, which
could be mitigated through settlement. Notice also that settle-
ment (S) will occur when Va ≤ S ≤ Vb57.
Thus, if the rule of law is not well defined and, for exam-
ple, Va= $10.000,00; da = 2 , and Vb thinks R = $5.000,00; db
= 2, even though both parties think their probability of win-
ning/losing are the same, dx = 2, which breaks the effect of over-
confidence and help the parties to settle58, and even though ex-
penses with discovery and attorney fees also create incentives to

57
Consider that if plaintiff expects to recover at least 100 and defendant expects to
pay at most 200, then there´ll be a settlement (provided that defendant has resources
for paying the settlement) range between 100 and 200. If plaintiff expects to recover
100 but defendant expects to pay only 50, there´ll be no settlement.
58
This happens because people are generally risk averse, and since there is already an
established rule of law, the parties will know who is liable (different than the court
that needs to discover that), and then will tend to settle.
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2263_

settle, the parties will litigate this case to the end rather than
reach a settlement, because Plaintiff Va will accept values equal
or bigger than $5.000,00 (VA ≤ 5000) and defendant Vb will
settle only when the amount of the bid is equal or smaller than
$2.500,00.
When the costs of litigation are high, the probability of
settlement will be higher (tend to one59). When transaction costs
to litigate are low, the probability of settlement will be lower
(tend to zero). The same is true when the rule of law is stable
and predictable. The probability of parties to settle will tend to
one under a clear and stable rule of law. When the rule of law is
not clear, the probability of an agreement will tend to zero. This
can be expressed as follows60:

Figure 1 - Probability of Settlement versus Rule of Law

59
We assume for purposes of this simple model that both parties will incur in the same
costs. If costs are different, then the likelihood of settlement will be affected differ-
ently. There may be one party more prone to settlement, while the other may refrain
from it.
60
In the graph, 1 means something that will certainly happen and zero means some-
thing that will certainly not happen.
_2264________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

CONCLUSION

We showed that the use of ADR benefits not only the


parties to the dispute, but also that ADR makes society econom-
ically and socially better-off than the use of the judicial system.
This happens because ADR allows for more productive ways to
allocate time and resources, consequently causing the enhance-
ment of economic growth and society´s quality of life. In the
second part, we explained that the use of ADR can be enhanced
through a well-defined rule of law.
We demonstrated that the judicial system is a high trans-
action cost, and the shift from judicial litigation to ADR would
enhance economic growth, the creation of new products and so-
ciety’s quality of life. This effect will be even higher under a
stable rule of law. To do so, we applied theoretical tests based
on a “standard model of litigation” designed by Robert Cooter
and showed when – and what makes – settlement more likely to
happen.

APPENDIX I
Years of 2006, 2007 and 2009 100.000 per population
United States at State level (Civil) 5976.09
United States at Federal level (Civil) 90.32
United States at State level (Family) 1859.22
Total United States 7925.63
Japan (Civil) 1773
Japan (Family) 599.84
Total Japan 2372.84
France (Civil) 2429.47
France (Family) 671.09
Total France 3100.56
Canada (Civil) 1472.79
Canada (Family) 798.3
Total Canada 2271.09
England and Wales (Civil) 3401.81
England and Wales (Family) 487.28
Total England and Wales 3889.09
Brazil at State level (Civil and Family) 7242.17
Brazil at Labor law level 1488.32
Brazil at Federal level (Civil) 1244.07
Total Brazil 9974.56
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2265_

Rates of litigation per country (Civil and Family cases com-


menced in a year)
Data from United States retrieved from Statistical Abstract of United States
(2009) and National Center for State Courts (2016).
Data from Japan, Canada and France retrieved from Ramseyer and Rasmusen
(2010).
Data from England and Wales retrieved from Ministry of Justice (2010).
Data from Brazil retrieved from Conselho Nacional da Justiça (2010). Cases
considered for State, Labor and Federal level were those new filed finding
complaints (“primeira instância”), enforcement of judicial decisions (“título
executivo judicial”) and enforcement of special contracts (“título executivo
extrajudicial”).


REFERENCES

Albiston, Catherine (1991). The rule of law and the Litigation


Process: The paradox of Losing by Winning. Berkeley
Law Scholarship Repository.
BRASIL. DECRETO-LEI No 2.848, DE 7 DE DEZEMBRO
DE 1940. Retrieved from:<
http://www.planalto.gov.br/ccivil_03/decreto-
lei/del2848compilado.htm>
BRASIL. LEI Nº 11.343, DE 23 DE AGOSTO DE 2006. Re-
trieved from:<
http://www.planalto.gov.br/ccivil_03/_ato2004-
2006/2006/lei/l11343.htm>
Brazil, Wayne (1998). Why Courts Should Offer Non-Binding
ADR Services. CPR Institute for Dispute Resolution. Vol
16. n. 5. May 1998.
Center for Law and Military Operations (2011). Rule of Law
Handbook: A practitioner’s guide for judges and advo-
cates.
Coase, Ronald (1960). The problem of Social Costs. The Journal
_2266________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

of Law and Economics.


Collier, Charles (1988). Precedent and Legal Authority: A Crit-
ical History. UF Law School Repository.
Conselho Nacional da Justiça (2010). Justiça em Numeros 2009:
Panorama do Judiciario Brasileiro. Retrieved from:
http://www.cnj.jus.br/programas-e-acoes/pj-justica-em-
numeros
Cooter, Robert (1982). Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A
Testable Model of Strategic Behavior. Berkeley Law.
Encyclopedia Britannica: https://www.britan-
nica.com/topic/gross-domestic-product. Retrieved on
28th June.
Erlanger, S.; Elizabeth, C.; Marygold, M. (1987) "Participation
and Flexibility in Informal Processes: Cautions from the
Divorce Context," 21 Law & Society Rev. 585-604.
Fishburn, Peter (1970). Utility Theory for Decision Making.
John Wiley & Sons. Inc.
Fiss, Owen (1984). Against Settlement. Faculty Scholarship Se-
ries. Paper 1215.
Folberg; Golann; Stipanowich; Kloppenberg (2016). Resolving
Disputes: Theory, Practice, and Law. 3th Ed. Aspen
Publisher.
Foote, Dan (1995). Resolution of Traffic Accident Disputes and
Judicial Activism in Japan. Law Japan. v. 25:19.
Gico Jr, Ivo. (2014). A Tragédia do Judiciário. Revista de Di-
reito Administrativo. v. 267.
H. L. A. Hart, (1958). Positivism and the Separation of Law and
Morals. 71 Harvard Law Review 593, 601-2.
Haley, John (1978). The Myth of the Reluctant Litigant. 4 J.
JAPANESE STUD. 359, 389.
Helliwell, J., Layard, R., & Sachs, J. (2018). World Happiness
Report 2018, New York: Sustainable Development So-
lutions Network.
Jean Baptiste-Say (1803). A Treatise on Political Economy:
RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4________2267_

production, distribution and consumption of wealth. Au-


gustus M. Kelley Publishers.
Jorgenson, Dale; Ho, Mun; Samuels, Jon (2014). Long-Term Es-
timates of U.S. Productivity and Growth.
Kendall, Keith (2011). The Use of Economic Analysis in Court
Judgments: A Comparison between the United States,
Australia and New Zealand. Pacific Basin Law Journal,
28(2).
Krueger, Anne (1974). The Political Economy of The Rent-
Seeking Society. The American Economy Review,
Kuznets, Simon Kuznets (1934). National Income, 1929-32. Na-
tional Bureau of Economic Research.
Laffont, Jean; Martimort, David (2001). The Theory of Incen-
tives: The Principal-Agent Model.
Landes, Willian (1971). An Economic Analysis of the Courts.
Journal of Law and Economics. 14. 16-xxx.
Murphy, Kevin; Shleifer, Andrei; Vishny, Robert (1991). The
allocation of Talent: Implications for Growth. The Quar-
terly Journal of Economics. V. 106. N. 2.
Murshed, S. (2001). Transaction Costs Politics, Institution for
commitment of Rent-Seeking. UNU World Institute for
Development Economics Research (UNU/WIDER).
Posner, Richard (1973). An Economic Approach to Legal Pro-
cedure and Judicial Administration. Journal of Legal
Studies. 2. 399-xx.
Ricardo, David (1817) On the principles of Political Economy
and Taxation. Batoche Books.
Samson, A. (Ed.)(2017). The Behavioral Economics Guide 2017
(with an introduction by Cass Sunstein). Retrieved from:
http://www.behavioraleconomics.com
Silva Neto, Orlando. Responsabilidade civil pela perda do tempo
útil: tempo é um ativo indenizável. (in English, Is time
spent in pursuit of compensation a indemnifiable asset?)
In. Rodrigues Jr., Otávio (org). Revista de Direito Civil
_2268________RJLB, Ano 6 (2020), nº 4

Contemporâneo, N. 2. V. 4, Ju/Sept. 2015, p. 139-162.


Shavell, Stephen. Economic Foundations of the Law. 2. ed.
Routledge. 2010.
Shavell, S. The Fundamental Divergence Between the Private
and the Social Motive to Use the Legal System. The
Journal of Legal Studies, 1997, 26(S2), 575-612.
doi:10.1086/468008
STATE OF NEW YORK. New York Consolidated Laws, Penal
Law – PEN. Retrieved from:< http://ypdcrime.com/pe-
nal.law/article220.htm>
Tetley, William (2000). Mixed Jurisdictions: Common Law v.
Civil Law (Codified and Uncodified). Louisiana Law
Review. Volume 60. Number 3.
Timm, Luciano Benetti. (2014). Direito e Economia no Brasil.
Atlas. 2 ed.
Timm, Luciano Benetti. Análise econômica da arbitragem.
https://lawle2014.fmiles.wordpress.com/2017/10/timm-
10042016-aed-da-arbitragem-livro-tarcicc81sio-lmj.pdf
2017.
United States Census Bureau (2009). Statistical Abstract of
United States: 2009. Retrieved from: https://www.cen-
sus.gov/library/publications/2008/compen-
dia/statab/128ed.html
William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner (1992). The Influence
of Economics on Law: A Quantitative Study. Chicago
Unbound.
Yu, H.; Guernsey, A. What is The Rule of Law. The University
of Iowa.
Zamboni, Alex (2016). O ENSINO JURIDICO E O TRATA-
MENTO ADEQUADO DOS CONFLITOS: Impacto da
Resolução n. 125 do CNJ sobre os cursos de Direito.
Master’s Thesis. Universidade Federal de São Paulo.

You might also like