Washington v. Glucksberg
Washington v. Glucksberg
Washington v. Glucksberg
Pain Control
Kant is quite clear that pain does not constitute a reason for suicide. According to the
Lectures on Ethics, Kant states, So neither the greatest advantages, nor the highest
degree of well-being, nor the most excruciating pains and even irremediable bodily
sufferings can give a man the authority to take his own life, to escape from anguish
and enter earlier upon a hoped-for higher happiness.32 Since the reason suicide is
not permitted is because it destroys rational agency, the permanent use of analgesics
that destroy rationality would also be prohibited, on Kant’s view.33 This has
relevance for current medical practice. At the present time, pain medications such as
morphine may be used to reduce pain and suffering even to the point at which the
person can no longer function as a moral agent. On the Kantian view described here,
pain control should not be administered so as to permanently destroy rational
agency. When the point is reached that controlling pain requires so much morphine
that increased doses will make the patient unable to function rationally, increases
should cease even though the pain becomes greater. Of course, it may happen that
the pain itself becomes so great that it makes rational agency impossible, and at that
point the pain can be suppressed without worry about rational agency. This provides
a rough principle for determining when pain is sufficiently extreme to justify
administration of pain medication that suppresses rational thought. The point is
reached when the pain is so extreme that it will itself suppress the rationality
required for moral agency. The use of pain medication or anesthetics that render one
temporarily incapacitated as a moral agent is, however, permissible when there is
adequate reason for it. Kant states, for instance, that the use of opium as a medicine
is permissible.34 Use of anesthetics that cause temporary loss of consciousness
would also be permissible on Kantian grounds. Such medications are used to
effectuate cures or surgery so as to restore one to better functioning as a moral
agent. Similarly, sleep is necessary to maintain one’s moral agency, even though one
is unable to function as a moral agent while asleep. The problem arises in the case of
terminally ill patients for whom pain control may mean a permanent loss of rational
agency. Terminal sedation is one way this can happen. The most extreme form of this
would be sedating a person into a coma and then allowing the patient to die of
dehydration, although a person can be sedated into semiconsciousness or even
unconsciousness while the body is kept functioning through nutrition and hydration.
Euthanasia Although Kant’s arguments against suicide cannot be sidestepped within
the framework of Kant’s central tenets, Kant’s arguments against suicide do not rule
out euthanasia for people who have permanently lost their rational agency.35 Once
someone has irretrievably lost rational agency, that person no longer has the sort of
Kantian dignity that would justify a duty not to perform euthanasia. When a person is
capable of functioning as a rational agent, however, he or she should not be
euthanized, even if he or she requests euthanasia in order to relieve suffering, since
killing him or her would treat humanity in that person merely as a means to an end.
It would be permissible, on this argument, to write an advance directive refusing life-
saving treatment, and even requesting euthanasia, in the event that one were to
suffer a permanent loss of rational agency. This would not violate Kant’s statements
applying the categorical imperative to suicide. The maxim of one’s actions could be
universalized. It is not inconsistent to will that it become a universal law that people
sign advance directives enabling their death after they have permanently lost their
rational agency. The motive here is not any sort of self-love that would be
inconsistent with the purpose of self-love generally, as in Kant’s example. Rather, the
motive is respect for the integrity of one’s dignity as a rational agent. Nor would one
be treating oneself merely as a means to an end, for at the point at which one died,
one would lack rationality and hence the dignity that makes persons ends in
themselves. Finally, an advance directive permitting euthanasia would not run afoul
of the Kantian duty to seek one’s perfection, since the person who has permanently
lost the ability to function rationally is, of course, unable to seek perfection.
Interestingly, the Kantian argument outlined here permits euthanasia even for
persons who have not made an advance directive requesting it so long as there is no
reason to believe that euthanasia would thwart what the person willed as a rational
agent. If a person expresses a desire not to be killed in the event that he or she
suffers a permanent loss of rationality, then there is reason to respect that desire,
just as there is reason to respect the directives of the deceased regarding property
distribution. Respect for rational agency requires both sustaining the conditions of
rational agency and respecting decisions made by rational agents. A supposed
kingdom of ends in which Kantian View of Suicide and End-of-Life Treatment 283
rational decisions were not respected after the loss of competence or death would
be less respectful of humanity and hence not a genuine kingdom of ends. In short,
Kant’s arguments against suicide do not present us with an a priori case against
euthanasia for those who have permanently lost their rational agency. We do,
however, need to take account of empirical considerations. Even if a maxim that we
will euthanize persons who have permanently lost rational agency and have not
previously expressed a wish to the contrary passes muster under the various
formulations of the categorical imperative, it might still fail of application in a
particular case. It might, for example, be simply too difficult to tell whether an
individual has in fact permanently lost rational agency. Obviously a maxim to perform
euthanasia in cases in which we are not certain whether rational agency has been
permanently lost would be incompatible with respect for rational agency. Empirical
considerations also provide room for state regulation.
State Regulation
Kant is a traditional political liberal. He holds that people have a right to be free to
pursue their own vision of happiness as long as they can do so in accord with
universal law.36 The bedrock of Kant’s political philosophy is the universal principle
of right, which states, “Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in
accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can
coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law.”37 Kant rejects
state paternalism in which the state attempts to coerce citizens into adopting a
particular vision of happiness and goes so far as to claim that “a paternalistic
government... is the greatest despotism thinkable.”38 Kant also holds that the mere
fact that an action will harm someone is not a justification for coercion if the action is
consented to by the person harmed.39 In addition, the state cannot force people to
be moral, because it cannot force people to act on the basis of certain maxims—the
state can merely coerce external behavior. Restraint on freedom is justifiable,
however, in order to protect freedom. Coercion is justifiable only if it is able to
“coexist with the freedom of everyone in accordance with universal laws.”40 This
ensures that those whose freedom is restricted by state regulation are coerced on
the basis of principles that they themselves have reason to accept. This provides the
framework for regulating euthanasia. In those cases in which we can tell that rational
agency has indeed been permanently lost, prohibition of euthanasia is not justified
on Kantian grounds. People who write advance directives permitting such euthanasia
can be viewed as acting on their own vision of happiness without violating the
universal principle of right. In fact, it may be important to a competent person’s
present view of happiness to know that he or she will not pose problems for family
and loved ones after he or she ceases to be a moral agent. It may also be important
to the person’s vision of his or her own dignity not to be kept alive after the
possibility of rational agency has ceased. Moreover, such actions can coexist with
everyone’s freedom in accordance with universal law. Such people are pro284 Martin
Gunderson tected by Kant’s liberal political theory. For the state to enforce its own
vision of happiness on such people would be just the sort of paternalism Kant
decries. Even if carrying out the advance directive would harm the no-longerrational
human (e.g., by depriving the person of enjoyable mental states), Kant’s political
theory would not justify prohibition, because the action had been consented to
when the advance directive was written. In the case of persons who have lost
rational agency but who have not written an advance directive permitting
euthanasia, however, whether they would be harmed by euthanasia is a
consideration. This should be dealt with on a case-by-case basis and is not an
appropriate matter for state prohibition. There is, however, room for some restrictive
regulation. The state must take account of the risks that a policy permitting
euthanasia would pose for those who are, at least potentially, moral agents and who
might be mistakenly killed. In the case of persistent vegetative state, for example,
there is risk of misdiagnosis. In addition, people who are accurately diagnosed as
being in a persistent vegetative state sometimes regain consciousness. As result, a
person must remain in a persistent vegetative state for a significant amount of time
before it can be determined with reasonable certainty that the vegetative state is
permanent.41 Kantian argument would, I believe, require a high degree of certainty
that a person had in fact permanently lost rational agency, though reasonable risks,
as we have seen, are justifiable on Kantian grounds. Where the lines should be drawn
depends on subtle empirical issues. Some have claimed that euthanasia should be
prohibited because of the potential for abuse.42 On this argument, some will kill
persons who are still rational agents and then claim that it was an instance of
euthanizing a person who had permanently lost rational agency. By prohibiting
euthanasia in all cases, the argument goes, the state is using coercion to protect the
freedom of persons and is thus justifiable on Kantian grounds. This argument
succeeds only if it is impossible to detect such abuses. If such abuses are detectable,
the state can protect freedom by prohibiting the abuses and adopting adequate
enforcement mechanisms. Once again, where the regulatory lines should be drawn
depends on the resolution of empirical issues.
Conclusion
Kant’s basic moral philosophy is compatible with, and even requires, his claim that
suicide is immoral, at least in medical contexts where end-of-life decisions are made.
Moreover, Kant’s ethics prohibits assisted suicide. For similar reasons, Kant’s
arguments would prohibit the use of pain control that results in permanent loss of
moral agency. Kant’s arguments do not, however, provide an a priori reason for
thinking that euthanasia is immoral in the case of persons who have permanently
lost their rational agency, such as those in a persistent vegetative state or the later
stages of Alzheimer’s disease. What regulations are justified and whether
prohibitions are justified depends on an assessment of empirical issues. Kant’s
arguments against paternalism, however, make it clear that the burden is on those
who would propose restrictive regulations. Kantian View of Suicide and End-of-Life
Treatment 285 Previous versions of this paper were presented to the Minnesota
Monthly Moral Philosophy Meetings and the College of St. Catherine. I am also
indebted to Geoffrey Gorham and David Mayo for their comments on earlier versions
of the paper