Kierkegaard and Phenomenology
Kierkegaard and Phenomenology
Kierkegaard and Phenomenology
Print Publication Date: Jan 2013 Subject: Religion, Theology and Philosophy of Religion
Online Publication Date: Jun 2013 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199601301.013.0024
This chapter examines Soren Kierkegaard's writings about and related to phenomenology.
It evaluates whether Kierkegaard's account of religious life can be considered a
phenomenology of religion, and reviews arguments for and against interpreting
Kierkegaard as a phenomenologist. The chapter also explores the relation between
Kierkegaard and phenomenology by examining the influence of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel's in Kierkegaard, and by comparing Edmund Husserl's and Martin Heidegger's
forms of phenomenology to that of Kierkegaard.
Keywords: Soren Kierkegaard, phenomenology, religious life, Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, Edmund Husserl,
Martin Heidegger
I. Introduction: Kierkegaard—a
Phenomenologist?
THE task of relating Kierkegaard to phenomenology immediately raises the question as to
which type of phenomenology is at issue. It would, of course, be anachronistic to call
Kierkegaard a ‘phenomenologist’ in the sense that this word acquired in the twentieth
century. However, Kierkegaard was without doubt acquainted with Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit, inspired Heidegger, and anticipated issues that became
prominent in the so-called ‘theological turn’ in French phenomenology.
Page 1 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
attempts have been used for in-depth investigations of Kierkegaard's works (Disse 1991;
Grøn 1997; Lincoln 2000; Welz 2008). The current debate is mirrored by the essays in
Hanson (2010).
Phenomenology in the broadest sense of the word deals with phenomena, i.e. with
appearances in the how of their appearing to someone. While it is uncontroversial that
Kierkegaard has offered viable descriptions of phenomena such as anxiety or despair, it is
highly controversial whether one can legitimately consider him to be a phenomenologist.
In particular, there is disagreement concerning the question as to whether Kierkegaard's
project includes a phenomenology of the divine and of religious life. Can God and faith be
taken as ‘phenomena’ at all? The question is radicalized further if connected to the
problem of theodicy and then leads to the question as to whether it is at all possible to
trace manifestations of divine love in human life.
If one answers in the affirmative, one presupposes that God enters and affects
(p. 441)
experience, although his properties such as wisdom and goodness can, according to
Kierkegaard, never be ‘right in front of our noses’ (SKS4: 246f./PF: 42). Neither evil nor
God's goodness can be seen ‘as such’. Rather, the way something appears is dependent
on the observer. In his 1853–5 journals, Kierkegaard claims that qua Spirit God is related
paradoxically or inversely to what appears phenomenally (SKS26: NB32:132 [JP3: 3099]).
Yet, if God's love can be hidden sub contrario, phenomenality does not so much reveal
God as become his hiding place.
For this reason, one might be sceptical about the idea that a phenomenological account
can show human existence to be indissolubly bound up with a God-relationship.
Experiences with God might count as a fact for the believer but remain no more than a
possibility for the phenomenologist. Does this mean that a phenomenology of religious life
—and all the more of the divine—is theoretically impossible? Can Kierkegaard's account
of religious life be incorporated into a phenomenology of religion only by omitting what is
most distinctive about this account or by reading Kierkegaard in a sense contrary to that
which he himself intended (Pattison 2010: 193)?
In what follows, the arguments that have been put forward for and against reading
Kierkegaard as a phenomenologist will be reviewed. In order to do justice to the
historical development, the relation between Kierkegaard and phenomenology will be
explored in five steps corresponding to different epochs in the history of phenomenology.
Firstly, I shall examine the heritage of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit in Kierkegaard. In
a second and third step, Husserl's and Heidegger's forms of phenomenology will be
compared to Kierkegaard. In a fourth step, it will be shown in what sense Kierkegaard
anticipated features prominent in French phenomenology. Finally, arguments against
seeing Kierkegaard as a phenomenologist will be reconsidered, followed by a proposal for
a classification of Kierkegaard's project in relation to these forms of phenomenology.
Page 2 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Grøn (1997: 35–9) suggests understanding The Sickness unto Death as a dialectical
negative phenomenology. Its point of departure is the problem that subjectivity tends to
escape our grasp precisely because subjectivity concerns us as a matter of what and who
we are. ‘In dealing with subjectivity, subjectivity itself comes in between’ (Grøn 2010: 84).
How, then, does it come to appear? According to Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
consciousness relates to its objects but not to itself as object. Yet the self-givenness of
subjectivity is not reducible to the ‘mineness’ of experience, to my experiencing of
something else, or to the ‘co-givenness’ of subjectivity in something else that is ‘given’.
Rather, the conscious subject of experience is itself changed through its experiencing,
coming to experience differently. As a consequence, the self-givenness of subjectivity, its
being-given to itself as a self, its self-understanding, has changed as well (Grøn 2010: 85–
8, 96).
The ‘development’ of the self portrayed in The Sickness unto Death takes place through a
negative analysis of forms and figures of despair defined as not being oneself (Grøn 2010:
88–92). The truth (being oneself) is reached through untruth (not wanting to be oneself).
What comes to appear is the self that fails in, or even resists, understanding itself, but in
its failure and resistance it is given to itself as the self that is to be acknowledged.
Wanting or not wanting to be oneself is not just an ordinary choice between A and B.
Rather, it is a matter of what one is doing and wanting in what one is doing and wanting.
It is a choice in one's choices, and one might not always be conscious of what this choice
consists in. Although the figure of despair becomes more and more conscious of itself in
Page 3 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
the course of Kierkegaard's book, the negative or broken character of this progression is
due to the fact that Kierkegaard deals not only with figures or stages of consciousness,
but also with movements of existence. In existence, consciousness and will (or rather:
unwillingness) are intertwined in such a way that despair is connected to repugnance: to
not wanting to be oneself (Grøn 1997: 137–42). At its extreme, human freedom presents
itself to itself as the possibility of unfreedom (Gonzáles 2010). Freedom is reached
through despair, although despair is generally a misuse of freedom (Dahlstrom 2010: 58–
62).
Both Hegel in his Phenomenology and Kierkegaard in Works of Love describe the
structure of the absolute as ‘reduplication’, ‘spirit’ and ‘love’ (SKS9: 182, 278/WL: 182,
280; SKS26: NB 33:23 [JP4: 4571]; Hegel 1986: 23). Yet, similarity in terminology does
not imply that Kierkegaard and Hegel mean the same. Since Works of Love and the
journal entries from that period are silent about Hegel, the relation between Hegel's and
Kierkegaard's positions can only be reconstructed on the basis of a systematic
comparison of their texts (Welz 2007a; 2008b: 72–83, 108–36, 219–25).
Page 4 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
(2) For Hegel, love can and ought to be an object of knowledge. For Kierkegaard,
this is possible only in a limited sense, since the origin, life, and works of love belong
to the sphere of inwardness and faith and therefore remain hidden (SKS9: 16f., 147,
278/WL: 8, 146, 280f.). Love shows itself in words, emotional movement, and actions,
but we have to believe in love and to trust that it is there in order to ‘see’ or
understand that it is love and not something else that shows itself. God's love
becomes phenomenally present only in its effects, i.e. in intersubjective relations that
are characterized by the formative influence of all participants, and only in actu, i.e.
in being expressed and realized in human actions and interpretations (Lincoln 2000:
38f., 244f.). Divine love and human love of neighbour are not additional phenomena
alongside others but offer a new interpretation of and another way of dealing with
existing phenomena. Kierkegaard's phenomenology remains idealistic in so far as it
envisions not only the worldly phenomena of erotic love, friendship, or neighbourly
love but also the horizon in which they appear, namely God's love. However,
otherwise than in Hegel, the latter is ‘known’ only as the unknowable.
(p. 444) (3) According to Hegel, the spirit gains experience through self-alienation
and self-appropriation (Hegel 1986: 38f.). Hegel polemicizes against the ‘upbuilding’
but ‘boring’ idea that divine life is just the ‘play of love with itself’, unspoilt identity
and unity with itself without gravity and pain, self-estrangement and its overcoming
(Hegel 1986: 24). As self-opposing reduplication, the absolute is self-reflection in
otherness. The life of the spirit endures negativity, death, and devastation (Hegel
1986: 36). Evil is an inalienable moment of the spirit (Hegel 1986: 566f.).
Kierkegaard, however, holds fast to the belief that God's eternal love remains
unchanged in the course of time. Its element is ‘infinitude, inexhaustibility,
immeasurability’ (SKS9: 180/WL: 180). It never turns into what is not love, and
therefore will always remain opposed to its opposite.
(4) Hegel's concept of the absolute spirit comprises the finite spirit that finally
knows its identity with the ‘eternal as such’, whereas Kierkegaard, assuming an
identical structure of the human and the divine spirit in the activity of loving, insists
that the temporally existing spirit that relates the body and the soul remains, for the
time being, ‘before God’. The works of love of which Kierkegaard speaks are actions
of finite subjects, not of an absolute spirit. Hegel interprets the absolute spirit's
being with the other of itself as love, while Kierkegaard distinguishes between God
as Spirit of Love and human spiritual power in relation to God (SKS9: 356/WL: 362).
Page 5 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
be done by, first, pointing to characteristics of Husserl's phenomenology that are absent
in Kierkegaard's work and, second, pointing to what is crucial for Kierkegaard but
bracketed in Husserl's phenomenology.
As to the status of phenomenology, Husserl held it to be not merely one positive science
among others, but the basis for all positive science and properly scientific work.
According to Logical Investigations, phenomenology establishes a domain of neutral
research in which various sciences have their roots (Husserl 1984: §1). In The Crisis,
however, phenomenology is also concerned with the lifeworld (Lebenswelt) and the
texture of lived experience. Like the later Husserl, Kierkegaard confronted a crisis in
European society and turned to what Husserl called the Lebenswelt as the place where
existential thinking is rooted (Dooley 2010: 169). Nonetheless, the ultimate objectives of
Kierkegaard and Husserl clearly diverge. Kierkegaard does not mention the suspension of
the ‘natural attitude’. Neither is he occupied with the laws of ‘constitution’ or with
‘intentionality’ in the context of phenomenology taken as a rigorous science.
Page 6 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
As the absolute, God is by definition beyond any possible intuition (Bloechl 2010: 30).
Kierkegaard's preoccupation with the paradox of God's incarnation in Jesus Christ, of the
eternal entering human temporality, raises the question of whether Husserlian
phenomenology can account for the dynamics of divine transcendence that affect and
surpass human consciousness. Kierkegaard was aware of the fact that seeing our lives in
terms of the movement of creation, fall, and redemption is not something that can be read
off from what we experience. Rather, it is a faith-based interpretation of life that comes
from beyond the limit at which human thought breaks down (Pattison 2010: 194).
Yet Husserl, too, took these problems seriously—for epistemological and for theological
reasons. It is well known that Husserl explicitly excluded God's transcendence from the
field of phenomenological research (Husserl 1976: 125). The thought of God can be
adequate only on condition that God is neither confused with inner worldly entities, nor
with the world as the horizon of possible experience or with the experiencing subject. For
this reason, Husserl cannot conceive of God as a given phenomenon among other
phenomena.
In his Nachlass Husserl describes God as the Alpha and Omega of all processes of
(p. 446)
constitution, as the ground, entelechy and telos of conscious life (Husserl 1973b: 608–10;
Hart 1986; Laycock 1986; and Ms. B II 2, 54; E III 4, 60–1; F I 24, 41b). As that which
‘aims’ in all intentional aiming and as the teleological ‘target’ of this aiming, God is
identical with the source and destination of transcendental (inter)subjectivity (Husserl
1973a: 9). Yet, neither the synthesis of all constituting subjectivity nor the synthesis of all
constituted objectivity is experientially given to us. Thus, Husserl has good reasons to
bracket divine transcendence. God is not given in experience but only in a reflection
about experience, i.e. in a second-order experience. There is nothing that compels us to
identify the ground, entelechy, and telos of experience with God. Such an identification
would assert more than the data of the experience itself (Welz 2008: 40–58).
Is it not precisely for this reason that Kierkegaard resists any attempt to prove the
existence of God? Husserl's reflections about God might be closer to Kierkegaard's than
hitherto assumed. When Shestov met Husserl in 1928, Husserl made Shestov promise to
read Kierkegaard (Shestov 1962; Paradiso-Michau 2006). Yet, it belongs to the desiderata
of future research to scrutinize Husserl's Kierkegaard-reception.
Page 7 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Despite integrating Kierkegaardian concepts into his own ontological project, Heidegger
relegated Kierkegaard to the category of an ontico-existentiell psychologist or religious
thinker (Wyschogrod 1954; Caputo 1987: 82f.; Dreyfus 1991; McCarthy 2011: 114;).
Although Heidegger understated his dependence on Kierkegaard, the following
arguments speak against understanding Kierkegaard as a phenomenologist in
Heidegger's sense: (1) Kierkegaard did not develop philosophy as universal
phenomenological ontology; (2) Heidegger's ambiguous relation to Kierkegaard makes it
difficult to depict the Dane as congenial phenomenologist; (3) Kierkegaardian faith
questions the reliability of the links between Being, manifestation, and consciousness
(Pattison 2010: 188, 191, 194, 202f.).
In his 1920 review essay, ‘Critical Comments on Karl Jaspers’ Psychology of Worldview’,
Heidegger praised ‘the height of methodological rigor’ that Kierkegaard reached (Kisiel
and Sheehan 2007: 147f.). Heidegger's formulations of the tasks of phenomenology are
remarkably reminiscent of Kierkegaardian formulations in The Sickness unto Death and
The Concept of Anxiety. Like Kierkegaard, Heidegger highlights the relationality and
historicity of the self: ‘The self is what it is in its relations to the world of the self’ (Kisiel
and Sheehan 2007: 142f.). Heidegger announces programmatically that the concrete self
must be made the starting point of the approach to the problems of existence. He
observes that the factic, i.e. historically actualized life is already at work within how we
approach the problem of self-appropriation. Heidegger's description evokes Kierkegaard's
analysis of the self that does not want to be itself in despair. Heidegger suggests applying
a hermeneutical method—‘the interpretive, historically actualizing explication of the
concrete modes of fundamental experience in which I have myself’ (Kisiel and Sheehan
2007: 143), thereby catching not only the universal but precisely the individual features
of human experience.
Page 8 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
this past ‘within a horizon of expectations placed ahead of itself by itself’ (Kisiel and
Sheehan 2007: 139f.). This connection between temporality and anxious concern (Danish:
Bekymring) can also be found in Kierkegaard's 1848 Christian Discourses, e.g. in ‘The
Care of Self-Torment.’ Self-torment consists in care about the next day. We can cause this
care because we can look ahead in ‘fear’, ‘presentiment’, and ‘expectancy’ (SKS10: 82/
CD: 73). Kierkegaard recommends turning wholeheartedly to the day today, turning our
back to the goal, trusting that God measures out the trouble that is enough for each day.
Self-torment loses its strength when one no longer lends one's own strength to it, the
strength of a being existing tensed, in the tension between past and future.
This fits well with Heidegger's lecture course ‘Introduction to the Phenomenology of
Religion’ where he sees the human being as ‘an object in becoming, standing within
time’ (Heidegger 2004: 25). For Heidegger, ‘the genesis of dogma can only be understood
from out of the enactment of Christian life experience’, which is constituted by
‘compressed temporality’ without time for postponement (Heidegger 2004: 79, 85). Like
Kierkegaard, Heidegger does not focus on the transcendental ‘I’ beyond time, but rather
on the embodied and ‘enworlded’ self that is intensely concerned about matters of life
and death. And like Kierkegaard, Heidegger does not accentuate theoretical approaches
to religion, but rather the practical implications of religious commitment.
However, in Being and Time Heidegger does not follow Kierkegaard who assumes that the
human being is compounded of the temporal and the eternal (SKS10: 80/ (p. 448) CD: 71).
It is not clear whether Heidegger, in prioritizing the future over the present, takes up
Kierkegaard's notion of the future as eternity's incognito, since he reduces human
existence to radical finitude. Further, Kierkegaard's concept of Bekymring does not
correspond to Heidegger's concept of Sorge, ‘concern’ or ‘care’ with which he
circumscribes the structure of existence. While Heidegger's agenda was clearly in line
with Kierkegaard's at the time of his lecture courses on the Phenomenology of Religious
Life, this is no longer the case in Being and Time.
Page 9 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
stuck ‘in the vulgar concept of time’ in the sense of the human being's ‘being-in-
time’ (Heidegger 1996: 412f. n. 3; Quist 2009).
This raises two questions. First, how are Heidegger's dismissive statements about
Kierkegaard in Being and Time related to his praise of Kierkegaard's methodological
rigour in 1920? Second, do Heidegger's descriptions of his relation to Kierkegaard
correspond to the way he actually works with Kierkegaard's thoughts?
(1) When reading Heidegger's early occasional writings, one can detect an astonishing
development. In 1920, Heidegger wrote to Karl Löwith that Kierkegaard ‘can only be
theologically unhinged’ and that ‘Kierkegaard must be appropriated anew, but in a strict
critique that grows out of our own situation. Blind appropriation is the greatest
seduction’ (Kisiel and Sheehan 2007: 97f.). Heidegger finds himself misinterpreted as a
Kierkegaardian and underscores that he at least wants something else. Curiously enough,
this is written in a Kierkegaardian spirit. Kierkegaard's theory and praxis of indirect
communication and his non-persuasive rhetoric fight against blind appropriation. Thus,
Heidegger did exactly what Kierkegaard wanted when reading him critically.
claims that ‘if philosophy is fundamentally atheistic’, then it has ‘decisively chosen factic
life in its facticity’ (Kisiel and Sheehan 2007: 165). Heidegger adds that philosophy's
‘atheism’ means ‘staying clear of the seductive activity concerned solely with arguing
glibly about religiosity’ (Kisiel and Sheehan 2007: 479f. n. 24). These quotes demonstrate
that Heidegger's growing distance from his Christian background goes in line with his
growing reserve towards Kierkegaard.
(2) Still, there is reason to suspect that Heidegger did use Kierkegaard's ideas, albeit
without either affirming or denying their origin. Heidegger's notes to his 1921 Freiburg
lecture course ‘Augustine and Neo-Platonism’ show that he interpreted Augustine with
the help of direct quotes from Kierkegaard without indicating where they come from
(Heidegger 2004: 130, 186, 192, 199, 202). In addition, Heidegger read Augustine's Latin
key terms in a Kierkegaardian way. The following two examples are worth mentioning:
First, Heidegger takes the term molestia, which literally denotes ‘trouble’, in order to
point to the burden, which pulls life down and endangers the having-of-oneself. He
establishes that hidden in this lies self-importance and the possibility of falling, but at the
same time the opportunity to win oneself and to appropriate the burden (Heidegger 2004:
181–3, 200). The movement in Heidegger's interpretation is noticeable. The negative
possibility of losing oneself is turned into an opportunity of being strengthened by what
drags one down. Kierkegaard, too, tries to reverse negativity so that it becomes
Page 10 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
something that gets one further. Discourse 7 in his Christian Discourses about ‘States of
Mind in the Strife of Suffering’ is entitled ‘The Joy of It: That Adversity Is Prosperity’. It
pleads in favour of accepting the inevitable and withstanding the temptation to give
oneself up and to let fall oneself.
The second example concerns Heidegger's notes on the term tentatio. On his view,
temptation is ‘no event, but an existential sense of enactment, a How of
experiencing’ (Heidegger 2004: 186). Identifying life with temptation, he defines tentatio
as an ‘opening in relation to oneself’, but also as ‘falling’ that does not simply happen, but
is experienced. Possibility turns out to be the true ‘burden’. These sketchy notes remind
us, again, of Kierkegaard's description of despair in its ambiguity of, on the one hand,
happening to oneself in so far as one becomes overwhelmed by it and, on the other hand,
being enacted by oneself in so far as it is oneself who despairs. The difficulty lies in the
fact that one has to relate somehow to what happens to oneself. Temptation discloses
possibilities that one would otherwise have missed. In The Concept of Anxiety,
Kierkegaard links up the anxiety provoked by the sight of one's possibilities with an
insight in the abyss of freedom that makes one dizzy (cf. SKS4: 365f./CA: 61).
It is natural to draw a line to Being and Time, where the two motifs appear again, albeit
modified. The realization that the temptation of and the tendency towards falling endure
throughout life is mirrored in Heidegger's characterization of human existence as Sorge,
which has threefold structure of Geworfenheit—Seinkönnen—Verfallen, i.e. of facticity or
thrownness, potentiality, and falling-prey-to. Already in one of his sketches from 1921, he
jotted down the questioning sentence ‘In how far the tentatio is a genuine
existential’ (Heidegger 2004: 191). In Being and Time, he made it into an existential.
Despite (p. 450) Heidegger's denials, his phenomenological analysis of human existence
was profiting considerably from Kierkegaard's discoveries. Denying Kierkegaard's
influence, Heidegger indulged in performative self-contradictions.
Theological Objections
Regarding the first point, we should not forget that Heidegger changed the original title
of the school binder in which he had bound his studies of the phenomenology of religion.
The original title was ‘Phenomenology of Religious Consciousness’. Later the word
‘consciousness’ was crossed out and replaced with the word ‘life’. Further, in contrast to
the usual philosophy of religion of his time, Heidegger concentrated not only on
Page 11 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
conscious religious experiences, but first and foremost on the historical situation in which
they were gained (Heidegger 2004: 52, 58, 259). He was well aware of the problem of
guiding or misleading preconceptions. Therefore, he developed the so-called ‘formal
indication’ that is designed to keep the problems open by keeping away preconceived
opinions or classifications, asking after (1) the experienced ‘what’, i.e. the content of
experience, and (2) after the ‘how’, i.e. the way in which it is experienced, and (3) the
relational meaning in which the experience is enacted (Heidegger 2004: §§11–13). This
procedure shows that Heidegger did not try to clarify what cannot be clarified, but rather
had the courage to face the ambiguities of faith and religious consciousness.
In the last two sessions of Bultmann's theological seminar on ‘Paul's Ethics’ at the
University of Marburg in 1923–4, Heidegger gave a lecture on ‘The Problem of Sin in
Luther’. Here he claimed, ‘Faith can be understood only when sin is understood, and sin
is understood only by way of a correct understanding of the very being of the human
being’ (Kisiel and Sheehan 2007: 194). He illustrated what this means by referring to a
remark found in Kierkegaard's journal of 1852, invoking ‘a human being who sits there in
mortal anxiety—in fear and trembling and great spiritual trial’ (Kisiel and Sheehan 2007:
194). The spiritual dimension has been deleted in Being and Time. Only the tendency of
(p. 451) falling that also pertains to sinning is taken over and integrated into a
description of the human condition which, however, is not seen as determined by the God-
relationship.
To sum up: Since Kierkegaard's concern is to live coram deo and not before being or
before death, he is not an ontologist in Heidegger's sense of the word (Hart 2010: 17f.).
For Heidegger, theology is an ontic, not an ontological science (Heidegger 1998: 41). Is it
possible to ground theological anthropology in Heidegger's fundamental ontology?
Heidegger would like to have the former inscribed in the latter. However, if the two are
located on the same level and offer competing views of the human being, this does not
work. While Heidegger developed his Phenomenology of Religious Life in a
Kierkegaardian style, he definitely departed from Kierkegaard's concern in Being and
Time. Therefore, Kierkegaard does surely not belong to the league of ontologically
devoted phenomenologists.
Page 12 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Scholarly attention has recently focused primarily on Lévinas’ relation to Kierkegaard (cf.
Janiaud 2006; Simmons/Wood 2008; Westphal 2008; Welz/Verstrynge 2008; Sheil 2010;
Paradiso-Michau 2011) and on Derrida's reception of Kierkegaard (Beyrich 2001a; Dooley
2001; Schmidt 2006; Mjaaland 2008; Llewelyn 2009). Derrida himself asserted (p. 452)
that ‘it is Kierkegaard to whom I have been most faithful and who interests me
most’ (Derrida/Ferraris 2001: 40). Accordingly, the first subsection deals with
Kierkegaardian motifs in Lévinas’ phenomenology, the second with Marion's and
Derrida's debate on the (im)possible gift, which is also a debate on the limits of
phenomenology, and the third summarizes the state of the art concerning the other
protagonists of the French debate.
Page 13 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
1999; Beyrich 2001b; Ferreira 2001, 2002). The following three Kierkegaardian motifs are
especially worth mentioning (Welz 2007a–c and 2008b: 277–326).
First, like Kierkegaard, Lévinas recurs to the Neoplatonic tradition of God as ‘the Good
beyond being’, i.e. to a conception of an absolute that can never become an object of
knowledge. Lévinas claims that God, in principle, does not manifest himself phenomenally
and therefore cannot be present and presented in the same way as worldly entities. God
does not appear, but remains an enigma beyond cognition and absent from perception
(Lévinas 1996: 66, 77). Lévinas appreciates the enigmatic character of the
Kierkegaardian God who, in his revelation, preserves his incognito instead of appearing
as a phenomenon (Lévinas 1996: 70f.), yet he rejects the Christological explanation
because for him, God's epiphany does not occur above all in the face of Christ, but, if at
all, in the face of any human other—without being identified. In the ethical relation to a
human You, God remains an anonymous He, ‘a third person or Illeity’, ‘the he in the depth
of the You’ (Lévinas 1996: 141).
Second, in Lévinas, the idea of God's non-presence and anonymity acquires a similar
function to the concealedness of God's love in Kierkegaard. It makes human beings
become present for each other, doing to each other directly what God can do only
indirectly. God's revelation is expressed through the love of the neighbour whose
vulnerability appeals to one's solidarity. Lévinas leaves behind the primacy of the
theoretical plane. This brings him close to Kierkegaard. Further, like Kierkegaard,
Lévinas finds it impossible to await action ‘from an all-powerful God’ (Lévinas 1998a: 94).
Yet, while Kierkegaard's God can be addressed personally, and while the activity of loving
can be ascribed to him, Lévinas interprets the divine attributes, above all, as imperatives
addressed to human beings.
Third, Lévinas observes that we have been accustomed to reason in the name of the
freedom of the ego—‘as though I had witnessed the creation of the world, and as though I
could only have been in charge of a world that would have issued out of my free will’—yet
this freedom is finite, and the subjectivity of a subject come late into a world does not
consist ‘in treating this world as one's project’ (Lévinas 1981: 122). He transfers the legal
(p. 453) metaphor from theodicy—God on trial?—to subjectivity so that it is not God
transcendent but me who is summoned to appear, the self in the accusative prior to the
ego taking a decision, answerable for everything and everyone, responsible even for what
I did not will and before having done anything (Lévinas 1996: 88, 90, 93f.). This
understanding of the subject as utterly responsible creature that is affected before being
able to (re)act can be read as a radicalization of Kierkegaard's understanding of
intersubjectivity. Both Kierkegaard and Lévinas affirm the antecedence of passivity to
activity in so far as we receive ourselves from elsewhere.
Page 14 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
However, even if we cannot see God and experience only our bedazzlement, the very
attempt to see or experience something presupposes intentionality, no matter if the
intentions are fulfilled, disappointed or overwhelmed. Therefore, Derrida reiterated
Janicaud's critique when discussing with Marion at Villanova University in 1997 (Caputo
and Scanlon 1999). It is doubtful whether a theory that rejects the condition of a horizon
as a ‘prison’ of phenomena, that denies the hermeneutical as-structure of manifestation
and challenges intentionality and constitution is rightly called phenomenology. If Marion
is a phenomenologist, then he is not one in Husserl's and Heidegger's sense. While
Heidegger defines theology as a thinking of Revelation (Offenbarung) and philosophy as a
thinking of revealedness (Offenbarkeit), Marion suggests taking phenomenology as
‘donatology’—a new ‘first philosophy’ as rational foundation for theology (Caputo and
Scanlon 1999: 63).
Marion seeks to avoid the aporia of the gift that Derrida sketches in his book Given Time
where the prime example for an impossible gift that is called a present and is said to be
given but nevertheless cannot be present as gift is time (Derrida 1992: 14f., 29). Derrida
claims that as soon as the gift is presented and recognized as a gift, its character as a
gracious gift begins to be destroyed because it will inevitably oblige its recipient and
enter a circle of exchange and payback (Derrida 1992: 12–14, 23). Therefore, the ‘pure’
gift has to remain aneconomic. Can the gift of God's presence then be preserved in an
oeconomia salutis? Marion alternately brackets the giver, the recipient, and the gift-
object. He wants to reduce the gift to givenness. However, seen from a theological
(p. 454) point of view, this is just as problematic as the implications of Derrida's
The problems of both approaches become clear when one confronts the debate on the
(im)possible gift with Kierkegaard's 1843 Upbuilding Discourses on James 1:17–22, which
are about the difficulties of receiving what God gave (SKS5: 39–56, 109–158/EUD: 31–48,
109–58). Kierkegaard's view of how God's presence as love can be given, received, and
communicated as a gift can function as a critical corrective of Marion's and Derrida's
views. Kierkegaard's insights question both Marion's extension of traditional Husserlian
Page 15 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
and Heideggerian phenomenology and Derrida's diagnosis of its aporetic character. (For a
more detailed argumentation, see Welz 2008: 327–74.)
For Chrétien, too, Kierkegaard is a significant point of reference (Chrétien 2002: 15, 36f.,
72f., 75; 2004: 52). However, to my knowledge, Chrétien's reception of Kierkegaard has
not yet been investigated more closely. Nor has Henry's reception of Kierkegaard,
although he discusses Kierkegaard's account of despair and takes Kierkegaard to be a
phenomenologist (Henry 1973: 676ff.).
Lacoste's so-called ‘liturgical reduction’ that involves ‘a certain bracketing of world and
earth’ (Lacoste 2004: 175), as the one who prays withdraws from world and earth but
remains before God, has been related to Kierkegaard's descriptions of the person in
prayer who is looked at by God and has to look to him—suggesting that Kierkegaard, too,
practiced a liturgical reduction where the ‘I’ that stands before God is exposed to the
counter-intentionality of the divine gaze and thereby called into question (Hart 2010: 15–
18). However, the same could be said about any praying person without this person
necessarily having to be a phenomenologist.
Thus, it remains a task of future research to explore in what sense Kierkegaard also has
inspired Chrétien, Henry, and Lacoste. So far, it has become clear that it is impossible to
reduce Kierkegaard's specific way of approaching phenomena to any type of existing
phenomenology that has been recognized as phenomenology. In what sense, then, if at all,
can Kierkegaard nonetheless be labelled a ‘phenomenologist’? This disputed question will
be reconsidered in the next section.
Page 16 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
(Ad 1) The phenomena described by Kierkegaard also belong to the subject area of
Husserl's and Heidegger's forms of phenomenology. Husserl's concept of intentionality
gives access both to corporeal reality and to ideality, phenomena can be given either in
perceptual presentation or in linguistic representation, and even ideal objects can appear
intuitively in a categorial fashion (Zahavi 2003: 17–35, 107f.). Husserl's and Heidegger's
phenomenologies of the mood attest to the fact that they also describe ambiguous,
concealed and oblique phenomena (Heidegger 1993: 277, 296; Lee 1993, 1998).
Phenomenology gives a perspective-bound interpretation of constituted objects, which
entails one's own meaning-giving contribution (Husserl 1984: 54, 397, 399). The
Heideggerian Dasein is far from being self-transparent. Therefore, phenomenology needs
hermeneutics to gain access to the phenomena, work through the coverings and explicate
them. It follows that hermeneutical phenomenology is not in principle unsuitable for the
explication of phenomena as unfathomable as anxiety and despair, sin or faith.
(Ad 2) It is correct that Works of Love is not scientific in Hegel's, Husserl's and
(p. 456)
Heidegger's sense. Kierkegaard does not even provide an extended ethical theory.
Instead, he understands ethics as an existential project of the individual. Nevertheless,
Works of Love can be read as a ‘phenomenology of love’ if phenomenology is defined in
the broad sense of a reflective method of describing phenomena, which is not only based
upon the attentive observation of phenomena, but also in search of appropriate linguistic
Page 17 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
distinctions that can catch the differences between a variety of similar phenomena.
Thereby it is crucial to consider again and again whether one's intuitions correspond to
one's descriptions, and to see how a certain matter discloses itself in various situations.
(Ad 3) Pattison's third objection addresses the most serious difficulties. (3.1) I agree that
including God in a general ontology is problematic, and human fallibility might distort the
ways we think, speak, and feel about God. However, the experience that God surpasses
our experience should not lead us to claim that divine transcendence has no relation
whatsoever to experience. At least the transformation of our experiences and concepts
can be experienced—through ‘someone’ or ‘something’ ultimately eluding our experience.
(3.2) Kierkegaard understands ‘becoming a Christian’ as a lifelong task, and therefore he
keeps distinguishing between the factuality of the life of those who understand
themselves as Christians and the biblical ideals of how a Christian life should be lived.
Consequently, Kierkegaard's work remains open to everyone who is ready to consider
handed-down concepts that challenge one's own experience and to reconsider both the
concepts and the process of experience.
A phenomenology of the invisible must deal with something behind the phenomena,
namely the horizon of interpretation. This horizon is, however, not just the background of
whatever appears; it is also the foreground that predetermines how we see what we see
and how we interpret what we cannot see. Kierkegaard's theological and ethical project
must involve a semiotic dimension because sin, faith, and love can be given as such only
in a linguistic process of signification, determination, and interpretation. If God appears
as present, this is not due to God's own perceivable (non)apparition but rather to the
mediation of his non-material presence by signs which do, in fact, appear. Signs do not
necessarily make visible what is invisible, but they can at least refer to that which
remains invisible.
Since we have no sensual impressions of God, we can only become aware of him
(p. 457)
with inner experience, but he is not given in it as a determinable thing being present.
Thus, any supposed phenomenology of ‘God’ turns out to be a phenomenology of the
human understanding of God. It is only retrospectively that we can find God's discreet
Page 18 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
traces: in newly oriented emotions and actions, thoughts and talks. Kierkegaard outlines
these existential changes and sketches what could be called a phenomenology of religious
life.
The comparison between Kierkegaard and Heidegger showed that the similarities in
hermeneutical methodology do not entail similarities in the results of their respective
explorations. To conclude, I would like to argue that although Kierkegaard's ethical and
theological project diverges from Heidegger's ontological project, there are nevertheless
at least three points of contact between Kierkegaard and Heidegger. The commonalities
concern that which motivates any phenomenological enterprise: difficulties that can
hardly be surmounted otherwise.
Page 19 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
solo, if possible in a more inward way, the original text of individual human
existence-relationships, the old familiar text handed down from the fathers’ (SKS7:
573/CUP1: 629f.).
(2) Second, when observing something, the observer has a blind spot, namely his or
her own first-person perspective. Phenomenology is dealing with precisely this
problem, the difficulty of not overlooking the one who is looking. Kierkegaard's texts
point to the reader and make apparent that humans come to appear in making things
appear (Grøn 2010: 92). For example, our own judgement about another reveals
what is in ourselves. Kierkegaard has elaborated on this dialectic in the first
discourse in Works of Love. In Being and Time, Heidegger speaks of the opacity of
Dasein that in average everydayness flees from or forgets its being, although it is
nearest and most familiar (Heidegger 1996: 41). We have the capacity of self-
understanding; yet, we do not ‘get’ ourselves. Kierkegaard, too, struggled with what
obstructs human self-understanding: temptation and self-deception—states and
movements in which self-consciousness can no longer be taken at face value (Gregor
2010: 140).
(3) Third, the tendency of self-evasion includes the difficulty of dealing with negative
experiences. In Kierkegaard, the figures of despair indicate the constant possibility
of failing oneself. What comes in between is, again, oneself: the self not wanting to be
itself. While Kierkegaard and Heidegger have the problem in common, they do not
support the same solutions. In Kierkegaard, the negativity of missing oneself and
misrelating to God in despair and sin is to be overcome with the help of faith. When
Kierkegaard advocates keeping the ‘wound of negativity’ open (SKS7: 84/CUP1: 85),
negativity is related to becoming, and we cannot overcome becoming. In The
Concept of Anxiety, negativity is a possibility related to human freedom. Does this
negative possibility correspond to the tendency of falling-prey-to that Heidegger
describes in Being and Time? In Heidegger, fallenness is described as an ontological
structure. This implies that it is unavoidable. We can at best appropriate
inauthenticity as a part of authentic existence. Kierkegaard would never accept this.
Here the ways part.
References
References
Beyrich, Tilman (2001a). Ist Glauben wiederholbar? Derrida liest Kierkegaard (Berlin: de
Gruyter).
Page 20 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Butin, Gitte (1999). ‘Encounter with the Other: A Matter of Im/Mediacy. Lévinas and
Kierkegaard on the Other and Mediation’, in Kerygma and Dogma 45, 307–16. (p. 459)
—— and Scanlon, Michael J. (eds.) (1999). God, the Gift, and Postmodernism
(Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).
Chrétien, Jean Louis (2002). The Unforgettable and the Unhoped For, trans. Jeffrey
Bloechl (New York: Fordham University Press).
—— (2004). The Call and the Response, trans. Anne A. Davenport (New York: Fordham
University Press).
Dalferth, Ingolf U. (2002). ‘,…der Christ muß alles anders verstehen als der Nicht-
Christ… Kierkegaards Ethik des Unterscheidens’, in Ingolf U. Dalferth (ed.), Ethik der
Liebe. Studien zu Kierkegaards ‘Taten der Liebe’ (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck), 19–46.
Derrida, Jacques (1992). Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money, trans. Peggy Kamuf (Chicago/
London: University of Chicago Press).
—— and Ferraris, Maurizio (2001). A Taste for the Secret (Cambridge: Polity Press).
Deuser, Hermann (1993). ‘Die Taten der Liebe: Kierkegaard's wirkliche Ethik’, in Wilfried
Härle and Reiner Preul (eds.), Gute Werke (Marburg: Elwert), 117–32.
Dooley, Mark (2001). The Politics of Exodus: Søren Kierkegaard's Ethics of Responsibility
(New York: Fordham University Press).
Page 21 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
—— (2002). ‘The Glory of a Long Desire. Need and Commandment in Works of Love’, in
Ingolf U. Dalferth (ed.), Ethik der Liebe. Studien zu Kierkegaards ‘Taten der
Liebe’ (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck), 139–54.
—— (2008). The Concept of Anxiety in Søren Kierkegaard, trans. J. B. L. Knox (Macon, GA:
Mercer University Press). (p. 460)
Hart, Kevin (2010). ‘The Elusive Reductions of Søren Kierkegaard’, in Hanson (ed.)
(2010), 5–22.
Page 22 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1986). Phänomenologie des Geiste, in: Eva Moldenhauer
and K. M. Michel (eds.), Werke 3 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp).
—— (1996). Being and Time: A Translation of Sein und Zeit, trans. Joan Stambaugh
(Albany, NY: State University of New York Press).
—— (2004). The Phenomenology of Religious Life, trans. Matthias Fritsch and Jennifer
Anna Gosetti-Ferencei (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).
Henry, Michel (1973). The Essence of Manifestation, trans. Girard Etzkorn (The Hague:
Nijhoff).
—— (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster
Teil 1905–1920 (Husserliana, vol. 13), ed. Iso Kern (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff).
—— (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter
Teil: 1929–1935 (Husserliana, vol. 15), ed. Iso Kern (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff).
Janicaud, Dominique (ed.) (2000). Phenomenology and the ‘Theological Turn’: The French
Debate, trans. Bernard G. Prusak (New York: Fordham University Press).
Page 23 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Kisiel, Theodore (1995). The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press).
Kisiel, Theodore and Sheehan, Thomas (eds.) (2007). Becoming Heidegger. On the Trail of
His Early Occasional Writings 1910–1927 (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press).
Lacoste, Jean-Yves (2004). Experience and the Absolute: Disputed Questions on the
Humanity of Man, trans. Mark Raftery-Shekan (New York: Fordham University Press).
(p. 461)
—— (1998). ‘Edmund Husserl's Phenomenology of the Mood’, in Dan Zahavi and Natalie
Depraz (eds.), Alterity and Facticity. New Perspectives on Husserl (Dordrecht: Kluwer),
103–19.
—— (1981). Otherwise Than Being or Beyond Essence, trans. Alphonso Lingis (The
Hague: Nijhoff).
—— (1996). Basic Philosophical Writings, ed. Adriaan T. Peperzak, Simon Critchley, and
Robert Bernasconi (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).
—— (1998b). ‘Existence and Ethics’, in Jonathan Rée and Jane Chamberlain (eds.),
Kierkegaard: A Critical Reader (Oxford: Blackwell), 26–38.
—— (2011). ‘Martin Heidegger: Kierkegaard's Influence Hidden and In Full View’, in Jon
Stewart (ed.), Kierkegaard and Existentialism (Burlington: Ashgate), 95–125.
Page 24 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Mjaaland, Marius Timmann (2008). Autopsia: Self, Death, and God after Kierkegaard and
Derrida (Berlin: de Gruyter).
—— (2010). ‘Kierkegaard and the Limits of Phenomenology’. in Hanson (ed.) (2010), 188–
207.
Schulz, Heiko (2010). ‘A Phenomenological Proof? The Challenge of Arguing for God in
Kierkegaard's Pseudonymous Authorship’, in Hanson (ed.) (2010), 101–27.
Sheil, Patrick (2010). Kierkegaard and Lévinas: The Subjunctive Mood (Farnham:
Ashgate). (p. 462)
Shestov, Lev (1962). ‘In Memory of a Great Philosopher: Edmund Husserl’, in Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research 22, no. 4 (June), 449–71.
Simmons, J. Aaron and Wood, David (eds.) (2008). Kierkegaard and Lévinas: Ethics,
Politics, and Religion (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).
Page 25 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Taylor, Mark C. (1980). Journeys to Selfhood: Hegel and Kierkegaard (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press).
Welz, Claudia and Verstrynge, Karl (eds.) (2008). Despite Oneself: Subjectivity and Its
Secret in Kierkegaard and Lévinas (London: Turnshare).
Westphal, Merold (1992). ‘Lévinas, Kierkegaard, and the Theological Task’ Modern
Theology 8, 241–61.
Page 26 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Suggested reading
Deuser (1997).
Janicaud (2000).
Lincoln (2000).
Pattison (2010).
—— Ricoeur, Paul (1980). Essays on Biblical Interpretation, ed. and trans. Lewis S. Mudge
(Philadelphia: Fortress Press).
Claudia Welz
Page 27 of 27
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).