The Constitutional Status of The
The Constitutional Status of The
The Constitutional Status of The
INTRODUCTION
Justice Frankfurter once ranked the rule requiring proof beyond a
reasonable doubt for a criminal conviction among "the boasts of a free
society."' Today, however, judicial doctrine has hedged that boast by
arbitrarily distinguishing elements of the charged offense, which the gov-
1665
1666 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
2. See Martin v. Ohio, 107 S. Ct. 1098 (1987); Patterson v. New York, 432 U.S. 197 (1977); 1
W. LAFAVE & A. ScoTr, SUBSTANTIVE CRIMINAL LAw 67-68 (1986); C. MCCORMICK,
MCCORMICK ON EVIDENCE 987 (3d ed. 1984).
3. See. eg., Allen, Mullaney v. Wilbur, the Supreme Court, and the Substantive Criminal
Law-An Examination of the Limits of Legitimate Intervention, 55 TEx. L. REV. 269 (1977)
[hereinafter Allen, Limits of Legitimate Intervention]; Allen, The Restoration of In re Winship: A
Comment on Burdens of Persuasion in Criminal Cases After Patterson v. New York, 76 MICH. L.
REv. 30 (1977) [hereinafter Allen, Burdens of Persuasion];Allen, StructuringJury Decisionmaking
in CriminalCases: A Unified ConstitutionalApproach to EvidentiaryDevices, 94 HARV. L. REV. 321
(1980) [hereinafter Allen, StructuringJury Decisionmaking]; Allen & DeGrazia, The Constitutional
Requirement of Proof Beyond Reasonable Doubt in Criminal Cases: A Comment Upon Incipient
Chaos in the Lower Courts, 20 AM. CRIM. L. REv. 1 (1982); Christie & Pye, Presumptions and
Assumptions in the CriminalLaw: Another View, 1970 DUKE L.J. 919; Jeffries & Stephan, Defenses,
Presumptions, and Burden of Proof in the Criminal Law, 88 YALE L.J. 1325 (1979). These
commentators are identified as "positivists" because they believe that substantive liability rules are
indistinguishable from procedural rules; both matter only to the extent that they may affect the
material consequences for the parties. Cf Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 461
(1897) ("The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I
mean by the law.").
For contrary views, see Nesson, Rationality, Presumptions,and Judicial Comment: A Response
to ProfessorAllen, 94 HARV. L. REV. 1574 (1981); Saltzburg, Burdens of Persuasionin Criminal
Cases: Harmonizingthe Views of the Justices, 20 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 393 (1983); Underwood, The
Thumb on the Scales ofJustice. Burdens of Persuasionin CriminalCases, 86 YALE L.J. 1299 (1977).
For an elaboration of how the argument presented here differs in important respects from those
offered by Professors Nesson, Underwood, and Saltzburg, see infra notes 201-17 and accompanying
text.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1667
that even when the substantive ground for exculpation claimed by the
accused is not itself required by the Constitution, due process requires
the government to define prospectively, and prove convincingly, the facts
that give rise to criminal liability. Thus, with respect to any fact that
determines criminal liability, the safeguard provided by the reasonable
doubt rule against unjust conviction is constitutionally compelled.
With the constitutional status of the reasonable doubt requirement
established by Part II, Part III returns to the case law and the commen-
tary. In light of the connection between the reasonable doubt rule and
the due process legality principle, the distinction between elements and
affirmative defenses appears untenable; the risk of unjust conviction is no
less urgent in the context of affirmative defenses. Neither deference to
historical practice nor concern for legislative flexibility can justify the
judicial distinction. Part III also suggests that the Court's critics have
failed to focus on the underlying constitutional right claimed by a
defendant invoking the reasonable doubt rule. Due process requires the
government to prove every element of the charged offense beyond a rea-
sonable doubt-and also to disprove claimed affirmative defenses beyond
a reasonable doubt when the evidence raises a reasonable doubt about the
defendant's guilt.4
I
POINTS OF DEPARTURE: THE SUPREME COURT
AND ITS CRITICS
The Supreme Court has held that due process requires the govern-
ment to bear the burden of proving beyond reasonable doubt some of the
facts necessary to establish criminal liability. But the Court also has held
that other facts necessary to establish criminal liability need not be
proved by the government. These latter cases permit shifting to the
defendant the burden of proving facts that establish affirmative defenses.
Legal scholars have criticized the Court for inconsistently forbid-
ding one method of allocating burdens of proof but upholding another
method, when the two may have indistinguishable effects. The leading
alternative approach would forbid easing the government's proof burden
only with respect to facts necessary to make a conviction constitutional.
This Part describes the conflicting doctrines endorsed by the
Supreme Court and the leading commentators. Subsequently, Part II
proposes an alternative constitutional analysis.
4. The approach I claim to be constitutionally required was followed by the federal courts, as
a matter of policy, for most of this century. See Patterson,432 U.S. at 202-03; Fletcher, Two Kinds
of Legal Rules: A Comparative Study ofBurden-of-PersuasionPracticesin CriminalCases, 77 YALE
L.J. 880, 917-18 (1968).
1668 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
5. See, e.g., County Court v. Allen, 442 U.S. 140 (1979); Sandstrom v. Montana, 442 U.S. 510
(1979); Barnes v. United States, 412 U.S. 837 (1973); Turner v. United States, 396 U.S. 398 (1970);
Leary v. United States, 395 U.S. 6 (1969); United States v. Romano, 382 U.S. 136 (1965); Roviaro v.
United States, 353 U.S. 53 (1957); Tot v. United States, 319 U.S. 463 (1943).
6. See, eg., Patterson v. New York, 432 U.S. 197 (1977); Mullaney v. Wilbur, 421 U.S. 684
(1975); In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358 (1970); Morrison v. California, 291 U.S. 82 (1934).
7. See C. MCCORMICK, supranote 2, at 965, 988. For example, the jury might be allowed to
infer the defendant's intent to kill from her use of a deadly weapon.
8. 442 U.S. 140 (1979).
9. Id. at 143-45.
10. Id. at 167.
11. Id. at 157 ("Because this permissive presumption leaves the trier of fact free to credit or
reject the inference and does not shift the burden of proof, it affects the application of the 'beyond a
reasonable doubt' standard only if, under the facts of the case, there is no rational way the trier could
make the connection permitted by the inference.").
1987] 9]REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1669
exist between the basic and presumed facts, and the evidence in its total-
ity must establish guilt beyond a reasonable doubt.12 The legislatively or
judicially noticed connection between the basic and presumed facts
becomes part of the evidence. If the evidence proves the elements of the
charge beyond a reasonable doubt in a particular case, the failure of the
basic fact alone to prove the presumed fact beyond a reasonable doubt is
13
irrelevant.
If the reasonable doubt rule is constitutionally required, the Allen
approach makes good sense. But the presumption cases assume, rather
than announce, such a constitutional rule.14 If the government need only
prove a particular fact by a preponderance of the evidence, there is no
reason to inquire whether the presumption, with or without other evi-
dence, satisfies the reasonable doubt test. 5 The more basic question,
then, is whether the reasonable doubt rule applies to a particular issue.
The second line of Supreme Court cases, those involving direct attempts
to assign the burden of proof to the defense, confronts this question.
was in possession of several rolls of dimes. His mother could not explain
his possession of the dimes, but only paper money had been stolen from
Mrs. Goldman.
The family court judge overruled a defense objection to the civil pre-
ponderance of the evidence standard applied in the proceeding. The
judge then found Winship guilty under the preponderance standard, but
conceded that the evidence did not convince him of Winship's guilt
beyond a reasonable doubt."8 The Appellate Division affirmed the judg-
ment, as did the Court of Appeals, over the dissent of Chief Judge
Fuld. 19
The Supreme Court reversed, holding that the juvenile court pro-
ceeding was criminal in character and that, in criminal proceedings, "the
Due Process Clause protects the accused against conviction except upon
proof beyond a reasonable doubt of every fact necessary to constitute the
crime with which he is charged." 2 0 Writing for the Court, Justice Bren-
nan based this interpretation of the due process clause on the widespread
acceptance of the reasonable doubt rule in common law jurisdictions, in
the history of American jurisprudence, and, at least implicitly, in
Supreme Court precedents.2 1
More fundamentally, the Winship Court recognized two characteris-
tics of the criminal process as supporting a constitutional reasonable
doubt rule. The first is the difficulty of defending against a charge of
crime, a "disadvantage" that would amount to a denial of" 'fundamental
fairness, if [the defendant] could be adjudged guilty and imprisoned for
years on the strength of the same evidence as would suffice in a civil
case.' "22 The reasonable doubt standard thus provides "a prime instru-
ment for reducing the risk of convictions resting on factual error."2 3
The second aspect of the criminal process on which Winship relied is
the difference in consequences attending erroneous acquittals and errone-
ous convictions.
Where one party has at stake an interest of transcending value-as a
criminal defendant his liberty-[the] margin of error is reduced as to him
by the process of placing on the other party the burden of... persuading
the factfinder
24
at the conclusion of the trial of his guilt beyond a reason-
able doubt.
Winship required reversal of the conviction.32 The court based its hold-
ing in part on the theory that Winship did not apply retroactively, a the-
ory subsequently rejected by the Supreme Court. 33 The state court also
relied on the structure of the applicable law of homicide. For more than
a century, Maine had classified murder and manslaughter as different
degrees of the single offense of felonious homicide.34 The provocation
defense raised by Wilbur thus implicated the appropriate sentence rather
than the adjudication of guilt or innocence. Since sentencing determina-
tions are not subjected to the reasonable doubt test, the Maine court con-
cluded that Winship did not apply. According to the Maine court, the
reasonable doubt standard governs the proof required to place the
defendant in a formal statutory category, but does not extend to facts
affecting the scope of liability within such categories.3
On Wilbur's petition for federal habeas corpus relief, the district
court and the First Circuit rejected the Maine court's construction of the
state homicide statute.36 The federal courts found that malice was an
element of a distinct crime of murder and vacated Wilbur's conviction.
While the state's petition for certiorari was pending, the Maine Supreme
Judicial Court in State v. Lafferty37 reaffirmed the reading it had given
the homicide statute in Wilbur. 8 In light of the new Maine ruling, the
United States Supreme Court remanded Wilbur.39 The First Circuit
again concluded that the writ of habeas corpus should issue; whether
provocation implicated an element of the crime or affected only the
applicable penalty was immaterial. The government could not shift to
the defense the burden of proof on an issue with such serious
consequences. 4°
A unanimous Supreme Court affirmed, in an opinion by Justice
Powell. 4 ' In holding that due process does not permit shifting to the
defense the burden of proving the absence of malice, the Court observed
that a murder conviction results in a more serious deprivation of liberty
and of reputation than does a manslaughter conviction. Since Winship
involved these same interests, the Court rejected the state's contention
that due process requires proof beyond a reasonable doubt only of the
elements of a unified "felonious homicide" offense. "Winship," the Court
declared, "is concerned with substance rather than this kind of
formalism."'4 2
The Court also rejected the argument that applying Winship to the
Maine statutory scheme would unduly interfere with the state's power to
define the substantive grounds of criminal liability. Accepting this argu-
ment, Justice Powell wrote, would invite the states to circumvent
Winship by redefining crimes in the broadest possible terms, shifting the
burden of proof to the defendant with respect to a host of newly denomi-
nated "mitigating factors."4 3 On the other hand, the Wilbur opinion rec-
ognized that inflexibly requiring proof beyond a reasonable doubt might
discourage the states from establishing new defenses. To guard against
this danger and to limit federal intervention to more fundamental
grounds of exculpation, the reasonable doubt standard was to govern
only the proof of historically established defenses or mitigating circum-
stances. Wilbur permitted the states to define crimes as they wished but
forbade the states from circumventing Winship by recasting essential and
well-understood elements of offenses carried over from the common
law. 44
The Wilbur approach thus involves both substantive and procedural
components. As a procedural matter, the government must prove
beyond a reasonable doubt every fact necessary to establish a charged
offense. As a substantive matter, the facts necessary to establish an
offense are not wholly subject to legislative modification. When a fact
has played a central role in the historical development of a crime's defini-
tion, the burden of proving that fact or its absence cannot be shifted to
the defense.
Wilbur fostered a great deal of confusion in the lower courts. 4 This
confusion resulted in part from ambiguities in the Court's opinion. But
the unhappy history of the Wilbur doctrine is in large part due to the
inherent difficulties in determining when a legal concept has become suf-
ficiently entrenched in the Anglo-American legal tradition. The defer-
ence due to history is more easily determined by a supreme court in
a single case than by trial courts in hundreds of diverse cases. 46 For
example, the concepts of intent and insanity often, but not always,
exclude each other.4 7 The Wilbur doctrine unquestionably would pre-
clude a state from convicting a defendant because she failed to establish
absence of intent. Yet by holding that Wilbur did not forbid shifting to
the accused the burden of proving insanity,4" the lower courts endorsed
the continued vitality of Leland v. Oregon.4 9 When one such case
reached the Supreme Court, the appeal was dismissed for failure to pres-
ent a substantial federal question.5
The emphasis on history, moreover, ran the risk of freezing the
criminal law in familiar forms.5 " Wilbur appeared to imply that the
states could not constitutionally abolish the manslaughter classifica-
tion." Yet this implication was not justified by reliance on the eighth
amendment's, cruel and unusual punishment clause or on a substantive
interpretation of the due process clause. Perhaps most disturbingly,
Wilbur appeared to prohibit legislative compromises recognizing new
provocation has been the "single most important factor in determining the degree of culpability
attaching to an unlawful homicide." Wilbur, 421 U.S. at 696. But at common law, the defense bore
the burden of proof with respect to provocation. Id. at 693. The historical support for holding the
reasonable doubt rule applicable to provocation was that "the clear trend" in twentieth century state
practice was toward this result. Id at 696. Justice Powell did not explain why common law practice
informs the constitutional inquiry as to the defenses for which the federal courts may properly
formulate rules of proof, but contemporary state practice governs the content of the rules which the
federal courts impose. Nor did the opinion suggest how lower courts should apply common law and
modern practice in subsequent cases. Moreover, Wilbur presented a relatively pristine variation on
Winship, namely, a traditional definition of substantive offenses and an aberrant allocation of proof
burdens. But what of a jurisdiction with a subjective view of provocation or self-defense? The
accused in such jurisdictions asserts a claim that was not cognizable at common law. Fidelity to the
Wilbur approach would seem to require the prosecution to disprove objectively reasonable self-
defense or provocation beyond a reasonable doubt, but allow the state to shift the burden with
respect to parallel subjective claims-claims that might often be plausible in the same case. A trial
judge forced to apply a historical constitutional analysis to a statute that shifts the burden of proof
without discriminating on a historical basis among substantive claims would have to devise a jury
instruction similar to a Chinese box.
47. As Judge Posner has astutely noted, if the defendant is "under the delusion that he was
shooting two gerbils rather than two human beings, he could not be guilty of murder, but if his
delusion took the form of thinking that he had a sacred duty to reduce the human population by two,
he could be guilty of murder, at least guilty prima facie, though he might have a defense of insanity."
Greider v. Duckworth, 701 F.2d 1228, 1236 (7th Cir. 1983) (Posner, I., concurring).
48. See, eg., Buzynski v. Oliver, 538 F.2d 6, 10 (1st Cir.), cert. denied, 429 U.S. 984 (1976);
United States v. Caldwell, 543 F.2d 1333, 1368-71 (D.C. Cir. 1974), cert. denied, 423 U.S. 1087
(1976).
49. 343 U.S. 790 (1952); see supra text accompanying note 27.
50. Rivera v. Delaware, 429 U.S. 877 (1976).
51. See Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1363-64.
52. See Tushnet, ConstitutionalLimitation of Substantive Criminal Law: An Examination of
the Meaning of Mullaney v. Wilbur, 55 B.U.L. REV. 775, 776 (1975) (Wilbur "stands for the
proposition that the due process clause limits governmental power to define crimes in whatever
manner desired"). The Court's reliance on the central role of provocation in the historical definition
of murder would be relevant only if historical importance qualifies an issue for enhanced
constitutional protection.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1675
for the risk of convicting for murder those in fact guilty only of man-
slaughter, the Court explained that "[d]ue process does not require that
every conceivable step be taken, at whatever cost, to eliminate the possi-
bility of convicting an innocent person."'62
Justice Powell, the author of the Wilbur opinion, dissented in an
opinion joined by two other Justices. 61 In his view, Wilbur had estab-
lished a substantive constraint on state power that precluded defining
crimes so as to circumvent the rule of Winship. He urged the Court to
forbid shifting the burden of proof by rearranging historically recognized
fundamental concepts but not to forbid defining new crimes or
defenses."
Patterson suggests that the constitutionality of burden shifting turns
solely on legislative form and not on the moral or legal significance of the
defendant's claim. 6' The Court's most recent pronouncement on the
question, Martin v. Ohio,6 6 reaffirms, and indeed extends, the formalistic
approach taken in Patterson. In Martin, the Court held that the state
may shift the burden of proving self-defense to one accused of homi-
cide. Self-defense is the defense most deeply rooted in our history and
shared morality. If due process or the eighth amendment requires state
law to recognize any exculpatory doctrine at all, self-defense would
surely rank among those required. The Martin holding, however, indi-
cated that the legislature, by classifying an exculpatory doctrine as an
affirmative defense, may shift the burden of proof even with respect to a
constitutionally required defense firmly rooted in the Anglo-American
legal tradition.
countrywide, that a State must disprove beyond a reasonable doubt every fact constituting any and
all affirmative defenses related to the culpability of an accused.").
62. Id. at 208.
63. Id. at 216 (Powell, J., dissenting).
64. Id. at 226-27 (Powell, J., dissenting) ("[A] substantial difference in punishment alone is not
enough. It also must be shown that in the Anglo-American legal tradition the factor in question
historically has held that level of importance. If either branch of the test is not met, then the
legislature retains its traditional authority over matters of proof.") (footnotes omitted).
65. See Jeffries & Stephan, supranote 3, at 1331 ("The trouble, of course, is that the distinction
is essentially arbitrary."). The authors elaborate:
Traditionally, the only functional difference between a "crime" and a "defense" has
been precisely the issue under consideration-allocation of the burden of proof.... To
make the scope of that doctrine depend on the legislative allocation of the burden of proof
is to assume the point in issue and thus to reduce Winship to a circularity.
Id at 1332. Justice Rehnquist has embraced this formalistic analysis with gusto. In his view,
Winship applies, under Patterson, only to elements; classification of elements and defenses depends
on legislative intent, and the surest guide to legislative intent with respect to classification as an
affirmative defense is a legislative directive shifting the burden of proof. See McElroy v. Holloway,
451 U.S. 1028, 1028-29 (1981) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari). This approach
would require overruling Wilbur explicitly and limiting Winship to its facts as a substantive holding
that the state must prove identity beyond a reasonable doubt in juvenile delinquency proceedings.
66. 107 S. Ct. 1098 (1987).
67. Id. at 1103.
19871 REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1677
Thus the Martin majority did not merely reject the Wilbur
approach, which Justice Powell defended again in dissent. 68 It also
rejected the possibility that the reasonable doubt rule might apply to
constitutionally required defenses without regard to legislative
classification.6 9
If the due process clause speaks about individual rights against the
state, in individual terms, this distinction between elements of a charged
offense and affirmative defenses is plainly arbitrary. But the legislative
classification of exculpatory facts as elemental or defensive corresponds
with one substantive factor, and that is legislative deliberation itself. The
clarity with which a legislature identifies exculpatory conditions as
affirmative defenses will likely vary with the legislative purpose to shift
the burden of proof. The Court's rule thus has the virtue of permitting
deliberate legislative compromises that balance substantive expansion of
exculpatory conditions against procedural concessions to the prosecu-
tion. Put another way, the Patterson holding treats Wilbur and Winship
as permitting the legislature to shift the burden of proof as long as it does
so knowingly. Such a requirement strikes a coherent, if contestable, bal-
ance between the risk of convicting innocent individuals and the risk that
broader grounds of exculpation will go unrecognized because of per-
ceived proof problems for the prosecution.7"
such as provocation or insanity, then the legislature may also take the
more modest step of shifting the burden of proof.
This analysis parallels the familiar positivist position regarding pro-
cedural due process cases involving nonconstitutional entitlements.7 2
The greater power of eliminating the defense is seen as including the
lesser power of shifting the burden of proof. It is no surprise that Justice
Holmes, author of McAuliffe v. Mayor of New Bedford,73 and Justice
Rehnquist, author of Arnett v. Kennedy,74 have found this position
attractive.
According to the positivists, federal courts properly may apply con-
stitutional scrutiny to procedural rules only when federal law also gov-
erns the underlying substantive issue.75 Punishing as a murderer one who
killed only after extreme provocation, or in objectively reasonable self-
defense, may violate substantive due process or the eighth amendment's
cruel and unusual punishment clause.76 Where the Constitution requires
72. See, eg., Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 274-79 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting);
Easterbrook, Substance and Due Process, 1982 Sup. Cr. REv. 85; Smolla, The Right-Privilege
Distinction in ConstitutionalLaw: The Price of Protesting Too Much, 35 STAN. L. REV. 69 (1982).
Cf Reich, The New Property, 73 YALE L.J. 733 (1964); Van Alstyne, The Demise of the Right-
Privilege Distinctionin ConstitutionalLaw, 81 HARv. L. REV. 1439 (1968). It would be tempting to
apply the rejection of the right-privilege distinction in the entitlement cases to the problem of proof
burdens regarding gratuitous defenses. There are, nonetheless, two reasons to avoid this approach.
The first is the Court's insistence, made explicit in Gerstein v. Pugh, 420 U.S. 103, 125 n.27 (1975),
on treating the criminal process differently from civil entitlements, even when that means extending
"less procedural protection to an imprisoned human being than is required to test... the custody of
a refrigerator," id. at 127 (Stewart, J., dissenting) (citation omitted). The second reason is that,
although the Court unambiguously rejected the right-privilege distinction in Cleveland Bd. of Educ.
v. Loudermill, 470 U.S. 532, 538-41 (1985), that rejection rested more on fiat than on persuasive
reasoning. The Court has neither expressly adopted a dignitary theory of due process nor explained
why it rejects the right-privilege distinction. Grounding a constitutional case for the reasonable
doubt rule on the procedural due process cases would therefore overcome the positivist argument
only by reference to its irrational rejection in another context--scarcely an enduring foundation for a
rule of constitutional law. Should the Court ever articulate a principled reason for rejecting the
positivist account in the entitlement cases and look more favorably on applying the entitlement cases
to the criminal context, the argument presented here, infra text accompanying notes 113-25, would
justify a general reasonable doubt rule under the analysis prescribed by Mathews v. Eldridge, 424
U.S. 319 (1976). Cf. Santosky v. Kramer, 455 U.S. 745 (1982) (applying Eldridge to require clear
and convincing evidence in child custody termination proceedings).
73. 155 Mass. 216, 220, 29 N.E. 517, 517 (1892) ("The petitioner may have a constitutional
right to talk politics, but he has no constitutional right to be a policeman."); see also Ferry v.
Ramsey, 277 U.S. 88, 94 (1928) (Holmes, J.) ("The statute in short imposed a liability that was less
than might have been imposed, and that being so, the thing to be considered is the result reached,
not the possibly inartificial or clumsy way of reaching it.").
74. 416 U.S. 134, 153-54 (1974) (plurality opinion); see also McElroy v. Holloway, 451 U.S.
1028, 1028 (1981) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari).
75. See Allen, Structuring Jury Decisionmaking, supra note 3, at 342-48; Jeffries & Stephan,
supra note 3, at 1365.
76. See Moran v. Ohio, 469 U.S. 948, 953-56 (1984) (Brennan, J., dissenting from denial of
certiorari); Engle v. Isaac, 456 U.S. 107, 122 n.22 (1982); Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1366-
79.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1679
II
WINSHIP REVISITED: THE REASONABLE DOUBT RULE
AND THE LEGALITY PRINCIPLE
82. The use of identical language suggests as much, and those who ratified the amendment
could not have understood otherwise. See R. Mo'r, DUE PROCESS OF LAW 163 (1926). Whether
those who drafted the amendment entertained a clear idea of what "due process of law" entailed is
less clear. See J. JAMES, THE FRAMING OF THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT 86-87 (1956)
(discussing Rep. Bingham's confusion); R. Ma-rr,supra, at 165 ("[Tihe members of Congress, with
the exception of a very few first-rate constitutional lawyers in that body, really had no definite
conception of what the phrase meant.").
83. See A. HOWARD, THE ROAD FROM RUNNYMEDE 298-315 (1968); H. TAYLOR, THE
ORIGIN AND GROWTH OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION 236-37 (1911). Dean Pound translated
Chapter 39 of Magna Charta as follows:
No freeman shall be arrested, or detained in prison, or deprived of his freehold, or
outlawed, or banished, or in any way molested; and we will not set forth against him, nor
send against him, unless by the lawful judgment of his peers and by the law of the land.
R. POUND, THE DEVELOPMENT OF CONSTITUTIONAL GUARANTEES OF LIBERTY 123 (1957). One
of the abuses inspiring Chapter 39 was disregard of the legality principle. See W. McKECHNIE,
MAGNA CHARTA 376-77 (1905); R. MOT, supranote 82, at 33 ("particular abuse which the section
aims to curb is that of execution before judgment").
Coke, in his Second Institute, published in 1642, equated "by the law of the land" with "due
process of law." 2 E. COKE, INSTITUTES OF THE LAW OF ENGLAND *50. Habeas corpus, available
at equity if the law courts were unavailable, both effected the guarantee and confirmed its nature.
"By these writs it manifestly appeareth, that no man ought to be imprisoned, but for some certain
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1681
cause: and these words, ad sujiciend. et recipiend. &c. prove that cause must be shewed: for other-
wise how can the court take order therein according to law?" Id at *53. The requirement of legal
cause could be satisfied by a bill of attainder (a concept repugnant to the founders, see U.S. CONST.
art. I §§ 9-10, but not unknown in post-revolutionary America) but Coke took pains to note that no
penalty could attach before the attainder. Id at *48. By Blackstone's time the procedural guaran-
tees against unjust punishment had been expanded, but the central principle that a person's liberty
could be terminated only for violations of law established by regular procedures remained. See IW.
BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *133-34, *136.
84. See R. POUND, supra note 83, at 109-10 [arguing for open-ended interpretation]:
But the terms "liberty" and "due process" were legal terms with well-understood meanings
known to lawyers; and when one notes the names of the great lawyers who signed the
original Constitution-one future Chief Justice and two future Justices of the Supreme
Court of the United States, a Chief Justice of New Jersey, and many who were then
accounted leaders of the profession, it is idle to assume that they did not know the
significance of the words they used.
H. TAYLOR, supra note 83, at 79-80, 237, objected to undue emphasis on the weight accorded Coke's
views by the founders, noting that Coke's Second Institute was written during the reign of James I,
when the Court of Star Chamber was still unchecked. Taylor argued that the broader conception of
due process articulated by Blackstone more closely approximates the framers' vision. Id But Coke
and Blackstone did not disagree about the incorporation of the legality principle in Magna Charta.
See supra note 83.
85. 2 J. KENT, COMMENTARIES ON AMERICAN LAW *12-13.
86. 2 J. STORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 565-67 (5th
ed. Boston 1891) (1st ed. Boston 1833).
87. 59 U.S. (18 How.) 272 (1855). Murray'sLessee involved the constitutionality of a distress
warrant for the seizure of property owned by a delinquent taxpayer. The Court, per Justice Curtis,
rejected the notion that the legislature could make "any process 'due process of law,' by its mere
will." Id. at 276. Instead, due process incorporated those procedures recognized at common law;
since the distress warrant had analogues in English common law, its use did not violate due process.
Id. at 277-80. The reasoning applied in Murray's Lessee could neither protect individuals from new
forms of oppression nor permit benign departures from common law procedures. For this reason,
the historical approach gave way to less restrictive interpretive techniques. See Hurtado v.
California, 110 U.S. 516 (1884) (upholding for the first time an indictment on information rather
than by the traditional grand jury); see also, Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U.S. 78, 101 (1908) ("It
does not follow, however, that a procedure settled in English law at the time of the emigration ... is
an essential element of due process of law."). Departure from historical standards in favor of natural
law interpretations invites the objection that the judges are indulging contemporary, idiosyncratic,
political preferences rather than applying an authoritative legal text. Cf.Lochner v. New York, 198
U.S. 45 (1905). This choice between inherited and contemporary arbitrariness remains at the heart
of most due process cases. See generally Kadish, Methodology and Criteria in Due Process
Adjudication-A Survey and Criticism, 66 YALE L.J. 319 (1957). I am not here proposing a general
1682 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
approach to due process cases; on the contrary, my thesis is that even on the narrower understanding
of due process as a technical provision governing criminal prosecutions' according to common law
standards, legality is the central element of due process.
88. Even Judge Easterbrook admits this much. See Easterbrook, supra note 72, at 98-100.
89. Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963).
90. Pointer v. Texas, 380 U.S. 400 (1965).
91. Webb v. Texas, 409 U.S. 95 (1972).
92. United States v. Wade, 388 U.S. 218 (1967).
93. Benton v. Maryland, 395 U.S. 784 (1969).
94. It might be objected that the jury system of the late 18th and 19th century, whether in
England or America, gave jurors power over law as well as fact. This system could be seen as
concerned less with measuring conduct according to legal criteria than with assessing the
defendant's moral fitness for punishment. The objection would be misplaced, however, because the
jury system has never been understood as authorizing extra-legal punishment. Even the most
vigorous defenders of the jury's power over questions of law understood the jurors to exercise solely
the power of reducing, not of increasing, the scope and severity of criminal liability. See T. GREEN,
VERDICT ACCORDING TO CONSCIENCE 261 (1985) (according to opponents of Stuart rule who
defended the jury's power over issues of law, "Right to jury was right to judgment by two lay bodies,
mainly to provide a double check on fact but also to prevent prosecutions for activity that was not
truly criminal."). Blackstone, who strongly defended the legality principle, see 1 W. BLACKSTONE,
supra note 83, at *92, pointed out that although the court could set aside jury verdicts of guilty, none
that acquitted the prisoner had been set aside, 4 id at *355. See, eg., The King & Smith, 84 Eng.
Rep. 1197 (K.B. 1681) (setting aside conviction against the evidence); The King & Primate v.
Fenwicke & Holt, 83 Eng. Rep. 1104 (K.B. 1663) (denying motion for new trial even though
acquittal resulted when defendant's servants kidnapped witnesses); The King v. Read, 83 Eng. Rep.
1987] RFSONABLE DOUBT RULE 1683
271 (K.B. 1660) (forbidding new trial after acquittal); see also W. HAWKINS, PLEAS OF THE CROWN
442 (2d ed. London 1724). Illegal acquittals were thus distinguished from illegal convictions which
were beyond the jury's power.
The court's authority to prevent an unjust guilty verdict was not, at common law, limited to
insufficiency of the evidence. Before trial, on a plea of demurrer or a plea of the general issue, the
judges would dismiss an indictment that charged the wrong crime or that failed to charge any crime.
4 W. BLACKSTONE, supra note 83, at *327-28. After a jury verdict of guilty, the defense could move
in arrest ofjudgment on the same ground. Id. at *368-69 ("a defective indictment is not aided by a
verdict"). If unsuccessful, review was available in the Court of King's Bench on writs of error and
certiorari. Id. at *262, *384.
Early American practice involved a similar refusal to permit juries to convict except according
to the law. See, ag., United States v. Villato, 28 F. Cas. 377 (C.C.D. Pa. 1797) (No. 16,622) (alien
cannot be guilty of treason); Commonwealth v. Hearsey, I Mass. *137 (1804) (plea of guilty to
indictment that failed to charge crime arrested by court acting sua sponte); Commonwealth v. Catlin,
I Mass. *8 (1804) (evidence of private sexual activity insufficient to support indictment for public
lewdness); State v. Boon, 1 N.C. (Tray.) 191 (1801) (jury verdict of guilty set aside because statute
forbidding killing slave was "too uncertain" to enforce); Respublica v. Richards, 2 Dall. 224 (Pa.
1795) (verdict of not guilty directed under statute forbidding enslavement of blacks because
defendant owned slave under laws of another state); Respublica v. Roberts, 2 DalI. 124 (Pa. 1791)
(unmarried man cannot be convicted of adultery, but only of fornication); State v. S.S., I Tyl. 180
(Vt. 1801) (indictment charging breach of the peace quashed because statute forbidding
"challenging" another did not apply to a written challenge to duel). Even when the indictment
charged a common law crime for conduct not previously condemned, the court retained the
authority to determine the scope of the common law of crimes. See, eg, Respublica v. Teischer, I
Dall. 335 (Pa. 1788) (malicious killing of horse is criminal at common law).
Aggregate data confirm that early American juries were not authorized to convict except
according to the law. Of 2718 federal indictments filed between 1801 and 1828, 902 ended in nolle
prosequ, 661 had no recorded disposition, and 80 were abated, quashed, discharged, discontinued, or
terminated by escape. Only 1075, fewer than half, ended in jury verdicts. D. HENDERSON,
CONGRESS, COURTS, AND CRIMINALS 46-47 (1985). Against this background, the Bill of Rights can
scarcely be seen as designed to assist the jury in a lawless inquiry about the defendant's moral fitness
for punishment. Rather, it establishes a fundamental defense against unlawful punishment.
95. Professor Kadish has observed:
The various procedural safeguards traditionally demanded in the name of due process
appear to be directed to two objectives. One is the goal of insuring the reliability of the
guilt-determining process-reducing to a minimum the possibility that any innocent
individual will be punished. It is not of crucial importance whether the individual tried is
in fact guilty or innocent, but it is of crucial concern that the integrity of the process of
ascertaining guilt or innocence never be impaired. If in this effort to insure that none but
those guilty be convicted, many guilty go free, the price is not too great in the long view of
democratic government. If there is any consideration basic to all civilized procedures it is
this, no matter how disparate the means chosen to give it effect.
This consideration, often expressed in terms of "fairness," gives meaning to the great
bulk of procedures that have become part of the due process of law: that the accused be
put on fair notice of the nature of the prohibited acts; that he be given an adequate
opportunity to present his side through counsel before a fair and impartial tribunal free
from prejudicial influences; that he be entitled to be continuously present at the trial, and
to confront and cross-examine his accusers; that he have the right to be free of the
damaging and untrustworthy influence of coerced confessions and testimony knowingly
perjured.
The relation between restrictions on process directed to this objective and the ultimate
values of human freedom is not obscure.... Due process thus serves the same end as a
1684 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
positive law, as contrasted with a law residing in the will of a ruling power-the attainment
of legal security and certainty.
Kadish, supra note 87, at 346.
96. See, eg., Kolender v. Lawson, 461 U.S. 352 (1983) (striking down a "stop and identify"
statute for vagueness because it encouraged arbitrary enforcement); Papachristou v. City of
Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156 (1972) (finding criminal vagrancy statute unconstitutionally vague);
Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 306 U.S. 451, 458 (1939) ("The challenged provision . . . [is] so vague,
indefinite and uncertain that it [is] repugnant to the due process clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment.").
97. See, e.g., Bouie v. City of Columbia, 378 U.S. 347, 355 n.5 (1964) ("We think it irrelevant
that petitioners at one point testified that they had intended to be arrested."). But see Rose v. Locke,
423 U.S. 48 (1975) ("crime against nature" statute not unconstitutionally vague as applied to forcible
cunnilingus). This pattern, involving a defendant who knows his conduct to be criminal but who is
prosecuted on an unforeseeable ground, should be distinguished from that involving defendants
whose conduct is clearly within a statute whose applicability to other conduct is uncertain; typically
such a defendant has no vagueness claim. See Parker v. Levy, 417 U.S. 733 (1974).
98. Explanations of the vagueness doctrine typically supplement the fair notice rationale with
the prevention of discriminatory enforcement, especially when enforcement might trench upon other
constitutional rights. See, eg., Papachristou,405 U.S. at 168-71; 1 W. LAFAVE & A. ScoTr, supra
note 2, § 2.3(c), at 132; P. Low, J. JEFcRIEs & R. BONNIE, CRIMINAL LAW 67-79 (1982). In my
view this account, although on the right track, is somewhat incomplete. Whether prosecution under
a vague statute is discriminatory or simply arbitrary, it risks making individuals suffer for reasons
insufficiently important to be articulated prospectively. Thus, the penalties imposed are
objectionable even when not inspired by official animus; gratuitous punishment is wrong even when
it is based neither on racial prejudice nor on a program of political oppression.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1685
that declaration, the state may not argue that the general interest
requires the suffering of a particular person. The chance that such an
argument is meritorious is too remote, the chance that the argument is
feigned too immediate, to justify its temptation in every case.
Several other arguments support the legality principle. It may pre-
vent political oppression9 9 and contribute to individual security."° More
categorically, it may simply be wrong to punish those who have not
offended an expressed rule. 01° But none of these arguments can explain
why the legality principle enjoys nearly complete priority over the public
interest in punishing wrongdoers-why punishment unauthorized by law
is, in civilized communities, simply beyond the pale. The priority of the
legality principle derives, I believe, from profound skepticism about
assertions that punishing legal conduct will contribute to the public inter-
est. In the face of the undoubted pain that accompanies any punishment,
this skepticism fully justifies the priority of the legality principle over the
general goals of punishment. 10 2
Many other Supreme Court precedents depend on the central role of
the legality principle in due process adjudication. The cases can be sepa-
rated into two categories, procedural and substantive. In the first cate-
gory, the Court has required state courts to follow specific procedures
designed to minimize the risk of erroneous conviction. These cases
include selective incorporation decisions in which the Court has iead the
due process clause as specifying procedures necessary to enforce the
legality principle and therefore implied or incorporated by the basic
guarantee of due process.10 3 In other cases in this category, the Court
has imposed procedures on the state courts on the basis of the due pro-
cess clause's independent potency. 1 4
The second category of cases involve direct, substantive efforts by
99. See Rawls, Two Concepts of Rules, 1955 PHIL. REV. 7-8.
100. See H.L.A. HART, PUNISHMENT AND RESPONSIBILITY 11-13, 17-24 (1968); Kadish, supra
note 87, at 346; Raz, The Rule of Law and Its Virtue, 93 LAW Q. REv. 195, 202-05 (1977).
101. See H.L.A. HART, supra note 100, at 22.
102. Legality, then, is an ultimately utilitarian principle. Indeed, frugality of punishment had a
prominent place in Jeremy Bentham's thought. See I J. BENTHAM, WORKS 398-99 (Edinburgh and
London 1859). The notion that retribution for immoral but legal actions might justify official
punishment is not implausible, but the cases in which such action might justifiably be taken are
always isolated, because the community can always reform the law prospectively. Allowing
punishment in one such case necessarily hazards many instances of unjustified suffering for every,
albeit outrageous, instance of lawful wrongdoing.
103. See cases cited supra notes 89-93. See generally Kadish, supra note 87. In a strained
attempt to avoid some unsavory implications of their theory that state power to define grounds of
liability entails state power to define the applicable procedures, the positivists argue that burden of
proof rules serve different functions than other aspects of due process. On the viability of this
distinction, see infra text accompanying notes 209-18.
104. See, eg., Betts v. Brady, 316 U.S. 455 (1942) (due process required state to provide counsel
to indigents in noncapital cases only in special circumstances).
1686 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
due process. "In our society liberty is the norm, and detention prior to trial or without trial is the
carefully limited exception." Id at 2105. The decision casts no doubt on the legality principle's
application to the adjudication of guilt.
111. 397 U.S. 358 (1970).
112. 443 U.S. 307 (1979).
113. When a given procedure forms an integral part of the federal right or when the absence of
the procedure would render the federal right nugatory, the supremacy clause requires at least this
much. See Monaghan, The Supreme Court, 1974 Term-Foreword:ConstitutionalCommon Law, 89
HARV. L. REV. 1, 22-23 (1975). The federal courts also have crafted various prophylactic rules-
that is, rules designed to enforce constitutional provisions even if they override state authority in the
absence of a constitutional violation. The Miranda rules are the classic example. See Miranda v.
Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966). In Professor Monaghan's view, rules of this type are legitimate,
though subject to legislative modification. Monaghan, supra, at 27-30. His position has been
criticized for endorsing judicial interference with political decisions in the absence of constitutional
authority, see Shrock & Welsh, Reconsideringthe ConstitutionalCommon Law, 91 HARV. L. REv.
1117 (1978), and for approving constitutional adjudication in the absence of a genuine case or
controversy, see Grano, Prophylactic Rules in Criminal Procedure. A Question of Article III
Legitimacy, 80 Nw. U.L. REv. 100 (1985).
At least with respect to the fourth amendment exclusionary rule and the Mirandawarnings,
Professor Monaghan's critics are wide of the mark. The problem in both situations is that the
outcome of a particular case may determine the constitutional rights of persons not before the court.
It is not the purpose of the fourth amendment to protect crime, but unless some criminals are
protected, the lawful enjoyment of privacy might be lost. See Dipps, Living with Leon, 95 YALE
L.J. 906, 918-22 (1986). Similarly, the Miranda rules may require exclusion of some voluntary
statements, but without such rules courts would admit a great many involuntary statements
1688 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
extracted by the police. See Schulhofer, The Fifth Amendment at Justice: A Reply, 54 U. Cai. L.
REv. 950, 956 (1987). The objections to the Monaghan thesis assume that the risk of future
violations of constitutional rights can never justify the reversal of a conviction that did not result
from a constitutional violation. This assumption is, in my view, mistaken.
With respect to the objection that constitutional authority is lacking, the refusal to reverse a
constitutionally rendered conviction, when reversal is the only way to prevent future constitutional
violations, amounts to treating the Constitution, not as an authority, but as a mere "code of ethics
under an honor system." Stewart, The Road to Mapp v. Ohio and Beyond, 83 COLUM. L. REv.
1365, 1383-84 (1983); see Dripps, supra, at 934-39. For illustration, consider Tennessee v. Garner,
471 U.S. 1 (1985), which holds that the fatal shooting of a nondangerous fleeing suspect amounts to
an unreasonable seizure under the fourth amendment. If the substantive holding is correct, any
enforcement of the suspect's fourth amendment rights would require an action by survivors -
individuals not themselves victims of the constitutional violation. There is thus no doctrinal
difference between the action allowed in Garner and the reversal of convictions under Mapp and
Miranda;in all three cases, the courts strike down state action because to do otherwise would foster
violations of the Constitution. In such situations, the article III objection confronts Chief Justice
Marshall's commonsense observation that the Court has "no more right to decline the exercise of
jurisdiction which is given, than to usurp that which is not given. The one or the other would be
treason to the constitution." Cohens v. Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264, 404 (1821); see also Moses
H. Cone Memorial Hosp. v. Mercury Constr. Corp., 460 U.S. 1, 15 (1983) ("[Federal courts have a
'virtually unflagging obligation to exercise the jurisdiction given them.'" (quoting Colorado River
Water Conserv. Dist. v. United States, 424 U.S. 800, 817 (1976)); Currie, The Supreme Court and
FederalJurisdiction:1975 Term, 1976 Sup. Cr. REv. 183, 213-15; Redish, Abstention, Separation of
Powers, and the Limits of the JudicialFunction, 94 YALE L.J. 71 (1984) (criticizing the abstention
doctrine as abdication of mandatory jurisdiction).
My point is not to condemn prudential abstention doctrines, which may be defensible on other
grounds. See Shapiro, Jurisdictionand Discretion, 60 N.Y.U. L. REv. 543 (1985). Rather, I suggest
that the Supreme Court has at least the authority, if not the obligation, to choose constitutional
overenforcement over constitutional underenforcement. Cf Sosna v. Iowa, 419 U.S. 393 (1975)
(expiration of claim of class representative did not moot case for the entire class). If this is so, then
Professor Monaghan's characterization of Mapp and Miranda is unfortunate, for these decisions are
in no way subconstitutional, although they do depend on empirical causal relationships that might
be altered by legislation. Cases announcing prophylactic rules are constitutional decisions insofar as
they recognize criminal defendants' standing to enforce the constitutional rights of other parties.
The rules announced in Mapp and Miranda, therefore, could not be modified without infringing on
the constitutional rights of individuals, albeit different individuals than those convicted as a result of
the modifications.
114. See Norris v. Alabama, 294 U.S. 587, 589-90 (1935); Monaghan, Constitutional Fact
Review, 85 COLUM. L. REv. 229, 271-76 (1985). Of course, federal courts may-and most
frequently do-decline to review the facts independently.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1689
115. See, e.g., Patterson v. New York, 432 U.S. 197, 201-02 (1977) ("[Wle should not lightly
construe the Constitution so as to intrude upon the administration of justice by the individual
States.").
1690 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
comply with the legality principle, that is, punish no one for crime with-
1 16 If
out a formal adjudication of conduct made criminal by positive law.
this much is legitimate, then cases like Mooney 117 and Thompson 18 are
also correct in requiring that the adjudication of guilt amount to some-
thing more than a palpable sham. At the other extreme, if federalism is
of any constitutional moment, then trial de novo in federal courts would
usurp the state responsibility that establishes the constitutional premise
of federal review.
Between preventing patently unauthorized punishment on the one
hand and avoiding trial de novo on the other, the Constitution provides
little guidance. Reasonable judges have endorsed at least three
approaches: (1) requiring nothing more than minimal legality-that is,
formal judgment, subject to federal review solely to prevent state use of
show trials designed to circumvent the adjudication requirement; (2)
requiring state trial courts to apply proof burdens and rules of evidence
that bias the outcome against erroneous conviction and toward erroneous
acquittal; and (3) requiring federal review of state judgments to ensure
that the judgment rendered satisfies these proof burdens and rules of evi-
dence, with substantial deference, in the interest of federalism, to the
state court judgment. Winship follows the second approach, and Jackson
the third. Patterson and Martin, in effect, apply the first approach to any
issue the state chooses to classify as an affirmative defense. The choice
among these competing approaches depends on the method used to
derive procedures and remedies from substantive constitutional
provisions.
2. ConstitutionalMethod
To choose among enforcement options for protecting constitutional
rights, the Court generally follows an instrumental approach, which
focuses on the purpose of the constitutional provision at issue. The
Court requires the states to follow procedures calculated to enforce effec-
tively the federal right, but does not require the most effective remedy or
most painstaking procedures. What procedures and remedies suffice
depends on the Court's perception of both how difficult it will be to
enforce the particular right in question and how costly additional proce-
dures would be.
Gerstein v. Pugh119 illustrates the Court's instrumental approach.
The Court held that the fourth amendment right against arbitrary deten-
116. Again, even Judge Easterbrook appears to admit this much. See Easterbrook, supra note
72, at 98.
117. 294 U.S. 103 (1935); see supra text accompanying notes 106-07.
118. 362 U.S. 199 (1960); see supra text accompanying notes 108-10.
119. 420 U.S. 103 (1975).
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1691
126. See, eg., J. ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DismusT 73-104 (1980) (defining and defending
"representation-reinforcing" approach to constitutional interpretation which focuses on the political
process). Cf United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938) (reserving
question of the level of scrutiny to be applied to legislation restricting the political processes that
might lead to repeal of undesirable legislation).
127. Justice Rehnquist's opinion for the Court in Schall v. Martin, 467 U.S. 253 (1984), offers
an excellent example. There, the Court upheld preventive detention of juveniles, in large part
because laws in every state provided for such incarceration. Id. at 267 n.16. Since juveniles are not
allowed to vote, process-based theory suggests that they are vulnerable to political abuse. The
existence of laws authorizing preventive detention of juveniles (based on predictions of future
criminal conduct) offers more empirical support for the process-based argument for
unconstitutionality than it offers for the reasoned-legislative-judgment argument for
constitutionality. On the implications of preventive detention for the legality principle, see supra
note 110.
The Court recently has disavowed any reliance on state practice in deciding whether due
process requires proof of crime beyond reasonable doubt. See Martin v. Ohio, 107 S. Ct. 1098, 1102-
03 (1987).
128. See Powell, Rules for Orfiginalists,73 VA. L. REv. 659, 677 (1987) ("Justices Hugo Black
and William Rehnquist, perhaps the two most consistent originalists in the Supreme Court's history,
have been equally consistent in their claims that the founders' views coincided with their own,
despite historial evidence to the contrary.").
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1693
129. But cf R. DwoRmIN, LAW'S EMPIRE (1986) (arguing that judges should interpret legal
texts so as to make them the best possible). Dworkin's approach runs the same risk that textual
indeterminism runs-namely, defeating the purpose of constitutions. Written constitutions have the
purpose of organizing and limiting government according to a dispositive authority. Once political
actors, including judges, have unfettered discretion to do as they please, the constitution is no longer
dispositive. Professor Dworkin thinks the constitution is determinate because he thinks political
morality is determinate; in other words, he thinks contemporary values will point to a right answer
from among the many allowed by the constitutional text. I think the point of a constitution is to
prevent contemporary values from operating politically except according to constitutional authority.
His view, I believe, would have effects indistinguishable from candid indeterminism. See Monaghan,
Our Perfect Constitution, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rnv. 353 (1981).
1694 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
136. See H. ZEISEL, THE LIMITS OF LAW ENFORCEMENT 19-21, 25-26 (1982).
137. Cf A. AMsTERDAm , supra note 131, § 280, at 1-402 ("That a criminal defendant is
presumed to be innocent until proved guilty is a canard. In reality, most criminal defendants must
prove their innocence .... ").
138. See, eg., Alschuler, The Prosecutor'sRole in Plea Bargaining 36 U. CHI. L. REv. 50, 60
(1968) ("The universal rule is that the sentence differential between guilty-plea and trial defendants
increases in direct proportion to the likelihood of acquittal.").
1696 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
143. 443 U.S. 307 (1979); see supra text accompanying note 112.
144. 294 U.S. 103 (1935); see supra text accompanying notes 106-07.
145. 362 U.S. 199 (1960); see supra text accompanying notes 108-10.
146. 397 U.S. 358 (1970); see supra text accompanying notes 16-27.
147. See Jackson v. Virginia, 443 U.S. 307, 313 (1979) (notwithstanding sufficiency of evidence
to establish second degree murder, issue remained whether state had proved premeditation element
of first degree murder beyond a reasonable doubt).
148. 337 U.S. 241 (1949).
149. See eg., Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1352-53 & n.79.
1698 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
150. A convict can make a legality-based objection if the judge enhances the sentence because of
the convict's lawful conduct. See North Carolina v. Pearce, 395 U.S. 711 (1969) (after conviction on
retrial, trial judge may impose a higher sentence if the higher sentence is within the statutorily
defined range and is not designed to punish the defendant for exercising a lawful right to appeal).
151. H.L.A. HART, supra note 100, at 8-11.
152. Id. at 11-13.
1987] 9]REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1699
deferential to legislative judgments. 157 But when the legislature itself has
concluded that punishment above the maximum for the lesser-included
offense would be disproportionate, the convict's claim is stronger. Those
who act in a certain way deserve punishment, and up to the maximum
there might be social advantage in punishing some of them. Beyond the
maximum, however, the legislature cannot foresee any community
advantage that might justify more severe penalties.
The constitutional liberty interest in freedom from unauthorized
punishment thus requires not only prospective definition of criminal con-
duct but also prospective definition of the potential punishment. Just as
the state may not imprison an individual for, say, possession of a hand-
gun unless some state law prohibits handgun possession, so too the state
may not sentence the defendant to ten years in prison for handgun pos-
session if the law provides a maximum sentence of one year for that
offense. The prescription made in advance has the imprimatur of neu-
trality; to depart from it once the convict's identity is known risks pun-
ishing the defendant for something she didn't do.
The Supreme Court has recognized the legality principle's place in
limiting the scope, as well as the existence, of criminal liability. In Specht
v. Patterson,15 8 the Court struck down a Colorado statute that permitted
the sentencing court, upon a conviction for a predicate sex offense, to
classify the defendant as a sexual psychopath and impose an indetermi-
nate sentence of from one day to life in prison.15 9 In effect, the statute
created a separate offense-liability to a distinct range of penalties upon a
finding of a specified fact-and permitted adjudication of the separate
charge without the procedural safeguards of a criminal trial."6
The federal courts, however, have retreated from the principle, if
not the explicit holding, of Specht. The circuit courts upheld the federal
dangerous special offender statute (repealed in 1985) under which the
trial court could increase the sentence of a "dangerous special offender"
to a maximum of twenty-five years. Classification as a dangerous special
offender was made by the trial court after a sentencing hearing governed
157. Cf Rummel v. Estelle, 445 U.S. 263, 304-06 (1980) (Powell, J., dissenting) (Fourth
Circuit's application of the proportionality analysis, eventually adopted by the Court in Solem v.
Helm, 463 U.S. 277 (1983), resulted in reversal of only three sentences in ten years).
158. 386 U.S. 605 (1967).
159. Id. at 607-08.
160. The majority opinion stated:
The Sex Offenders Act does not make the commission of a specified crime the basis for
sentencing. It makes one conviction the basis for commencing another proceeding under
another Act to determine whether a person constitutes a threat of bodily harm to the
public, or is an habitual offender and mentally ill. That is a new finding of fact that was not
an ingredient of the offense charged.
Id. at 608 (citation omitted).
19871 REASONABLE DOUBT RULE
161. The special offender statute, 18 U.S.C. § 3575 (1982), was repealed in 1985. Pub. L. No.
98-473, tit. II, ch. II, § 212(a)(2), 98 Stat. 1987 (1984). For cases upholding the statute, see, e.g.,
United States v. Schell, 692 F.2d 672, 676-79 (10th Cir. 1982); United States v. Bowdach, 561 F.2d
1160, 1172-75 (5th Cir. 1977); United States v. Stewart, 531 F.2d 326, 332-35 (6th Cir.), cert denied,
426 U.S. 922 (1976). But see United States v. Duardi, 384 F. Supp. 874, 882-83 (W.D. Mo. 1974),
aff'd on other grounds, 529 F.2d 123 (8th Cir. 1975). Specht antedates Winship, and the federal
courts have limited the procedural protections guaranteed by Specht to those constitutionally
established at the time of that opinion. Cf.Schell, 692 F.2d at 677. The statute nonetheless created a
separate offense, just as in Specht, for once the defendant was shown to be a dangerous special
offender (defined in section 3575 (e) & (f) as a person who has committed two prior offenses of
specified types and who requires additional confinement for the protection of the public), the
maximum sentence for any of the predicate felonies could be increased to as much as twenty-five
years. Whether the trial court actually increased the sentence depended on the sentencing judge's
assessment of the defendant's dangerousness. Sentencing judges routinely make precisely this sort of
determination but usually within a range predetermined by the legislature. To my mind, the
government should have been required to prove the predicate felonies and dangerous proclivities
beyond a reasonable doubt. Otherwise, the defendant would be exposed to a range of liability far in
excess of that prescribed prior to the conduct. As Judge McKay noted in a thoughtful opinion:
A statute that imposes an additional sentence through a separate post-conviction
proceeding results in a reclassification of the defendant for the purpose of enhanced
punishment. This reclassification is essentially identical to an additional criminal
conviction. Consequently, the defendant's liberty interest that survived the original
conviction is entitled to procedural protections, similar to those provided at trial, in the
post-conviction proceeding.
Schell, 692 F.2d at 682 n.1 (McKay, J., concurring and dissenting) (citing Specht, 386 U.S. at 608-
10).
162. 106 S. Ct. 2411, 2420 (1986).
163. Id. at 2418.
164. Id. at 2416-18.
1702 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
III
POINTS OF DEPARTURE REVISITED
167. See eg., Note, The Constitutionality of Statutes Permitting Increased Sentences for
Habitual or DangerousCriminals, 89 HARV. L. REv. 356, 385-86 (1975).
168. See eg., R. v. Gardiner, 140 D.L.R.3d 612 (Can. 1983) (Supreme Court of Canada held
that sentencing constitutes a part of the trial process and therefore the Crown bears the burden to
prove all disputed facts); see also Wasik, Rules ofEvidence in the Sentencing Process, 38 CURRENT
LEGAL PROBS. 187, 194-200 (1985).
169. See Gardner.v. Florida, 430 U.S. 349 (1977) (plurality opinion) (due process violated by
death sentence imposed on the basis of information that defendant did not have opportunity to refute
or explain); Weissman, Sentencing Due Process: Evolving ConstitutionalPrinciples, 18 WAKE FoREST
L. REV. 523 (1982).
170. In rejecting the claim that the elements test would permit the states to recast traditional
criteria of liability in the form of mitigating circumstances to be considered at sentencing, the
Pattersonmajority stated that "there are obviously constitutional limits beyond which the States may
not go in this regard." Patterson v. New York, 432 U.S. 197, 210 (1977). This appears to indicate
that the Williams approach may not be extended to the trial of legislative grading determinations,
and that the inconsistency between the procedures required at sentencing and those required at trial
may be resolved only by gradually increasing the scrutiny of the sentencing process.
1704 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
reexamines the case law and the commentary from the standpoint of the
legality principle.
The risk of unauthorized punishment is no less grgent in the context
of affirmative defenses than in the context of proving elements of the
offense. Neither history nor the need to facilitate legislative reform can
justify altering the constitutional protection against unauthorized punish-
ment according to legislative classifications. The positivist commentators
have rightly condemned the Court for failing to provide a neutral princi-
ple that justifies requiring the reasonable doubt standard sometimes, but
not always. But the positivists have also misunderstood the nature of the
constitutional right at issue. As a result, they have urged an approach
that would logically entail abandoning constitutional restrictions on state
criminal procedure with respect to a very large proportion of the issues
raised in typical litigation. Yet ironically, the positivists have failed to
offer a coherent justification for the reasonable doubt standard. Neither
the positivists nor other commentators have grounded the reasonable
doubt rule on a convincing constitutional warrant.
Basing the reasonable doubt rule on the legality principle therefore
offers important advantages over the positions thus far advanced in the
case law and the legal literature. I first consider the judicial distinction
and then turn to the positivist commentary.
mental hospital, see Jones v. United States, 463 U.S. 354, 381 n.16 (1983) (Brennan, J., dissenting),
there is far less to fear from an erroneous insanity acquittal than from an erroneous acquittal based
on entrapment or absence of intent. The bete noirfor the foes of the insanity defense is the Hinckley
case, which indeed led to the passage of a federal statute shifting the burden of proof to the defense
on this issue. See 18 U.S.C. § 20 (Supp. III 1985). Yet few would disagree with the proposition that
Hinckley was insane at the time of his attack on the President. Apparently, the point of shifting the
burden of proof is to reduce arbitrarily the number of successful assertions of the defense. If this
rationale is correct, the defense should be abolished, not rationed according to the defendant's ability
to hire psychiatrists and lawyers. Cf. N. MORRIS, MADNESS AND THE CRIMINAL LAW 53-76 (1985)
(proposing abolition of special defense of insanity, returning to common law principles of actus reus
and mens rea). On the other hand, since the difference between conviction and commitment is
relatively slight, an erroneous rejection of an insanity claim less significantly implicates the core
concern of the legality principle-minimizing useless punishment-than does the erroneous rejection
of other defenses. If the Court believes an exception for insanity is indispensable, this distinction
might rationalize such an exception. In any event, if certain issues, such as sanity, are so clearly
distinct from the typical issue of historical fact that an exception to the government's burden must be
recognized, the elements test remains indefensible, for it looks to legislative classification rather than
to susceptibility to proof in determining the certainty required for conviction.
173. Withdrawal from conspiracy or attempt is typically an affirmative defense, yet the overt act
element of conspiracy, and the dangerous proximity element of attempt, are typically classified as
elements. These elements and defenses govern the same ambiguous issue of culpability, namely
whether unfulfilled criminal intent deserves to be punished.
174. See 432 U.S. at 226-30 (Powell, J., dissenting); see also supra text accompanying notes 63-
64.
175. See 432 U.S. at 209-11 & nn.ll-13; see also supra notes 57-62 and accompanying text.
176. See Fletcher, supra note 4, at 902-03.
177. 160 U.S. 469 (1895) (federal jury cannot convict where it has a reasonable doubt whether
defendant was mentally competent at the time of the killing).
178. See Fletcher, supra note 4, at 917-18; see also Patterson, 432 U.S. at 202-03:
1706 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
preting the due process clause could justify a distinction between ele-
ments and defenses.
Nevertheless, the constitutional values served by the reasonable
doubt rule are implicated equally whether the legislature has classified a
fact as an element or as a defense. Whatever else it may mean, due pro-
cess of law surely means that individuals whose conduct has not violated
the law may not be subjected to criminal punishment. This value judg-
ment speaks to reality and not to procedural appearances. In terms of
substantive legality, one who kills on reasonable provocation is not guilty
of murder, whether state law deems provocation a defense or malice
aforethought an element. Similarly, one who kills in the reasonable belief
that lethal violence is immediately necessary to save her own life has
committed no crime, whether self-defense constitutes an affirmative
defense or negates the element of unlawfulness.17 9
Extending the reasonable doubt rule to affirmative defenses would
therefore not involve an assertion of judicial values not expressed in the
due process clause itself. Extending the rule would only impose a proce-
dural safeguard to protect a constitutionally recognized value. The
Court has often, and justifiably, extended contemporary procedures to
protect constitutional values in the area of criminal justice.
Two well-known examples suffice to illustrate this extension process.
In Katz v. United States,18 the Court held that electronic surveillance
that exposes private communibations may yield admissible evidence only
if the techniques conform with fourth amendment standards. Wiretaps
and bugs were unknown to the founders; the framers, therefore, could
not have intended to subject them to fourth amendment standards. The
Court, however, did not depart from a principled understanding of the
fourth amendment in its holding. The Court did no more than extend a
familiar and accepted procedure to protect the central value judgment of
1 81
the amendment.
Davis... had wide impact on the practice in the federal courts with respect to the burden
of proving various affirmative defenses, and the prosecution in a majority of jurisdictions in
this country sooner or later came to shoulder the burden of proving the sanity of the
accused and of disproving the facts constituting other affirmative defenses, including
provocation.
179. That certain crimes depend on elements that amount to moral judgments, in addition to
historical facts, is immaterial. The inclusion of such elements-recklessness, for example-expresses
the judgment that absent a jury's judgment of unreasonableness, punishment is unjustified. The risk
of gratuitous punishment is, as with predictions of dangerousness, at least as high in this situation as
it is when guilt hinges on historical facts. Of course, defining guilt solely in terms of the jury's moral
sense is a different matter entirely. See Giaccio v. Pennsylvania, 382 U.S. 399 (1966) (statutes that
allow a jury to impose penalties on the basis of the jury's moral sense of the defendant's conduct are
unconstitutional).
180. 389 U.S. 347 (1967).
181. See Monaghan, supra note 113, at 22-23.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1707
Sandstrom holding."' 8
Due regard for the role of history thus does not compel a distinction
between elements and defenses. The Court has, in parallel contexts,
found a contemporary need for new procedures to safeguard undisputed
constitutional rights, and it has followed this practice with respect to
elements in the context of the Winship rule itself.
Finally, even if history is taken both as countenancing burden-shift-
ing and as determining the constitutional inquiry, the current distinction
between elements and defenses remains arbitrary. Classification as an
element is, according to the Patterson and Martin majorities, terminable
at will by the legislature. Justice Powell's Patterson dissent offers the
only reasonable basis for historically distinguishing between elements
and defenses. That basis is history itself, not latter-day legislative classifi-
cations that conflict rather than conform with the Anglo-American legal
tradition.
192. A glance at the compilation in Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1398-1407, proves the
point.
193. See Patterson, app. at A-7 to A-8 (No. 75-1861) (psychiatrist's testimony) (microfiche).
194. See J. KAPLAN & R. WEISBERG, CRIMINAL LAW: CASES AND MATERIALS 263 (1986).
195. Patterson, app. at A-84 & A-92 (trial court charge).
196. See Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1398-1407.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1711
197. For example, a subjective view of provocation and self-defense might be adopted in
exchange for abolition of the insanity defense.
198. See Easterbrook, supra note 72, at 112 ("There will be terms of trade between process and
procedure for almost any statute.").
199. It is easy to point out new grounds of exculpation that in fact have been linked to a shift in
the burden of proof, but this does not demonstrate a causal connection. If the compromise
hypothesis were correct, we would expect conservative states to retain the older rules in the absence
of a compromise. However, this does not appear to be the case. For example, several very
1712 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
conservative jurisdictions adopted the Model Penal Code definition of voluntary manslaughter
without shifting the burden of proof. See ARK.. STAT. ANN. §§ 41-110, -1504 (1981); Ky. REV.
STAT. ANN. §§ 500.070, 507.020 (Michie/Bobbs-Merrill 1985); MONT. CODE ANN. §§ 46-16-602,
45-5-103 (1983); N.D. CENT. CODE §§ 12.1-01-03, -16-01 (1985). Perhaps New York is indeed less
susceptible to progress than Arkansas, but I suspect proponents of the compromise approach would
be slow to come to that conclusion.
200. If gnly to confirm the cynicism of the compromise argument, it is worth pointing out that
the wave of recodification is now largely spent. Reviving Wilbu?s recourse to historical practice
therefore offers the Justices a fine opportunity to rook the state legislatures out of their conservative
procedures, given that legislative inertia is likely to maintain the liberal substance of "progressive"
compromises.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1713
205. In spite of Paul v. Davis, 424 U.S. 693 (1976) (reputational harm alone does not implicate
liberty or property interests), authority can still be found that emphasizes the importance of stigma
as an independent deprivation of constitutionally protected liberty. See Saltzburg, supra note 3, at
405.
206. Legality protects the substantive value of avoiding gratuitous or oppressive punishment,
and formal legality alone may not protect that fundamental value. See supra text accompanying
notes 98-110. Cf Tribe, The Puzzling Persistence of Process-Based ConstitutionalTheories, 89 YALE
L.J. 1063 (1980) (discussing the procedural norms mandated by substantive values underlying
specific constitutional provisions).
207. See supra notes 82-94 and accompanying text.
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1715
208. See Saltzburg, supra note 3, at 400; Underwood, supra note 3, at 1329-30.
209. See, eg., Allen, supra note 203, at 1150-58; Allen, Burdens of Persuasion,supra note 3, at
45 n.60; Jeffries & Stephan, supra note 3, at 1351 & n.76.
210. U.S. CONsT. amend. VI; see United States v. Cronic, 466 U.S. 648, 654-55 (1984) (sixth
amendment requires not merely the formal provision of counsel but actual "assistance" of counsel).
211. Faretta v. California, 422 U.S. 806 (1975).
212. Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 691-96 (1984).
1716 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:1665
213. United Bhd. of Carpenters v. United States, 330 U.S. 395, 408 (1947); Sparf & Hansen v.
United States, 156 U.S. 51, 105-06 (1895).
214. U.S. CONST. amends. V & VI.
215. See H. KALVEN & H. ZEMEL, THE AMERICAN JURY 190 (1966) ("Trial by jury is not an
instrument of getting at the truth; it is a process designed to make it as sure as possible that no
innocent man is convicted.") (quoting Lord Devlin, Jan. 1960).
216. See United States v. Cronic, 466 U.S. 648, 656 n.19 (1984).
217. Nesson, supra note 3, at 1582-84; Nesson, Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences:
The Value of Complexity, 92 HARV. L. REv. 1187, 1201-02 (1979).
218. Saltzburg, supra note 3, at 400 n.45 ("mhe degree of accuracy required is intimately
connected to the question of who bears the burden of proof .... ).
219. I am surprised that Professor Allen would prefer to extend the greater-includes-the-lesser
1987] REASONABLE DOUBT RULE 1717
CONCLUSION
Winship, as it turns out, was on the right track. The purpose of the
reasonable doubt rule is to enforce the legality principle. The Supreme
Court, following a simplistic analysis of how legislatures might react to a
principled application of the reasonable doubt rule, has lost sight of the
principles underlying Winship. As a result, the Court has taken the para-
approach to counsel and jury trial rather than to abandon its application to the burden of proof. See
Allen, Burdens of Persuasion,supra note 3, at 45 n.60.
The positivists might respond by noting that the right to counsel extends to sentencing
proceedings, see, ag., Mempa v. Rhay, 389 U.S. 128 (1967), which I have distinguished as not
implicating the legality principle. Accordingly, the argument might go, the right to counsel must
serve some function independent of the legality principle.
This rejoinder, however, fails to extricate positivists from the reductionist tendency of their
position. Presumably they would deny the right to counsel at sentencing precisely because a valid
conviction extinguishes the constitutional liberty interest. See Greenholtz v. Nebraska Penal
Inmates, 442 U.S. 1, 7 (1979); Meachum v. Fano, 427 U.S. 215, 224 (1976). As at trial, the provision
of counsel at sentencing serves the interests of the client, not any general commitment to rationality.
Unless the positivists can articulate a justification for the right to counsel that applies generally at
trial, and on the same constitutional basis at sentencing, the objection based on sentencing does no
more than identify another line of precedents with which the positivist approach is inconsistent.
Rationality in sentencing cannot explain the role of counsel at sentencing hearings because the sixth
amendment does not extend to administrative proceedings that may have a more significant effect on
the sentence served by the convict. See Gagnon v. Scarpelli, 411 U.S. 778, 787-90 (1973) (states are
not constitutionally required to provide counsel for indigents in all probation or parole revocation
hearings).
As for my linking the right to counsel with the legality principle, it is entirely plausible that the
sixth amendment embodies a generalized solicitude for criminal defendants, at trial as well as at
sentencing. At trial, however, this solicitude extends no further than protecting the legality
principle, for the accused surely has no right to the assistance of counsel in urging jury nullification
or in presenting perjured testimony. See Nix v. Whiteside, 475 U.S. 157, 173 (1986) ("right to
counsel includes no right to have a lawyer who will cooperate with planned perjury"). But whatever
purpose counsel at sentencing may serve, the government could circumvent that function simply by
illegally imprisoning the convict for some reason other than violating the statute under which he is
sentenced.
220. See Johnson v. United States, 805 F.2d 1284, 1288 (7th Cir. 1986) (Posner, J.) ("To punish
a person criminally for an act that is not a crime would seem the quintessence of denying due process
of law.").
1718 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW