Writing Sample 2
Writing Sample 2
Writing Sample 2
By
Hongding Zhu
July 2022
Preceptor: Yan Xu
Self-fulfilling Stigmatization: An Evolutionary Game
Abstract
To illustrate how the stigmatization of social movements arises from its micro-
ticipants of a social movement and outsiders in the general public. Based on the
are hostile toward the general public, and haters in the general public reproduce
each other. Suppose there are enough such hostile members so that it exceeds the
conflicts with haters outside the movement. The stigmatization of a social move-
ment can be a self-fulfilling prophecy. When there are initially enough haters, even
if a social movement is peaceful at the beginning, the speed at which the movement
becomes hostile under outgroup pressure will outpace the rate at which it can win
censorship.
MA Thesis 1
1 Introduction
More and more social movements—from Black Lives Matter to MeToo, from the climate
movement to Occupy Wall Street—are being initiated and are happening online (Hara
and Huang, 2011). The ease of setting up groups, the global reach of networked com-
munities, and the convenient facilitation of organizational activities all contribute to the
widespread use of social media sites for social movements (Wall, 2007). Moreover, un-
der the tremendous political risk of offline activism, social movements in autocracy rely
on online discourse even more than their counterparts in democracy (Feng, 2017; Tan,
2017). In cyberspace, people can quickly obtain information about a social movement and
interact with its participants, forming their opinions about the movement accordingly.
advocated value are distorted, and the participants are tagged with negative character-
istics. We see significant conflicts between participants of a social movement and the
general public. Previous studies Harel et al. (2020); Bar-Tal (2007) notice that ideolog-
ical divergence and emotional confrontation are the micro-foundations of social conflicts
in cyberspace. Conflicts exist in both intergroup and intragroup interactions, and out-
group pressure leads to further polarization inside a specific social group. Meanwhile,
social media amplify the emotional factors that drive the conflicts. I follow this micro-
social movements in a dynamic process, discussing how the macro outcome of stigma-
I first go through the informal literature related to the conflicts in social movements,
online interaction, and arguing that conflicts can manifest themselves through the device
on their application to the question of interest. Then, using evolutionary game theory,
I build a model to capture the dynamics of opinion evolution and conflict between two
populations—the participants of a social movement and the general public. In the model,
participants are either hostile or moderate towards the general public, while the outsiders
of the movement are either haters or sympathizers. Conflicts happen inside the movement
between hostile and moderate participants of a social movement; outside the movement,
only moderate participants and sympathizers maintain peace. The assumption that a
peaceful person loses more utility in conflicts than an emotionally hostile person drives
The model has several theoretical implications. First, hostile participants of a social
movement and haters in the general public conflict with but also reproduce each other.
Second, there exists a stigmatization threshold so that if there are enough hostile mem-
bers of a social movement and haters in the general public, the evolutionary outcome is
the stigmatization equilibrium in which all players choose the hostile/hater strategy. The
larger the initial proportion of haters in the general public, the less hostile a social move-
is not hostile at the beginning and is winning more sympathizers outside the movement,
but enough level of initial stigmatization (haters in the general public) is creating more
hostile participants of a social movement. If the latter effect is stronger than the former
effect, then hostility toward the social movement still crosses the stigmatization thresh-
old. In the situation above, severe stigmatization at the beginning produces a social
MA Thesis 3
movement that is antagonistic to the general public in the end. In others words, when
the general public expect the movement to be extreme at the beginning, the movement
2 Literature review
Some social movements suffer severe stigmatization among the public (?Kim, 2018; Bav-
oleo and Chaure, 2020; Yang, 2014; Ka, 2021). Take the feminist movement worldwide as
an example. South Korea’s backlash against radical feminism became a solid voting base
for conservative parties in the 2022 presidential election(Kim and Lee, 2022). In China,
feminist expression online easily suffer from trolling, (Mao, 2020) and the antagonism
between men and women has become a salient phenomenon in Chinese cyberspace 1 . In
India, feminism is widely perceived as a western ideological invasion and hated among
male anti-feminist Nicholas and Agius (2018); Rothermel (2020). Conflicts are inevitable
between the thriving, progressive force and reactionary social structure (Pachter, 1974).
The reactionary structure and its apparatuses stigmatize their challengers and have many
happens when some people hold false beliefs that a social movement and its participants
cuss who stigmatizes and why they stigmatize. The privileged group usually has limited
empathy for the oppressed (DiAngelo, 2018). It thus holds negative perceptions of social
movements that try to address social injustice and stigmatize them as“seeking privilege”
and “creating oppression ”(Dignam and Rohlinger, 2019; Van Valkenburgh, 2021).
1
see https://www.bbc.com/zhongwen/simp/chinese-news-55571627
4 Hongding Zhu
However, social movements also find their allies in the general public. Whether the
privileged can be recognized as participants of a social movement has always been de-
bated. For example, they De Beauvoir (2010) argued that men could not be called fem-
inists because they lacked life experience as women. Putting aside the naming problem,
apart from those who already identify themselves as participants of the movement, some
sympathizers are generally pro-movement or open to its ideas. For instance, the sup-
and support, if not “participation”, were made possible by the unity legacy of shared
Besides stigmatization and conflict outside the social movements, there are also in-
Harel et al. (2020) Shows that unaligned ideology in reciprocal interactions is an im-
portant foundation for conflicts to happen. Ideological divergence translates into hostile
emotion and behavior, and intragroup ideological pressure further leads to opinion po-
larization and friction inside the socio-political group. Work Bar-Tal (2007) argues that
in intractable social conflicts, people justify their own group and stigmatize other groups
movements mainly, conflict happens between the moderate and radical factions. The
Baader-Meinhof (Aust, 2009) complex was one of the most extreme parts of the radical
left in West Germany, and it finally broke up with the more moderate left-wing, resort-
ing to terrorism to achieve its cause. The Scum ManifestoSolanas and Avital (2004)
broadcasts the voice of radical feminism, and this legacy is appreciated and criticized by
The discussion above indicates that first, there are several different strategies in the
MA Thesis 5
sympathizers in the general public, and enemies in the general public; second, ideological
Then, what kind of ideologies divergence mainly cause conflict and stigmatization? Koo
(2020) understands conflicts and stigmatization in the South Korean radical feminist
not involve clear political agenda. Feminists in such forums like Megalia and Womad
were trolled because they were not aggressive to biological men enough or did not agree
with the tactic of “mirroring misogyny”. Kim (2018) argues that the trolling and gender
(2021) also documents that rather than political blueprints, stigmatization and conflicts
are driven by hostile sentiments. She also notices that even though there is a high diversity
of ideologies in a social movement, people use reduced tags to label themselves as “radical”
and “moderate” feminists, which is an emotional division of how hostile you are towards
men and patriarchy rather than their political agendas. For instance, participants of
the 6B4T feminist movement in China and South Korea usually identify themselves as
radical feminists due to their strong criticism of patriarchy. However, they only adopt
individualistic resistance such as “no marriage” to resist without radical demand for social
reform de facto. Hence, the conflicts in social movements may not necessarily be between
radical and moderate groups but between people with hostile emotions and less hostile
emotions towards the status quo. Similarly, people in the anti-movement forces also have
a higher emotional hostility towards the movement, while self-identified sympathizers are
less hostile.
I consider this emotion-driven approach valuable to help explain conflicts and stigma-
6 Hongding Zhu
tization of social movements in the social media era. I then discuss how emotion and
In the era of social media, some mechanisms make online communities more prone to in-
terpersonal emotional hostility and conflict. First, social media reduces the coordination
cost of social movements Van Laer and Van Aelst (2010); Kelly Garrett (2006), facilitating
the spread of opinion and creating more chances for online interaction related to a par-
ticular social movement. For example, Crossley (2015) argues that social media not only
helps the mobilization of feminism but also amplifies the voice of feminist influencers and
helps information diffusion. However, social media also has the same effect on the anti-
movement force, intensifying the conflict between the two forces. Second, information
segregation and the logic of community feedback help social media amplify the impact
common feature on the internet (McPherson et al., 2001). This opinion polarization is
more likely to happen when the topic is political (Barberá et al., 2015), and it naturally
translates into sentiment polarization (Harel et al., 2020)—more extreme emotional sta-
tus of people overall. Empirical evidence shows that negative emotion (Del Vicario et al.,
2016) is infectious, and someone who receives negative feedback tends to send more of
such feedback to others in the futureCheng et al. (2014). Therefore negative emotion
among the population reinforces itself on social media platforms. Finally, the anonymous
online environment reduces the cost of trolling and other violence and amplifies the voices
This branch of literature conveys that social media amplify ideological and emotional
MA Thesis 7
aspects and platform interaction logic, emphasizing the interaction between people and
the dynamic nature of opinions and emotions. Next, I will show models related to the
dynamic evolution of opinions and discuss where my model can build on.
Linking macro and micro level of analysis is an important task for social scientist(Coleman,
1994; Sawyer and Sawyer, 2005; Raub et al., 2011). It is usual to set up a formal model to
discuss how macro outcomes emerge from micro-interactions. Literature on the stigmati-
zation of social movements and social media suggest that the micro foundation of stigma-
people’s opinion and attitudes. Accordingly, we need a model that can explain stigmati-
zation by showing the process of opinion evolution, linking the macro outcome with the
micro mechanism.
Previous models that involve opinion evolution incorporate one single population only
and consider “persuasion” in multiple forms are the mechanism. In other words, people
change their minds because of social feedback (Banisch and Olbrich, 2019; Bertotti and
Delitala, 2008; Chen et al., 2020; Di Mare and Latora, 2007; Yuan et al., 2021). Some
benchmark models try to find the condition of convergence or explain the formation
Furthermore, no model considers the effect of censorship, which is a crucial and om-
8 Hongding Zhu
opinion evolution can enrich the knowledge of the effect of censorship. Currently, stu-
persuasion (Gehlbach et al., 2021) and its role in preventing collective action (King et al.,
2013) and discouraging opposition but also bringing about self-censoring, which reduces
the information capacity of an autocrat. Nevertheless, no study has yet examined the
outsiders in the general public, rather than a single population. This captures the reality
that intergroup and intragroup interaction both exists (Harel et al., 2020), and allows me
to examine the effect of outgroup pressure (emotional hostility) on the opinion evolution
of the social movement. Second, my model provides another possible approach to opinion
evolution that results from netizens’ population replacement and culture inheritance in
in the existing literature. This setting is a weaker assumption that allows people to be
stubborn—opinions as strategies are assigned and unchangeable once the players enter the
game, rather than assuming that they easily change their minds due to others’ opinions.
Third, I incorporate the effect of censorship and Echo Chamber into my model as two
the participants of social movements and the general public. The macro outcome of
MA Thesis 9
and this requires a model that is able to link both macro and micro levels. In the social
media era, such ideological conflicts happen on digital platforms, and emotional hostility
affects the stigmatization of social movements and online conflicts more in the social
media era, which requires the academia to incorporate the emotion-driven approach in
Several models of opinion dynamics relate to my research question in that they discuss
how people’s opinion change and how macro pattern is produced through this dynamic.
However, they are not enough to settle my question. First, they only contain one single
population, neglecting the reality that conflicts exist in both intergroup and intragroup.
Second, they also do not involve censorship, which widely exists in authoritarian regimes
and has a significant impact on the stigmatization of social movements. Third, previ-
ous models only consider the persuasion effect of feedback as the driving force of the
theory model to capture the opinion dynamics of social movements online. My model
contains two populations —the participants and outsiders in the general public, consider-
ing evolutionary fitness and population replacement as a new approach to frame opinion
dynamics and discuss the effect of censorship and Echo Chamber as model extensions.
3 Method
This paper is the first one to leverage evolutionary game theory as a tool to analyze the
strategic (Osborne et al., 2004; McCarty and Meirowitz, 2007). However, the strong
assumption of rationality is not always the case. Apolitical random events impact voters’
behavior, such as the occurrence of shark attacks influencing election outcome (Achen
and Bartels, 2012); ignorance is an important explanatory variable of why voters support
trade protectionism (Rho and Tomz, 2017). These examples suggest that in discussing
decentralized group behavior, it is more realistic to set up weaker assumptions about the
strategic, so their strategies (genes) are assigned once they enter the game, and it never
changes. Therefore, in a basic evolutionary game theory setup, a player’s strategy is the
same as her type. The proportions of different strategies in a certain population change
(payoffs) as a function of the overall strategy profile (the proportions of all strategies of
all populations), and the probability that a certain strategy leave ”offspring” is positively
correlated with their fitness. Hence, the fittest survive in the evolutionary game, and
to apply evolutionary game theories? Weibull (1997) and Friedman (1998) both introduce
the evolutionary game to social science and argue that evolutionary game theory is of
great value for analyzing large-scale decentralized behavior of players (individuals, firms,
MA Thesis 11
and so on). Different from biology, the inheritance of strategies in social science is through
norms, culture, and social networks. For the research question of this paper—how the
evidence shows that the behavior and opinion of new users of a specific social media plat-
form are strongly decided by the pattern of current existing users (Cheng et al., 2014),
which satisfies the “inheritance” approach of evolutionary games. Furthermore, the evo-
lutionary game model assumes random matching between players, which is common in
social media subgroups where everyone has access to interact with other members. It
is easy to incorporate the effect of homophily to make the matching rule more realistic.
cific online community. Readers should restrict the interpretation of my model to small
to medium-size online communities where netizens intensively interact with each other.
The next section is a detailed introduction of the baseline model setup, including the
4 Model
There are two sub-populations in the game: participants of a social movement A and
and among the general public exists two strategies, haters B1 and sympathizers B0 . Table
participants and all individuals outside the movement evil and only maintain peace with
their kind. Examples of this strategy could be gender essentialist feminism discussed
in Koo (2020). Readers should notice that this is an ideal type. Meanwhile, moderate
participants (A0 ) can maintain peace with their own kind and moderate outsiders but
will conflict with any hostile individual. Among the general public, the sympathizers
B0 can interact peacefully with moderate participants of the social movement but not
the hostile participants; the haters B1 hate the movement and conflict with both types
of participants. The alternative rightists make ideal examples of the “hater” strategy
in online interactions (Van Valkenburgh, 2021; Dignam and Rohlinger, 2019). The level
The initial proportions of all strategies are decided by factors not included in the
model, such as culture, propaganda, or historical memory. The strategies of players when
T = 0 refers to their initial expectation of how other players’ strategies are, because it is
The participants interact with both participants and outsiders, while outsiders only
play with participants. This setup is justified that a participant may spend much time
getting information from and chatting with both their peers in the movement (for alliance
or opinion exchange) and outsiders (for propaganda and voicing for the movement). In
contrast, a typical outsider in the general public spends limited time deciding whether to
MA Thesis 13
hate or sympathize with the movement based on their interaction with the participants.
Outsiders do not spend much time discussing the movement with their peers (there are
so many social movements, but so much work and so little time!), which means the game
The baseline model adopts random matching between players. The chance that a
player meets a certain kind of strategy depends on the global proportion of that strat-
egy. The definition of “interaction” in this study is general—it can be direct and dyadic
tion flows.
The fitness form (Table 2) of an evolutionary game is similar to the strategic form
decided by several assumptions. First, people lose psychological utility from conflicts
online. Second, in conflicts, people with moderate attitudes (A0 and B0 ) lose more
utility than hostile people (A1 and B1 ), which is the critical assumption of this model.
This assumption is inspired from the theory of emotional contagion Del Vicario et al.
emotion so that it should be a dominant strategy when facing another player with hostile
strategy. The second assumption means that m < e ∈ (0, 1) and γ ∈ (0, 1). Let aα,β
14 Hongding Zhu
denotes the fitness when strategy α meets β. The fitness of a strategy is:
X X
(1) uAi = Aj aAi ,Aj + Bj aAi ,Bj
X
(2) uBi = Aj aBi ,Aj
After clarifying the fitness form, we can calculate the replicator dynamics—the growth
rate of a particular strategy in terms of the proportion in its own sub-population with
respect to continuous time parameter t. The decision of signs of the replicator dynamics
are simple: the proportions of those strategies with higher-than-average fitness in their
own sub-population grow. The following equations specify the growth rate of a strategy:
1. Nature chooses the initial xt0 =(A1t0 , B1t0 ) by a generic distribution F , so that the
2. All players in the whole population interaction with each other in time t according
3. The fitness of the strategies is realized by aggregating the fitness of players that
adopt it.
5 Analysis
By looking at the fitness form, we infer that this game is similar to a coordination game
where players across populations want to match their types. In other words, if new
entering players in time t anticipate other players more likely to be moderate (A0 or
B0 ), they are more likely to inherit the moderate/sympathizer strategy, otherwise they
are more likely to inherit the hostile/hater strategy. There exists three Nash equilibria
in a basic coordination game, but the unique interior solution is not an ESS because it
does not have a uniform barrier of invasion (Weibull, 1997) so that any external shock at
the interior Nash equilibrium will lead to convergence to the other two ESSs. Therefore,
Proposition 1 (Evolutionary Stable States) There exists two evolutionary stable state.
First, the peace equilibrium xP∗ = {A1 = 0, B1 = 0} in which all players are moder-
xS∗ = {A1 = 1, B1 = 1} in which all players are hostile participants or haters of the
movement.
The proof of which is trivial. Proposition 1 shows that in any ESS, both participants
and outsiders match their type. The first ESS in which all players adopt the moderate
or sympathizer strategies is the peace equilibrium and there is no conflict and stigma-
tization, while the second ESS in which all players adopt hostile or hater strategies is
the stigmatization equilibrium, and there are conflicts and stigmatization between the
movement and the general public. The result is not intuitive since it is common that
16 Hongding Zhu
opinion divergence exists in the movement and the general public empirically. However,
readers should notice that, first, the interaction environment in the model is where all
players can interact with each other, hence the equilibrium result is restricted to certain
online communities, forums, or platforms, rather than the internet as a whole; second,
the equilibrium can be interpreted as the tendency and direction of evolution according
with respect to time t, therefore what we observed in real life can be still in-progress of
the evolution.
Now I analysis the dynamics of evolution. Before the global mixed strategy x con-
verge to any ESS, the proportion of strategies change according to the signs of replicator
dynamics. Because there are only two strategies in a certain sub-population, if the pro-
portion of one strategy grows, the other one must decline. Therefore, the conditions for
m
(7) C1 : A1 =
e + m − eγ
(ep + mp)A1 m
(8) C2 : B1 = − +
(1 − p)(e + m − eγ) (1 − p)(e + m − eγ)
MA Thesis 17
and the four domains are shown in Figure 1. In figure 1, point (A∗1 , B1∗ ) is the interior
Nash equilibrium of the game, C1 satisfies uB0 = uB1 and C2 satisfies uA0 = uA1 . Denote
and the game converges to the stigmatization equilibrium xS∗ , else if xt is in Area 2, A1
and B1 both decline, and the game converges to the peace equilibrium xP∗ . This result is
intuitive and reflect the situations in reality that when both participants and outsiders of
a social movement is hostile (moderate) enough, the relationship between the movement
and the general public is high-conflict (peaceful). The property of replicator dynamics in
Area 1 and 2 is formalized as Lemma 1, which is important for analysis of Area 3 and 4.
m (ep+mp)A1t m
satisfies that A1t > e+m−eγ
and B1t > − (1−p)(e+m−eγ) + (1−p)(e+m−eγ) , the evolutionary out-
come converges to xS∗ when t → +∞; if xt = {A1t , B1t } satisfies that A1t < m
e+m−eγ
and
(ep+mp)A1t
B1t < − (1−p)(e+m−eγ) + m
(1−p)(e+m−eγ)
, the evolutionary outcome converges to xP∗ when
t → +∞.
It is more interesting to discuss dynamics in Area 3 and 4, In these two areas, the A1
and B1 evolve in the opposite direction. In Area 3, there are too many haters B1 in the
general public so that the proportion of hostile participants grows as retaliation, while at
the same time, because there are enough moderate participants to interact peacefully with
the general public, the proportion of sympathizers of the movement also grows. Situation
in Area 4 mirrors the dynamics in Area 3 so that the social movement is becoming
moderate while the proportion of its haters in the general public grows. Clearly, the
xP∗ or the stigmatization equilibrium xS∗ —depends on the relative speed at which two
if the speed at which the movement becomes more hostile overwhelms the trend of the
general public to be more friendly to the movement, xt will reach Area 1 at some t, and
To complete the discussion of dynamics in Area 3 and 4, I now formally derive the
absorption domains of the two ESSs, which is equivalent to derive the solution of the
initial value problem for an ordinary differential equation system f (t, x).
∂A1
∂t
∂B
1
(9) f (t, xt0 ) = ∂t
A1 (0) = A1t0
B1 (0) = B1t0
MA Thesis 19
Particularly, the initial value problem f (t, (A∗1 , B1∗ )) solves a unique curve C ∗ that an-
nounces the absorption domains of the two ESSs. Therefore, C ∗ is the Stigmatization
Threshold.
through the interior Nash equilibrium (A∗1 , B1∗ ). Any xt0 below C ∗ leads to xP∗ and any
The proof of Proposition 2 is in the appendix. The baseline model generates three the-
oretical implications. First, the dynamic of large enough hostility and stigmatization
between the movement and the general public is a process of reinforcing each other. Sec-
ond, the dynamics in Area 3 shows that stigmatization of a social movement can be a
self-fulfilling prophecy when the proportion of haters are large enough. Haters in the gen-
eral public stigmatize and attack all participants of the movement, which in turns creates
more hostile participants in the movement and if this “hostility as retaliation” effect is
strong enough, everyone becomes hostile to each other in the end. Third, the shape of
the stigmatization threshold C ∗ indicates that if one side of the game, participants or
outsiders, is more hostile/hating, it lowers the threshold of sufficient hostility of the other
6 Extensions
and Willer, 2017; Barberá et al., 2015; McPherson et al., 2001; Fiore and Donath, 2005;
Sánchez et al., 2016). People tend to interact with other people of similar ideas, creating
20 Hongding Zhu
an Echo Chamber that exacerbate the homogeneity of opinions locally. Echo Chamber
effect is strongly correlated to opinion polarization. Intuitively, the Echo Chamber effect
seems relate itself with more stigmatization and conflict online. But is it the case in this
model?
The baseline model predict two ESSs, which present convergence instead of polariza-
tion within a single population, however, the two equilibrium are different in terms of
pants and outsiders are inclusive to each other without conflict, thus meaning convergence
between the two sub-populations; in the stigmatization equilibrium, though both popu-
lation are internally convergent, they attack each other in intragroup interaction, thus is
equivalent to polarization. In this equilibrium, players have the right beliefs about other
players in the end, but the self-fulfilling nature of the bad equilibrium indicates that there
hi that the strategy Ai meet itself in time t, and probability 1 − hi that Ai is randomly
matching with all other strategies just like in the baseline model. The fitness of B is
X X
(10) uhAi = hi + (1 − hi )( Aj aAi ,Aj + Bj aAi ,Bj )
∂Ai
the sign of ∂t
is decided by uhAi − uhA− i = (1 − h)(uAi − uA− i ), which means that
when both strategies have the same level of homophily, the Echo Chamber effect only
changes the velocity of replicator dynamics, making the elimination of one strategy slower,
MA Thesis 21
but does not change the evolutionary result. Only when h1 > h0 , which means hostile
participants A1 are more like “birds of a feather” than moderate participants A0 , will the
old Ch∗ that goes through the interior Nash equilibrium {A∗1h , B1h
∗
}. Ch∗ is below C ∗ if and
only if h1 > h0 . Echo Chamber enlarges the strategy space that induces xS∗ if and only if
The proof of Proposition 3 is in the appendix. When the Echo Chamber effect among
the hostile participants is stronger than it among the moderate participants, the strategy
space that induces the peace equilibrium is smaller than in the baseline model because the
stigmatization threshold Ch∗ in the Echo Chamber model is strictly below the threshold
in the baseline model (see figure 2). Hence, surprisingly, in our model, homophily does
not necessarily help stigmatization, but different level of homophily between different
strategies does. The intuition is that while Echo Chamber among the hostile participants
secures more psychological payoff for new entering users to be hostile, it has the same
effect of encouraging users to be moderate. When people talk about Echo Chamber and
polarization, they assume if people have more exposure to diverse information, there
information. However, in this model, I show that the interaction with outside information
does not necessarily make a person similar to them, but instead, when the interaction
is not satisfactory, it strengthens the existing biases. The counter-intuitive result arises
because if moderate people have more “protection” from emotionally hostile content, they
are more like to stick to their strategy. This is the case when social media is not founded
and people with extreme stances are hard to find their allies. Therefore, Echo Chamber
22 Hongding Zhu
effect on social media helps more for extreme opinions rather than moderate opinions
because such Echo Chamber does not widely existed before social media era.
6.2 Censorship
selectively delete information or even prevent the generation of information. Yet in the
spirit of Adena et al. (2015), censorship could also be a form of repression that warning
someone that her opinion is not appreciated. I incorporate both effects of censorship by
setting up a probability b that interaction with a certain kind of strategy is blocked (in-
formation manipulation) and a dead weight cost c on the fitness of strategies (repression).
Similar to the previous extension, we know that if the effect of censorship on the fitness
is symmetric for both A1 and A0 , then the replicator dynamics is unchanged. Therefore,
for parsimony and clarity, I only add the treatment on the ”more censored” strategy.
In autocracy, censorship mainly targets posts with collective action potential (King
MA Thesis 23
et al., 2013) and alternatives of the official ideology (Shue, 1990) which is generated
more by the moderate participants of a social movement, rather than hatred speech,
trolling, or other forms of offense and language violence generated by hostile participants.
Take the Douban forum, the headquarter of Chinese feminist movement, as an example,
censorship targets at Douban groups that systematically criticize patriarchy and voice
clear political agenda, rather than the groups that express hatred towards biological men
or troll their enemies2 , which makes moderate participants instead of hostile participants
more vulnerable to censorship because they are emotionally moderate but politically
X X
(11) ucA0 = Aj aA0 ,Aj + Bj aA0 ,Bj − c
X
(13) ubAi = A1 aAi ,A1 + (1 − b)A0 aAi ,A0 + Bj aA0 ,Bj
Both setups reduce the fitness of moderate participants. In time t, the fitness of ucA0 in the
2
see working paper by Hongding Zhu and Jose E. Trinidad, available on
https://docs.google.com/document/d/1stlpfjHY8wUfXEM0Q anE9LcMmB6AEQJRIzd4qYphbY/edit?usp=sharing
24 Hongding Zhu
repression extension is smaller than in the baseline model and accordingly the replicator
and more participants of the social movements choose to be hostile than in the baseline
model, which in turn results in more stigmatization (more haters) of the movement.
Proposition 4 (The Effect of Censorship) For any b, c > 0, there is a unique stigma-
tization threshold Cc∗ that goes through the interior Nash equilibrium {A∗1c , B1c
∗
}. Cc∗ is
The proof of Proposition 4 is trivial because it uses exactly the same logic and steps as
Proposition 3. When participants of a social movement suffer extra cost for articulating
their ideas and agenda in peaceful language, they gradually turn to trolling and emotional
hostility. This story is the case in the Chinese cyberfeminist movement. Feng (2017);
Shen (2021) shows that censorship creates a narrower space for feminists in China to
7 Conclusion
I set up a two-population evolutionary game to model the opinion evolution and dy-
participants of the movement and between the participants and the general public.
haters in the general public tend to reproduce each other. If the initial proportion of
hostile participants of the movement exceeds the stigmatization threshold, the evolution-
MA Thesis 25
ary outcome is the stigmatization equilibrium, where all participants are hostile to the
public, and all outsiders are haters of the movement. The stigmatization threshold is
pinned down by the proportion of haters in the general public so that the higher the
initial stigmatization, the lower the threshold to induce the stigmatization equilibrium.
I also discuss the typical situation in which stigmatization of a social movement is a self-
fulfilling prophecy. In this situation, the movement itself is moderate at the beginning;
however, severe enough social stigmatization (haters in the general public) will drive the
movement to become more and more hostile, and finally, the conflict between the public
The effect of the Echo Chamber and censorship on the stigmatization of social move-
ments are discussed in the extensions. The analysis shows that Echo Chamber only helps
collective action potential and alternative ideologies other than the official one instead
of trolling and language violence, which means that moderate participants, instead of
These results contribute to the theoretical discussion from several aspects. First, it
which complements the static analysis in the literature. The mechanism of stigmatization
as a self-fulfilling prophecy helps explain how an initially moderate and peaceful social
movement can descend into bitter conflict with its opponents in society. Second, in addi-
tion to complex ideological and structural factors, stigmatization of social movements can
26 Hongding Zhu
also arise from micro-emotional conflicts in online interactions, which is a crucial feature
in the social media era and is supported by empirical observations (Koo, 2020; Ka, 2021).
Third, different from previous studies (Harel et al., 2020) that claim outgroup pressure
intensifies opinion polarization inside a social group, my model suggests that in a micro
online community, stigmatization from the public induces only intragroup polarization
but externally hostile strategies. Hence, we should reconsider the does the previous claim
hold only at a macro level. And finally, the logic of evolutionary games suggests that in
studying the opinion dynamics, population replacement and ideological inheritance from
Readers should also be aware of the limitations of this study. First, the assumption
of random matching in the model restricts its analytical level to a micro online commu-
nity where the discourse of a social movement circulates rather than the global dynamics
on the internet. Second, the four strategies in the game are ideal types, and this ty-
pology captures only limited aspects of individual opinions in social movements. Third,
the theoretical implications of the model require further empirical evidence to prove its
credibility.
MA Thesis 27
References
Christopher H Achen and Larry M Bartels. Blind retrospection: Why shark attacks
are bad for democracy. Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions, Vanderbilt
University. Working Paper, 2012. 10
Maja Adena, Ruben Enikolopov, Maria Petrova, Veronica Santarosa, and Ekaterina Zhu-
ravskaya. Radio and the rise of the nazis in prewar germany. The Quarterly Journal
of Economics, 130(4):1885–1939, 2015. 22
Stefan Aust. Baader-Meinhof: The inside story of the RAF. Oxford University Press,
USA, 2009. 4
Sven Banisch and Eckehard Olbrich. Opinion polarization by learning from social feed-
back. The Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 43(2):76–103, 2019. Publisher: Taylor
& Francis. 7
Pablo Barberá, John T Jost, Jonathan Nagler, Joshua A Tucker, and Richard Bonneau.
Tweeting from left to right: Is online political communication more than an echo
chamber? Psychological science, 26(10):1531–1542, 2015. Publisher: Sage Publications
Sage CA: Los Angeles, CA. 6, 19
Bárbara Inés Bavoleo and Desireé Chaure. Korean cyberfeminism: emergence, charac-
teristics and results. Anuario en Relaciones Internacionales del IRI, 2020, 2020. 3
Maria Letizia Bertotti and Marcello Delitala. On a discrete generalized kinetic approach
for modelling persuader’s influence in opinion formation processes. Mathematical and
computer modelling, 48(7-8):1107–1121, 2008. Publisher: Elsevier. 7
Alexander Bor and Michael Bang Petersen. The psychology of online political hostility:
A comprehensive, cross-national test of the mismatch hypothesis. American political
science review, 116(1):1–18, 2022. 6
Andrei Boutyline and Robb Willer. The social structure of political echo chambers:
28 Hongding Zhu
Tinggui Chen, Qianqian Li, Peihua Fu, Jianjun Yang, Chonghuan Xu, Guodong Cong,
and Gongfa Li. Public opinion polarization by individual revenue from the social
preference theory. International journal of environmental research and public health,
17(3):946, 2020. Publisher: Multidisciplinary Digital Publishing Institute. 7
Alison Dahl Crossley. Facebook feminism: Social media, blogs, and new technologies of
contemporary us feminism. Mobilization: An International Quarterly, 20(2):253–268,
2015. 6
Michela Del Vicario, Gianna Vivaldo, Alessandro Bessi, Fabiana Zollo, Antonio Scala,
Guido Caldarelli, and Walter Quattrociocchi. Echo chambers: Emotional contagion
and group polarization on facebook. Scientific reports, 6(1):1–12, 2016. 6, 13
Alessandro Di Mare and Vito Latora. Opinion formation models based on game theory.
International Journal of Modern Physics C, 18(09):1377–1395, 2007. Publisher: World
Scientific. 7
Robin DiAngelo. White fragility: Why it’s so hard for white people to talk about racism.
Beacon Press, 2018. 3
Pierce Alexander Dignam and Deana A Rohlinger. Misogynistic men online: How the
red pill helped elect trump. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 44(3):
589–612, 2019. 3, 12
Feng. Hard times for feminists in China. SupChina, 2017. URL https://supchina.
com/2017/03/08/hard-times-feminists-china/. 1, 24
MA Thesis 29
Andrew T Fiore and Judith S Donath. Homophily in online dating: when do you like
someone like yourself? In CHI’05 extended abstracts on Human factors in computing
systems, pages 1371–1374, 2005. 19
Scott Gehlbach, Zhaotian Luo, Anton Shirikov, and Dmitriy Vorobyev. A Model of
Censorship, Propaganda, and Repression. 2021. 8
Tal Orian Harel, Ifat Maoz, and Eran Halperin. A conflict within a conflict: intragroup
ideological polarization and intergroup intractable conflict. Current Opinion in Behav-
ioral Sciences, 34:52–57, 2020. 1, 4, 6, 8, 26
bell hooks. Feminist theory: From margin to center. Pluto Press, 2000. 4
Fei Ka. douban nvquan, jiafeng zhong xingcheng de ”zhongguo tese nvquan”.
Initium Media, March 2021. URL https://theinitium.com/article/
20210308-opinion-china-douban-feminism-awakens-or-failure/?utm_source=
twitter&utm_medium=twitter&utm_campaign=twpost. 3, 5, 26
Bo-Myung Kim. Late modern misogyny and feminist politics: The case of ilbe, megalia,
and womad. Journal of Korean Women’s Studies, 34(1):1–31, 2018. 3, 5
Hannah June Kim and Chungjae Lee. The 2022 south korean presidential election and
the gender divide among the youth. Pacific Affairs, 95(2):285–308, 2022. 3
Gary King, Jennifer Pan, and Margaret E Roberts. How censorship in china allows gov-
ernment criticism but silences collective expression. American political science Review,
107(2):326–343, 2013. 8, 22
30 Hongding Zhu
JiHae Koo. South korean cyberfeminism and trolling: The limitation of online feminist
community womad as counterpublic. Feminist Media Studies, 20(6):831–846, 2020. 5,
12, 26
Chengting Mao. Feminist activism via social media in china. Asian Journal of Women’s
Studies, 26(2):245–258, 2020. 3
Nolan McCarty and Adam Meirowitz. Political game theory: an introduction. Cambridge
University Press, 2007. 10
Miller McPherson, Lynn Smith-Lovin, and James M Cook. Birds of a feather: Homophily
in social networks. Annual review of sociology, 27(1):415–444, 2001. Publisher: Annual
Reviews 4139 El Camino Way, PO Box 10139, Palo Alto, CA 94303-0139, USA. 6, 19
Lucy Nicholas and Christine Agius. # notallmen,# menenism, manospheres and unsafe
spaces: Overt and subtle masculinism in anti-“pc” discourse. In The persistence of
global masculinism, pages 31–59. Springer, 2018. 3
Werner Raub, Vincent Buskens, and Marcel ALM Van Assen. Micro-macro links and
microfoundations in sociology. The Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 35(1-3):1–25,
2011. Publisher: Taylor & Francis. 7
Sungmin Rho and Michael Tomz. Why don’t trade preferences reflect economic self-
interest? International Organization, 71(S1):S85–S108, 2017. 10
R Keith Sawyer and Robert Keith Sawyer Sawyer. Social emergence: Societies as complex
systems. Cambridge University Press, 2005. 7
MA Thesis 31
Vivienne Shue. The reach of the state: sketches of the Chinese body politic. Stanford
University Press, 1990. 23
Cass R Sunstein. The law of group polarization. University of Chicago Law School, John
M. Olin Law & Economics Working Paper, (91), 1999. 6
Jia Tan. Digital masquerading: Feminist media activism in China. Crime, Media, Culture,
13(2):171–186, 2017. 1
Jeroen Van Laer and Peter Van Aelst. Internet and social movement action repertoires:
Opportunities and limitations. Information, Communication & Society, 13(8):1146–
1171, 2010. 6
Shawn P Van Valkenburgh. Digesting the red pill: Masculinity and neoliberalism in the
manosphere. Men and Masculinities, 24(1):84–103, 2021. 3, 12
Melissa A Wall. Social movements and email: expressions of online identity in the glob-
alization protests. New media & society, 9(2):258–277, 2007. 1
Yuke Yang. Jijin de nvquan biaoqian: Nvquan zhuyi ruhe zai meijie pingtai bei wum-
inghua. Journalism and Communication, 2014:94, 2014. 3
Jiangjun Yuan, Jiawen Shi, Jie Wang, and Weinan Liu. Modelling network public opinion
polarization based on SIR model considering dynamic network structure. Alexandria
Engineering Journal, 2021. Publisher: Elsevier. 7
32 Hongding Zhu
Appendix
Proof of Proposition 2
Because the first-order ODEs f (t, x) are polynomials about x, they satisfy the Lipschitz
condition and have one unique solution {A1 (t), B1 (t)} according to Picard-Lindelöf The-
orem. Which means any initial value problem has a unique evolutionary track—a unique
curve that goes through it. Therefore, there exists a unique curve C ∗ in Figure 1 that
goes through the interior Nash equilibrium (A∗1 , B1∗ ) and any xt0 not on C ∗ never cross
C ∗ during the replicator dynamics. Hence, any xt0 below C ∗ must arrive at Area 2 at
some t and any xt0 above C ∗ must arrive at Area 1 at some t. And according to Lemma
Proof of Proposition 3
Denote the two curves which is the solution of uhB0 = uhB1 and uhA0 = uhA1 as C1h and
C2h , it solves:
m
(15) C1h : A1 =
e + m − eγ
(16)
(1 − h)m p[e + (1 − h)m]A1
C2h : B1 = −
(1 − p)[e + (1 − h)m − (1 − h)eγ] (1 − p)[e + (1 − h)m − (1 − h)eγ]
in which C1h remains the same as C1 while C2h is strictly below C2 when h1 > h0 .
line model. Accordingly, there is a unique stigmatization threshold Ch∗ that goes through
(A∗1 , B1∗ ). Suppose C ∗ h crosses C ∗ at some point, then at the intersection point (Ã1 , B̃1 ),
MA Thesis 33
the replicator dynamics (growth rate) of B1 is the same in the baseline and the Echo
Chamber model, while the replicator dynamics of A1 must be smaller than in the base-
line model in the two situation in Figure 3. However, in the setup we know that on
any point (A1 , B1 ), the replicator dynamic of A1 is larger than in the baseline model
since uhA1 > uA1 on any point (A1 , B1 ). There are contradictions. So the intersection
situations in Figure 3 does not exist, and accordingly Ch∗ is always below C ∗ . ■