Tushnet & Bugaric, What Is Constitutionalism
Tushnet & Bugaric, What Is Constitutionalism
Tushnet & Bugaric, What Is Constitutionalism
What Is Constitutionalism?
What is constitutionalism? The only sensible follow-up is this: why do you want
to know? Scores of books have been written offering scores of descriptions of con-
stitutionalism: descriptions of the real world of constitutions and prescriptions
for the authors’ “best” account of constitutionalism as a system of values. Each
author has in mind some purpose for which she is providing the description. As
should be clear already, our purpose is to provide some leverage on the analysis
of contemporary populism.
That purpose sets some important guidelines for our answer to the question
posed in the chapter’s title. Because we are interested in contemporary populism,
we are interested in contemporary constitutionalism. We aren’t going to spend
time on describing “Athenian” constitutionalism, or “medieval” constitution-
alism, although for other purposes examining those and many other forms of
constitutionalism would be quite valuable.
More important, we aren’t going to discuss constitutionalism as what
philosophers call a “regulative ideal”—a reasonably comprehensive set of values
that we could use as a benchmark against which we could measure actual con-
stitutional performance. Consider a relatively simple question: Are laws against
hate speech consistent with constitutionalism as a regulative ideal? On some ac-
counts, clearly no—such laws violate ideals of freedom of expression. On other
accounts, clearly yes—such laws are required to ensure that everyone can partici-
pate in civic life on an equal basis. Proponents of each view will of course provide
elaborate arguments rooted in stories about individual autonomy, democratic
self-governance, and the like to justify their particular view of constitutionalism
as a regulative ideal. Precisely because each view is reasonable—as are many
others—we think it unhelpful to rely on “regulative ideal” versions of constitu-
tionalism in our inquiry into the relation between contemporary constitution-
alism and contemporary populism.
Of course, we do need some benchmark—some rough idea of what we mean
by “constitutionalism”—if we are to make any progress toward our goal. The
“regulative ideal” approach to the question relies upon what we call a “thick” ac-
count of constitutionalism. Thick accounts build a fair amount of detail into the
story. A thick account might for example provide answers to questions about the
Power to the People. Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugarič, Oxford University Press. © Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaricˇ
2021. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197606711.003.0002
10 The Framework
1 We think it worth noting that the linkage between constitutionalism and some version of lib-
eralism, and in particular with democracy, developed in the early modern period, well after the
concepts of constitutionalism and democracy came on the scene. In a sense, then, our “thin” consti-
tutionalism can be treated as a branch of a tree of which thicker versions are other branches.
2 For a similarly thin definition of constitutionalism, see Wojciech Sadurski, Constitutional
Democracy in the Time of Elected Authoritarians, 18 International Journal of Constitutional
Law 324 (2020), at p. 328 (listing “free, fair, and regular elections,” “civil and political rights, in par-
ticular those which are instrumental to unconstrained political communication necessary for a dem-
ocratic electoral choice,” “separation or dispersion of powers,” and “the rule of law . . . [including]
constitutional rules which [the government] cannot change at will whenever political expediency so
demands”). Sadurski’s exposition of these principles, though brief, suggests that he would give them
somewhat more content that we would. See also Jeremy Waldron, Political Political Theory
(2016), ch. 2 (“Constitutionalism: A Skeptical View”); Tom Ginsburg & Aziz Z. Huq, How to Save
a Constitutional Democracy (2018), at p.10: “Our definition aims to be as minimalist as possible
without simply equating democracy with elections alone.”
3 Paul Blokker, Populist Understandings of the Law: A Conservative Backlash?, 13 Participazione
é Conflitto 1433 (2020), offers a sociolegal account of what he calls “embedded constitutional de-
mocracy,” in which the idea of constitutional democracy takes different forms depending upon the
socio-historical context. Perhaps our “thin constitutionalism” can be understood as our attempt to
dis-embed the idea of constitutionalism as much as possible, to take account of all the variations that
What Is Constitutionalism? 11
4 Specifications can be understood as the way in which reasonable disagreements about constitu-
tional meaning manifest themselves. For a discussion of such reasonable disagreements, see Jeremy
Waldron, Law and Disagreement (1999).
12 The Framework
one—which implies that having laws against hate speech and prohibiting them
as unconstitutional are both consistent with constitutionalism on a thin
understanding.
These elements seem simple enough, but when we examine each in detail, real
complexities emerge. And the elements interact in complicated ways.5
5 A cautionary note: we always have to keep in mind that we are discussing thin constitution-
alism. Real-world constitutions narrow the range of policies subject to choice by popular majori-
ties by entrenching some policies and having an extensive list of entrenched rights and structures.
For example, the current constitution of Brazil entrenches a balanced-budget requirement, that of
Germany commits the nation to social welfare policies, some nations give constitutional status to
their central banks, and others create ombuds offices with protections akin to those given judges.
Some or all of these might be good ideas, but none, we think, are required by a thin understanding of
contemporary constitutionalism.
What Is Constitutionalism? 13
6 In British constitutional theory A.V. Dicey made this the centerpiece of his definition of par-
liamentary supremacy. Recent controversies over the existence of “constitutional” statutes in the
United Kingdom have revived interest in this definition. We discuss some of these controversies in
Chapter 6, on Brexit.
7 Thin constitutionalism is thus not intrinsically unstable—does not put all policy choices up for
grabs at every moment—because voters (and political leaders) decide which policies to reconsider.
8 This is the first place where we see how the elements of thin constitutionalism interact.
9 Again, specific national constitutions might include more people in the group whose preferences
count—in some places, for example, young people, in others long-term resident noncitizens.
Excluding such groups is consistent with thin constitutionalism, though.
14 The Framework
fall into patterns. The most widespread one is probably that the well-educated
and well-to-do vote at higher rates than the less well-educated and the less well-
to-do. Thin constitutionalism—in contrast to constitutionalism as a regulative
Free and fair elections. For elections to be reasonably free, candidates and
•
parties have to be able to present a full range of policy options to the public:
of course, that the current government should be replaced, but also that
taxes should go up or down, that public services should be expanded or
privatized, and so on through the list of all matters on which policy can be
made. Reasonably free and fair elections, that is, require freedom of political
expression.
We don’t want to offer a full theory of free expression here.10 Any such ac-
count, though, has to begin with the observation that freedom of expression
always competes with other important values—social stability, personal
privacy, civic equality, and much more. Thin constitutionalism requires
only that the balance struck between political expression and those com-
peting values be reasonable. And that, we think, is going to vary with so-
cial and political circumstances. Some restrictions on political expression in
highly polarized nations with a history of civic violence might be reasonable
even when the same restrictions elsewhere would be unreasonable. New
10 For the views of one of us, see Mark Tushnet, Advanced Introduction to Freedom of
Expression (2018).
16 The Framework
information technologies might alter the balance among the concerns for
autonomy, public understanding, and other considerations underlying the
general account of free expression.
13 From different traditions, the work of Lon Fuller in jurisprudence and Joseph Schumpeter and
Robert Dahl in political science converge on this conclusion. See Lon Fuller, The Morality of
Law (1964); Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (1942); Robert
Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy (1982).
14 Venezuela since around 2015 might be thought a counterexample, but as we argue in our case
study of Venezuela, though Hugo Chávez, who died in 2013, was a populist leader, his successor
Nicolas Máduro is a straightforward authoritarian.
15 We note here, and discuss in more detail in Chapter 4’s case study of Hungary, that the substance
of constitutional amendments adopted even in regular form can be inconsistent with thin consti-
tutionalism when they undermine the ability of current policy to reflect current majority views by
making it exceedingly difficult to displace a government whose policies no longer reflect those pre-
ferred by the majority. This is a different problem from the one discussed in the text, that populist
enthusiasm for amending constitutions is itself an indication of an anti-constitutional mindset.
18 The Framework
whether they would regard the choice as a reasonable one. The second is an insti-
tutional perspective: should courts assessing the choice find it outside the range
of reasonable options a democratic majority should have available? We take that
B. Entrenchment
16 The example isn’t quite what we need, because the proposal can be characterized as an amend-
ment aimed at correcting the Supreme Court’s misinterpretation of the First Amendment and
restoring the amendment’s proper interpretation. To clean up the example, imagine that the consti-
tution entrenches a specific set of rules about campaign finance, which a current majority comes to
believe, reasonably, no longer fits the nation’s conditions.
What Is Constitutionalism? 19
17 For the term “speed bumps,” see Tom Ginsburg, Aziz Z. Huq, & Mila Versteeg, The Coming
Demise of Liberal Constitutionalism, 85 University of Chicago Law Review 239 (2018), at p. 253
(“At best, constitutional design features serve as speed bumps to slow the agglomeration and abuse of
political power; they cannot save us from our worst selves completely.”).
18 We’ve used examples of written constitutions with entrenched provisions and written amend-
ment rules. Entrenchment occurs even where the constitution is unwritten and sometimes in the
interstices of written constitutions. Entrenchment where the constitution is unwritten comes in the
form of settled practices and strong norms protecting them against change. These norms mean that
a politician who wants to change the entrenched rules ordinarily has to build up a great deal of sup-
port for change, more than she needs to secure changes in ordinary policy. Or, where the politician
manages to implement a change in norms without supermajority support, the changed norm won’t
“stick” when the politician leaves the scene.
20 The Framework
Some men look at constitutions with sanctimonious reverence, and deem them
like the ark of the covenant, too sacred to be touched. They ascribe to the men
of the preceding age a wisdom more than human, and suppose what they did to
be beyond amendment. I knew that age well; I belonged to it, and labored with
it. It deserved well of its country. It was very like the present, but without the ex-
perience of the present; and forty years of experience in government is worth a
century of book-reading; and this they would say themselves, were they to rise
from the dead.20
19 At the U.S. constitutional convention George Mason said that an amendment procedure was
needed because the new constitution “will certainly be defective.” Similar observations were made
during the French constitutional convention a few years later.
20 Thomas Jefferson to Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1816, available at https://founders.archives.gov/
?q=Ancestor%3ATSJN-03-10-02-0128&s=1511311111&r=2, archived at https://perma.cc/97S5-NXM3.
What Is Constitutionalism? 21
21 Some but not all of these difficulties can be handled by creative constitutional interpretation—
finding that some substantial move toward centralization actually is consistent with federalism prop-
erly understood, or finding that some public recognition of a religion is consistent with secularism
properly understood.
22 Sometimes the terminology is “substitution” rather than “replacement,” but the underlying idea
is the same.
23 See Rosalind Dixon & David Landau, Tiered Constitutional Design, 86 George Washington
Law Review 438 (2018).
24 They have sometimes pressed the definition of “amendment” and “replacement,” with critics
contending that what populists have described as an “amendment” is actually a “replacement” that
didn’t go through the more stringent processes for replacements. We provide a few examples in our
case studies, but our general view is that here too a standard of reasonableness applies: Is it reasonable
to treat a change as a (mere) amendment rather than as a replacement?
25 A possible counterexample is provided by the 1999 constitutional revision in Venezuela, which
expressly departed from the requirements in the constitution-in-place for replacing the constitution.
The case is complicated by the fact that the (non-populist dominated) high court held that departing
from the constitution’s requirements was lawful. For a more complete discussion, see Chapter 3.
22 The Framework
amendment rules.26 We think that they can be done away with through what has
to be understood as a revolutionary transformation of the constitutional order,
one that expressly breaks the bounds of the existing constitution.27 Relative to
By now readers may be impatient at our failure to say anything about what they
might think at constitutionalism’s heart: constitutionalism, on one common
view, is about limiting government power, to protect the natural liberties people
have and want. The well-regarded Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy’s first
sentence on constitutionalism is this: “Constitutionalism is the idea, . . . that gov-
ernment can and should be legally limited in its powers.”29
We don’t include an expansive idea of limited power in our conception of thin
constitutionalism. Of course, whatever happens to be entrenched operates as a
temporary limitation on government power. And equally of course “rule of law”
requirements that are within our conception of thin constitutionalism are them-
selves limitations on government power. Thin constitutionalism places some
limits on pure majoritarianism, but “limiting government power” isn’t the ulti-
mate goal of constitutionalism, as some formulations occasionally suggest. The
reason: we limit government power to protect liberty. Sometimes, though, exer-
cising power protects liberty. The most obvious cases involve the use of national
power to control abuses of power by petty local tyrants who corruptly abuse their
public positions to put people under their thumb. These cases are easy even if we
define “liberty” as something that can be threatened only by public power. That’s
26 The question is not entirely theoretical. The U.S. Constitution provides that each state, no matter
what its population, shall have equal representation in the upper house (currently, two senators per
state), and that no amendment can change the principle of equal representation. Many in the United
States, though almost certainly not a supermajority, believe that that “eternity” provision is a bad one.
And courts are sometimes protected by an eternity clause or, more often, by a judicially created “basic
structure” doctrine.
27 For clarity’s sake we note that a prominent recent work, Bruce Ackerman, Revolutionary
Constitutionalism (2020), employs a notion of revolutionary constitutionalism that is, we think,
quite a bit different from the one so thinly outlined here. Exploring our disagreements would blur our
focus on our primary effort to discuss populism and constitutionalism.
28 The scholarly literature on this point divides between those who argue that revolutionary trans-
formations are not constrained by law in any sense, and those who contend that such transformations
are bound by some (rather thin) specifications of fundamental human rights. We take no position on
this dispute.
29 Wil Waluchow, “Constitutionalism,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring
2018 ed., Edward N. Zalta ed.), available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/con-
stitutionalism/.
What Is Constitutionalism? 23
one conceivable definition, but not the only one—and so not a definition that
should be built into the idea of constitutionalism.
Suppose we care about human liberty because it’s a good thing for people to
30 Here are two relevant quotations from classic liberal writers: Montesquieu—liberty means that
“the government must be such that one citizen cannot fear another citizen”; Locke—“The Injury and
the Crime is equal whether committed by the wearer of a Crown, or some petty Villain.” Both are
quoted in Steven Kautz, “On Liberal Constitutionalism,” in The Supreme Court and the Idea of
Constitutionalism (Steven Kautz et al. eds. 2011), at p. 32.
31 Martin Loughlin, The Foundations of Public Law (2010), provides a good account of the
long history of republican and “political” constitutionalism, ideas that don’t rest on principles of neg-
ative liberty.
24 The Framework
32 More precisely, by preserving the status quo a larger set of veto gates and speed bumps leaves a
wider range of policies to be determined by the choices made by private parties regulated by private
rather than public law.
What Is Constitutionalism? 25
33 Jan-Werner Müller shows how after 1945 “a highly constrained form of democracy” emerged
as a response to the totalitarian excesses of the 1930s and 1940s. Key parts of this “post-war con-
stitutional settlement” were powerful constitutional courts. Jan-Werner Müller, Contesting
Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth Century Europe (2011), at pp. 128–40.
34 In designing his proposed constitutional court, Hans Kelsen didn’t include a provision for re-
view of claims that legislation violated individual rights. The post-war paradigm of constitutional law
does require such review, and we think it reasonable to conclude that contemporary constitution-
alism does so as well. But, as we argue in the text, that requirement can be satisfied in ways compatible
with populism’s commitment to majority rule.
35 Samuel Issacharoff, Fragile Democracies: Contested Power in the Era of
Constitutional Courts (2015). See also Carles Boix, Constitutions and Democratic
Breakdowns (2005);
26 The Framework
Almost always these ideas will be expressed in general terms. The U.S.
Constitution says that “Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom
of speech”; the German Basic Law says, “Every person shall have the right freely
41 See Shingori Matsui, Why Is the Japanese Supreme Court So Conservative?, 88 Washington
University Law Review 1375 (2011), at pp. 1388–89; Yoon Jin Shin, “Proportionality in South
Korea: Contextualizing the Cosmopolitan Rights Grammar,” in Proportionality in Asia (Po Jen
Yap ed. 2020), at pp. 90–91.
What Is Constitutionalism? 29
our thin constitutionalism supports criticisms that reach beyond parochial views
of what constitutionalism requires.
That’s the general argument—a system consisting of reasonable specifications
Free expression: libeling public officials. Public officials have to expect that
•
someone sometime will criticize them quite severely for what they’ve done
either in their public roles or in their private lives. That criticism can harm
their reputations. When the criticism is unfair—for example, when it rests
on a factually false premise—a legal system might reasonably give the public
official a remedy for the harm to reputation. That’s what the law of libel does.
We’ll assume, we think accurately, that contemporary constitutionalism
bars nations from adopting the classical common law rules of libel law: strict
liability for publishing reputation-damaging falsehoods, a presumption
that false statements do harm reputation, the burden of proving truthful-
ness on the publisher. Even with those elements ruled out, many possibil-
ities remain. The United States gives false statements about public officials
a high degree of protection: the official loses unless she can show that the
falsehoods were published by someone who either knew that they were false
or acted with “reckless disregard” of their truth or falsity. Elsewhere public
officials can win if they show that the publisher failed to comply with pro-
fessional standards for verifying factual statements before publishing them.
In yet other nations the officials can win if they prove that the statements
were false and provide evidence that the statements did indeed harm their
reputations.
Now consider a government that proposes to change the libel rules cur-
rently operating—say, from the stringent U.S. rule to the somewhat less
speech protective “journalistic standards” one. Is this intrinsically a “retro-
gression”—an erosion of constitutionalism?
Here are two arguments why it isn’t. First, the government might provide
reasons for the change, pointing for example to changes in the media envi-
ronment that have generated a much larger number of scurrilous and false
allegations about public officials that had been the case when the highly
speech-protective rule was adopted (with the effect, perhaps, of making it
more difficult to attract people to public service). If that’s a reasonable argu-
ment, we think it difficult to describe the change as a retrogression; it’s just
a change. Second, and more straightforward, if the “journalistic standards”
rule had been in place from the beginning, we wouldn’t worry that the
30 The Framework
42 The problem gets more complicated if the court’s size is constitutionally entrenched. All is well if
the government’s majority is large enough to secure a constitutional amendment. If it isn’t, the ques-
tion we discussed earlier—what to when the amendment rule in place is too stringent—arises.
What Is Constitutionalism? 31
Maybe that sort of veneration is a good thing (though we doubt it), but we’re
reasonably confident that constitutionalism doesn’t require it.
43 Politicians and political parties can propose referendums and other mechanisms for deter-
mining majority preferences outside of elections, and can take positions on referendums and the like.
Our exposition is eased by focusing solely on elections, but our general points apply to politicians’
role in every preference-determining mechanism.
32 The Framework
The constitutionalism we’ve been discussing so far, thin or thick, is all about
institutions—elections, courts, and more. For some time now, though, it’s been
clear that there’s more to constitutionalism than institutions. Constitutionalism,
again whether thin or thick, can be sustained only if there’s something like a
pro-constitutional culture behind it, a commitment by most of a nation’s people
to the idea of constitutionalism itself. And, we’ve come to understand, a pro-
constitutional culture is sustained by norms and guardrails, to use terms popu-
larized by political scientists Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt.45
Norms and guardrails are political practices that guide the behavior of
politicians and ordinary citizens. For Levitsky and Ziblatt, the most important
thing is that you treat the people you disagree with about politics as wrong but
44 Of course, if the opposition doesn’t offer an attractive alternative, as our case study of Venezuela
suggests, elections aren’t going to help.
45 Steven Levitsky & Daniel Ziblatt, How Democracies Die (2018).
What Is Constitutionalism? 33
not your enemies. They have misguided views about what’s good for the country,
but they’re working with you in the common political endeavor of making the
country better. That’s the most general one, but it gets worked out in more partic-
46 A word about two items on the list: some classical political theorists supported what’s known
as the “doux commerce” theory, according to which the ordinary face-to-face interactions between
traders induced mutual tolerance of disagreements (after all, traders had to bargain with each
other). Agrarian theorists argued to the same effect about how the daily activity of farming and sel-
ling what one raised created communities of mutual tolerance. And not all political parties have
pro-constitutional effects. For an argument that elite-dominated conservative parties have some-
times facilitated the displacement of democracy by autocracy, see Daniel Ziblatt, Conservative
Parties and the Birth of Democracy in Europe (2017).
34 The Framework
discussion in Chapter 8 of judicial reform proposals in the United States gives the
arguments concrete content, and Chapter 10 examines the arguments in detail.
Here we preview the arguments we make there.
the contributions we can make with the distinctive tools that lawyers can deploy
and use.