Geneology
Geneology
Geneology
The aim of this essay1 is to elucidate the logical structure of genealogy as a prac-
tice of critical reflection and, in doing so, to illustrate, dispel and account for the
confusion concerning this practice which has characterised its reception, perhaps
especially among philosophers working within the tradition of the Frankfurt
School. The essay advances five claims which can be stated in summary as
follows:
1. Setting aside the cases of contingent error and of ignorance, we can note that
there are (at least) two logically distinct forms of self-imposed, non-physical
constraint on our capacity for self-government: being held captive by an ideol-
ogy (i.e., false consciousness) and being held captive by a picture or perspec-
tive (i.e., what one might call ‘restricted consciousness’).
2. Critical Theory as ideologiekritik2 is directed to freeing us from captivity to an
ideology; genealogy is directed to freeing us from captivity to a picture or
perspective.3
3. Philosophers working within the tradition of Critical Theory have typically
misinterpreting genealogy as a (empirically insightful but normatively
confused) form of ideologiekritik.
4. This category mistake is the product of an illicit generalisation of ideological
captivity as the only form of self-imposed, non-physical constraint on our
capacity for self-government.
5. Once this ‘craving for generality’ is dispelled, we are able to grasp both geneal-
ogy and Critical Theory as addressing distinct aspects of enlightenment and
involving distinct kinds of dialogue.4
The argument of this essay is presented in five parts, each corresponding to one
of the theses summarised above.
European Journal of Philosophy 10:2 ISSN 0966–8373 pp. 216–230 © Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2002. 108 Cowley Road, Oxford
OX4 1JF, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
On Genealogy and Critical Theory 217
Social institutions are not natural phenomena; they don’t just exist of and
by themselves. The agents in a society impose coercive institutions on
themselves by participating in them, accepting them without protest, etc.
Simply by acting in an apparently ‘free’ way according to the dictates of
their world-picture, the agents reproduce relations of coercion. (Geuss
1981: 60)
A ‘limit’ can mean either the characteristic forms of thought and action
which are taken for granted and not questioned or contested by partic-
ipants in a practice of subjectivity, thereby functioning as the implicit
Thus, to repeat, what matters in this context is (a) our capacity to free ourselves
from our captivation to the ways of thinking in question – to recognize and
loosen the grip that the picture or perspective expressed by these ways of
thinking has on us – in order (b) to evaluate the value of this picture or
perspective relative to other possible pictures or perspectives. Hence, as
Foucault remarks, the point of his philosophical work consists in ‘the endeav-
our to know how and to what extent it might be possible to think differently’
(Foucault 1986: 7).
At this stage, it should not be difficult to see that the ‘unfree existence’ to
which those held captive by a picture or perspective are subject is a form of self-
imposed constraint on their capacity for self-government. It is a constraint on
their capacity for self-government because it prevents those subject to it from
exercising their powers of judgment concerning the value of such and such a
picture or perspective by presenting this picture or perspective as the only way
of reflecting of the topic in question. This constraint is self-imposed because it
is held in place by our practices – and, more generally, the relations of power
and domination that govern our ways of reflecting and acting in the world.7 To
adapt Geuss’ remark concerning false consciousness, we might say that simply
by acting in an apparently ‘free’ way according to the dictates of their world-
picture (where ‘picture’ refers here to a system of judgments), the agents repro-
duce their condition of subjection and that the power of the subjection to which
agents are subject derives solely from the fact that they do not realize that it is
self-imposed. Now we might be tempted to say that in a certain respect this
kind of self-imposed captivity does, like ideological captivity, involve a false
belief but that it does not involve a false first order belief, rather it involves a
false second order belief (i.e., a false belief about one’s beliefs). This way of
reflecting on aspectival captivity would lead us the following claim: aspectival
captivity involves the agents holding the false belief that the range of possible
beliefs (whether true or false) open to them are the only possible range of beliefs
open to them. But to accept this conceptualization of aspectival captivity would
be misleading and mistaken for the following reason: an agent held captive by
a picture cannot have such a second order belief about the range of first order
beliefs available to him or her; there is, as it were, no logical space for such a
belief to arise for the agent. The point can be put this way: it is a necessary
condition of the agent having such a false second order belief that the agent
recognizes the possibility of such a second order belief being true-or-false but to
be held captive by a picture or perspective is just to fail to recognise this possi-
bility as a possibility.8 This is why it is appropriate to refer to this condition as
one of ‘restricted consciousness’.
II
This section will establish the claim that just as ideologiekritik is directed to freeing
us from ideological captivity or false consciousness, so genealogy is directed to
freeing us from aspectival captivity or restricted consciousness. As in the preced-
ing section, I will briefly summarise the relevant points concerning ideologiekritik
in order to focus primarily on the more interesting – since more controversial –
case of genealogy.
In so far as ideological captivity is characterised by agents both holding false
beliefs which legitimize oppressive social institutions and being blocked in some
way from recognizing the falsity of the beliefs that they hold, the aim of the prac-
tice of ideologiekritik – as its very name proclaims – is to enable them to recognize
this fact. As Wittgenstein put it:
One must start out with error and convert it into truth. That is, one must
reveal the source of error, otherwise hearing the truth won’t do any good.
The truth cannot force its way in when something else is occupying its
place.
To convince someone of the truth, it is not enough to state it, but rather
one must find the path from error to truth. (Wittgenstein 1993: 119)
From this it follows immediately that the beliefs in question are reflec-
tively unacceptable to the agents and that the repressive social institution
these beliefs legitimize is not legitimate. (Geuss 1981: 68)
Hence, as Jim Tully notes, Foucault’s genealogical exercises consist ‘of historical
studies undertaken to bring to light the two kinds of limit: to show that what is
taken for granted in the form of the subject in question has a history and has been
otherwise; and to show ‘in what has been given to us as universal, necessary and
obligatory, what place is occupied by whatever is singular, contingent and the
product of arbitrary constraints’. These studies enable us ‘to free ourselves from
ourselves’, from this form of subjectivity, by coming to see that ‘that-which-is has
not always been’, that it could be otherwise, by showing how in Western cultures
people have recognised themselves differently, and so to “alter one’s way of look-
ing at things” ’ (Tully 1999: 94).
However, what motivates genealogy is not simply the condition of being held
captive by a picture or perspective but that this captivity prevents us from
making sense of ourselves as subjects or agents in the ways that matter to us. In
other words, whereas ideologiekritk seeks to disclose a contradiction between our
beliefs and our epistemic principles, genealogy aims to elucidate a disjuncture
between the ways in which we are intelligible to ourselves with respect to some
dimension of our subjectivity or agency, on the one hand, and our cares and
commitments, on the other.10 This disjuncture is not a matter concerning our
beliefs but of the relationship between a picture or perspective and our capacity
to experience ourselves as subjects or agents in the ways that matter to us. Two
examples may clarify this point.
Nietzsche’s concern is this: we are held captive by a picture of morality – which
he refers to as the ascetic ideal – that renders us increasingly unable us to make
sense of ourselves as moral agents. This concern has two dimensions. The first,
given dramatic expression in section 125 of The Gay Science, is that we fail to
recognise that, following the death of God, the conditions of intelligibility of
many of our moral concepts no longer apply and, hence, continue to use our
moral words as if they expressed the concepts which, prior to the death of God,
they expressed.11 The second is that as we come to acknowledge the meaning of
the death of God, i.e., that our moral words no longer express these moral
concepts, we will recoil into a condition of nihilism – God is dead and hence
everything is permitted. This latter point becomes clear if we take, as Nietzsche
does, Kant’s moral theory as an expression of this picture and recall Kant’s
famous argument in the ‘Critique of Teleological Judgement’ that morality
requires certain matters of faith and that without the res fidei there is only
nihilism, where nihilism can be glossed as the condition of being unable to make
sense of ourselves as moral agents. Nietzsche agrees that this picture of morality
does generate the requirement for such matters of faith – but the point of his
efforts to enable us to free ourselves from this picture of morality is to free us
from the entailment of Kant’s view that, once we acknowledge the death of God,
nihilism is all that remains. Hence, Nietzsche’s task is to free us from captivity to
this picture; a task that he takes up by providing a genealogical account of how
we have become subject to it.
There are three stages in this genealogical process of self-reflection. First, by
providing an account in which two types of morality stand in relation to one
another, Nietzsche unsettles the view that what he refers to as ‘slave morality’ is
the only type of morality. Second, by giving an account of the emergence and
development of the ascetic ideal, Nietzsche shows us both how our moral
concepts are interwoven with a particular form of life and how we have become
captivated by this picture of morality as well as how this captivation leaves us
open to the threat of nihilism. Third, in devaluing this picture of morality by
showing that it entails our becoming obscure to ourselves qua moral agency,
Nietzsche’s account motivates us in terms of our own commitment to making
sense of ourselves as moral agents to engage in the practical task of revaluing our
moral values.12 In other words, Nietzsche’s genealogical account attempts to
articulate a way in which we can make sense of ourselves – and, in particular,
make sense of our current failure to make sense of ourselves – as moral agents
which guides us to engage in the revaluation of our moral values.
The second example is provided by Foucault’s work in Discipline and Punish
and The History of Sexuality: Vol. 1. Here, Foucault’s concern is based on the
thought that we are held captive by a picture of politics fundamentally shaped by
discourses and practices of sovereignty – and which leads us to assume that
sovereignty is the pre-eminent locus of political reflection. As he puts it:
isn’t how it is!’ and ‘Yet this is how it must be!’, the kind of self-reflection that
genealogy aims to produce has the following form:
(a) it identifies a picture which holds us captive, whereby this captivity obstructs
our capacity to make sense of ourselves as agents in ways that matter to us,
(b) this account involves a redescription of this picture which contrasts it with
another way of seeing the issue in order to free us from captivity to this
picture,
(c) it provides an account of how we have become held captive by this picture
which enables us to make sense of ourselves as agents and, more particularly,
to make sense of how we have failed to make sense of ourselves as agents in
ways that matter to us,
(d) and in so far as this account engages with our cares and commitments, it
motivates us to engage in the practical working out of this re-orientation of
ourselves as agents.
It is in this way that genealogy performs its inherent aim to be the self-conscious-
ness of a process of enlightenment and emancipation. As Foucault puts it, geneal-
ogy ‘will separate out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the
possibility of no longer being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think . . .
seeking to give new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work
of freedom’ (1997: 315–6).
III
It is hard to overlook the contrast between the account of genealogy provided in the
preceding section and the readings of genealogy which have been characteristic of
writers working within the traditions of the Frankfurt School. For such authors,
genealogy is predominantly seen as failed or botched form of critique. This is a
picture of genealogy presently most famously, and most bluntly, by Jurgen
Habermas (1987) and endorsed in its central claims by numerous others, even
where, as with Nancy Fraser (1989), they write with more sympathy and subtlety.
What is most noteable about these criticisms of genealogy, however, is that they
share a common assumption concerning the demands of critique or responsible
criticism. There are two ways of elucidating this unquestioned presumption. The
first way is to frame genealogy in terms of critique. It goes like this:
Thus we can see that the unquestioned presumption is that genealogy needs to
articulate normative criteria and can’t do so. Consequently, there are two ways of
responding to this line of argument. The first is to argue that genealogy can
generate normative criteria in the appropriate way. This seems unpromising and
I won’t pursue it here. The second kind of response is to say that responsible crit-
icism does not require the articulation of any such normative criteria. This is the
more radical response and it strikes me as the right one. Let me explain why.
The first point to note is that to say that genealogy does not provide normative
criteria is not to say that it isn’t motivated by specific normative interests.
Foucault is explicit about genealogy being motivated by an interest in freedom or,
more accurately, self-government which is one reason why he makes the follow-
ing remark:
Consequently, it is clear that on the first framing of the issue, Foucault can and
should simply deny that genealogy is a form of critique and on the second fram-
ing he can and should deny that responsible criticism requires the articulation of
normative criteria. Both of these equivalent responses provide a cogent riposte to
his Frankfurt School critics by undermining the unquestioned presumption
which frames their critical attacks.
IV
If the argument thus far is cogent, we confront a puzzle: why has the reception of
Foucault’s practice of genealogy within the tradition of Critical Theory taken the
form that it has? One could with reasonable plausibility suggest that Foucault
was not always very clear about what he was doing himself, but this is does not
seem adequate as an explanation of the phenomenon which we are concerned. A
more plausible explanation, I’d suggest, is that precisely insofar as these writers
are working from within the tradition of Critical Theory, their focus generates a
blindspot concerning the issue of aspectival captivity which genealogy addresses.
Or, to put it another way, they are held captive by a picture.
We can approach this suggestion by reference to the following question: what
are the conditions which would legitimate the claim that responsible moral or
political criticism must articulate normative criteria for the justification of moral
norms and/or the legitimation of political institutions and practices? Whence this
despotic demand (to borrow Wittgenstein’s phrase)? It would seem that a neces-
sary condition for the legitimacy of this claim is that the only threat to the exercise
of our capacity for self-government which requires critical reflection (as opposed
to action) is the existence of false beliefs concerning the justifiability of our moral
norms or the legitimacy of our political institutions and practices, where such
false beliefs are the products either of ignorance and mistakes or of ideological
captivity. If this is so, a condition of the legitimacy of this ‘must’ is that ideologi-
cal captivity is the only form of non-physical, self-imposed condition which is a
threat to the exercise of our capacity for self-government. Hence, in so far as the
tradition of Critical Theory is committed to this claim concerning responsible crit-
icism or critique – and this is, I think, the case – so it is also committed to the latter
claim concerning ideological captivity. Consequently, it should not surprise us
that adherents to this tradition have systematically misunderstood the philo-
sophical character of genealogy because, precisely in so far as they are committed
to a central tenet of this tradition, they will also be blind to the kind of non-phys-
ical, self-imposed captivity which genealogy is designed to address.
The aim of this paper has been to elucidate the philosophical structure of geneal-
ogy and in so doing to illustrate and dispel the systematic confusion surrounding
Conclusion
This essay has defended the claim that genealogy is best understood as a practice
of critical reflection directed to enabling us to free ourselves from a condition of
aspectival captivity. Understood as such, it is a form of self-reflection directed to
enlightenment and emancipation. Although I have not explored it here,15 it
should be noted that this defence helps to account for Foucault’s late concern with
enlightenment and practices of criticism. However, be that as it may, if the argu-
ment presented in this essay is cogent, it follows that the confused and critical
reception of Foucault’s genealogical work by philosophers working within the
traditions of Critical Theory may be accounted for in terms of their own captivity
to a picture of criticism which cannot acknowledge the point of genealogy. I hope
that this essay has gone some way to dispelling this confusion.16
David Owen
Department of Politics/Centre for Post-Analytic Philosophy
University of Southampton
Southampton SO17 1BJ
UK
[email protected]
NOTES
1 The issues raised in this essay have been discussed over several years with Aaron
Ridley and Jim Tully who also gave me detailed comments on an earlier draft and I am
most grateful to them. I am also grateful to Jane Bennett, Chris Brown, Tom Dumm, Rainer
Forst, Jocelyn Maclure, Gregor McLennan, Denis McManus, Tom Osborne, Peter Niesen,
Paul Patton and Jon Simons for their helpful remarks. This paper was first presented at a
conference on Foucault at the J.W. Goethe University in Frankfurt am Main in September
2001 and I am grateful to my co-panellists Raymond Geuss and Martin Saar for their
comments on my argument and to the other participants, notably Axel Honneth, and
Judith Butler, for their remarks. On a later occasion, it was also given to the Postgraduate
Political Theory Group at Balliol College, Oxford and I owe thanks to Monica Mookerjhee,
Michael Frieden and the postgraduate students present for pressing me on some of my
formulations. I am also grateful to an anonymous referee for the journal who pushed me
to clarify some important features of my argument.
2 In specifying Critical Theory as ideologiekritik I do not mean to suggest that critical
theorists limit themselves to this kind of criticism; on the contrary, as Peter Niesen and
Rainer Forst have both pointed out to me (forcefully and rightly), theorists such as
Habermas and Honneth also engage in Gesellschaftskritik (roughly, social criticism). I
restrict my attention to ideologiekritik in this essay simply to present as clearly as possible
the contrast between this form of criticism and genealogy. For consideration of the debate
between Foucault and Habermas across a wider terrain of issues, see Ashenden & Owen
(1999) and Kelly (1994).
3 I made this case elsewhere in respect of a focus on Wittgenstein in two related essays
(Owen 2001 and 2002). The first of these was presented to the Philosophy Society at the
University of Aarhus and I am grateful to them for helping me to clarify my views, partic-
ular thanks are due to Morten Raffnoe-Moeller for his comments. The second was occa-
sioned by an invitation from Cressida Hayes to contribute to a collection on Wittgenstein
and political philosophy and I am also grateful for her comments.
4 I have addressed the contrasting form of enlightenment and dialogue at stake in the
5 A referee for this essay has suggested that it is not a condition of an ideological belief
being ideological that it is false. This may well be the case but within the tradition with
which I am concerned here, falsity has been taken as a central feature of ideological beliefs
and so I will abide by these terms for the purposes of this essay.
6 Such an assessment will include, but not be reducible to, reflection on the truth value
captivity as ‘self-imposed’ in that both conditions are tied to the prevalence of asymmetri-
cal relations of power; but in respect of our collective social condition of being subject to
either of these forms of captivity, they are held in place by our ways of reflecting and
acting, and in this respect are ‘self-imposed’.
8 I am grateful to Denis McManus for discussion and clarification of this point.
9 For further reflection on critical theory and genealogy in relation to enlightenment,
see Owen (1999). It should be noted that in advancing this argument concerning geneal-
ogy, I am not only rejecting the view of genealogy as ideologiekritik but also the view
advanced by Raymond Geuss in relation to Nietzsche that, for example, his genealogy of
morality is simply an attempt to be better history than that which the (Christian) moralists
can provide, where the fact that his genealogy provides a better history indicates the supe-
riority of his perspective. This view is mistaken on two counts in my view. First, it misses
the sense in which genealogy attempts to accomplish a re-orientation of our thinking.
Second, it makes the claim of genealogy hang on its truth or, more broadly, its satisfaction
of the norms of historical inquiry; but while the historical truth of Nietzsche genealogy
may contribute to its perspicuity, it does not in any way follow that its perspicuity is
dependent on its historical truth. For Geuss’s position, see his essay ‘Nietzsche and
Genealogy’ (Geuss 1999: 1–28).
10 A theme which has also been significantly discussed by Stanley Cavell (1990) in his
remarks on Nora in Ibsen’s play A Doll House; remarks whose drift supports the basic
claim of this essay.
11 On this point, see Conant (1995).
12 An important element of this devaluation is given in Nietzsche’s attempt to
persuade us that the idea of a view from nowhere is an error, not because it is false but
because it is incoherent – and as a consequence of its incoherence gives rise to false beliefs.
13 It is, of course, the case that Foucault does not seek to provide a justification for why
Saar both suggested that this account of genealogy failed to acknowledge the centrality of
power to Foucault’s genealogy and the sense in which a genealogy provides a historical
ontology of ourselves. This suggestion is based on a confusion for which I am no doubt
responsible. It should be clear, first, that to be subject to captivity by a picture is to exhibit
a particular form of subjectivity, a mode of being in the world, and, second, that the picture
is held in place by our practical ways of going on in the world, where these are signifi-
cantly shaped by power relationships. I did not emphasise these features here because my
concern was with genealogy as a practice of critical reflection; but it is of course the case that
part of giving such a genealogical account is tracing the ways in which our captivity – our
being what we are – is held in place and this involves, obviously enough, attending to
power relations. Nothing I say in this essay is in tension with these points and I have
explored this issue at length elsewhere (Owen 1994 and 1996).
REFERENCES
Ashenden, S. and Owen, D. (eds.) (1999), Foucault contra Habermas, London: Sage.
Baker, G. (1991), ‘Philosophical Investigations Section 122: Neglected Aspects’ in R.
Arrington and H-J. Glock (eds.) Wittgenstein’s ‘Philosophical Investigations’, London:
Routledge.
Cavell, S. (1990), Conditions Handsome and Unhandsome, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Conant, J. (1995), ‘Nietzsche, Kierkegaard and Anscombe on Moral Unintelligibility’ in T.
Tessim and M. von der Ruhr (eds.) Morality and Religion, New York: St. Martins Press.
‘Florence, M.’ (Foucault, M.) (1994) ‘Foucault, Michel, 1926–’ in G. Gutting (ed.) The
Cambridge Companion to Foucault, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Foucault, M. (1978), Discipline and Punish, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Foucault, M. (1986), The Use of Pleasure, New York: Random House.
Foucault, M. (1988), Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and Other Writings, 1977–84 (ed.
L.D. Kritzman) London: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (1997), Ethics: The Essential Works: Vol.1 (ed. P. Rabinow), Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books.
Fraser, N. (1989), Unruly Practices, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Geuss, R. (1981), The Idea of Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Geuss, R. (1999), Morality, Culture and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Habermas, J. (1987), The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT
Press.
Kelly, M. (ed.) Critique and Power, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
Owen, D. (1994), Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the Ambivalence of
Reason, London: Routledge.
Owen, D. (1996), ‘Foucault, Habermas and the Claims of Reason’, History of the Human
Sciences 9 (2): 119–38.
Owen, D. (1999), ‘Orientation and Enlightenment’ in S. Ashenden and D. Owen (eds.)
Foucault contra Habermas, London: Sage, pp. 21–44.
Owen, D. (2000), ‘Wittgenstein and Genealogy’, Sats (Nordic Journal of Philosophy) 2 (2):
5–29.
Owen, D. (2002), ‘Genealogy as Perspicuous Representation’ in C. Heyes (ed.) Wittgenstein
and Political Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, forthcoming.
Tully, J. (1999) ‘To Think and Act Differently’ in S. Ashenden and D. Owen (eds.) Foucault
contra Habermas, London: Sage, pp. 90–142.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Invesitigations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittenstein, L. (1969), On Certainty, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.