Adj Cross Ling 1988
Adj Cross Ling 1988
Adj Cross Ling 1988
net/publication/290830649
CITATIONS READS
128 1,489
1 author:
Sandra A. Thompson
University of California, Santa Barbara
143 PUBLICATIONS 20,122 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Sandra A. Thompson on 28 July 2017.
followlll.g wa~: he a~sumes that each 'semantic type' has a basic or 'norm' (2) Whether or not there is a category of Adjectives, the words expressing
connection with a smgle part of speech (p. 27), and that since Property Concepts tend to fall into categories which either share
many properties with the class of Nouns, or many properties with the
alliangu<~ges.appear to have NoUl~and Verb but some lack a major class of Verbs.
class Adjective, ... some semantic types must be associated with
diffe.rent parts of speech in different languages ... M<)'J'ION, My own research, based on a further sampling (again not random) of some
AffECT, GIVING, CORPOREAL le.g. lallgh, sneezel, and other forty languages, has confirmed these findings.
types seem almost always to be classed together -this is the class that The problem, then, is this: It seems to be a fact that the distinction
is in all languages called Verh. OIl.JE<TS, KIN, and olher types arc belween Noul/.\' and V('fb,~ ilself is a language universal, where largely the
almosl always classed together - this is the class Ihat is in all sallie sel of concepls are found in each of Ihese categories from language
languages called Noun. (p. 2H).' to language (see Givlln 1979, 19.H4), Hopper and Thompson 19H4,
Jacobsen 1979, Schachler 1985 and references cited in these works for
Later he suggests 'what it means to say that a language has "a class discussion). Independently of whether or not there is an identifiable class
of ?djectives". Thi~ is a set of lexical ite~ls, distinguished on morpho- of Adjective, Ihe lJuestion which then arises is:
logical ami syntactic grounds from the uJ1lversal classes Noun and Verb'
(pp.62-3). Why should a given set of concepts, namely Property Concepts, he
Becaus~ Dixon assumes that each semantic type has, in a given distributed across these two quite distinct lexical categories, namely
langua¥e, lis own "no~mal' grammatical properties, he proposes to isolate Noun and Verb, in the world's languages (as opposed, say, to being
the ulllversal Adjective types by looking at the 'basic members' of the exclusively treated by grammars of languages as a subclass of either
Adjective c1.a.ss)ust ~n En¥lisl~, and .t1~ento investigate their linguistic Noun or Verb, or as a separate class of Adjective)?
category affiliations III Adjective-deficient languages. The types which
emerge, based on semanlic, syntactic and morphological criteria, are Before considering Ihe discollrsc proposal, let us hrieny consider some of
these: the sorts of evidence lhallead 10 these conclusions.
First, Ihere arc languages in whit:h Properly Concepls form a semantic
I DIMENSION - big,lillle, long, wide, ... subclass of the category Verh. For example, in Acehnese (northern
2 PHYSICAL PROPERTY - hard, heavy, smooth, ... Sumatra) (Durie 1985), there are a number of pieces of evidence showing
3 COLOUR that Property Concepts do not form a separate lexical category from
4 HUMAN PROPENSITY - jealolls, happy, clever, generolls, prolld, Verbs. First, they may take optional Undergoer cross-referencing just as
other non-controlled Verbs do:
5 AGE -I/ew, yo III/g, old, ...
6 VALUE - good, bud, pllre, delidolls, ... (2) gopnyan saket =geuh
7 SPEED - jil.\l, slow, quick, ... 3 sick =UNDGOEH
's/he's sick'
Fo~ the remainder of this paper, I will take these seven types of concepts,
which express ~rorerties of entities, as definitional for the term 'Property (3) gopnyan rhet =geuh
Concept. That IS, If a word expresses one of these types of properties in a 3 fall=UNDGOER
language, I will call it a Property Concept Word. 's/he is falling'
Dixon's findings, based on a non-random sample of seventeen lan-
guages,2 are summarized in (I ):
(I) Languages may have a category of Adjectives which can be identified (4) gopnyan ka saket =geuh
on language-internal morpho-syntactic grounds. No matter how small 3 INCHO sick =UNDGOER
or restricted this category is, it is likely to include at least these four 's/he's gollen sick'
(5) gopnyan ka geu~woe they take the same possessive suffixes and enclitic pragmatic particles
3 INCIIO AG-return (Karlsson 1983: 22). :rhus, in the sentence:
's/he has already returned'
~ (10) Auto on sininen
Third, any Verb can be used attributively with no morpho-syntactic ado: car:NOMCOP blue:NOM
'the car is blue'
(6) aneuk muda nyan
child young that
'that young child' the form si"i"ell 'blue' inflects for case and takes the copula,just as a Noun
would:
(7) ureueng pula pade nyan
person planl rice that
(11) iso-ssa auto-ssa
'that person planting rice' big-INESS car -INESS
'in the big car'
Finally, many non-controlled Verbs may take that 'very':
(12) Pekka on mies
(8) ureueng nyan carl;ng that P.:NOM COP man:NOM
person that clever very 'Pekka is a man'
'that person is very clever'
(9) Ibn galak that kcu jih Similarly, in a language with gender or noun class, such as Diyari
I like vcry DAT 3 (Austin 1981), spoken in South Australia, as well as a number of Indo-
'I like him/her very much' European and African languages, there is a class 'nominal', which can be
said to subsume 'Nouns' and 'Adjectives' as subcategories, with common
Other languages in my sample for which similar arguments can be made morpho-syntactic categories, such as case, number and gender or noun
include: class, though of course Noun and Adjective will always be kept distinct by
the fact that only Nouns, but never Adjectives, are subcategorized for
Aghem (Bantoid) (Hyman 1979) inherent gender.
Chinese (Chao 1968, Li and Thompson 1981) Other languages in my sample for which analogous arguments can be
Lakhota (Buechel 1939) made include:
Noni (Cameroon, Beboid Bantu) (Hyman 1981)
Thai (Noss 1964) Arabic
Turkana (E. Nilotic) (Dimmendaal 1983) Asmat (Papuan) (V oorhoeve 1965)
W. Makian (Papuan) (Voorhoeve 1982) Bantu languages
Wappo (California) the Chadic languages Hausa (Cowlln and Schuh 1976) and Margi
the Austronesian languages: Samoan (Marsack 19(2), Indonesian (Mac- (Hoffman 19(3)
Donald 1976), MokiJese (Harrison 1976), Palauan (Josephs 1975), Dyirbal (Dixon 1972)
UJithian (Sohn and Bender 1973), Woleaian (Sohn 1975), Kusaiean the Dravidian languages Kannada (M. Nadkarni, personal communica-
(Lee 1975) and Wolio (Indonesia) (Anceaux 1952).' tion) ami Malayalam (George 1971)
Fore (E. New Guinea) (Scott 1978)
That is, in each of these languages, whether or not a class of Adjectives can Israeli Hebrew (Rosen 1977)
be identified on language-internal distributional grounds, Property Con- the Indo-European languages Persian (Elwell-Sutton 1979), Polish
cept Words share many features with verbs. (Laskowski 1979), Icelandic (Glendening 1961), Latin, DUlch
Second, it is also well-known that thcre are a number of languages in (Donaldson 1981) and German (Schulz and Griesbach 1960)
which Property Concept Words pattcrn very similarly to Nouns. For Kalkatungu (Pama-Nyungan, Australia) (Blake 1979)
example, in Finnish, Nouns and Property Concept Words have much in Quechua (Adelaar 1977)
common: they are inflccled in the same way, for number and case, and Tagalog (Schachter and Otanes 1972).
However, while both of these pallerns exist, that is, Property Concepts should exhibit features related to the fact that they are more time-stable
sharing many features with Verbs and with Nouns, they do not necessarily than Verbs; similarly, we would also predict that in languages where
characterize languages, since it also happens, as in some West African 'Adjectives' are a subclass of Nouns, they should exhibit features relaled to
languages (for examplc, Kusaal (Gur) (Ladusaw 1985) and Yoruba (Kwa) the fact that they are less time-slable than Nouns. Now, while support for
(f. Serzisco, personal communication» or Japanese (Y. Koide, personal the former prediction is abundanl, support for Ihe laller prediction is nol.
communication), for example, that within a given language some Property Thus, as a subclass of Verbs, Property Concepts onen exhibit morpho-
Concepts will be categorized with features shared with Nouns, while syntactic evidence of their stat;!';t)', their greater lime-stability when
others will havc features shared with Verbs. compared to prototypical Verbs; they are often constrained not to occur
Finally, of course, there are languages, such as English, Fula (Arnott with certain tense-aspect morphemes, for example.
1970), Jacaltec (Craig 1977), Cherokee (Lindsey and Scancarelli 1985) But the primary way in which Property Concepts can be identified as a
and Manam (Austronesian) (Lichtenberk 1983), in which a class of subclass of Nouns different from prototypical Nouns is, as mentioned
Adjective can bc identified which shares fcw or no obvious propcrties ahove, Ihal Iheir gender calegories arc derived, while those of Nouns arc
wilh eilher Nouns or Verbs. Iypically inhercnl. I do not see a way to relale Ihis fact 10 the lower degre.c
The fact remains, howevcr, that cross-linguistically, Property Concepts of time-stability of Property Concepts as compared to Nouns. Rather, 1\
may show up as either Nouns or Verbs (see Dixon 1977 and Schachter has to do with the use to which Property Concepts are put by speakers.
1985 for further discussion). Givon's semantic explanalion in terms of time-stabilily, then, does not
BUI why should this bc so'! This is the question which I will try to answer help me to explain the facts given in ( I). In fact, while I believe that such
in the rest of this paper. semantic features as the stativity of verb-like Property Concepts have
significant morphosyntactic consequences, I Ihink that the explanation for
the specific cross-linguistic facts in (I) may not be found in semantics at
all. I suggest instead that a satisfying account of the lexical categorization
of Property Concepts in the world's languages can only be stated in terms
Giv6n (1979, 1984) has suggested a semantic factor underlying the of the use of Property Concepts in actual d;scourse.4
categorization of cognitive 'percepts', namely, time stability. 'Experiences
... which stay relatively stable over time ... tend to be lexicalized in
human language as nouns ... At the other extreme of the lexical-
phenomenological scale, one finds experiential clusters denoting rapid
changes in the state of the universe ... languages tend to lexicalize them
as verbs' 11984: 51-2, emphasis original). According to Givon, the class To support this claim, I have taken a first step by investigating the use of
Adjective, for languages which have it, occupies 'the middle of the Property Concept Words in two languages: English and Mandarin
time-stability scalc' (1984: 52). But there are two problems with this Chinese. In English, of course, it is a straightforward maller to argue for a
explanation. class of Adjectives to which Property Concepts belong. In Mandarin, on
First, while time slability may be involved in distinguishing prototypical Ihe other hand, there is an extremely restricted category of Adjective, but
cxcmplars of the eategorics Noun and Verb in the world's languagcs, I most Property Concept WOlds are indislinguishablc from Vcrbs (for
question its relevancc for the calegory Adjectivc, since, as Givlln admits, discussion, see Li and Thompson 191{I and Schachler 1(85).
the 'prototypical adjectival qualilies' are 'Ihose of stclble physical qualilies So far, these are the only two languages whose discourse use of Property
such as size, shape, texture, color, taste, or smell' (1984: 53, emphasis Concept Words I have investigated in any depth. However, the results are
mine). In fact, all of Dixon's seven 'semantic types' which characterize the similar enough in these two genetically and areally unrelated languages to
class of Adjectives in English, except possibly SPEED, denote relative suggest thai investigations of similar data in other languages will yield
stable characteristics. Thus, it does not appear to be true that 'adjectives similar results.5
occupy the middle of the time-stability scale'. For English, since Property Concepts correlate largely with the
The second problem with the time-stability explanation for the category of Adjectives, I will describe my findings for this language in
categorization of Property Concepts is that it makes the wrong prediction terms of the shorter term 'adjective' rather than 'Property Concept'.
about a particular set of morphosyntactic facts. That is, if 'Adjectives' I have looked at more Ihan 100 pages of transcribed natural spontane-
indeed occupied the 'middle of the time-stability scale', then we would ous conversational discourse with 301{ Property Concept words, or
predict that in languages where 'Adjectives' are a subclass of Verbs, they adjectives. I did not counl Nouns used as modifiers, such as steak place or
broccoli pie ,nor did 1count adjective-Noun combinations which 1took to (I R) But 1did have lots of fun up at Lehigh. That was a good school (C 14)
be single lexical items, such as blind llate.
(19) (talking about apartments)
~ 1found that English adjectives are used in essentially Iwo ways: see tahle
7.1. Let us look at some examples." Examples of adjectives playing a 1/: Well, theirs is a lIice apartmellt really. (rrie25)
predicale role fell into two synlactic categories, having to do with
peculiarities of English grammar. First, there were those in which the (17-19) show instances of an attributive adjective functioning as it
adjective appeared as a predicale adjective with a copular verb, as in: predicate because its predicate nominal head is anaphoric. But there are
also cases where an attributive adjective functions predicatively because
(13) and her parents apprently weren't even that wealthy (C I) its predicate nominal head is (relatively) empty. Here is an example of
such a case:
(14) I was getting kind of good at playing in Ihe rain, really (Frie 19)
(20) She and 1 are gonna go out and get drunk at four o'clock in the
(15) that golme so mad (11035)
afternoon. It's a religiolls thillg we're gonna have (Fra9)
(16) aren't some chapters of Understanding Media appropriate?
(Frie35) In (ZO), a grammatically atlributive adjective (religious) is functioning as
the predicate of its clause, because its predicate nominal head is non-new-
Most of my examples of adjectives functioning as predicates (209, or 86 information-bearing. The difference between (20) and (17)-( 19), how-
percent of the 242 instances of predicate function) were of this predicate ever, is that this time the non-new-information-bearing head is an empty
adjective type. noun (thillg).
Here is another example of this type of situation:
(24) (talking ahout a movic) In all of these examples, thc adjectives are playing lhe role of introducing a
and there's something really sad that happens (HG 13) new participant into the discourse.
Now, if adjectives are heavily involved in the introduction of new
In (24), the new referent is something unspecified except for its property participants into the discourse, then we would expect lwo corollaries: ( I)
of being sad. In the successive discourse, the speaker goes on to describe we would expect the noun l'lhrases in which these refcrcnt-introducing
the sad thing, so it is clear that it is being introduced as a new referent in the adjectives arc found to bc grammalically indefinite or non-referential; (2)
discourse - the point is that it is the adjective which is carrying the burden we would expect that the nominal positions in which these referent-
of tagging this new referent for subsequent use in the later discourse, introducing adjectives occur will he just those recorded independently for
namely by identifying it as sad. This, then, is an example of the new new participants.
referent being introduced by an adjective plus an empty head noun. Both of these predictions are borne out by the data. First, these referent-
Here is a similar example: introducing adjective phrases are all grammatically indefinite or non-
referential, with one exception. What I found hardly any examples of,
interestingly enough, were t!t1illite noun phrases with adjectives in thcm.
In fact, only Ollce among allthc 30Madjectives in my corpus did I find an
fl.'. "
In (26) you can see an example of the other situation in which an
'j' instance of an adjective re-idelltijyillg or distingllishing an already
~~ introduced referent. This one example is shown in (29):
adjective plays the major role in the introducing of the new referent: that in
which the new referent is introduced by an adjective plus an allapllOric
head noun: (29) (descrihing a movie)
and this boy is Jewish
(26) H: We've got to get umbrellas. (several turns later)
S: Why don't we get two, since there are two of us, good, that means There's this one part between lhis lewish glly and the girl (HG 13)
I can get a pretty fallcy felllillille olle (FrieI8-19)
Clearly the adjective in the phrase this lewish glly in (29) is functioning to
In (26), we see that the new referent, a pretty fancy feminine umbrella, is re-identifY, and not to introdllce, a discourse referent. The fact that these
distinguished from other referents in this discourse only by the properties cases, while perfectly easy to produce as examples, are so rare in these
dala, though, serves to underscore my claim that the two major functions
of adjectives are their referent-introducing function and their predicating
function. The referent-disti1lRl/ishi1lR function turns out to be an
extremely rare function in actual conversntionnllanguage. a fact which is Predicating a property or an e~tllhlished discourse rderent: 7t%(N=24.1)
contr:""7 10 eX'p~cta~i~lI1 and which could not have been arrived at by Introducing a new di~cour~e rderenl 29% (N = 97)
examll1l1lgone s II1tulltons. TOlal: 100% (N = .140) I
The second prediction of my hypothesis is also borne out by the data:
the nominal posi.tions in which these attributive adjectives occur are in just
Here is a Mandarin example of the predicating function for Property
thos~ recorded mdependently for the introduction of new participants,
Concept Words:
and III roughl.y the same proportions (Du Bois, 19H 7): that is, patient (45
percenl). obhque (I () per cent) and the S of an intransilive clause (30
(30) xue yuwen fangmiande ... suanshi bijiao chixiallgyidian
percent), but never the t\ position of a transitive clause.
sludy lang. aspect can:be:considered relatively popular a:little
The discovery of this referent-introducing function of adjectives, then,
'studying languages could be considered relatively popular' (kh IR)
is intriguing in two respects. First, it is intriguing hecause it is unexpected.
Simply knowing that adjectives can function 'nllributively' does not allow
In .(3 I) and (32) .you can see examples of Ihe referent-introducing
us to predict that tirey, Hnd not their 'head nouns'. do the majority of the
function for Mandann Property Concept Words:
work of introducing new referents in the noun phrases in which they
occur. Thus Hn examinHtion of how people talk ha.s uncovered a hitherto
(31) (talking about Chinese children studying English in school)
underestimated use of adjectives, which is not the one usually discussed in
trealmcn1.s of contcxl-free artificial examples. Second. thi.s discovery is zai hen yukuaide qifell -zhong xue, na shi zui haode
inl riguing because of the finding that the noun in such constructions is so at very happy atmosphere-in leal'll, that he most good
often superfluous. II is reasonable, then, to describe adjectives as referenl- 'to learn in a very happy atmosphere, that's Ihe best' (kh22)
inlroducing:
Example (31) is parallel to the English (22) above: both the Property
So far, then, we have seen that adjectives in English function in
spontaneous. natural conversation to predicnte a property of a referent Concept word yukuaide 'happy' and the noun qifell 'atmosphere' are
int.roducing the new referent, an atmosphere which has the property of
and to introduce a new referent into the discourse.
bemg very happy.
Implicit in my discussion so far is a claim which I can now make explicit:
Mandarin also exhibits the other type of situation, in which the Property
these two functions may also be viewed as differing in the discourse status
Concept Word is taking most of the burden of introducing the new
of the referent to which a given Property Concepl is being ascribed. That
referent: (32) shows a Property Concept Word with an al/apllOric head
i.s, a predicaling Property Concept ascribes H property to a referent
noun:
already established in the discourse, while a referent-introducing Prop-
erty Concept ascribe.s a property to a new referent, one which has not
(32) (talking ahout entrance examinations)
heen estahlished in the discourse. Semantically, of course, one could say
lhal in bolh funclion.s Ihe Property Concepl serve.s as a predicatc (as suoyi women zhcnde shi xiwang ncnggou you yige hcn gcng
implied in analyses of attributive adjectives as being semantically related so we rcally be hope able have a very IJIOIT
to relative clauses); however, the data reported here clearly suggest that 'so we really hope that we can have a much 1110reideal exam'
grammars renect the discourse status of the referent to whom the property /iximlgde kaoshi
is being ascribed rather than Ihe semantic function of predication. ideal exam
For Mandarin, I have looked at similar data again of natural spon- (kh2S)
taneous language. The results, for 340 Property Concept Words, are
strikingly similar to those found in English, as shown in table 7.2. From the In (32), the noun kaos!li 'exam' has already been introduced into the
table it is clear, then. that the same two functions as I found for English discourse; the whole discussion at this point is about the entrance
adjectives can be seen with Mandarin Property Concepts, and with examinations. As we saw with the analogous English examples, the new
roughly the .same frequency in the data. Thi.s time, there were 110 in.stances referent is contrasted with similar referents; what is lIew here is an
of a Property Concept serving to rc-idclI/i!y an already established examination which has the property of being ideal.
referent. That is, there were no analogues to the English case of (29). Analogous to the English cases described above in which Ihe Properly
b--
Concept Word was attributive to an empty head noun are instances in
Mandarin of a Property Concept word standing alone, that is, with a zero
head noun. About 3 percent of the referent-introducing Property Concept
Words in my data are of this type, of which (33) is an example: In this paper I have tried to suggest a discourse explanation for the way in
which languages tend to categorize Property Concepts. I have taken
(31) (talking abollt the grading of exams) Dixon's semantic study of Property Concepts as a starting-point, and
... geng zlumgyllo -de shi women yao tigao xuesheng shown that Property Concept Words tend to share features with both
even:more important-NOM COP we want raise student Nouns and Verbs cross-linguistically. I rejected a semantic explanation for
'... Ithel even more important Ithingl is that we want to raise the this fact, since semantically, Property Concept Words tend to denote
stable precepts like Nouns do, so that the widespread tendency to
xlIexi Yingyll-de nengli
categorize Property Concepts as Verbs remains unaccounted for. Instead
learn English-GEN ability
I have suggested Ihal a consideration of the jilllction of Properly Concepl
ahilily of our students to learn English'
Words in discourse might shed somc light on the pattcrns we find in the
way they are categorized in many languages. That is, given that Property
So far, what I have shown, then, is that in ordinary conversational
Concept Words share the predicating function with Verbs, and the
language, Property Concept Words, or adjectives if we're talking about
referent-illlrodllcing function with NOII/lS,this sharing of both verbal and
English, have exactly two functions, as listed in tables 7.1 and 7.2: one, to
nominal functions in discourse provides an explanation for the fact that
predicate a property of an established discourse referent, and two, to
Property Concepts will sometimes be categorized with morpho-syntactic
introduce a new discourse referent.
properties similar to those of Verbs, and sometimes with morpho-
As I mentioned earlier, I think that these same discourse functions for
syntactic properties similar to those of Nouns, while sometimes, since they
Property Concept Words will be found in any language; if this is so, they
are neither prototypical Nouns nor prototypical Verbs, they are categor-
provide the basis for an explanation of the facts about how languages
ized as a separate lexical category of Adjective.
categorize Property Concepts given in (I):