A Consequentialist Morality
A Consequentialist Morality
A Consequentialist Morality
A Consequentialist Morality
In utilitarian ethical theory, no action in itself
(the act per se) can be considered or called as good
or bad, right or wrong, apart from its outcome or
end. Utilitarian claim that there is nothing that we
can say in terms of moral worth of the act that is
not dependent, in one way or the other, to its
consequences. Actions, for them, do not have
intrinsic moral value.
In the An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Chapter 1, Sectio3n
1), Jeremy Bentham (174 1832), one of the most prominent advocates and
founders of Utilitarianism writes:
• Nature has placed mankind under the governance of
two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for
them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well
as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the
standard of right and wrong, on the other chain of
causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. They
govern us in all we do, in all we say, in all we think:
every effort we can make to throw off our subjection,
will serve but to demonstrate and confirm it.
Hence for Utilitarianism, right and wrong, are dependent
on the pleasure or pain that an act will bring or result to. If
an4
act produces pleasure, it is considered right or good; If it
results to pain, it is considered wrong or bad. Everything
else
is viewed as insignificant or unimportant in assessing the
act ’s
moral worth or value.
This in a way, echoes a very old but still a very influential
ethical school of thought that has its origin in ancient
Greek
Philosophy – The theory of Ethical Hedonism. This theory
advocates a philosophy that holds that the primary reason
Principal of Utility 5
Number
• What makes Utilitarianism so appealing to a lot of
people is its special emphasis on the social dimension
of
morality. In fact, this is where the theory becomes
influential. Our political system is so dominated by
• selfish
But it was not in Mill or in Bentham that this emphasis
interest
on of few
the social individuals
dimension that the pursuit
of happiness, where ofmorality
the
greatest
has
welfare
its has had
meaning beenoriginated
neglected.but the honor belongs to the
Scottish philosophe Francis Hutcheson (1694-1746). It
was
he who first formulated the now famous, though
controversial utilitarian phrase – The greatest good for
Bentham’s Hedonic Calculus 8
(Cost-Benefit Analysis)
• In ethical or moral decision making, Bentham claims that
what truly matters in the end is the maximization of
pleasure
or happiness and the minimization if not the total
•
eradication
of pain or suffering.
This particular scheme which Bentham called the
“Hedonic Calculus” (Hedons is a Greek term means
Pleasure,
Calculus is a science of calculation), is used for
9
The Hedonic Calculus (Bentham 1976:64-67)
1 Intensity – the more intense the pleasure, the better. One
is morally bound to do an act that offers stronger degree of
happiness or contentment. Not all pleasures are the same.
Some pleasures are stronger or are more intense than others.
2 Duration – the longer the pleasure lasts, the better. One is
morally obliged to perform those actions that provide longer
experience of pleasure. Pleasures also vary as to how long
they last. They are long-term pleasures and there are also
pleasures that are short-lived.
10