Buddhist Logic and Apologetics
Buddhist Logic and Apologetics
Buddhist Logic and Apologetics
Jiang Wu'
I. Introduction
in China, whose polemical essays repudiated the first several chapters of
Matteo Ricci's The True Meaning of the Lord of Heaven (7(±' セ IN@ The Bud-
dhist syllogism is a type of inference in the Buddhist logical tradition (Ch.
Yinmzng fZJSJ.l; Skt. Hetu-vicjya) that was fully developed in India and Tibet.
Buddhist logicians constructed inference by using three steps of reasoning:
thesis, reason, and example. The study of this branch of Buddhist knowl-
edge in China, however, was not prominent except for a short period of
time in the Tang セ dynasty (618-907), when Xuanzang Uイセ@ (602?-664) first
introduced it to China. It seems strange that Buddhist syllogisms "sud-
denly" reappeared in a seventeenth-century anti-Christian polemic. Basically,
in his use of Buddhist logic, Feiyin Tongrong devised three syllogisms ac-
cording to the rules of Buddhist logic. The last of these syllogisms is a hy-
pothetical Christian argument that he fabricated. Pointing out the logical
inconsistency of this imagined syllogism, Feiyin Tongrong sought to invali-
date the Christian belief in the existence of a creator God.
To facilitate an understanding of the content of these Buddhist syllo-
gisms and the historical context in which Buddhist logic was used, I will
first introduce some historical backgrounds, especially the rise .of Chan
Buddhism and the spread of Yogacara studies. Then, special attention will
be given to the content of Feiyin Tongrong's three syllogisms. Finally, I will
elaborate on the relation between logic and apologetics in the Buddhist tra-
dition.
II. The Rise of Chan Buddhism and the Spread of Yogacara Studies
In Seventeenth-century China
1 The field of early Jesuit mission in China and the Sino-European cultural exchange is well
developed 00 the basis of the archival studies of Jesuit materials in Rome, Paris, and Shang-
hai. For representative studies, see Zurcher; Muogello 198'9 and 1994; Standaert 1988 and
1995.
Wu: Buddhist Logic & Apologetics in Seventeenth-Century China 275
2 The maj or existing edition is a Japanese reprint in 1855: However, Prof. XlA Guiqi IOll'l:J
found another earlier edition and published it in Hong Kong. See Xia.
276 Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy
3 For detail of Miyun Yuanwu and his involvement in the anti-Christian campaign, see Wu
2002: 197-204.
4 Master Hong'en was usually called Master Xuelang セャエGZN@ The Jesuit sources indicate that he
had a debate with Matteo Ricci. However the author of Fonti Riccione mistakes his name as
Sanhuai ]MセN@ See Spence: 254 and Elia: 2/75-76. According to his biography written by his
good friend Hanshan Deqing, Master Hong'en was attracted to doctrinal studies at the age
of 12 an<;l thus entered the sangha. Residing at Bao'en ᆬセスL@ monastery in Nanjing WJ*, he
studied with Master Wuji Mingxin セeェLヲゥ@ (1512-1574) who had traveled to Beijing and
transmitted the knowledge of Huayan learning-and Yogacara teaching to the south. See Z no.
1456,73: 676c-679a. For a detailed study of the rise of Yogacara studies in the late Ming
dynasty, see Z. Zhang: RYQMTセN@
5 It must be noted that the Nyayapravesa, an introductory essay, only represented a small
portion of Buddhist logic because Xuanzang only translated Dignaga's early .works,
Nyayamukha and Nyayapravesa. After Dignaga, some significant changes were made by
DharmakTrti.
Wu: Buddhist Logic & Apologetics in Seventeenth-Century China 277
6 The remarkable development in his work is that Zhencheng was able to use Buddhist logic.
to point out the illherent errors in Sengzhao's reasoning. Using Buddhist syllogisms com-
posed of thesis, reason, and example, he commented that Sengzbao's argument is incorrect
. because Sengzhao concludes, according to Zhencheng, that things are immutable since their
nature is permanently abiding. However, the standard Madhyamaka theory should assert that.
things are not shifting because there is no existence of the inherent nature. Therefore, while
Sengzhao's conclusion is similar to the Madhyamaka thought, his reason is entirely wrong.
Zhencheng's real purpose was not to develop a theory of Buddhist logic; instead , he tried to
use syllogisms as a tool to structure his argument. JIANG Canteng イjQZセL@ who has con-
278 Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy
ducted a detailed study of this debate, argues that Zhencheng's use of the Buddhist syllogism
in the late Ming Buddhist doctrinal debates "was the fJ.rst time [in Chinese Buddhism] when
speculative tools were used to conduct theoretical analy·sis and to evaluate whether a notion
is true or false" Giang 1996: 106).
Wu: Buddhist Logic & Apologetics in Seventeenth-Century China 279
7 Dignaga's version of these three aspects is as follows: "1. Its presence in the subject of
inference. 2. Its presence in similar instances. 3. Its absence in dissimilar instances." Dhar.
maklrti modified it as follows: "1. The necessary presence of the reason in the s";bject's total-
ity. 2. Its necessary presence in Similars only, although Dot in their totality. 3. Its necessary .
absence from Dissimilars in their totality." For detail, see Stcherbatsky: 24345.
278 Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy
due ted a detailed study of this debate, argues that Zhencheng's use of the Buddhist syllogism
in the late Ming Buddhist doctrinal debates "was the first time [in Chinese Buddhism] when
speculative tools were used to conduct theoretical analysis and to evaluate whether a notion
is true or false" Giang 1996: 106).
280 Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy
both parties" eCho Gong bi liang セエ エNrZ L@ Skt. siidhiiralJa-iinumiina). It was in-
tended to serve as the common ground for further debate. Therefore, it
must be accepted as true by both parties. The second syllogism expresses
Feiyin Tongrong's thesis that is inferred from the first syllogism. The pur-
pose of this reasoning is to prove the validity of a Buddhist point of view,
which Feiyin Tongrong supported. However, the third -syllogism is sup-
posed to express Feiyin Tongrong's opponent's (Ricci's in this case) thesis.
Based on the first syllogism, which is accepted by both Feiyin Tongrong
and Matteo Ricci, the third syllogism should be demonstrated as invalid. In
addition, the structure of these three syllogisms was designed to ward off
the accusation of partiality: both parties' theses are grounded on a com-
monly agreed proposition and no one will introduce additional as sumptions.
Therefore, as a result of Feiyin Tongrong's reasoning, the Buddhist position
is true because it is a logical inference of the first syllogism and Ricci's posi-
tion is wrong because logical contradictions were discovered.
In this following section, I will first give an outlined form of these syl-
logisms according to Feiyin Tongrong's presentation . .Because Buddhist
syllogisms follow a format different from Aristotelian logic, as conclusion
rather than the premise is stated flrst, it is not easy to comprehend the
meaning of the syllogisms in the beginning. Therefore, I will explain their
content by using the concepts and terms of Aristotelian logic, which we are
accustomed to. However, this way of explanation by no means implies the
commensurability of the two logical systems .
Syllogism One:
Subject. The completely true great Way (iij"$ [dhamnn) : Jェャeᆪセ@
Them-. [The completely true great Way) contains the myriad things in the world
entirely (7.i<: セᄆエャQッOIjゥ N@ .
Reason: [The completely true great Way] is equal to what is beginningless and
・ョ、ャウセ Z@ MセJ セIN@ . .
Similar example: Like space, because space is continuous and unlimited, arid con-
tains myriad things (fCllljj.]: Y dセL@ NMェLセw[mャk]QGit@j ヲセャゥjエ@
セIN@
Dissimilar example: Like turde hair and rabbit horn which do not exist. They ru:e
different from what is beginningless and endless and cannot contain myr-
iad things entirely HセijャuZ@ Yd[jゥ]bセヲエGャ@ L@ JセーヲゥL@ セtQA|ゥL@ =1'mii! ....
セヲエュ IN@ .
This syllogism is similarly inscrutable. Again, for the convenience of our intui-
tive understanding, I will convert it to an Aristotelian syllogism, although some
logical relationships entailed in the original syllogism are unfortunately lost:
Syllogism Three:
Subject The Lord of Heaven m$: [rセI@
Thesis: [The Lord of Heaven] is able to create birds, animals, grass, and wood
that have a beginning and an end (*: セァQhUNャエAェ{Z[Y@
fuasorr. [The Lord of Heaven] is not created by what is beginningless and endless
(t2SI: El エIZjAャゥヲUセᆬ}fNーsS@
Similar example: Like that turtle hair creates things. Because turtle hair is not cre-
ated and is originally nonexisten('it has no reason to ·create things ([5]
DIM: ヲイoセGUZャッOjL@ エIj[GU}fNーヲゥeャSセL@ JセーヲゥL@ jャuセZッOzIN@
Dissimilar example: Like that human beings create human beings. Because hu-
mans are the same species, they are different from the beginningless and
endless Lord of Heaven who was not created but is able to produce what
has a beginning and an end, such as grass and wood (J!,Il!iV: frOA1:.,A, tJ.
Wu: Buddhist & China 283
The of this
off 8:
i\t this point, it becomes evident to us that this polemic the
Christians was reinforced the use of The correct logical forms
were followed and .the basic of Knrlrl,h1 We
could con tinue to this a.UIi1.LH.d
logical of view and an of view. However, also ap-
parent m these is the apologetic of the author
and towards Although
claimed an imparti!Jl we can sense that the Christian view bad been
abstracted and ridiculed. conclusion of a logical of these
would make better sense if were ap-
pr()ac:nea as a new in the Buddhist apologetic tradition rather
than in its logical tradition. To illustrate this let us the rela-
tion between arid in the tradition
has been by the
m response
in the seventeenth as
Feiyin is first of
an intentional advancement of the
logtcal Buddhist apologetics was a conscious reaction to
LUlU'.""'",, from other religions. In Indian Buddhism, ap()logetlc セuBGj@
イBGセョーャ@ sporadically in works "With other rel!g1()Us m
Sanskrit (Ch. waidoo Pali: """JUY,"', C()nCeDt refers
to who have taken a than the Buddhist one. Al-
though these paths are not
are acknowledged by Buddhists as
betans term it, tfrthikas are stones in the river.? In to this
mdusive of the presence of other religions, a more exclusive
version of as and harmful. In their
that respond to various tfrthikas, early Buddhist were
concerned the presence of other traditions and were eager
to distinguish themselves from the followers of other The
result of this kind of apologetic effort was various versions of ta.."{onomy of
firlhika, which classified all sorts of Indian religions according to their roots
of "fallacy." During encounters with other religions, the Buddhist apolo-
getic tradition was developed and closely related to the advance of Buddhist
logic (see Jackson).lo
In China, under the rubric of "protecting the dhanna" (hufa セZDIL@
Buddhist apologetic essays can be found in different historical periods.
Prior to the fifth century, apologetic treatises were collected in A Collection if"
EssC!)'s that Illuminate the Dharma サUafᆬャセス@ (T no. 2102, 52: 1-96) edited by
Sengyou fjiil/i (445-518). During the Tang dynasty, Damman セ 'Ef (596-667)
assembled a large amount of apologetic materials and compiled An Extensive
Collection if"Essqs that Illuminate the Dharma HAjゥ「fᆬャセI@ (T no. 2103, 52: 97-
362) and The Debates between Buddhism and Daoism in History HセエUTヲZュ@
セI@ (T no. 2104, 52: 363-396). Early apologetic works such as the Master
Mau's Treatise that Removes Our Doubts HゥftSAiセI@ in the fourth century
and The Treatise that Ridicules the Dao HセI@ in the sixth century focus
more on historical and moral arguments (see Keenan and Kohn).
After the Tang セ dynasty, the Buddhist religion was fumlygrounded
in cィゥョ・セ@ society, and there were only a few public debates between Bud-
dhism and other religions. The most notable is perhaps the Buddhist-Daolst
debate during the Yuan 5t dynasty that resulted in the persecution ofDao-
ists. Most Buddhist apologetic writings in later times targeted Neo-
Confucianism and were written by literati followers. The rhetoric of the
"Unity of Daoism, Confucianism, and Buddhism" became the central ar-
gument of these works. For example, ZHANG Shangying セイュ@ (1043-
1121), a Prime Minister during the Song dynasty, wrote the famous Trea-
tisl! an the Protection if"the Buddhist Dharma \セFャヲェス@ (T no. 2114 52: 637-645)
to repudiate critiasms of Buddhism by early Song Confucians OUYANG
Xiu i[xmセ@ (1007-1072), CHENG Yi セュ@ (1033-1107), and CHENG Hao
[ヲゥセ@ (1032-1085). LI Chunfu JセQゥ@ (1185-1231), a scholar in theJin 3lz: dy-
nasty of Northern China controlled by the Jurchens, also compiled the
Comments on the Collection that Illuminates the W try HbェセidャI@ to defend Bud-
dhism against Neo-Confucian critiques. During the Ming Iljj dynasty, apolo-
getic works continued to be written: SONG Lian's *1ll (1310-1381) Records
if"Protecting the Dharma HセョIL@ Daoyan's セid@ (or YAO Guangxiao セL@
1335-1418) Records if"the Remainder if" the WC!)' サSQ{セスL@ and Tu Long's jAセ@
(1542-1605) Records if" the Protectors if" the Buddhist Dharma HサセョI@ were
- representative writings. .j<
The use of Buddhist logic, however, was not present in these apolo-
10 For example, Dhannakirti, the most important Buddhist logician in the seventh centUry,
was deeply involved in the refutatioo of the Hindu theistic argUment for the existence of the
highest God fSvara. See Jackson. -
286 Dao: A Journal of Comparative PhiJosopfry
getic works. Even in the Tang dynasty, when the study of Buddhist logic
was promoted by Xuanzang, there Is no evidence that Buddhist logic was
successfully used in actual debates as an apologetic too1. l1 In this sense, the
emergence of Buddhist logic in the context of the seventeenth-century anti-
Christian movement signaled a new development in Buddhist apologetics.
This religious appropriation of logic in the seventeenth century be-
. came possible because logic in religious traditions often served an apolo-
purpose. From its genesis, logic is not by. nature apologetic. As a tool
reasoning, it was developed to master the rules of correct thinking.
However, when a religious tradition grows into a comprehensive system of
learning, logic is incorporated as an important branch of divine knowledge
and serves the purpose of validating faith and eliminating heterodoxy. The
Christian theologian Anselm (1033-1109), for example, employed Aristote-
lian logic, which is neutral to religion, to construct his ontol<;>gical argument
for the existence of God. In a similar way, Buddhist logic can be also trans-
fonned into an apologetic art of debate. As the author of the NyayapraveSa
states, "the property that is desired to be proved is whether it is eternal or
noneternal" (Stcherbatsk:y: 105). TIris shows that Buddhist logic should first
of all validate Buddhist doctrinal tenets. The Chinese translation of the
NyayapraveSa even clearly articulates that yinming, the Chinese translation
for hetu-vidyii, is intended to combat "heterodoxy" (xie $) and defend "or-
t:hodoxy" (zheng
This ideological intent, which is inherited in Buddhist logic, is not ob-
vious when we talk about logic as an independent branch oflearning within
the Buddhist tradition and judge this body of knowledge purely in tenns of
logic rather than in terms of religion. However, Buddhist logic is also a
subdivision of religious knowledge that was developed under the aegis of
religious dogmas. It cannot be separated from the context in which these
logical theories were nourished. Its application in a particular historicalpe-
riod IS often concomitant with the emergence of strong opposition to Bud-
dhism from other religious traditions. In the seventeenth century, when
Christianity became a strong challenge to l?uddhism, Buddhist logic was
once again appropriated as a powerful apologetic too1)2
11 The most notable use of syllogism by the Chinese was certainly Xuanzang's inference for
'vijiiaptimiitratii (zhcmveishi liang セiャェᆪuL@ the inference of true consciousness-only) composed
in India, which might have inspired the sbenteenth-century Buddhists to use it in real de-
bates. However, this event occurred during Xuanzang's stay in India. See Frankenhauser
1996: 73-75:
12 The revival of the interest in Buddhist logic under pressure from other traditions is not
unique in Buddhist history. In the twentietb century;Jor example, when the Western threat
to Chinese Buddhism became imminerit, Buddhist logic was once again advocated by a
group of Buddhists, represented by OUYANG Jingwu セQiャゥエ}@ (1871-1943) and LU Cheng
Wu: Buddhist Logic & Apologetics in Seventeenth-Century China 287
V.Conclusion
Abbreviations:
SCPX] Shl1ngchao poxigi oQeAェゥbャァエDセス@ ,8 vols. Ed. by:XU Changzhi セᄃ@
. 1639; reprinted in Japan, 1855-1856.
T Taisho shinsho daiiPkyo HJieセW[ZェゥudL@ 100 vols. Edited by
Takakusu Junjir6 イGVjZmゥョセ@ et al. Tokyo: Daizo Shuppan, 1924-
32.
Z Shinsan dai Nihon zokuzfJkyo HセJbRヲ^ZゥudL@ 90 vois. Tokyo:
Kokusho Kank6kai, 1975-1989; originally published as Dainihon
zokuiPkyo JbZコエ[QヲゥセL@ 750 vols. Kyoto: Zoky6 Shoin, 1905-1.2.
References