German Idealism 1
German Idealism 1
German Idealism 1
Chapter 1
German Idealism
The two main streams of philosophy flowing into Kant were Empiricism
(Locke, Berkeley, and Hume) and Rationalism (Descartes, Spinoza, and
Leibniz). The former stressed the senses and the later emphasised the
mind. Kant was able to synthesise these two movements by claiming
that the content of our knowledge comes from the senses but the final
form of knowledge comes from the categories of the mind.
Unfortunately, this led to an Agnosticism which concluded that we
cannot know reality (the noumena) but only appearances (the
phenomena). Thus the stream of Empiricism turned to Positivism
(scientism) which gave up metaphysics for the physical science. And the
stream of Rationalism became Idealism which confessed that our ideas
did not apprehend reality in itself.
Kant's solution was to propose that while we can know, via sensory
experience, particular facts about the world (which he
termed phenomena), we cannot know the form they must take prior to
any experience (which he called noumena). That is, we cannot
know what objects we will encounter, but we can know how we will
encounter them. Kant called his mode of philosophising "critical
philosophy", in that it was supposedly less concerned with setting out
positive doctrine than with critiquing the limits to the theories we can set
out. The conclusion he presented, as above, he called "transcendental
idealism".
Kant said that there are things-in-themselves, noumena, that is, things
that exist other than being merely sensations and ideas in our minds.
Kant held in the Critique of Pure Reason that the world of appearances
(phenomena) is empirically real and transcendentally ideal. The mind
plays a central role in influencing the way that the world is experienced:
we perceive phenomena through time, space and the categories of the
understanding. It is this notion that was taken to heart by Kant's
philosophical successors.
Fichte was the first to promote Idealism after Kant. This ideal dominated
German philosophy during the early nineteenth century. However, Fichte
called his doctrine ‘critical idealism’ in order to differentiate it from
Kant’s. Fichte took the ‘thing-in-itself’ as the dividing line between
dogmatism— accepting the thing-in-itself—and idealism which denies
it. The conflict between these two according to Fichte is the striking
difference between free determination of one’s will and some standard
of truth illustrating a sense of necessity. Kant pushed for an individual a
priori in each science and in morality. Fichte strived to show their
interconnectedness and interdependence. He initially sided with Kant
that religion is derived from ethics but takes this further and posits that
God is manifested within the universal moral order. To accomplish this
task, he introduces what he calls the “science of sciences” or “science of
knowledge.” Here he illustrates an a priori associated with every science
positing a universal knowledge associated with this ‘new science.’
positing that there is a pure ego insinuates that there is one and only one
transcendent ego that actively and infinitely manifests itself in the finite
consciousnesses. He even goes as far as to identify it as a spiritual Life
who creates all phenomena. He is pressing for both a phenomenology of
consciousness and a metaphysics of Idealism.
Fichte’s moral law is the law of nature where God orders the
universe. The material world is apparent to man’s senses. The
human will is free and his soul is immortal. A person should
exercise his freedom without impinging upon the freedom of others.
Each person comes into the world with a unique vocation for which
he is to perform. However, his duty is never completely fulfilled in
this life; hence, the immortality of the soul makes allowance for its
completion. Each person is to feel the responsibility to conduct his
life in such a way as to work towards his unique calling. Our moral
nature shows that he has ‘natural’ impulses for certain activities only
because he wants to do those certain behaviors. On the other hand,
humans perform other activities to where he leaves them undone
with no regards to an end. This provides evidence for a person’s
inner moral and ethical nature. Humans are a product of ego,
harness non-ethical interests. Eventually, the need for the state will
disappear but for the time being, the state is indispensable and
carries with it great moral responsibility.
11
The focal point of religion is in the obedience to the moral law. Faith is
faith in the ontological moral order. It can be seen that this dynamic
panentheistic idealism is based on faith and not based on knowledge. In
order to fulfill the moral vocations there is the requirement of faith in a
living and active moral order, the infinite Reason and Will. However,
Fichte in The Way to the Blessed Life concerns himself with edifying the
uplifting his hearers and reassuring them that his philosophy is not at
odds with the Christian religion.
12
15
spiritual beings. Add to this the importance of beauty and the aesthetic
value of reason coupling to a new mythology tying together philosophy
and religion.
of God and the soul. The years at the close of his career was occupied
with the interpretations of myths and the historical forms of religious
belief. These apparent shifts of his philosophy illustrated his hold on the
dialectic and the problems that came along with them. This fallout is
associated with the major question of Schelling’s speculations: “Why is
there anything at all? Why not nothing?” (Philosophy of Revelation, I,
1.)
16