维特根斯坦与列维纳斯
维特根斯坦与列维纳斯
维特根斯坦与列维纳斯
Ludwig Wittgenstein and Emmanuel Levinas are two of the most influ-
ential and challenging thinkers of the twentieth century. Despite this,
their writings are seen as coming from opposed philosophical camps and
as a result little work has been done comparing the two philosophers.
This book explores the hitherto neglected affinities and tensions between
their philosophies, and the often antagonistic intellectual traditions each
represents.
The two competing philosophical accounts of the ethical are juxta-
posed in order to allow the reader to deepen their understanding of one
by means of the other. The two systems of thought are brought to bear on
each other in the areas of faith, guilt and vulnerability, concepts central to
the discussion of ethics, and in doing so a surprising amount of common-
ality is highlighted. The central focus of the book is the complex, yet
mutually illuminating, interplay of a number of ethical-religious themes in
both Wittgenstein’s mature thinking on religious belief and suffering, and
Levinas’s distinctive account of ethical responsibility.
This unique book demonstrates how a critical engagement with
Wittgenstein and Levinas facilitates a rethinking of some of the most
pressing religious, ethical and political problems facing the twenty-first
century. As such, the book will be of use to postgraduate students of
Continental and Analytic philosophy, as well as those interested in
contemporary theology.
Bob Plant completed his Ph.D. in Philosophy and French at the University
of Aberdeen in 2001. He has published widely on philosophers from both
‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’ traditions, most recently in Philosophy and
Literature, Philosophical Investigations, Philosophy and Social Criticism, Inter-
national Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Modern Theology, Journal of Scottish
Philosophy and Journal of Religious Ethics.
Routledge studies in twentieth-century philosophy
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
2 Donald Davidson
Truth, meaning and knowledge
Edited by Urszula M. Zeglén
5 Aesthetic Order
A philosophy of order, beauty and art
Ruth Lorland
6 Naturalism
A critical analysis
Edited by William Lane Craig and J.P. Moreland
10 Hilary Putnam
Pragmatism and realism
Edited by James Conant and Urszula Zeglén
11 Karl Jaspers
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
15 Real Metaphysics
Edited by Hallvard Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra
18 Laws in Nature
Stephen Mumford
25 Philosophy of Time
Time before times
Roger McClure
Wittgenstein and Levinas
Ethical and religious thought
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Bob Plant
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s
collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
This ribald laughter clawed at my heart. How could they laugh like that
when somewhere someone was groaning in despair, suffering boundless
torments?
Stefan Zweig, Beware of Pity
The question is not: How much are you going to get out of it? Nor is it
How much are you going to put into it? But rather: How immediately are
you going to say Yes to no matter what unpredictability, even when what
happens seems to have no relation to what one thought was one’s commit-
ment?
John Cage, A Year from Monday
Contents
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Preface xii
Acknowledgments xiv
Introduction 1
Hauntings 1
Wittgenstein: radical pluralism and the natural 3
Levinas: the guilt of the survivor 7
Saintliness and Levinas’s anti-naturalism 8
A note on ‘radical otherness’ 9
Synopsis 199
Notes 201
Bibliography 269
Index 286
Preface
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
This book is a revised version of my doctoral thesis, written under the super-
vision of Dr. Jonathan Friday and Dr. Ian Maclachlan at the University of
Aberdeen between 1997 and 2001. That is the abridged account. The
slightly longer version goes something like this: I began studying philosophy
(of a broadly ‘Analytic’ type) in 1992, and soon became preoccupied with
the significance of Wittgenstein’s later work for ethics and the philosophy of
religion. Then, between 1995 and 1997, I studied for a postgraduate degree
in modern ‘Continental’ philosophy. My reasons for taking this route were
entirely circumstantial, but it was here that I first encountered Levinas. I will
not pretend that my initial reaction to his philosophy was anything other
than hostile. Nevertheless, by working through selected essays and inter-
views I gradually found myself warming to certain aspects of Levinas’s think-
ing. (As the reader will discover, I am not wholly persuaded by Levinas’s
distinctive oeuvre.) To the dismay of some of my tutors, throughout this
period my interest in Wittgenstein persisted, and it was here that I first read
On Certainty – a text that continues to preoccupy me more than any other of
his writings. All this eventually culminated in a Masters dissertation on the
question of religious apologetics in Wittgenstein and Levinas. It was on the
basis of this piece that I began my doctoral work in 1997.
Throughout the following chapters I draw on the work of a number of
philosophers from both so-called ‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’ traditions.
However, in all this a rather special place is reserved for Derrida. Given
the explicit focus of this book I should therefore say something about my
interest in him.
I came to Derrida’s voluminous writings very late. In fact, prior to
beginning my doctorate I had conscientiously avoided him. The image I
then had of Derrida (an image that continues to dominate much ‘Ana-
lytic’ philosophy) was of an insidious – albeit playful – ‘postmodern’
skeptic. After reading his work on a variety of ethical-political questions, I
was therefore surprised to discover that Derrida was not only a deeply
humane thinker but anti-skeptical in a not dissimilar way to Wittgenstein.
Moreover, in his recent articulation and development of a number of Lev-
inasian themes, Derrida’s work fed naturally into many of my most persis-
Preface xiii
tent philosophical interests. It therefore seemed (and still seems) to me
entirely appropriate that he should be allowed to ‘haunt’ the following
analysis of Wittgenstein and Levinas.
It is customary at this juncture to force a neat, linear narrative out of
such biographical details. But that would give a false impression of how
this book came about. Instead, I would like to cite a few passages from
Wittgenstein’s last notebooks On Certainty, for these encapsulate the
central themes of the following chapters.
Toward the end of On Certainty Wittgenstein imagines someone whose
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
beliefs and practices seem ‘radically’ different from his own. He there writes:
This book would not have been possible without the encouragement, philo-
sophical rigor and therapeutic laughter of Jonathan Friday and Ian
Maclachlan. It is also due to their friendship that my time spent under their
supervision at the University of Aberdeen has left me with only the happiest
of memories. I would also like to thank Simon Glendinning for his support
and, not least, for setting the precedent in openly ignoring the so-called
‘Analytic/Continental divide.’ Sincere gratitude to the departments of
Philosophy and French at the University of Aberdeen for providing such a
hospitable environment in which to work, and to Paul Tomassi and Gordon
Graham in particular for their comments on early drafts of Chapters 2 and
3 (respectively). Thanks also to Eric Matthews for his perceptive remarks on
my doctoral thesis, and to Peter Baumann for so many stimulating conversa-
tions that sharpened my awareness of (to borrow Derrida’s formulation)
‘the production of the extraordinary within the ordinary.’ For their friend-
ship and generosity a special thank you to Jackie Rattray and Audrey Small.
Sections of this book have appeared (in condensed form) in a number of
journals. I am grateful to them for granting me permission to reproduce
some of the material here. A version of Chapter 1 was published as ‘The
End(s) of Philosophy: Rhetoric, Therapy and Wittgenstein’s Pyrrhonism’, in
Philosophical Investigations, Vol. 27, No. 3 (July 2004), 222–57. Parts of Chapter
2 were published as ‘Our Natural Constitution: Wolterstorff on Reid and
Wittgenstein’, in Journal of Scottish Philosophy, Vol. 1, No. 2 (Autumn 2003),
157–70. Parts of Chapters 2 and 3 appeared as ‘Blasphemy, Dogmatism and
Injustice: The Rough Edges of On Certainty’, in International Journal for Philo-
sophy of Religion, Vol. 54, No. 2 (October 2003), 101–35. Parts of Chapters 5
and 6 were published as ‘Ethics without Exit: Levinas and Murdoch’, in Philo-
sophy and Literature, Vol. 27, No. 2 (October 2003), 456–70. Parts of Chapters
5 and 7 were published as ‘Doing Justice to the Derrida–Levinas Connection:
A Response to Mark Dooley’, in Philosophy & Social Criticism, Vol. 29, No. 4
(July 2003), 427–50. I would also like to thank three anonymous readers for
their remarks on an earlier draft of this book, and Joe Whiting, Amrit
Bangard, Terry Clague and Yeliz Ali at Routledge and Gail Welsh and Alan
Fidler at Wearset for their help and encouragement in this project.
Introduction
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
This life of ours is a hospital, in which all the patients are obsessed with a
desire to change beds. One would prefer to suffer near the stove, and
another thinks he would soon recover near the window. I always have the
feeling that I would be better anywhere except where I actually am, and
the idea of a removal is one which I am constantly discussing with my Soul.
C. Baudelaire, The Poems in Prose
If our condition were truly happy, we should not have to divert our
thoughts from it in order to be happy.
B. Pascal, The Pensées
Hauntings
Levinas was once asked whether, contrary to structuralism, his work
represented ‘an attempt to preserve subjectivity in some form?’ His
response was unequivocal: ‘My thinking on this matter goes in the oppos-
ite direction to structuralism.’ Levinas’s commitment is not, of course, to
the Cartesian ‘self-sufficient cogito’ (1984: 63) but rather to an ethically
constituted subject. For the ‘other haunts our ontological existence and
keeps the psyche awake . . . Even though we are ontologically free to
refuse the other, we remain forever accused, with a bad conscience’ (ibid.:
63–4). Although the philosophical grounding and implications of these
remarks are hardly self-evident, there are two reasons for my beginning
with them. First, part of my objective is to show that the sentiments
expressed here form the nucleus of Levinas’s philosophy. That the other
‘haunts our ontological existence’ is the guiding thread running through-
out Levinas’s writings, and it is in this sense that his work constitutes an
extended meditation on existential ‘guilt.’ The second reason for citing
these passages is that they foreground the central themes of my argument
more broadly. I will now explain how.
That the human subject cannot adequately be understood abstracted
from its relation to others is a broad enough claim to raise little
philosophical interest. What is significant is how Levinas’s specific
2 Introduction
understanding of this relationship renders a distinctly ethical account of
subjectivity. It is the aforementioned notion of ‘being haunted’ that I will
therefore explore within a number of ethical, political and religious con-
texts. But posing the question of subjectivity in this way simultaneously
moves us within the orbit of certain aspects of Wittgenstein’s thinking.
This may seem a surprising claim given that Wittgenstein’s later work
appears to lack a ‘developed notion of the self’ (Werhane 1995: 62).
While this may be true if one means by ‘self’ something akin to the Carte-
sian res cogitans,1 there is nevertheless a sense of ethical subjectivity in
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
While Wittgenstein is not a systematic thinker, his later writings have been
extensively quarried and their central ‘arguments’ extracted. But this
general philosophical appropriation has been undertaken with little
regard for the broader therapeutic-naturalistic vision therein.8 Due to his
recurrent emphasis on ‘language-games’ (1958: §24), ‘forms of life’ (ibid.:
p. 226) and ‘world-picture[s]’ (1999: §167), Wittgenstein’s later work is
often seen to be fundamentally concerned with linguistic-conceptual ‘plu-
rality.’ This is perhaps unsurprising given that his avowed ‘interest is in
shewing that things which look the same are really different’ (Drury 1981:
171).9 Nevertheless, two important questions need to be raised here: (1)
What are the philosophical motives for Wittgenstein’s concern with these
‘differences’?10 And (2) how deep do such ‘differences’ actually go? I will
now briefly indicate what is at stake in these two questions, and the role
each plays in my argument.
anyone who is familiar with the thought of the later Wittgenstein will
have difficulty sharing the optimism of [Werner Marx] who calculates
that an ethics of compassion appears capable of surmounting the het-
erogeneity of language games and the corresponding forms of life.
(1999: 58)
Although both Greisch and Smart express the same general misgiving
about Wittgenstein’s later work (namely, that it divides human life into
fundamentally incommensurable ‘forms of life’),21 Greisch puts a dis-
tinctly ethical-political twist on the matter. This emphasis is correct, not
least because the question of religious ‘fideism’ is already an ethical-polit-
ical question of how to engage justly with a ‘world picture’ other than
one’s own.22 However, what is striking about Greisch’s remarks is how he
overlooks the role of ‘primitive’ behaviors (including those of ‘sympathy’
(Wittgenstein 1993: 381)) in Wittgenstein’s own thinking – behaviors
upon which ethical-political life is hinged.
This is how the first few chapters of the book are oriented. In Chapter 5,
however, I focus on Wittgenstein’s ethicalization of certain ‘religious’
themes. Specifically what interest me here are his suggestions concerning
the relationship between the notion of ‘immortality’ and ‘ethical ideas of
responsibility,’ and how the latter are connected with an experience of
guilt ‘that even death couldn’t stop’ (1994b: 70).23 The sentiments
expressed here are not uncommon in Wittgenstein’s work, for the inti-
mated fissure between the ethical ‘ought’ and ontological ‘can’ is a recur-
rent feature of his account of genuine religiosity.24 Toward the end of
Chapter 5 I therefore argue that, rather than reading Wittgenstein’s anti-
apologetics as essentially fideistic, we might instead read him as gesturing
toward an ethicalized conception of religiosity where the believer is
promised nothing ‘in return’ for their commitment. The possibility of
faith without eschatological assurance is, I believe, a more philosophically
interesting way of understanding Wittgenstein’s claim that the ‘man who
stated . . . [his religious convictions] categorically was more intelligent
than the man who was apologetic about it’ (ibid.: 62–3). It also helps us to
Introduction 7
elucidate the relationship between religious belief and ethical respons-
ibility. Yet despite these tantalizing possibilities, Wittgenstein never
systematically worked out his views on religion and ethics. What is beyond
serious dispute, however, is that he firmly believed that the religious and
ethical dimensions of human life are intimately connected – so much so
that no real sense could be made of the former without reference to the
latter. Wittgenstein’s fragmentary reflections on religion thus call for sup-
plementation, and – as I argue in Chapters 6 and 7 – Levinas provides this.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
of morality?’ (1988a: 175). Not only does Levinas’s rhetoric parallel that of
more ‘confessional’ Holocaust writers, his concern with the ‘nakedness’
(1993: 102), ‘exposure’ (1998b: 145) and ‘vulnerability’ (1996a: 102) of
the other necessarily leads us to reflect on the daily realities of the death
camps. Yet, it is in Levinas’s remarks on the ‘shame of surviving’ (1998b:
169) that the philosophical force of the Holocaust on his writings truly
emerges.
Relating Levinas’s ethics to Heidegger’s ontology is a more precarious
enterprise, given the former’s suspicions concerning the ethical-political
implications of the Heideggerian project. Although Levinas considers
Being and Time to be ‘one of the finest books in the history of philosophy’
(1992: 37), he remains unsure that Heidegger’s notorious affiliation with
the Nazis (and specifically his ‘silence concerning . . . the Holocaust’
(1989: 487)) can be entirely dissociated from the central themes of that
‘extraordinary book’ (ibid.: 488). Nevertheless, in Chapter 6 I argue that
§§54–60 of Being and Time (regarding the ‘call of conscience’ and ontolog-
ical ‘guilt’) are crucial for understanding both Levinas’s ethics and
Derrida’s subsequent articulation of many of the former’s central themes.
(I turn explicitly to Derrida in Chapter 8.) Although these themes are
intimately connected to Heidegger’s analysis of Dasein as that ‘entity
which in its Being has this very Being as an issue’ (1999: p. 68) which
Levinas rejects, they nevertheless provide the latter with the raw philo-
sophical material from which to assemble his own ethicalized account of
subjectivity – that is, a subject who is haunted not by its own ‘potentiality-
for-Being’ (ibid.: p. 276) but by the other who calls its murderous being-in-
the-world into question.
nology, and yet it is routinely assumed that ‘radical otherness’ makes per-
fectly good sense. Although I focus on this in Chapters 3 and 5, the hazard
with such notions can be easily summarized. Even if one accepts that the
other is ‘radically other’ (and this is far from unproblematic), nothing of
any ethical consequence necessarily follows; one might just as well talk of
the ‘relation’ with the other in terms of wonder, astonishment or simple
befuddlement.29 If the other is indeed radically ‘other’ then how could one
ever know that there had been an encounter with the other, for as such
the other ‘would not even show up’ (Derrida 1992a: 68)?30 A second ques-
tion emerges at this juncture that relates specifically to Levinas’s work. By
stressing the relation between self and the singular ‘other,’ Levinas must
account for the passage between the ethical relation and the political rela-
tion concerning those other ‘others’ outside the intimacy of the face-to-face
relation. So, something substantive needs to be said in order to: (1)
account for the very notion of ‘radical otherness,’ and (2) bridge the gap
between the mere encounter with this ‘radically other’ and the demands
of ethical-political responsibility. Although Levinas does attempt to
explain this movement from ethics to justice, his recurrent emphasis on
the absolute singularity of the ‘other’ inevitably makes the realm of the
political appear as a ‘betrayal’ (1994a: 158) of the ethical relation.
Without simply rejecting the notion of ‘otherness,’ I want to temper its
purported radicality by reference to Wittgenstein’s minimal naturalism.31
My contention is that critically negotiating between Levinas and Wittgen-
stein in this way not only brings their respective philosophical projects
into close (though not always comfortable) proximity, but also enables us
to address matters of ethical, political and religious importance.
Before substantiating these claims, there is one further point I would
like to make concerning the assumed ‘otherness’ of so-called ‘Contin-
ental’ philosophy in ‘Analytic’ circles (and vice versa). While I recognize
that it is possible to maintain the distinction between these ‘traditions,’ in
this book I do not do so. It is not that I have deliberately avoided this relat-
ively recent demarcation, but rather that it simply does not interest me.
Likewise, I do not think that those in the Continental camp are inherently
‘difficult’ while those on the Analytic side are blessed with innate ‘clarity’
– philosophers are ‘difficult’ in many different ways. I make no apologies
for all this, although some will doubtless think a justification is necessary.
Introduction 11
To those readers all I can say is that if there is any value in the proceeding
analyses (and, as always, that is for others to judge) then it is due to my
experiencing a quasi-Pyrrhonian indifference when faced with the routine
antagonisms haunting contemporary philosophy. The practice of philo-
sophy always involves tacit meta-philosophical decisions concerning what
counts – and what should count – as ‘philosophy.’32 So, for example, in the
UK Continental philosophy has pulled ranks against a wider philosophical
establishment that often simply refuses to acknowledge the former as ‘seri-
ously philosophical.’ But it would be mistaken to think that Continental
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
I have noticed that children are rarely afraid of thunder unless the claps
are terrible and actually hurt the ear. Otherwise this fear only affects them
when they know that the thunder sometimes hurts or kills. When reason
brings fear, reassurance comes through habit.
Rousseau, Emile
Introduction
Wittgenstein once remarked that he had ‘reached a resting place’ insofar
as he knew that his method was ‘right.’1 He proceeded: ‘My father was a
business man, and I am a business man: I want my philosophy to be busi-
ness-like, to get something done, to get something settled’ (Drury 1981:
125–6). Despite Wittgenstein’s awareness of his ‘special’ philosophical
‘ability’ (ibid.: 91), for most of his life he was nevertheless ‘making plans
to forsake this work and to live an entirely different mode of existence to
that of the academic philosopher.’ Drury concludes:
Now we may indeed be glad that nothing final came of these various
plans, and that he continued to work at his philosophical writings up
to a few days before his death. But I am certain that we will not under-
stand Wittgenstein unless we feel some sympathy and comprehension
for his persistent intention to change his whole manner of life.
(1981: 92)
In short, Wittgenstein’s plans to change his life ‘were not just a transitory
impatience but a conviction that persisted for years until the time came
when he realized that such a change was no longer a possibility’ (ibid.).
These reflections of one of Wittgenstein’s few close friends2 are of both
biographical and philosophical interest. Drury was right to emphasize that
Philosophy as therapy 13
Wittgenstein’s desire to abandon philosophy was no mere psychological
idiosyncrasy, but rather central to his conception of good philosophic
practice.3 Moreover, in his insistence that we will misunderstand Wittgen-
stein’s work if we ignore this motivation – or overlook that his work had ‘a
real goal’ (ibid.: 96) – Drury identifies the risks involved in ignoring
Wittgenstein’s craving for the non-philosophical life.
Of course, conceding this does not eliminate the suspicion that it is
Wittgenstein’s anti-philosophical conception of philosophy that betrays
something deeply idiosyncratic. But such a judgement would be hasty. For
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
[I]n order to decide the dispute that has arisen about the criterion
[of competing truth-claims], we have need of an agreed-upon crite-
rion by means of which we shall decide it; and in order to have an
agreed-upon criterion it is necessary first to have decided the dispute
about the criterion. Thus, with the reasoning falling into circularity
mode, finding a criterion becomes aporetic.
(Sextus 1996: 2:20–5)19
But ‘nobody . . . disputes about whether the external object appears this
way or that, but rather about whether it is such as it appears to be’ (ibid.:
Philosophy as therapy 15
20
1:23–7). The failure of traditional philosophy thus lies in its encourage-
ment of a certain cognitive inflexibility in the face of natural forces. In
their respective claims to have provided the necessary foundations upon
which to live, philosophers fail to appreciate that their theories simply
compound the problems they aim to resolve.21 Engagement with any such
philosophy requires numerous epistemic and normative commitments,
but it is precisely these that augment22 existential disease by hampering
natural instinct.23 What is needed to attain ataraxia is not dogma but the
inculcation of a natural pliancy in the face of life’s unpredictabilities.24 In
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
short, the Pyrrhonist wants to extract the normative from her life and
thereby emphasize that ‘we can just go on living as nature takes us,
without a . . . view about how things ought to go on’ (Nussbaum 1991: 531).
What therefore underpins the Pyrrhonian attitude is an appeal to the
realm of animality. Indeed:
Leaving aside for the moment its problematic normativity, this model
clearly sits uncomfortably alongside the dominant tendency of Western
thought to elevate the human realm far above that of the animal. But for
the Pyrrhonist humanity has much to learn from its bestial neighbors if
the desire for ataraxia is to be satisfied.25 After all:
as [she] becomes more and more used to the skeptic way she will,
quite possibly, come to hold all of her convictions more and more
lightly; so she will need, progressively, weaker and weaker arguments.
Argument gradually effects its own removal from her life. At the end, I
imagine that the bare posing of a question will already induce a shrug
of indifference, and further argument will prove unnecessary.
(1991: 540)
The critical point here is that there is nothing within the Pyrrhonian
framework to ensure that this ‘shrug of indifference’ would not also mani-
fest itself in the social-political realm.60 Indeed, in Sextus’ own description
of the Pyrrhonian life we are explicitly told that, given the equipollence of
different lifestyles,61 accepting the prevailing ‘laws and customs’ provide
the Pyrrhonist with the criteria of what is good and bad ‘in the conduct of
life’ (1996: 1:23–4). That is, the Pyrrhonist follows ‘a certain rationale
that, in accord with appearances, points [her] toward a life in conformity
with the customs of [her] country and its laws and institutions’ (ibid.:
1:17).62 These passages do not merely suggest that prevalent ‘[c]ustoms of
friendly and marital loyalty will be observed’ (Nussbaum 1991: 554).
Taking into account that: (1) the normative dimension of the pre-
Pyrrhonian (dogmatic) life is, during conversion, extricated along with
belief,63 and (2) the Pyrrhonist prides herself on her ability to conform to
the prevailing social-cultural milieu,64 the suggestion that she would
remain unaffected by ‘social prejudices’ is untenable. For if the Pyrrhonist
finds herself in a cultural setting ingrained with (what we, including Nuss-
baum, would consider to be65) ‘social prejudices,’ then on what grounds
could she legitimately avoid indulging in such practices? After all, to
shun these activities would be conducive neither to the attainment nor
maintenance of ataraxia. In her defense one might argue that here the
20 Philosophy as therapy
Pyrrhonist could attain ataraxia because she would not adopt the beliefs
fuelling such ‘prejudices.’66 The Pyrrhonist would not believe Jews to be fit
only for extermination, or homosexuality to be an abomination before
God. Nor would she believe that women are naturally subordinate to men.
She would, however, follow others and engage in racist, homophobic
and/or sexist activities if doing otherwise would jeopardize her attaining
ataraxia.67 Could the Pyrrhonist here propose ataraxia as an alternative to
such customs? Could she, for example, advocate to her fellow citizens an
attitude of racial, sexual and gender ‘blindness’? Presumably not, for
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
‘I don’t believe anything you tell me,’ Nately replied, with a bashful
mitigating smile. ‘The only thing I do believe is that America is going
to win the war.’
‘You put so much stock in winning wars,’ the grubby iniquitous old
man scoffed. ‘The real trick lies in losing wars, in knowing which wars
can be lost. Italy has been losing wars for centuries, and just see how
splendidly we’ve done nonetheless . . .’
Nately gaped at him in undisguised befuddlement. ‘Now I really
don’t understand what you’re saying. You talk like a madman.’
‘But I live like a sane one. I was a fascist when Mussolini was on top,
and I am an anti-fascist now that he has been deposed. I was fanati-
cally pro-German when the Germans were here to protect us against
the Americans, and now that the Americans are here to protect us
against the Germans I am fanatically pro-American . . .’
‘But,’ Nately cried out in disbelief, ‘you’re a turncoat! A time-
server! A shameful, unscrupulous opportunist!’
‘I am a hundred and seven years old,’ the old man reminded him
suavely.
‘Don’t you have any principles?’
‘Of course not.’
(Heller 1961: 261–2)
Unless one understands this, then I do not think one can understand
Wittgenstein’s conviction that philosophy is important. For he did not
think that philosophy is important in the way in which therapy is
22 Philosophy as therapy
important to the patient . . . Philosophy, as he practiced it, was ‘the
bloody hard way’ in the sense of being opposed to looking for conso-
lation . . . And it was not only a way of thinking and working, but a way
of living as well. And the ‘hardness’ was really a criterion of the sort of
life that was worthwhile. Perhaps I should add ‘for him.’
(Rhees 1969: 169–70)
extent that we seek to attain, improve and then retain our state of ‘health’
– however the latter is construed. Like all therapies, philosophy is not
intrinsically valuable, but rather parasitic upon the depth of bewilderment
from which we seek liberation.83 While the world would doubtless be
‘better’ were medicine not needed, so too would it be ‘better’ were philo-
sophy not needed (which is distinct from the claim that the world would be
‘better’ were medicine and/or philosophy simply no longer practiced).84
What ultimately concerns Wittgenstein here is therefore something
broadly ethical – namely, the conceptual vulnerabilities of human beings:
When we ask on what occasions people use a word, what they say
about it, what they are right to substitute for it, and in reply try to
describe its use, we do so only insofar as it seems helpful in getting rid
of certain philosophical troubles . . . We are interested in language
only insofar as it gives us trouble. I only describe the actual use of a
word if this is necessary to remove some trouble we want to get rid of
. . . Sometimes I have to lay down new rules because new rules are less
liable to produce confusion or because we have perhaps not thought
of looking at the language we have in this light.
(Wittgenstein 1979b: 97)85
It is not our aim to refine or complete the system of rules for the use
of our words in unheard-of ways.
For the clarity that we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But
this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely
disappear.
The real discovery is the one that makes me capable of stopping
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
doing philosophy when I want to. – The one that gives philosophy
peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions which bring itself
in question. – Instead, we now demonstrate a method, by example;
and the series of examples can be broken off. – Problems are solved
(difficulties eliminated), not a single problem.
There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed
methods, like different therapies.
(1958: §133)
(1991: 532)). On this striking similarity Nussbaum has nothing to say. Yet
through this distinctly Wittgensteinian formulation she highlights an
important feature of Wittgenstein’s own philosophical project. For although
he is less explicit than Sextus regarding the non-philosophical life, Wittgen-
stein nevertheless shares something of Pyrrhonism’s yearning for a more
unaffected (and for him rather Tolstoyan) kind of existence. Indeed, as I
will argue in Chapter 3, Wittgenstein’s injunction: ‘Don’t take the example
of others as your guide, but nature!’ (1994a: 41) receives considerable
philosophical grounding in both his emphasis on the derivative nature of
the linguistic from the pre-linguistic,92 and his critique of Frazer’s anthro-
pology.93 But it is to Wittgenstein’s own understanding of the sources of
philosophical ‘disease’ that I first want to turn.
According to the Pyrrhonist, it is the propensity toward belief that gen-
erates unnecessary anxiety. Given that human life inevitably involves a
degree of suffering, believing such things to be inherently evil or of divine
orchestration simply compounds one’s misery. To evade such burdens
one must abandon belief, adopt an ethos of non-resistance and thereby
learn to bend with the flux of the world. In the Pyrrhonian schema the
source of anxiety is thus spawned from certain natural tendencies, and yet
the key to overcoming such anxieties is also located in the animal submis-
sion to natural (and to some extent cultural) forces. In short, nature is
here both curse and cure. As I said before, I am not overly concerned with
the internal coherence of this picture – of how, for example, the Pyrrhon-
ist can legitimately favor one aspect of the natural order (primitive human
drives) over another (the natural tendency toward belief). What interests
me is that a similar pattern emerges in Wittgenstein’s work. Where then,
according to him, do we find the source of philosophical ‘disquietudes’
(1958: §111)? Wittgenstein insists that the root of the problem lies in our
being ‘bewitched’ (1999: §31)94 or fascinated by certain ‘forms of expres-
sion’ (1969: 27) or ‘grammatical illusions’ (1958: §110). The new descrip-
tive philosophy is therefore characterized as a ‘fight’ (1969: 27) and
‘battle’ (1958: §109) against these tendencies.95 But why are the latter so
irresistible? It is here tempting to read Wittgenstein as laying the blame
solely at the feet of traditional philosophy, and there are indeed numer-
ous passages that support this hypothesis. To choose two particularly strik-
ing examples, he employs the following analogies:
26 Philosophy as therapy
Philosophers often behave like little children who scribble some
marks on a piece of paper at random and then ask the grown-up
‘What’s that?’ – It happened like this: the grown-up had drawn pic-
tures for the child several times and said: ‘this is a man’, ‘this is a
house’, etc. And then the child makes some marks too and asks:
what’s this then?
(1994a: 17)
‘I know that that’s a tree’, pointing to a tree that is near us. Someone
else arrives and hears this, and I tell him: ‘This fellow isn’t insane. We
are only doing philosophy . . . ’
(1999: §467)96
The aspects of things that are most important . . . are hidden because
of their simplicity and familiarity. (One is unable to notice something
– because it is always before one’s eyes.) . . . we fail to be struck by
what, once seen, is most striking and most powerful.
(1958: §129)102
As long as there is a verb ‘to be’ which seems to function like ‘to eat’
and ‘to drink’, as long as one talks about a flow of time and an
expanse of space, etc., etc., humans will continue to bump up against
the same mysterious difficulties, and stare at something that no expla-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Wittgenstein thus sees language itself as the villain insofar as it imposes mis-
leading trains of thought upon us.105 ‘Ordinary language’ is both the place to
which philosophic language must be relocated and the scene of our seduc-
tion.106 In other words, Wittgenstein presents ordinary language as simultan-
eously ‘home’ (1958: §116) and a site of estrangement or exile. The upshot
of this is that philosophical perplexity is a quite natural phenomenon. It is
not the philosopher’s language that creates such a ‘mythology,’ rather, philo-
sophy itself draws its life force both from language’s own latent ‘forms’
(1993: 199) and a ‘certain instinct’ (Moore 1993: 114) or ‘urge’ on our part
to ‘misunderstand them’ (Wittgenstein 1958: §109).107 Such urges provoke ‘a
constant battle and uneasiness’ (1993: 163),108 not least because these are dif-
ficulties ‘not . . . of the intellect, but of the will’ (ibid.: 161).109 Indeed, just ‘as
it is difficult to hold back tears, or an outburst of anger,’ so is it often difficult
‘not to use an expression’ (ibid.: 161) that confuses us.110
Although Wittgenstein says relatively little about the nature and origins
of such ‘confusions,’111 the previous passages clearly suggest that they are
not artificially constructed, but rather as natural as our disposition to cry
at the death of a loved one or stamp our feet in rage. But just as the
medical doctor need not offer hypotheses concerning the genetic basis of
the illnesses she treats, so too is it inessential for Wittgenstein to provide
analogous speculations on the underlying causes of conceptual disease.
While ‘very general facts of nature’ are relevant to his therapeutic project
(as I will argue in later chapters, they are absolutely central to its ethical
dimension), Wittgenstein insists that he is neither doing ‘natural science’
nor ‘natural history’ (1958: p. 230). Thus for both medical and Wittgen-
steinian therapists it is sufficient that they be able to point out the ways
such illnesses are transmitted and what can be done to combat them. This
is not to say that such therapists require no understanding of the under-
lying causes, but rather that this knowledge need not be especially deep.112
The general point I have wanted to highlight here is how both Sextus and
Wittgenstein maintain that the origin and (potential) cure of such dis-
eases are located within the natural realm – that is, in primitive tendencies
or urges, and the turn to a more peaceable state of non-philosophical life.
28 Philosophy as therapy
Seeing the world aright: Wittgenstein’s rhetoric
The following question arises here: Is Wittgenstein’s claim that ‘peaceful
thoughts’ are ‘what someone who philosophizes yearns for’ (1994a: 43)
itself descriptive or normative?113 Another way of formulating this is to ask
precisely whom the various appeals to ‘we’ refer to in remarks such as: ‘We
are struggling with language. We are engaged in a struggle with language’
(ibid.: 11), and ‘we may not advance any kind of theory. There must not
be anything hypothetical in our considerations. We must do away with all
explanation, and description alone must take its place’ (1958: §109)? On
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
I might say: if the place I want to get to could only be reached by way
of a ladder, I would give up trying to get there. For the place I really
have to get to is a place I must already be at now . . . Anything that I
might reach by climbing a ladder does not interest me.
(1994a: 7)126
The way to solve the problem you see in life is to live in a way that will
make what is problematic disappear . . . The fact that life is problem-
atic shows that the shape of your life does not fit into life’s mould. So
you must change the way you live and, once your life does fit into the
mould, what is problematic will disappear . . . But don’t we have the
feeling that someone who sees no problem in life is blind to some-
thing important, even to the most important thing of all? Don’t I feel
like saying that a man like that is just living aimlessly – blindly, like a
mole, and that if only he could see, he would see the problem? . . . Or
shouldn’t I say rather: a man who lives rightly won’t experience the
problem as sorrow, so for him it will not be a problem, but a joy . . . a
bright halo round his life, not a dubious background.
(1994a: 27)
The ideal, as we think of it, is unshakeable. You can never get outside
it; you must always turn back. There is no outside; outside you cannot
breathe. – Where does this idea come from? It is like a pair of glasses
on our nose through which we see whatever we look at. It never
occurs to us to take them off.
(1958: §103)
This passage is striking, not only because it presents the question of justifi-
cation and persuasion as themes of Wittgenstein’s investigations, but also
because it captures something of the rhetorical orientation of those very
investigations. But in order to explain this it is first necessary to say some-
thing about the general style of the later writings.
It is here worth reiterating that the therapies of both Sextus and
Wittgenstein ought to lead not to the theoretical solution of philosophical
problems but rather to their dissolution.138 I am not suggesting that the
methodological maneuvers made by each philosopher are identical. After
all, the standard dialectical movement philosophical texts commonly
make139 is complicated by Wittgenstein’s later ‘criss-cross’ (1958: p. ix)
style, whereas Sextus remains more obviously within the (albeit radically
curtailed) dialectical model.140 Nevertheless, even this apparent difference
is not straightforward. It could be argued that Wittgenstein’s work does
engage in some form of dialectical movement – at least of the restricted
Pyrrhonian type. For in both Wittgenstein and Sextus the first two ele-
ments of the dialectic are in operation. In Sextus’ work this is represented
in the opposition of theses (thereby demonstrating the equipollence of con-
flicting assertions, in turn leading to epoche and finally ataraxia), while in
Wittgenstein’s writings a comparable opposition appears in his strategic
employment of examples showing ‘intermediate’ (ibid.: §122) cases. Thus,
Wittgenstein speaks of the
particular peace of mind that occurs when we can place other similar
cases next to a case that we thought was unique, occurs again and
again in our investigations when we show that a word doesn’t have . . .
just one meaning (or just two), but is used in five or six different ways.
(1993: 175)
Philosophy as therapy 33
To do justice to this quasi-dialectical feature of Wittgenstein’s work would
require a detailed analysis, and I will not attempt that here. Instead, I want
to focus on the more obvious ‘fragmentary’ nature of his later writings.141
In the preface to Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein concedes:
never ceased wanting to ‘stop doing philosophy’ his own conceit barred
his way. That is, Wittgenstein’s aspirations remained essentially Pyrrhon-
ian, despite the fact that he could not manage to actualize them. (2) On a
more subtle interpretation we might say that while Wittgenstein did
indeed come to recognize the boundlessness of his new descriptive philo-
sophy, this remained not only a continual source of ‘wonder’ (Holland
1990: 22) for him but also itself a potential source of liberation from the
philosophic enterprise. While the task of philosophy now appeared infi-
nite (for why should language-games ever reach a point of static equilib-
rium, thereby providing philosophy with a determinate field of enquiry?),
that task had itself become redefined so as to allow him to embrace this
essential indeterminacy without the lamentations accompanying his
earlier Tractarian perfectionism.161 Although each of these interpretations
is distinct, they are nevertheless unified on one crucial point: that the
practical success/failure of Wittgenstein’s Pyrrhonism was ‘a difficulty
having to do with the will, rather than the intellect’ (1994a: 17).
Reconstructing the Pyrrhonian dimension of Wittgenstein’s work we
can thus summarize as follows: There is a perfectionist dimension to the
Tractatus insofar as it purports to provide a full explanation of the rela-
tionship between mind, language and world. In its strict determination of
meaning, this project should thereby bring about the conclusion of philo-
sophy. In the later writings, however, Wittgenstein’s position becomes
more complex insofar as meaning itself is no longer determinable in any a
priori sense, but instead seen as the function of a variety of language prac-
tices.162 Having thus abandoned the ‘preconceived idea of crystalline purity’
(1958: §108) of the Tractatus there was little sense in despairing that the
wheels of philosophy kept turning.163 Wittgenstein’s objective was rather
to ensure that they did not continue to turn in isolation from the actual
mechanisms of language usage.164 Whereas before there had been one
fixed, identifiable goal, now the philosopher was faced with many specific
and constantly fluid objectives. And this is why Wittgenstein (like Sextus)
makes use of the medical analogy, insisting that ‘[p]roblems are solved . . .
not a single problem,’ and that there ‘is not a philosophical method,
though there are indeed methods, like different therapies’ (ibid.: §133).
Thus far I have focused on questions pertaining to Wittgenstein’s
method, style and meta-philosophy. These are important themes that
Philosophy as therapy 37
require considerable clarification, not least because they constitute essen-
tial preparatory material for any credible investigation of more ethical-
political matters emerging from Wittgenstein’s work. It is to the latter that
I will now turn.
But this is not merely a biographical point, for Nyíri proceeds to suggest
that such a reading is ‘a necessary step toward a more complete picture of
Wittgenstein’s philosophy’ (ibid.: 45).167 On specifically methodological
matters Nyíri develops this correlation by noting Kaltenbrunner’s remarks
concerning the conservative’s general ‘distaste for . . . theory,’ their
related devotion ‘to the familiar’ (a ‘decisive preference for the experi-
ences of life as opposed to the constructions of the intellect’), and finally
that the conservative ‘always begins with that which is concrete’ (ibid.: 46).
On this reading of conservatism (which, for argument’s sake, I will not
question) the aforementioned ‘hostility’ towards theory finds its ‘most
38 Philosophy as therapy
radical expression’ in a certain ‘preference for silence’ when faced with
what is ‘concrete’ (ibid.: 47). In short: ‘the given form of life is the ulti-
mate givenness’ (ibid.: 59).168 Likewise, this time citing Grabowsky, the
conservative’s ‘ “silent reverence for the impenetrable” ’ (ibid.: 56) (which
encapsulates the very essence of the ‘conservative attitude’ (ibid.: 55)) is
aligned with Wittgenstein.169 But Nyíri is not alone in these suspicions.
Bloor similarly argues that ‘Wittgenstein’s texts show how, time and again,
he develops the characteristic themes of conservative thinkers’ (1983:
161).170 Identifying what he perceives to be the central tenets of On Cer-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
theoretical ‘solutions’ to the problems of life are simply not required, and
thus neither is the philosophical quest that seeks these as its end. Life is
neither made easier nor more valuable through philosophical theorizing;
life has been and remains entirely livable (and not merely bearable) outside
the philosophical enterprise. Thus the right way of ‘solving’ the problems
of life (and philosophy) is to dissolve them so they are no longer experi-
enced as problems. Although this therapeutic process of dissolution is
rarely easy, it ultimately has a liberating effect on one’s life, even becom-
ing a source of ‘joy’ (1994a: 27). It would therefore seem that Wittgen-
stein’s work, to the extent that it is Pyrrhonian, does lend itself to the
conservative reading outlined above. But despite this initial plausibility,
Nyíri’s and Bloor’s broad-brush approach ultimately distorts Wittgen-
stein’s mature thinking.178 For what lies at the root of these suspicions is
not Wittgenstein’s conservatism but rather his seemingly radical anti-
foundationalism. Although the correlations Nyíri and Bloor make are
interesting, their articulation of the question in such explicitly political
terms tends to divert attention from the underlying philosophical issue.
There is something ethically and politically significant about Wittgen-
stein’s later work, but it is not adequately represented by the appeal to his
alleged conservatism. Rather, it is Wittgenstein’s Pyrrhonian naturalism
that both opens his work to questions of ethics and politics and ultimately
transcends the troubling quietism displayed by the thoroughgoing
Pyrrhonist. What Nyíri and Bloor focus on is one specific – though admit-
tedly prominent – dimension of Wittgenstein’s work; namely, its apparent
quasi-communitarian anti-foundationalism. But by emphasizing Wittgen-
stein’s frequent appeals to community, tradition and training, one is
prone to overlook the deeper naturalism that both underpins and also
tempers such themes in his later writings.179
In this chapter I have already identified one aspect of Wittgenstein’s
naturalism; namely, his claim that philosophical perplexity is not merely
the symptom of philosophical speculation but rather of both ‘ordinary
language’ and our natural ‘urge’ to misunderstand its manifold functions.
It is clearly significant that Wittgenstein, like Sextus, should ultimately
locate both one’s philosophical puzzlement and potential liberation in the
natural realm. This is not, however, the most important aspect of his natu-
ralism. Rather, as intimated above, the crucial question here is to what
40 Philosophy as therapy
extent Wittgenstein’s naturalism relates to ethical-political matters? In the
next chapter I will pursue this by means of a detailed interrogation of On
Certainty. Focusing on this text is necessary for three reasons because: (1)
its continual emphasis on community, tradition and training would
appear to corroborate the general claims made by Nyíri and Bloor, (2)
here, perhaps more than anywhere else, the potential ethical-political
stakes of Wittgenstein’s mature thinking can be discerned most readily,
and (3) despite the more obviously ‘communitarian’ overtones of this text
Wittgenstein provides an important indicator as to the ethical implications
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Contempt for truth harms our civilization no less than fanatical insistence
on the truth. In addition, an indifferent majority clears the way for fanat-
ics, of whom there will always be plenty around . . . We have the right to
stand by our beliefs.
L. Kolakowski, Freedon, Fame, Lying and Betrayal
Introduction
In Chapter 1 I explored the most striking correlations between Wittgen-
stein and Pyrrhonism.1 But my primary interest there was the (apparently)
similar ethical-political implications of each therapeutic philosophy. Thus,
although the ‘conservative’ interpretation of Wittgenstein is not wholly
unfounded, I suggested that it is nevertheless inadequate. Indeed, a
detailed examination of Wittgenstein’s later writings makes it increasingly
difficult to determine any obvious political orientation therein. One
reason for this is that the quasi-communitarian reading of Wittgenstein
facilitates a number of ethical-political interpretative possibilities. It is
therefore possible to identify the roots of a liberal, pluralistic,2 and even
relativistic dimension to these texts. On other occasions (particularly, as
we will see, in his reflections on religious belief) Wittgenstein seems to
provide an apologetic for dogmatism. Any attempt to ‘politicize’ Wittgen-
stein’s work (to either identify an existent political subtext or utilize his
writings to develop a particular political agenda) must therefore handle
such interpretative possibilities carefully. We must, as it were, ensure that
we ‘put the question marks deep enough down’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 62).
42 Trusting in a world-picture
As I will argue in Chapter 3, this necessitates an investigation into the nat-
uralism underpinning Wittgenstein’s mature work. For although this
crucial dimension of his thinking is not synonymous with any specific
political outlook, it is prerequisite for ethical-political theorizing as such.
In this chapter, however, my interest lies with the apparent communitar-
ian-relativism of On Certainty – a text that (allegedly) embodies the ‘entire
categorical framework of conservative thought’ (Bloor 1983: 161–2).
Although Bloor’s claim warrants serious attention, there is too much at
stake in On Certainty which leaves the role of those specific emphases
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
tion, ‘knowledge’ and ‘doubt’ are in fact two sides of the same conceptual-
linguistic coin.18 One of Moore’s mistakes is to assume that ‘the
proposition “I know . . . ” ’ is ‘as little subject to doubt as “I am in pain” ’
(ibid.: §178).19 The crucial point here is that the grammar governing ‘I
know’ is ‘restricted’ (ibid.: §554) in a way quite foreign to Moore’s own
applications.20 (The sort of propositions Wittgenstein has in mind are:
‘here is one hand’ (ibid.: §1),21 ‘I am a human being’ (ibid.: §4),22 ‘[t]here
are physical objects’ (ibid.: §35),23 ‘the earth existed long before my birth’
(ibid.: §84),24 ‘I have spent my whole life in close proximity to the earth’
(ibid.: §93),25 ‘[m]y body has never disappeared and reappeared again
after an interval’ (ibid.: §101), and ‘all human beings have parents’ (ibid.:
§240).26) What Moore overlooks is the conditionality of the use of ‘I know,’
for he ‘forgets the expression “I thought I knew” ’ (ibid.: §12).27 To ‘know’
something entails that one can offer justification (evidence, reasons, and
so on) for that claim,28 and this is where Moore begins to go astray in his
various attempts to articulate the absolute epistemic certitude of his
propositions. In keeping with his later descriptive methodology, Wittgen-
stein is therefore concerned with how knowledge-claims are made ‘in
ordinary life’ (ibid.: §406),29 free from the ‘metaphysical emphasis’ (ibid.:
§482) philosophers often impose.30 This is why, for each of Moore’s
propositions, one ‘can imagine circumstances that turn it into a move in
one of our language-games, and by that it loses everything that is philo-
sophically astonishing’ (ibid.: §622).31 In other words, it is Moore’s
repeated application of the phrase ‘I know’ outside any specific context32
that renders it of ostensible philosophical significance. But despite this
principal confusion, Moore’s position remains worthy of philosophical
attention. His self-assurance33 may be of little interest in itself, but the
‘propositions . . . which Moore retails as examples of such known truths
are . . . interesting’ because one does not ‘arrive at any of them as a result
of investigation’ (ibid.: §§137–8).34 That is, Moore’s examples transcend
the conditionality of the language-game of knowledge and doubt,35 and
thus cannot meaningfully be doubted in ordinary circumstances.36 What
Moore erroneously concludes from this is that he therefore ‘knows’ such
propositions ‘to be true’ (Moore 1994a: 48).37 Wittgenstein, however,
refuses to subsume these types of proposition under the rubric of ‘know-
ledge’ because their epistemic status is more fundamental than Moore
Trusting in a world-picture 45
38
recognizes. Thus, Wittgenstein remarks: ‘Moore does not know what he
asserts he knows, but it stands fast for him, as also for me; regarding it as
absolutely solid is part of our method of doubt and enquiry’ (1999: §151).
One does not ‘arrive at any of [these propositions] as a result of investiga-
tion’ because they are a necessary part of what constitutes ‘an
investigation.’39 Without such propositions being immune from critical
interrogation ‘a doubt would . . . drag everything with it and plunge it into
chaos’ (ibid.: §613) – or at least change dramatically ‘the role of “mistake”
and “truth” in our lives’ (ibid.: §138). In such extreme skeptical circum-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
adds nothing to the initial gesture – or to the course of daily life in which
hands have a role – other than philosophical confusion. Thus, Moore’s
error should perhaps be located, not in his saying too much but rather in
his ‘urge’ (Wittgenstein 1958: §109) to say anything at all; in his trying to
‘express by the use of language’ (say) what is ‘embodied in . . . grammar’
(Moore 1993: 103) (shown).
If the same ‘grammar’ governs both doubt and knowledge then one
cannot – as Descartes assumes55 – choose to doubt at will. For if know-
ledge-claims demand the possibility of further justification and specific cir-
cumstances in which to operate, then so too must doubt-claims.56 Thus,
Wittgenstein maintains, one must have ‘grounds for doubt’ (1999: §122)
or ‘reasons for leaving a familiar track’ (1993: 379). But he opposes the
Cartesian method even more resolutely than this. For doubt, we are told,
is essentially parasitic upon certitude;57 if someone were to try to ‘doubt
everything’ she would ‘not get as far as doubting anything,’ for the ‘game
of doubting itself presupposes certainty’ (1999: §115):58
How does someone judge which is his right and which his left
hand? How do I know that my judgement will agree with someone
else’s? How do I know that this colour is blue? If I don’t trust myself
here, why should I trust anyone else’s judgement? Is there a why?
Must I not begin to trust somewhere? That is to say: somewhere I must
begin with not-doubting; and that is not, so to speak, hasty but excus-
able: it is part of judging.
(Wittgenstein 1999: §150)59
Answering the question: ‘Why do I not satisfy myself that I have two feet
when I want to get up from a chair?’ one cannot provide reasons or evid-
ence more certain than that which is in doubt.60 And this is why Wittgen-
stein’s own response to that question (‘[t]here is no why. I simply don’t.
This is how I act’ (ibid.: §148)) should be interpreted neither as equivoca-
tion nor – as Nyíri and Bloor would see it – as inherently ‘conservative.’ For
if someone is continually unsure about the existence of her feet, hands, or
the external world, then it would simply beg the question to suppose she
should trust her reason, senses or the testimony of a third party (or any
combination of these) in determining their existential status.61
Trusting in a world-picture 47
Moore’s examples are thus worthy of further attention insofar as they
identify the sort of propositions only upon which learning can be
‘hinged.’62 The possibility of a child learning anything depends upon a
natural orientation toward others, and specifically their first trusting or
‘believing the adult.’63 Doubt can only occur after belief,64 for ‘how could a
child immediately doubt what it is taught? That could mean only that he
was incapable of learning certain language games’ (ibid.: §283). When
learning about history a child must initially trust both what her teachers
and ‘text-books’ (ibid.: §§162, 599) tell her; she must take these to be the
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
according to Morawetz:
One’s own way of thinking is one’s only resource for recognizing the
behavior of others as ‘giving grounds’ or as ‘making judgements,’ and
it is one’s only measure for truth and falsity. To say that p is true for
someone else, someone who makes judgements in a recognizably dif-
ferent way, is no basis at all for my saying that it is true, partly true, or
something I cannot judge. The concepts one uses to describe alien
ways of thinking are one’s own concepts; one’s attitude toward the
truth and falsity of the beliefs of others is determined by one’s own
criteria for what is true. The question whether one’s own point of view
ought to have this role is really the nonsensical question whether what
I call judgement and evidence are really judgement and evidence.
(1978: 133)91
from God.’ Still, the sort of ‘testing’ advocated here is clearly not empiri-
cal or hypothetical, for no ‘result’ would ever sanction the conclusion that
God had been found wanting. The most such ‘testing’ could demonstrate
would be a failing (of faith, trust or understanding) on our part. This qual-
ification aside, obvious questions arise concerning the very possibility of
‘testing’ religious beliefs in the aforementioned way. But this is not the
point I want to pursue. Rather, what interests me is the extent to which in
even considering such a possibility one would have already misunderstood
the pivotal position such beliefs play in the religious life. Belief in the Last
Judgement ought not to be interpreted as arising from quasi-inductive
procedures – as though one was naturally led from experience to this
belief. (As Wittgenstein remarks: ‘experience does not direct us to derive
anything from experience’ (1999: §130).) Because such beliefs form ‘the
background against which [one will] distinguish between true and false’
(ibid.: §94) they play a crucial part in constituting what an individual (and
her community) will count as ‘proof,’ ‘evidence’ or a ‘valid deduction.’ 128
So, for example, an individual’s non-belief need never be undermined by a
‘visionary’ experience. The non-believer might judge such a phenomenon
to be of religious significance, and thus it might shake her world-picture at
its roots. She might subsequently seek counsel from a priest. But equally
might she judge the ‘vision’ to be of purely psychological origin, and
instead seek psychiatric advice. There is nothing in the phenomenon itself
that dictates which of these interpretations she should follow.129 Rather,
the inherited world-picture in which she has been trained and through
which she acquires her judgement-criteria will, most likely, inform her
response to the aforementioned ‘vision.’ 130 This would not be ‘hasty but
excusable,’ rather, it is an essential part of what for her constitutes
‘judging’ (ibid.: §150). This is not to deny that the non-believer’s world-
picture can be undermined by such occurrences. The point is that such
phenomena need not undermine her world-picture, for here she may
simply close her eyes to doubt. 131 The non-believer’s ‘vision’ can thus be
adequately (and, given her training, more straightforwardly) explained
without her entertaining a religious interpretation at all. There is,
however, an instructive oversimplification in this example. For experienc-
ing such a phenomenon as even negotiable (that is, subject to delibera-
tion132) will likely not be considered a legitimate option from within each
54 Trusting in a world-picture
respective world-picture.133 For the non-believer to even consider visiting a
priest for advice would likely be judged by the non-believing community
(and perhaps even herself) as demonstrating a prior ‘weakening’ toward
the religious point of view.134 Likewise, for those believers who consider
such visions as religiously significant, to even entertain the possibility of
seeking psychiatric assistance here would likely constitute a prior inclina-
tion toward the secular viewpoint (or even a sort of blasphemy). In short,
at the heart of each world-picture lies a law of prohibition against seeking
interpretative possibilities outside its own designated perimeters – or, for
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
possible.192 That is, if two parties do not possess the same criteria for
judging what constitutes a ‘blunder’ or ‘false move,’193 then the process of
‘giving reasons’ must terminate.194 At this point the prospect for non-
coercive, non-combative communication looks bleak, as one is forced to
use increasingly rhetorical means.195 The problem here does not merely
concern how a pre-established, shared criterion is to be applied (what
Lyotard calls a problem of ‘litigation’ (1988: p. xi)196), but more seriously,
the criterion itself; concerning what criterion to use and how one can justify
such a decision given that that too requires a criterion, and so on.197 If, as
On Certainty seems to suggest, one’s criteria for judgement are a central
part of one’s socialization into the world-picture(s) of a specific commun-
ity, then the terminus for rational argumentation between communities
that train their members differently will soon be reached – assuming, of
course, there is enough commonality for such argumentation to begin.198
What is therefore in question here is whether ‘making a decision’ begins
to lose its usual sense of being a rational, deliberative and justifiable pro-
cedure.199 Without recourse to some shared judgement-criterion (be it
one emerging from reason, human nature or divine Will) the process of
decision-making between world-pictures begins to look – as the Pyrrhon-
ists hoped to demonstrate – radically arbitrary. I would briefly like to illus-
trate this potential crisis of judgement with reference to Quine and, more
specifically, Kuhn.
Although Quine speaks of there being ‘much latitude of choice’
regarding ‘what statements to reevaluate in the light of . . . contrary
experience’ (1994: 42–3) (‘no statement is immune to revision,’ perhaps
not even ‘the logical law of the excluded middle’ (ibid.: 43)), he neverthe-
less yokes the pragmatic criteria of ‘efficacy’200 and ‘simplicity’ to ‘our
natural tendency to disturb the total system as little as possible’ (ibid.: 44).
Given that Quine insists that science is merely ‘a continuation of common
sense’ (ibid.: 45) – which is itself cashed-out in terms of how human
beings can most effectively work ‘a manageable structure into the flux of
experience’ (ibid.: 44) – his movement toward ontological simplicity201 in
our belief-systems is ultimately grounded in human nature and broadly
evolutionary motivations. Thus, despite the fact that Quine considers even
science’s ontology to be ‘imported into a situation’ to provide ‘convenient
intermediaries’ which are themselves ‘comparable, epistemologically, to
Trusting in a world-picture 61
the gods of Homer’ (‘the physical objects and the gods differ only in
degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conception only as
cultural posits’ (ibid.)), his pragmatic naturalism guarantees the superior-
ity of the sciences over other world-pictures. A similar, though more strik-
ing, maneuver is made in Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions – a
text notable for echoing a number of Wittgensteinian themes.202 Concern-
ing the incommensurability between scientific paradigms (and pertaining
specifically to the theory-ladenness of observation203) Kuhn makes the
apparently radical claim that ‘the proponents of competing paradigms
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
decision.
(1996: 199–200)
[W]hy should not a king be brought up in the belief that the world
began with him? And if Moore and this king were to meet and discuss,
could Moore really prove his belief to be the right one? I do not say
that Moore could not convert the king to his view, but it would be a
conversion of a special kind; the king would be brought to look at the
world in a different way.
Remember that one is sometimes convinced of the correctness of a
view by its simplicity or symmetry, i.e., these are what induce one to go
over to this point of view. One then simply says something like: ‘That’s
how it must be.’
(1999: §92)
start by discussing the awful state of the world, with its increase in
drug taking, crime, war and violence. Only if they find that the poten-
tial recruit agrees will they then proceed to hint that the only solution
to these problems is to be found in the teachings of their movement.
(Nelson 1987: 138)
With this passage in mind, I would like to develop the illustration Wittgen-
stein himself provides in §§608–12 of On Certainty. Suppose A’s ‘system of
Trusting in a world-picture 67
reference’ is scientific whereas B’s is magical; in circumstances where A
appeals to empirical research, B consults an oracle.244 During their conver-
sation A and B reach justificatory bedrock, for what A offers as ‘reasons’ in
favor of her world-picture B does not recognize as such (and vice versa).245
The quest for shared judgement-criteria has therefore failed, as each party
feels ‘inclined to say: “This is simply what I do.” ’ (Wittgenstein 1958:
§217). At this point A nevertheless feels compelled to challenge B, for it is
an integral part of A’s position to consider all alternatives as mistaken.246
She does this by providing a brief inventory of science’s most impressive
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
achievements in space travel: ‘If you want to travel to other planets,’ A pro-
claims, ‘then Western science will get you there. Magic will not.’247 To this
B happily concedes: ‘You are doubtless right, but we do not want to travel
to other planets. We see no value in doing such things.’ A might now
accuse B of simply being a ‘fool,’ not because the latter fails to recognize
the efficacy of modern science but rather because this sort of achievement
does not interest him; it has no role in B’s cultural ‘form of life.’248 If A’s argu-
ment is to have any rhetorical force then it must simultaneously persuade
B that activities such as space travel are themselves valuable,249 and as such
the appeal to scientific rationality here has a normative dimension.250 Let
me sharpen these points somewhat. Suppose the stakes were not the effi-
cacy of science vis-à-vis space travel but rather its medical achievements. A
thus confidently assures B: ‘With Western medical techniques I can cure
your children of river-blindness.’ Surely in this scenario B could legiti-
mately be condemned a ‘fool’ (or worse) for not accepting the challenge
and/or not conceding the positive results A’s procedures yield. But even
here the situation is not straightforward. First, there is no compelling epis-
temic reason why B should accept A’s challenge in the first place. What for
A constitutes river-blindness may conceivably for B represent an act of
divine retribution (akin to how some fundamentalists perceive AIDS) or
perhaps a test of faith. Where A sees needless suffering, B might see the
price paid for his ancestors’ irreligiousness, and a punishment which, if
interfered with (as A wishes to do), would constitute a sort of blas-
phemy.251 But suppose that this initial obstacle was circumvented by A’s
secretly ‘curing’ a child and presenting this test case to B. Would B then
be compelled to admit the superiority of A’s world-picture – at least
regarding matters of health? He would not. After all, this test case could be
judged a fluke occurrence, having nothing to do with A’s medical proce-
dures (a verdict frequently made by science against alleged ‘miracle heal-
ings’252). Suppose then that A ‘cures’ a number of children whilst under
the supervision of B. Throughout the process A ‘describe[s] the actual
procedure[s]’ (Wittgenstein 1999: §671) of her medical intervention,
explaining to B about infection, how the human eye functions, even
perhaps showing him microscopic evidence to support her claims.
(Indeed, A may also show B that she can repeatedly cause river-blindness
and then cure it.) Must B now concede that his own world-picture is
68 Trusting in a world-picture
deficient and therefore needs to be either revised or abandoned? Is there
any reason why he should not conclude that A’s apparent ability to restore
sight derives from some demonic force?253 Again, there is no reason why B
must make such a concession,254 for his resistance will never be epistemo-
logically unfeasible. No matter how one refines this sort of scenario B’s
determination to ‘stay in the saddle’ of his world-picture – however frus-
trating for outsiders – need never lack epistemic acumen. (Moreover,
whether or not B accepts the efficacy of A’s world-picture, this in itself need
never undermine the former’s conviction that, though effective, A’s inter-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
limp bodies, broken minds, damaged lives’ (1993: 41).259 But in order to
substantiate this claim I must first clarify a number of questions that arise
in Wittgenstein’s work pertaining to the issues of pluralism, tolerance,
exclusivism and what might be called ‘conceptual imperialism.’ In other
words, what requires more thorough investigation is the extent to which
Wittgenstein’s own methodological principle of non-interference (the
prohibition against both judging one world-picture by the standards of
another260 and of interfering with ‘the actual use of language’ (1958:
§124)261) has been explicitly applied to ethical-political matters.
3 Pluralism, justice and
vulnerability
Politicizing Wittgenstein
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
A state without plurality and a respect for plurality would be, first, a totali-
tarian state, and not only is this a terrible thing, but it does not work . . .
Finally, it would not even be a state. It would be, I do not know what, a
stone, a rock, or something like that.
J. Derrida, ‘A Word of Welcome’
Introduction
In the previous two chapters I explored the relationship between Witt-
genstein’s later work and Pyrrhonian Skepticism. In Chapter 1 I pursued
this by showing where the therapeutic strategies of Sextus and Witt-
genstein intertwine, and specifically how each is motivated by the non-
philosophical life. In Chapter 2 I extended this analysis by examining
Wittgenstein’s On Certainty – a text that Nyíri and Bloor insist betrays
fundamentally ‘conservative’ themes. At first glance On Certainty does
appear ‘conservative’ in Nyíri’s and Bloor’s sense. But such readings
remain insufficient, for a thorough examination of Wittgenstein’s later
work reveals a more unifying picture that stresses the natural ‘common
behavior of mankind’ (1958: §206). In addition to the aforementioned
‘conservative’ interpretation, it is often alleged that Wittgenstein was lat-
terly concerned with radical or ‘irreducible plurality’ (Greisch 1999: 50).
In this chapter I will argue against this view by providing a broadly
Wittgensteinian critique of certain trends in contemporary pluralistic
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 71
thinking. Having set up the analysis by examining Feyerabend’s demo-
cratic relativism, Hick’s religious pluralism, and Lyotard’s politics of ‘dis-
sensus,’ I will then turn to Wittgenstein’s reflections on embodiment. This
will enable me to demonstrate how the rhetorical force of each of the
aforementioned positions hinges on a more-or-less repressed naturalism.
and concludes (though not with Quine) that the ‘just’ society is therefore
one in which no ‘particular creed’ has more ‘rights,’ ‘power’ (ibid.: 246) or
access to resources than any other. This is not to deny Western reason its
place. Rather:
[O]ne thing must be avoided at all costs: the special standards which
define special subjects and special professions must not be allowed to
permeate general education and they must not be made the defining
property of a ‘well-educated person’. General education should
prepare a citizen to choose between the standards, or to find his way in a
society that contains groups committed to various standards but it must
under no condition bend his mind so that it conforms to the standards of one
particular group.
(Feyerabend 1988: 167)11
stitutes the ‘best option’ (and, not least, the genuinely ‘ethical-political’) will
be one of the most fundamental differences between such traditions.
Feyerabend’s political theorizing is hopelessly simplistic. Nevertheless, the
issues with which he attempts to grapple emerge in the work of other
philosophers more directly associated with social-political matters – those,
for example, explicitly concerned with contemporary religious pluralism.16
Thus, in Hick’s writings we find an analogous tension emerge between
respect for religious traditions as they are, and the endorsement of (or at
least ‘hope’ (1977: 183) for) pluralistic tolerance in a violently sectarian
world.17 It is to this more focused type of pluralism that I will now turn.
Hick is correct to insist that there is nothing a priori violent or homoge-
nizing about the idea of pluralism, and that any shortcomings of the plu-
ralistic hypothesis must not simply be assumed to be part of a broader
Western ‘imperialism.’18 Indeed, in this regard it is important to acknow-
ledge that the genealogy of pluralism, at least in its various religious mani-
festations,19 is historically and culturally better established than is
commonly assumed.20 Nevertheless, Hick concedes that in recent times
the West has been forced to recognize the presumptuousness of any
claims it may have made regarding its own ‘moral superiority’ (1995: 14).
As such, contemplative Christians have had to accept that the fruits of the
spirit ‘do not occur more abundantly’ (ibid.: 16) within Christianity than
other faiths. This awareness, coupled with the promising fact that these
‘religions are now meeting one another in a new way as parts of the one
world of our common humanity,’ leads Hick to conclude that the ‘reli-
gious imperialism’ (1977: 182) hitherto endorsed by traditional Christian
theology (which, at best, only pitied those of other faiths) is in desperate
need of revision.21 It is no longer legitimate to claim that ‘all who are
saved are saved by Jesus of Nazareth.’ What the enlightened Christian can
say ‘gladly’ is that the ‘Ultimate Reality has effected human consciousness
for its liberation or “salvation” in various ways’ within a multiplicity of
cultural-religious ‘forms of life’ (ibid.: 181).22
The main tension within Hick’s position is worth exploring because it is
pertinent to many of the themes discussed in Chapters 1 and 2. I am not,
therefore, concerned with the finer details of how Hick proposes to revise
the traditional, exclusivist theological perspective.23 What concerns me is
the essentially normative trajectory his pluralism takes, despite his
74 Pluralism, justice and vulnerability
attempts to secure it in ‘the facts of the history of religions’ (1995: 51).
For while Hick rejects the idea of an homogenizing ‘new global religion’
(ibid.: 41), and speaks instead in quasi-Wittgensteinian terms of leaving
‘the different traditions just as they are’ (ibid.: 41–2),24 he nevertheless
admits that his own pluralism violates the exclusivist self-image of both
traditional Christian theology and numerous other religions.25 On this
point Hick is clearly troubled by the resurgence of fundamentalism,26 and
even speculates that Christianity may soon be divided into two factions:
one liberal, the other fundamentalist, with each side ‘seeing the other as a
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
have thus shown how pluralism – at least in this specific form – lacks rhet-
orical force and ultimately only addresses those who are already sympa-
thetic to its general principles and aims.42 That our differences can be
simultaneously resolved and respected is the central dilemma facing any
such political-religious project. For identifying what differences one can
sacrifice (or legitimately demand the other to sacrifice) for the sake of
pluralistic harmony, without thereby jeopardizing the singularity of one’s
own (or the other’s) position, is precisely what differentiates each position
in the first place. Indeed, to this extent there is no better propaganda for
the exclusivist and pluralist (respectively) than the practices and pro-
nouncements of the other. Each could address their respective audiences by
showing them the alternative world-picture and rhetorically inquiring: Is
this really what you think God wants?
What inspires Hick’s pluralism is a deep respect for ‘the peace and
diversity of the human family’ (1995: 118). Thus, underpinning his assault
on exclusivism, lies an appeal to a ‘common humanity’ (1977: 182) of
which we are all a part, despite the differences between our historical,
political, ethical and religious practices and status. Surin correctly identi-
fies this unifying backdrop to Hick’s narrative, but proceeds to condemn
him for neglecting to notice that ‘this ahistorical affirmation of “a
common human history” is . . . irredeemably ideological.’ Indeed, in post-
Enlightenment culture there is no more effective way of veiling real social-
political injustices than to dress one’s theorizing ‘in the garbs of a
universalistic “pluralism” ’ (Surin 1990: 120).43 Surin’s caution is not
wholly unreasonable, for what lies at the heart of every pluralism is the
belief that the categories of ‘plurality’ and ‘unity’ cannot be straightfor-
wardly dissociated.44 Nevertheless, that the conception of a ‘common
humanity’ both can be and has been45 used as an ideological weapon of
oppression does not mean that it is an inherently oppressive notion.46 It is,
after all, singularly difficult to think of any principle (including Surin’s
respect for the ‘intractable “otherness” of the Other’ (ibid.: 126) and
desire to ‘safeguard’ this unique ‘strangeness’ (ibid.: 125)) that could not
be used to facilitate political violence, oppression or indifference.47 I will
return to this point later. First, however, I want to develop Surin’s sugges-
tion that the very notion of a ‘human family’ is simply part of a more clan-
destine attempt at cultural-political-conceptual homogenization (and is
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 77
thus itself inherently exclusivist). I will do this with reference to Lyotard’s
more radical pluralistic vision.48
or ‘religions’ (as Hick does) the degree to which these are represented as
either fundamentally incommensurable or unified will determine the sort of
ethical-political conclusions one reaches. Of course, by definition all plu-
ralisms concede a degree of plurality within the social arena. But whether
this plurality is ultimately judged to be of an irreducible sort (as Surin
advises it should be judged49) is another matter. Thus, Hick’s acknowledg-
ment of the ‘given’ multiplicity of religious traditions is tempered by what
he sees as their mutual concern with human salvation and the elimination
of egocentrism, and a shared ‘human family’ of which all ‘the great world
faiths’ (1995: 17) are a part. These criteria enable Hick to demarcate
‘genuine’ religiosity from the manifold dangers of absolutism. But, as pre-
viously discussed, by this demarcation Hick marginalizes from the start those
for whom his discourse is presumably intended; namely, religious exclu-
sivists. According to a more radical form of pluralism, however, this tem-
pering of singularity by positing a ‘common humanity’ is precisely what
the question of social-political justice hinges on. For here the task is to
‘define a pluralism of radical separation, a pluralism in which the plurality
is not that of a total community, that of cohesion or coherence of the
whole’ (Derrida 1999b: 96). Thus, like Feyerabend, Lyotard employs a
number of Wittgensteinian themes50 in order to emphasize the fragmenta-
tion of contemporary social life and thereby pose the question of how we
are to conceive and deploy justice when ‘the position of the other remains
always irreducibly other’ (Barron 1992: 31). In response to this dilemma
Lyotard advocates a ‘pagan’ attitude of ‘acceptance . . . that one can play
several games, and that each of these games is interesting in itself insofar
as the interesting thing is to play moves.’ The pagan thereby tries ‘to
invent new games,’ ‘figure out new moves’ previously ‘unexpected and
unheard of,’ and even ‘move from one game to another’ (1985: 61).51
What is characteristic of the non-pagan is their tendency to ‘stick to [their]
signified’ and ‘think that they are in the true’ (ibid.: 62).52 Such self-
assured dogmatism is misplaced because, while language-games are
indeed given, the way one proceeds to ‘play’ them remains essentially
open.53 On the basis of this radical individuation of language-games
Lyotard thus proceeds to define ‘oppression’ in terms of the proclivity (of
non-pagans) to ‘import into a language game a question that comes from
another one and to impose it’ (ibid.: 53).54 The question of justice arises
78 Pluralism, justice and vulnerability
because political efficacy demands that language-games employ the same
conceptual vocabulary; the language of a ‘common humanity’ or universal
‘we.’55 The implicit injunction in traditional politics is thus ‘be operational
(that is, commensurable) or disappear,’ and this, we are warned,
inevitably ‘entails a certain level of terror’ (1997a: xxiv).56 According to
Lyotard, then, the most fundamental ethical-political right is the right to be
other; to ‘play’ different games or the same games differently.57 Any state
that confines its members to specific, pre-established narratives is – albeit
surreptitiously – essentially totalitarian.58
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
undeserving of a voice.
Lyotard’s work presents one attempt to conceptualize an instance of
‘two principles’ meeting that ‘cannot be reconciled with one another,’
where each party simply declares ‘the other a fool and heretic’ (Wittgen-
stein 1999: §611). If, as Lyotard maintains, the imposition of the rules of
one language-game upon another is ‘inherent to oppression’ (1985: 53),
then, conversely, respect for ‘difference’ is the core of justice itself. What
must be resisted is the temptation to consider one’s own practices to be
either fixed once and for all or (whether ‘fixed’ or not) inherently supe-
rior to the practices of others. In short, what should be avoided is the
assumption ‘that one’s own village and strange customs it contains are the
navel of the world’ (Feyerabend 1987: 28). Lyotard’s concern to avoid
linguistic-conceptual domination70 – and thereby ‘bear witness to’71 the
absolute ‘heterogeneity of language games’ (1997a: xxv) – thus highlights
the possible ethical-political significance of Wittgenstein’s later work. I
have thus far remained uncritical of Lyotard’s politicization of Wittgen-
stein. But I would now like to consider one particularly striking example
of how Lyotard’s ‘pagan justice’ or ‘politics of dissensus’ has been applied
by Readings – one of his chief exponents. This will enable me to focus crit-
ical attention on the Lyotardian project toward the end of the chapter.
Taking Herzog’s Where the Green Ants Dream as his inspiration, Readings
claims that what this film highlights is the incommensurability between
‘Aborigines and . . . liberal capitalist democracy’ (1992: 171). In its por-
trayal of a dispute between the Aborigines and a local mining company
regarding land ownership, Herzog’s film ‘does not represent an other so
much as bear witness to an otherness to representation, a différend’ (ibid.:
176). Readings proceeds to summarize Where the Green Ants Dream in typ-
ically Lyotardian fashion:
[T]he dispute . . . takes place at the edge of the Empire, in the Aus-
tralian desert, on a site which is at the same time central to the polit-
ical struggles currently animating the west: the rights of indigenous
peoples in the wake of the Empire. In the course of the film a radical
aporia in legal arbitration appears as a structural necessity of the mod-
ernist insistence on the representability of the human and the possi-
bility of universal justice . . . Where the Green Ants Dream shows that
80 Pluralism, justice and vulnerability
ethical responsibility demands a quasi-aesthetic experimentation if
justice is to be done to an Aboriginal claim . . . Doing justice is a
matter of experimentation rather than of corresponding to models.
(1992: 172–3)
The plaintiff and defendant ‘do not merely speak different languages,
they participate in utterly incommensurable language games’ (ibid.: 180)
– an incommensurability that becomes apparent in, for example, the Abo-
riginal understanding of temporal and spatial relations73 and methods of
enumeration.74 But most crucial is how the Aborigines conceive their rela-
tion to the ‘sacred land, where the green ants dwell,’ for they ‘belong to
the land’ in a quite specific way: ‘Not belong to the land: there is no possi-
bility of even a thought of separation or abstraction. They can’t be trans-
planted, immigrate elsewhere. They have no abstract human nature that
would survive in another place, anywhere else’ (ibid.: 183). Due to the
Enlightenment (and hence liberal) dream that ‘all difference can be over-
come’ by reference to the ‘universal language’ or ‘ “common law” of
humanity,’75 the Aboriginal voices are effectively silenced. It is not that the
court openly forbids the Aborigines from speaking, but that, despite the
‘sham’ (ibid.: 181) of their being permitted a legal voice, in its very
demand for a ‘unitary “we” ’ (ibid.: 180) the other’s language-game is
inevitably suppressed. Thus, one might say, the Aborigines are rendered
conceptually mute. The implicit command of the court is ‘speak as we do!’
for without this much commonality, understanding and the goal of
mutual compromise become impossible.76 For Readings, the injustice of
the trial emerges from the untranslatability of the language of the Aborig-
ines into that of ‘common law,’ and thus of ‘common humanity.’
Although an ‘encounter takes place, it happens’ there is ‘no language
available [in which] to phrase it’ (ibid.: 183). What Herzog’s film bears
witness to ‘is not an incidental act of injustice’ but rather ‘the necessary,
structurally implicit terror that accompanies the encounter of a people
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 81
that says “we” with a community that is not modern, that doesn’t think
itself as a people’ (ibid.: 184). The ‘paradox that arises is that neither side
is wrong,’ for ‘ “We” have no way of saying who is right here, the mining
company or the Aborigines. No “we” can pronounce once and for all on
their dispute. All we can do . . . is to try to tell another story,’ namely ‘one
that doesn’t seek to synthesize or assimilate them but to keep the dispute
and the difference an open question’ (ibid.: 185).77 What Lyotard’s
‘paganism’ thus demands is a movement away from a politics that seeks to
absorb the other and deny radical difference. In much the same way as
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Surin criticizes Hick, for both Lyotard and Readings the ‘suggestion that
all cultures are fundamentally the same is the trade mark of the imperial-
ism of modernity.’ The real challenge of contemporary politics is how ‘to
think liberation otherwise than as an abstraction into ever more splendid
(more universal) isolation’; that is, of how to rethink ‘the notion of
community under the horizon of dissensus rather than of consensus’
(ibid.: 184).
As Readings’s synopsis of Where the Green Ants Dream suggests, the waters
of incommensurability may indeed be abyssal, but the question remains:
are they unfathomable? In my analysis of On Certainty in Chapter 2 I showed
how Moore misconstrues the epistemic status of his ‘hinge’ propositions.
Keeping this in mind I now want to explore why Readings’s conclusions
are premature, for what requires further analysis is the possibility of there
being ethical foundations (analogous to the trans-epistemic foundations
Moore inadvertently draws attention to) upon which human interaction is
‘hinged.’ If such ethical foundations can indeed be identified then this
would not only facilitate a more comprehensive understanding of those
anxieties intermittently haunting Wittgenstein’s own work (notably On
Certainty), it would also curb Surin’s worries concerning Hick’s religious
pluralism and, more crucially, reveal why the Lyotardian position is unten-
able. The best way of negotiating these issues is, indirectly, through
Wittgenstein’s alleged anti-foundationalism, for this reading of his later
work naturally lends itself to such theoretical extravagances as Feyer-
abend’s naive relativism and Readings’s Lyotardian ‘paganism.’ As will
become clear, however, this anti-foundationalist reading is both inaccu-
rate and unsound.
A succinct example of the aforementioned position can be found in
Greisch’s recent work. For there we are told that ‘Wittgenstein developed
the theory of the irreducible plurality of language games anchored in
“forms of life” ’ where he hoped ‘to resolve the difficult question of values
in terms of plurality,’ whereas (for example) ‘Husserl strove towards some
kind of teleological unity’ (1999: 46).78 According to this synopsis, then,
Wittgenstein’s later writings revolve around the notion of ‘irreducible plu-
rality.’ Thus, having outlined Werner Marx’s work on the primacy of ‘sym-
pathy’ as a ‘unifying principle’ (ibid.: 50) in ethics, Greisch somberly
concludes:
82 Pluralism, justice and vulnerability
[A]nyone who is familiar with the thought of the later Wittgenstein
will have difficulty sharing the optimism of [Werner Marx] who calcu-
lates that an ethics of compassion appears capable of surmounting the
heterogeneity of language games and the corresponding forms of life.
(1999: 58)
Here Wittgenstein is clear that, even when faced with cultural difference –
even where language practices are seemingly incommensurable – one is not
entirely at a loss. Despite the manifold divergences between one’s own
culture and that of another, the ‘common behavior of mankind’ is never-
theless capable of breaking through the mutual bewilderment83 (indeed,
without this underlying commonality it would be impossible to learn
another’s language). Encountering another culture is patently not the
same as finding oneself amidst a colony of alien beings who lacked an
even vaguely determinate bodily form or behavioral repertoire.84 Aside
from extreme borderline cases, one immediately distinguishes the human
from the non-human,85 and this reaction is deeply rooted in our ‘natural
history’ (ibid.: §25).86 It is of course true that, for example, after a road
accident it may be difficult to distinguish the driver’s body from the wreck-
age. Gross disfigurement – and perhaps especially of the face87 – clearly
can make such identification less than ‘immediate.’ But such hesitancy is
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 83
not only relatively exceptional, it is particularly horrific precisely because
such identification requires deliberation. This natural ‘immediacy’ in
inter-personal relations effectively means that taking a hypothetical atti-
tude toward others only occurs in highly ‘abnormal’ circumstances. And
this is why Wittgenstein demarcates between having ‘an attitude towards a
soul’ and merely being ‘of the opinion that [someone] has a soul’ (ibid.:
p. 178).88 For what it actually means to ‘believe that men have souls’ lies in
the practical application of this ‘picture’ (ibid.: §422).89 However, in order
to appreciate both the ethical significance of these remarks and what con-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
The meaning of saying that someone (or some ‘thing’) ‘has a soul’ is again
manifested, not in one’s hypothetical beliefs but rather through one’s general
orientation toward them.124 In other words, to ‘believe that men have souls’
lies in the application of this ‘picture’ (ibid.: §422), and this is why ‘[m]y atti-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
tude towards him is an attitude towards a soul. I am not of the opinion that he
has a soul’ (ibid.: p. 178).125 Given this deeply non-hypothetical characteriza-
tion of ‘attitude,’ it is clear why such a ‘picture’ is central to our sense of
ethical concern for others who are ‘mortal . . . [and] vulnerable to misfor-
tune’ (Gaita 2000: 239).126 Contrary to Surin, Lyotard and Readings there is
something primordially significant about the human form – so much so that
it determines the limits of what or who the concepts ‘pain,’ ‘consciousness’
and ‘soul’ can be meaningfully attributed to.127 That people campaign for the
rights of non-human animals and the unborn fetus is not unintelligible, even
to those who passionately disagree.128 It is not as though such individuals were
campaigning for the rights of carpets or iron filings – which clearly would
raise questions concerning what such ‘rights’ could possibly amount to.129
Indeed, it is in this sense that caution is needed when speaking of the
‘intractable “otherness” of the Other’ (Surin 1990: 126).130 For any criterion
that proscribes such markedly peculiar claims about the ‘rights’ of carpets and
iron filings would be enough to incur limitations on the very notion of the
radically ‘other.’131
Our responsiveness to others should not, however, be construed as
deliberative,132 or resulting from a reasoning ‘by analogy’ (Wittgenstein
1990: §537).133 Rather, we must ‘remember that it is a primitive reaction to
tend, to treat, the part that hurts when someone else is in pain; and not
merely when oneself is’:
But what is the word ‘primitive’ meant to say here? Presumably that
this sort of behavior is pre-linguistic: that a language-game is based on
it, that it is the prototype of a way of thinking and not the result of
thought.
‘Putting the cart before the horse’ may be said of an explanation
like the following: we tend someone else because by analogy with our
own case we believe that he is experiencing pain too . . .
(Wittgenstein 1990: §§540–2)
In other words:
None of this is to deny that there are times when the meaning and sincerity
of another’s behavior is in question,135 but rather to suggest that in prin-
ciple: ‘ “I can only believe that someone else is in pain, but I know it if I am” ’
is only to say that ‘one can make the decision to say “I believe he is in pain”
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
instead of “He is in pain”. But that is all . . . Just try – in a real case – to
doubt someone else’s fear or pain’ (1958: §303).136 To reiterate a familiar
Wittgensteinian theme from Chapter 2, in such circumstances one needs
‘reasons for leaving a familiar track,’ for ‘[d]oubt is a moment of hesitation
and is, essentially, an exception to the rule’ (1993: 379).137 That is:
This, then, is why the amoralist’s demand for cogent ‘reasons’ why they
should care about anything or anyone is so troubling. For, as Williams
puts it: ‘it is very unclear that we can in fact give the man who asks it a
reason – that, starting from so far down, we could argue him into caring
about something.’ What such a person requires is ‘help, or hope, not rea-
sonings’ (1973: 17).146 If the amoralist is (in a quasi-Pyrrhonian sense147)
‘at a loss’ as to why the needless suffering of children is a tragedy, then ini-
tially one must ask whether some tragedy has befallen them; whether their
life has been damaged in such a way that they cannot feel ‘the force of
pity’ (Nuyen 2000: 421).148 Reactions of moral indifference often bear
witness to temporary moral exhaustion. While there are obvious correla-
tions between the symptoms of exhaustion and amoralism, and while the
former provides a fairly secure route to the latter, to find oneself buckling
under the weight of others’ suffering should not be confused with the per-
sistent indifference displayed by the genuine amoralist. Here we need to
distinguish, and in turn respond to, what is effectively an appeal for assis-
tance. If, as Wittgenstein suggests, belief in predestination is ‘less a theory
than a sigh, or a cry’ (often born from ‘the most dreadful suffering’
(1994a: 30)), then much the same might be said of extreme moral skepti-
cism.149 In this sense then even the genuine amoralist does not challenge
the authority of morality.150 Amoralism does not provide grounds for a
radical critique of our normal moral reactions and sensibilities. Nor does
it establish grounds for our becoming skeptical. On the contrary, the
provocation of amoralism lies in its capacity to call our own potential for
moral responsiveness into question.151 That is, what the amoralist chal-
lenges is the ‘good conscience’ we may harbor regarding our own compe-
tence at helping the helpless or giving hope to the hopeless. Morality is far
from being undermined here, for we are, implicitly, being petitioned to
be more moral – probably more than we can bear. In this respect the
genuine amoralist is the most helpless and hopeless individual one is ever
likely to encounter.
Mindful of these points it becomes clear why the idea of a ‘moral
community’ is fundamentally dissimilar to, for example, that of a ‘scient-
ific community’ or ‘artistic community.’ As Winch rightly notes: ‘there
could not be a human society which was not also, in some sense, a moral
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 89
community.’ Moral concern cannot adequately be described as either a
‘form of activity’ or – as Lyotard suggests – a ‘form of life’ (or ‘language-
game’) which one may choose to either partake in or ignore.152 Rather,
moral problems ‘force themselves on you’ insofar as they emerge from the
‘common life between men and do not presuppose any particular forms
of activity in which men engage together’ (Winch 1960: 239–40).153 What
constitutes suffering is not primarily an epistemic or hypothetical matter;
it is central to the natural life of human beings. The other’s suffering com-
mands us to help, his misery ‘calls for action: his wounds must be tended’
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
[I]f anyone believes that certain concepts are absolutely the correct
ones, and that having different ones would mean not realizing some-
thing that we realize – then let him imagine certain very general facts
of nature to be different from what we are used to, and the formation
of concepts different from the usual ones will become intelligible to
him.
(1958: p. 230)162
In short, the concepts and practices we have are not a priori necessary or
determined. This implies two things: (1) given the facts of our actual
natural history, a considerable degree of conceptual variety is nevertheless
possible, and (2) were this natural history different then so too would our
present concepts and practices. In effect what we are presented with here
is simultaneously a recognition of cultural diversity and a commitment to
the basic commonality of human life as it is ‘given.’163 It is in large part the
philosophical-anthropological necessity of maintaining this dual emphasis
that ‘Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough’ addresses.
For Wittgenstein the central problem with Frazer’s anthropology is its
implicit scientism, and specifically Frazer’s tendency toward interpretation
and explanation. According to Wittgenstein the ‘very idea of wanting to
explain a [religious] practice . . . seems wrong’ (1996a: 61), for one should
‘only describe and say: this is what human life is like’ (ibid.: 63). Echoing
numerous other passages in his later writings,164 Wittgenstein here high-
lights both his ontological commitments regarding the ‘givenness’ of lan-
guage practices and how this ought to determine the philosophical
enterprise insofar as we cannot explain why a certain form of life exists,
‘[a]ll we can do is to describe it – and behold it!’ (Malcolm 1993: 76).165
Having ‘put the question mark deep enough down’ (having gone ‘right
down to the foundations’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 62)) explanatory and justi-
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 91
ficatory discourse ‘comes to an end’ (1999: §204). At this point ‘all one
can say is: where that practice and these views occur together, the practice
does not spring from the view, but they are both just there’ (1996a: 62).
That ‘the practice does not spring from the view’ is an important and
recurrent theme in ‘Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough,’ not least because
Frazer misrepresents ‘the magical and religious views of mankind’ as
pseudo-scientific ‘errors’ or ‘pieces of stupidity.’166 But, Wittgenstein insists,
religious and magical rituals can only be ‘erroneous’ to the extent that
they ‘set forth a theory’ (ibid.: 61) and thereby constitute hypothetical
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
explanations.
(1996a: 65–6)
What Frazer thus fails to appreciate is the nature of the ‘kinship’ between
‘those savages’ behavior’ (ibid.: 70) and ‘any genuine religious action of
today’ (ibid.: 64). In other words: ‘All these different practices show that it
is not a question of the derivation of one from the other, but of a
Pluralism, justice and vulnerability 93
175
common spirit’ (ibid.: 80) or a ‘general inclination’ (ibid.: 78) – that is,
natural propensities that relate to Wittgenstein’s various remarks on ‘prim-
itive behaviors’ and ‘instinct reactions’ previously discussed. One might
therefore say that the initiation and longevity of religious rituals are
dependent upon their ability to bear witness to the most basic tendencies
and concerns of human beings,176 and thus are not, as Frazer construes
them, rooted in confused quasi-scientific conjectures. Frazer’s mistake is
to take instrumental, means–ends oriented actions to be the archetype of
all meaningful human activities. Assessing ritual activities in this way
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
That a people, as a people, ‘should accept those who come and settle
among them – even though they are foreigners,’ would be the proof [gage]
of a popular and public commitment [engagement], a political res publica
that cannot be reduced to a sort of ‘tolerance,’ unless this tolerance
requires the affirmation of a ‘love’ without measure.
J. Derrida, ‘A Word of Welcome’
‘There is neither God nor the Good, but there is goodness’ – which is also
my thesis. That is all that is left to mankind . . . There are acts of stupid,
senseless goodness.
E. Levinas, Is It Righteous To Be?
discussion, I would briefly like to comment on two passages; the first from
Wittgenstein’s Zettel, the second from Levinas’s ‘Meaning and Sense.’
In accordance with much of what Wittgenstein says in On Certainty
about ‘stay[ing] in the saddle’ (1999: §616) of belief and our learning ‘not
one proposition but a nest of propositions’ (ibid.: §225), in Zettel he
remarks:
If someone does not believe in fairies, he does not need to teach his
children ‘There are no fairies’: he can omit to teach them the word
‘fairy’. On what occasion are they to say: ‘There are . . . ’ or ‘There are
no . . . ’? Only when they meet people of the contrary belief.
(1990: §413)
it a unique sense.
(1996a: 46)
Keeping §413 of Zettel in mind, what Levinas says here concerning the
acquisition of natural languages might equally be applied to Wittgen-
stein’s ‘world-pictures.’ That is, the question Levinas provokes is: How are
we to understand one’s peaceful ‘orientation’ toward another’s world-
picture? How are we to make sense of the fact that, very often, encounter-
ing a world-picture that differs from one’s own does not lead to our
‘declaring it to be barbarian,’ but rather to our ‘preferring speech to
war’?4 As Levinas points out elsewhere:
[T]he great problem placed in the path of those who expect the end
of violence starting from a dialogue that would only need to perfect
knowledge is the difficulty . . . of bringing to this dialogue opposed
beings inclined to do violence to each other. It would be necessary to
find a dialogue to make these beings enter into dialogue.
(1998a: 142)5
Introduction
In Chapter 3 I explored both the natural limits that frame intersubjectivity
and how even the ‘radical’ pluralism of Surin, Lyotard and Readings
necessarily presupposes such boundaries. While Wittgenstein’s later work
seems to emphasize the ‘irreducible plurality of language-games’ (Greisch
1999: 50), this appearance is deceptive. For while the diversity of cultural
practices should not be underestimated, the basis for any recognition and
understanding of such practices (even as ‘cultural practices’) lies in those
‘fundamental notions’ that ‘determine the “ethical space,” within which
the possibilities of good and evil in human life can be exercised’ (Winch
1964: 322). When faced with contemporary theorizing of ‘otherness’ and
‘radical difference’ we should therefore remember that in any justifiable
designation ‘other culture’ one has already identified ‘the other’ in some
minimally intelligible way.1 For radical pluralists like Surin, Lyotard and
Readings such identification constitutes a violation of the other’s alterity
102 Wretchedness without recompense
insofar as it (allegedly) renders her essentially a reflection of oneself. On
this account the other’s ‘absolute singularity’ is degraded in the positing
of a more-or-less homogeneous ‘we.’ But, as Derrida notes, we should be
careful when condemning this as ‘violence,’ for it is ‘at the same time non-
violence, since it opens the relation to the other’ (1997c: 128–9).2 That is,
this ‘preethical violence’ (ibid.: 128)3 marks the very beginning of ethics,
politics and justice.4 The purpose of the following two chapters is to
determine: (1) how the ethical and political are constituted through
such an ineliminable ‘violence,’ and (2) what this ‘violence’ amounts
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
‘These people rigorously hold the opinion (or view) that there is a
Last Judgement’. ‘Opinion’ sounds queer.
It is for this reason that different words are used: ‘dogma’, ‘faith’.
We don’t talk about hypothesis, or about high probability. Nor
about knowing.
In a religious discourse we use such expressions as: ‘I believe that
so and so will happen,’ and use them differently to the way in which
we use them in science.
(1994b: 57)15
Wittgenstein thus warns that between the respective claims of believer and
non-believer lies a vast conceptual-linguistic chasm. There is in fact no
‘contradiction’ (ibid.: 53) here because such people ‘think entirely differ-
ently’; they have ‘different pictures’ (ibid.: 55) or an ‘entirely different
kind of reasoning’ (ibid.: 58).16 He proceeds:
Wretchedness without recompense 105
If some[one] said: ‘Wittgenstein, do you believe in this?’ I’d say: ‘No.’
‘Do you contradict the man?’ I’d say: ‘No.’
If you say this, the contradiction already lies in this.
Would you say: ‘I believe the opposite’, or ‘There is no reason to
suppose such a thing’? I’d say neither.
Suppose someone were a believer and said: ‘I believe in a Last
Judgement,’ and I said: ‘Well, I’m not sure. Possibly.’ You would say
that there is an enormous gulf between us. If he said ‘There is a
German aeroplane overhead,’ and I said ‘Possibly. I’m not so sure,’
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
stein’s point is that not only are our respective epistemologies not
‘fundamentally’ (1996a: 74) different42 but, more crucially, neither is the
religious-ritualistic life of the ‘primitive’ so far removed from our own
‘civilized’ existence. Their practices may seem at odds with those of
modern Western society, but scratch the surface of the latter and one
soon finds the same non-instrumental, ritual activities that are (to the
Western eye) more immediately conspicuous in the former.43
What I referred to above as Wittgenstein’s project of ‘reconciliation’ is
not therefore merely of biographical import concerning his own self-
understanding (though it may indeed begin there44). Other religious
believers and non-believers alike (not to mention radical pluralists like
Surin, Lyotard and Readings) would benefit from reminding themselves
that, despite the linguistic-conceptual gulf that sometimes divides human
beings, there nevertheless remain natural grounds upon which mutual
understanding can be built – though, of course, ‘peaceable’ intercourse
can never be guaranteed.45 This is not, as it is for Frazer, simply to render
‘foreign’ practices palatable to people who think as we do.46 Rather, such
‘connecting links’ between the life of religious belief and non-belief (or
between different faiths, cultures, and so on) demonstrate the ‘common
spirit’ (ibid.: 80) we share as human beings. But neither is this to suggest
that religious practices can simply be reduced to primitive human activ-
ities.47 Such a position would not only render Wittgenstein’s account
fundamentally atheistic, it would also underestimate the inherent com-
plexities of such practices as they have hitherto developed and continue to
change.48 Maintaining that ritual is not an activity peculiar to the explicitly
‘religious’ sphere – but rather finds a place in many regions of human
life49 – is not to trivialize religious rituals in their particularity but simply to
deny their radical singularity. For without rooting such activities in ‘primi-
tive’ human tendencies they would become irredeemably alien phenom-
ena, and as such unidentifiable as ‘religious rituals’ – or indeed as ‘rituals’
of any sort.
This, then, is how Wittgenstein’s naturalism feeds into his account of
religious belief. It also suggests how Wittgenstein’s later work need not be
silent regarding questions of social justice. But, as previously suggested,
this naturalism leads him to a distinctly ethical interpretation of specific
religious concepts. It is to these that I will now turn.
Wretchedness without recompense 109
Immortality and ethical responsibility
Regarding the notion of immortality, Wittgenstein elucidates further his
reason for hesitancy between assent and dissent:
‘If you don’t cease to exist, you will suffer after death’, there I begin to
attach ideas, perhaps ethical ideas of responsibility. The point is, that
although these are well-known words, and although I can go from one
sentence to another sentence, or to pictures [I don’t know what con-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
A great writer said that, when he was a boy, his father set him a task,
and he suddenly felt that nothing, not even death, could take away
the responsibility [in doing this task]; this was his duty to do, and that
even death couldn’t stop it being his duty. He said that this was, in a
way, a proof of the immortality of the soul – because if this lives on
[the responsibility won’t die.]
(1994b: 70)52
This was not an isolated remark, for Malcolm similarly recalls Wittgenstein
suggest that ‘a way in which the notion of immortality can acquire a
meaning is through one’s feeling that one has duties from which one
cannot be released, even by death’ (1958: 71):
Suppose somebody made this guidance for this life: believing in the
Last Judgement. Whenever he does anything, this is before his mind.
In a way, how are we to know whether to say he believes this will
happen or not?
Asking him is not enough. He will probably say he has proof. But
he has what you might call an unshakeable belief. It will show, not by
reasoning or by appeal to ordinary grounds for belief, but rather by
regulating for all in his life.
. . . Suppose you had two people, and one of them, when he had to
decide which course to take, thought of retribution, and the other did
not. One person might, for instance, be inclined to take everything
that happened to him as a reward or punishment, and the other
person doesn’t think of this at all.
(1994a: 53–4)59
If someone who believes in God looks around and asks ‘Where does
everything I see come from?’, ‘Where does all this come from?’, he is not
craving for a (causal) explanation; and his question gets its point from
being the expression of a certain craving. He is, namely, expressing an
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
I believe the best way of describing [this feeling] is to say that when I
have it I wonder at the existence of the world. And I am then inclined to
use such phrases as ‘how extraordinary that anything should exist’ or
‘how extraordinary that the world should exist.’
(1993: 41)
notion of immortality does denote the continuation of the self beyond the
demise of the body. But it would be wrong to consider this belief to be
inherently ‘religious.’ For one may profess such convictions ‘either reli-
giously or nonreligiously’ (Malcolm 1972: 215); that is, either with or
without a practical-ethical attitude. There is nothing to prevent someone
from believing that they will ‘survive death’ as though this was merely an
incidental, quasi-empirical fact. It is not necessary that anything need follow
from such a conviction.70 Of course, this is not to suggest that such classifi-
catory ‘wrong turnings’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 18) are easily avoided.71 On
the contrary, what often leads us astray is the ‘power language has to make
everything look the same’ (ibid.: 22) when abstracted from its manifold
practical settings.72 The notion of immortality – like Moore’s fundamental
propositions discussed in Chapter 2 – begins to look like a quasi-empirical
hypothesis due to the very language in which it is couched.73 As Wittgen-
stein notes, we naturally become confused ‘by certain analogies between
the forms of expression in different regions of language’ (1958: §90), not
least because ‘our language has remained the same and keeps seducing us
into asking the same questions’ (1994a: 15).74 Thus:
Philosophers who say: ‘after death a timeless state will begin’, or: ‘at
death a timeless state begins’ . . . do not notice that they have used the
words ‘after’ and ‘at’ and ‘begins’ in a temporal sense, and that tem-
porality is embedded in their grammar.
(1994a: 22)75
a man did not ever pray for help or forgiveness, or have any inclina-
tion toward it; nor ever felt that it is ‘a good and joyful thing’ to thank
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
God for the blessings of his life; nor was ever concerned about his
failure to comply with divine commandments – then . . . he could not
be said to believe in God . . . [B]elief in God in any degree does
require, as I understand the words, some religious action, some
commitment, or if not, at least a bad conscience.
(1972: 211)79
Suppose one of you were an omniscient person and therefore knew all
the movements of all the bodies in the world dead or alive and that he
also knew all the states of mind of all human beings that ever lived, and
suppose this man wrote all he knew in a big book, then this book would
contain the whole description of the world; and what I want to say is,
that this book would contain nothing that we would call an ethical judge-
ment or anything that would logically imply such a judgement.
(1993: 39)
[T]he point of the book is ethical. I once wanted to give a few words
in the foreword which now actually are not in it, which, however, I’ll
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
write to you now because they might be a key for you: I wanted to
write that my work consists of two parts: of the one which is here, and
of everything which I have not written. And precisely this second part
is the important one.
(1996b: 94)112
[I]f I say that it is important for me not to catch cold I mean that catch-
ing a cold produces certain describable disturbances in my life and if I
say that this is the right road I mean that it’s the right road relative to a
certain goal. Used in this way these expressions don’t present any dif-
ficult or deep problems. But this is not how Ethics uses them.
(1993: 38)
He then proceeds:
Supposing that I could play tennis and one of you saw me playing and
said ‘Well, you play pretty badly’ and suppose I answered ‘I know, I’m
118 Wretchedness without recompense
playing badly but I don’t want to play any better,’ all the other
man could say would be ‘Ah then that’s all right.’ But suppose I had
told one of you a preposterous lie and he came up to me and
said ‘You’re behaving like a beast’ and then I were to say ‘I know I
behave badly, but then I don’t want to behave any better,’ could
he then say ‘Ah, then that’s all right’? Certainly not; he would say
‘Well, you ought to want to behave better.’ Here you have an absolute
judgement of value, whereas the first instance was one of a relative
judgement.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
(1993: 38–9)
would the ‘responsibility’ not ‘die’ (1994b: 70). Here the reality of the
immortal soul does not offer potential recompense for (or an annulment
of) one’s mortal ethical responsibilities. Rather, the ‘proof’ that the soul is
immortal lies in the sense that one’s obligations to another hold even
beyond death. In short, the immortal soul does not achieve Pyrrhonian
ataraxia but instead retains its state of ‘wretchedness’ eternally. The
second point to note here is how many of Wittgenstein’s reflections
provoke a rethinking of ethical responsibility itself, and specifically how
much traditional ethical theory constitutes the theoretical circumscription
of a primordially boundless responsibility – itself prompted by a certain
experience of guilt.126 As Levinas suspects, and as I will discuss in Chapter
6, perhaps the realm of the ‘human’ in general (and ‘scruples’ in particu-
lar) ‘are always already remorse’ (1999: 179).
It is widely acknowledged that Dostoyevsky’s work fascinated Wittgen-
stein at least as much as Tolstoy’s.127 Indeed, Malcolm recalls that when
Wittgenstein was incarcerated at Monte Cassino ‘he and a fellow prisoner
read Dostoyevsky together . . . it was this writer’s “deeply religious attitude”
that commended him to Wittgenstein’ (1993: 8). Redpath similarly notes
that Wittgenstein read Crime and Punishment ‘at least ten times, and both
in that novel and in The Brothers Karamazov he thought Dostoyevsky
expressed “a whole religion” ’ (1990: 53).128 And likewise, Monk reports
that Wittgenstein had read the latter text ‘so often he knew whole pas-
sages of it by heart’ – indeed, The Brothers Karamazov was one of the very
‘few personal possessions’ (1991: 136) he had taken to the Eastern Front
in 1916. We can only speculate as to what portions of Dostoyevsky’s work
Wittgenstein had deemed worthy of committing to memory, but there is
one passage in The Brothers Karamazov (a passage that preoccupies
Levinas) that encapsulates perhaps the most significant aspect of Dos-
toyevsky’s work; namely, its treatment of guilt as ‘having a positive func-
tion’ (Johnston 1991: 123). There he writes:
[N]o profit can be made except at another’s expense . . . let anyone search
his heart and he will find that our inward wishes are for the most part born
and nourished at the expense of others.
M. Montaigne, Essays
‘You shall not steal! You shall not kill!’ – such words were once called holy;
in their presence people bowed their knees and their heads and removed
their shoes. But I ask you: Where have there ever been better thieves and
killers in the world than such holy words have been? Is there not in all life
itself – stealing and killing?
F. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra
Introduction
If the question emerging from both Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and ‘A
Lecture on Ethics’ ultimately concerns the possibility of writing on ethics
in a conceptual vocabulary too ontologically laden (indeed, this ‘running-
up against the limits of language is Ethics’ (Wittgenstein 1978: 80)), then
Levinas’s work represents one attempt to do precisely this.1 That is,
Levinas endeavors ‘to run against the boundaries’ (Wittgenstein 1993: 44)
of a language that seems to prohibit any genuine expression of the
ethical, and this leads him toward writing philosophy ‘as a poetic
composition’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 24).2 It would be an exaggeration to
suggest that Levinas succeeds in writing the explosive ‘book on Ethics’
Wittgenstein refers to – indeed, it will become clear later why the very
notion of ‘success’ is problematic here.3 Nevertheless, the general aspira-
tions of Levinas’s work can initially be framed in this way. An important
question thus arises: If both Levinas and the later Wittgenstein can be read
as responding to the challenges outlined in the Tractatus and ‘A Lecture
on Ethics,’ to what (if any) extent do their respective responses inter-
Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice 123
twine? One recent commentator approaches this question by recommend-
ing that Levinas’s work be read as a non-foundationalist4 account of the
‘transcendental language game’ (Greisch 1991: 70).5 Provocative though
this suggestion is, I will resist its ‘non-foundationalist’ trajectory, not least
because it is inconsonant with the deeper spirit of both philosophers’
work.6 What is more philosophically interesting is the extent to which
Wittgenstein and Levinas each bear witness to a certain experience of guilt.
Toward the end of Chapter 5 I cited a passage from The Brothers Karama-
zov that usefully brought together a number of Wittgenstein’s concerns.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
But that excerpt was selected for another, equally important, reason. For
Levinas is also much taken with Dostoyevsky (along with those other
Russian literary figures who were to influence his early thinking7), and
expressly the idea that ‘every one of us is responsible for everyone else in
every way, and I most of all’ (Dostoyevsky 1967: 339).8 What fascinates
Levinas about this passage is, as I will argue later, the way in which both:
(1) my responsibility is presented as exceeding the reciprocal economics of
what he deems to be ‘traditional’ ethical thinking (including Buber’s I and
Thou 9 ), and (2) subjectivity itself can be characterized in terms of ‘an origi-
nary . . . responsibility or guilt’ (Robbins 1999: 147).10 However, in order to
illuminate how guilt functions in Levinas’s work it is first necessary to
situate it in relation to Heidegger’s exposition of Conscience and Guilt11 in
Being and Time – a text Levinas considered ‘one of the finest books in the
history of philosophy’ (1992: 37) (despite the fact that its author has ‘never
been exculpated . . . from his participation in National-Socialism’ (ibid.:
41)).12 The extent to which Levinas transforms Heidegger’s ontological
analyses into something distinctively ethical should not be underestimated.
But the root of Levinas’s thinking here is not exclusively Heideggerian.
Close attention must also be paid to the profound influence the Holocaust
has on both the rhetoric and substance of his work.13 Only through a com-
bined appreciation of these two sources will we be in a position to discern
the pivotal position Guilt plays in his philosophy.
The work produced refers not only to the ‘towards-which’ of its usabil-
ity and the ‘whereof’ of which it consists: under simple craft con-
ditions it also has an assignment to the person who is to use it or wear
it. The work is cut to his figure; he ‘is’ there along with it as the work
emerges . . . Thus along with the work, we encounter not only entities
ready-to-hand but also entities with Dasein’s kind of Being – entities
for which, in their concern, the product becomes ready-to-hand; and
together with these we encounter the world in which weavers and
users live, which is at the same time ours. Any work with which one
concerns oneself is ready-to-hand not only in the domestic world of
the workshop but also in the public world.
(1999: 100)22
thereby ‘factically submitted’ (ibid.: 344) to the world. That is, through
being ‘brought into its “there” . . . not of its own accord’ (ibid.: 329)
Dasein’s potentiality-for-Being is inevitably restricted.30 But even taking
into account that such ‘thrownness’ often renders choice difficult, Dasein
is always able to make some choices.31 Absorbed in the everyday anonymity
of the ‘they’ Dasein is prevented ‘from taking hold of [its] possibilities’
(ibid.: 312) and subsequently ‘kept away’ from authentic Being.32 Dasein
cannot simply escape responsibility by losing itself in the ‘they,’ for this
‘losing oneself’ (or choosing not to choose33) still constitutes a choice for
which Dasein is responsible.34 In other words, although Dasein cannot
escape choosing, what it chooses is always (relatively) open.35
It is at this juncture that Heidegger introduces the notion of ‘Con-
science.’ As traditionally delineated the ‘call of conscience’ provides an
inner voice of moral guidance. More specifically, this ‘ordinary’ experience
of conscience is thought to occur ‘after the deed has been done or left
undone’ (ibid.: 335–6) and thus ‘follows the transgression and points back
to that event which has befallen and by which Dasein has loaded itself with
guilt’ (ibid.: 336–7). In its Being-toward-death, however, ‘Dasein “is” ahead
of itself,’ for although the voice of Conscience ‘does call back . . . it calls
beyond the deed which has happened . . . to the Being-guilty into which
one has been thrown, which is “earlier” than any indebtedness’ (ibid.: 337)
(I will return to this later). Heidegger’s concept of Conscience therefore
differs from the traditional rendering insofar as the former is constitutive of
Dasein’s Being, and as such is ‘manifestly not present-at-hand’ (ibid.: 343).
Conscience calls with a commanding voice, ‘wrenching’ Dasein ‘away from
das Man’ (Macann 1992: 230). Furthermore, in contrast to the ‘ontical
common sense’ (Heidegger 1999: 314) interpretation, Conscience lacks
explicit content36 and thereby demands a special sort of ‘hearing’ (ibid.:
314). The call of Conscience, Heidegger claims, ‘asserts nothing, gives no
information about world-events, has nothing to tell.’ Nevertheless, this
‘keeping silent’ (ibid.: 318) – though informationally barren – possesses ‘the
momentum of a push – of an abrupt arousal’ (ibid.: 316) in its invoking
‘the Self to its potentiality-for-Being-its-Self’ (ibid.: 319). That is, the ‘call of
conscience has the character of an appeal to Dasein by calling it to its
ownmost potentiality-for-Being-its-Self,’ and ‘this is done by way of summon-
ing it to its ownmost Being-guilty’ (ibid.: 314).37
126 Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice
Given that Conscience is said to both ‘appeal’ to Dasein and constitute
Dasein’s Being, the relationship between that which calls and that which is
called requires elucidation. According to Heidegger then, this ‘alien’
(ibid.: 321) call does not come from anywhere other than Dasein’s own
Being.38 From its ‘lostness’ (ibid.: 319) or ‘hiding-place’ in the ‘they,’
Dasein ‘gets brought to itself by the call’ (ibid.: 317). But this is not simply
a moment of soliloquy, for in its disclosure39 the call possesses the capacity
to surprise Dasein; to come ‘against [its] expectations and even against
[its] will’ (ibid.: 320). In being called by Conscience Dasein is thus force-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
fully summoned ‘to its ownmost Being-guilty’ (ibid.: 319). ‘Where . . . shall
we get our criterion for the primordial existential meaning of the
“Guilty!”?’ Heidegger rhetorically inquires:
From the fact that this ‘Guilty!’ turns up as a predicate for the ‘I am’.
Is it possible that what is understood as ‘guilt’ in our inauthentic inter-
pretation lies in Dasein’s Being as such, and that it does so in such a
way that so far as any Dasein factically exists, it is also guilty?
(1999: 326)
The crucial point here is that Dasein – in its very status as an ‘I am’40 – ‘is
guilty’ (ibid.: 331), and it is this ‘primordial’ (ibid.: 332) Guilt that arouses
the call of Conscience.41 Moreover, the charge of ‘Guilty!’ picks out
Dasein as a particular ‘I.’42 On this view, then, the notion of a ‘public con-
science’ is little more than ‘the voice of the “they.” ’ As Heidegger causti-
cally remarks: ‘A “world-conscience” is a dubious fabrication, and Dasein
can come to this only because conscience, in its basis and its essence, is in
each case mine’ (ibid.: 323). Insofar as Dasein’s Guilt has thus been
divorced from any common, social morality, one might ask what it is that
Dasein is supposed to be Guilty of? But for Heidegger, posing the question
this way would be simultaneously problematic and philosophically reveal-
ing insofar as it perpetuates certain errors inherent in the ‘common
sense,’43 ‘ordinary’ (ibid.: 327),44 ‘everyday’ (ibid.: 336) understanding of
being-guilty. Asking ‘What Dasein is Guilty of ?’ implies a specific object of
Guilt, and thereby lends itself to the economic interpretation of guilt as
‘ “owing”, of “having something due on account” ’ or ‘as “having debts” ’
(ibid.: 327) commonly proffered by the ‘they.’45 For the latter guilt is like
a ‘business procedure that can be regulated’ (ibid.: 340), but the ontologi-
cal understanding both grounds and undercuts this economic model:
‘Being-guilty does not first result from an indebtedness . . . but that, on the contrary,
indebtedness becomes possible only “on the basis” of a primordial Being-guilty’
(ibid.: 329).46 According to Heidegger then, the ‘they’ understand Being-
guilty as a being-in-arrears; as a situation ‘in’ which one sometimes finds
oneself.47 This interpretation suggests the possibility of neutralizing the
burden of debt by ‘reckoning things up’ or ‘balancing them off.’48 (At the
very least it suggests that the occasions of one’s being-guilty might be
Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice 127
‘balanced off’ against periods of innocence.) But for Heidegger Dasein’s
Being-guilty prohibits such compensatory moves, and this is why here
‘there is no counter-discourse in which . . . one talks about what the con-
science has said, and pleads one’s case. In hearing the call understand-
ingly, one denies oneself any counter-discourse’ (ibid.: 342).49 In short,
the primordiality of Heideggerian Guilt renders all apologetics – ontologi-
cally speaking – both impotent and inauthentic.
Now, although Heidegger problematizes any talk of ‘what’ Dasein’s
Being-guilty amounts to, he does suggest one way of approaching this
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
question:
Dasein is its basis existently – that is, in such a manner that it under-
stands itself in terms of possibilities, and, as so understanding itself, is
that entity which has been thrown. But this implies that in having a
potentiality-for-Being it always stands in one possibility or another: it
constantly is not other possibilities, and it has waived these in its exis-
tentiell projection . . . what we have here is . . . something existentially
constitutive . . . The nullity we have in mind belongs to Dasein’s Being-
free for its existentiell possibilities. Freedom, however, is only in the
choice of one possibility – that is, in tolerating one’s not having
chosen the others and one’s not being able to choose them.
(1999: 331)
That Levinas here has Being and Time in mind becomes clear when he re-
casts this general point as follows:
The self is the very crisis of the being of beings in the human . . .
because I myself already ask myself if my being is justified, if the Da of
my Dasein is not already the usurpation of someone’s place. A bad
conscience which comes to me from the face of the other who, in his
mortality, uproots me from the solid ground where, as a simple indi-
vidual, I stand and persevere naively – naturally – in my stance. A bad
conscience which puts me in question.
(1998b: 148)70
This ‘bad conscience’ resulting from my being ‘accused’ for my ‘very pres-
ence’ (1999: 21) is not therefore to be understood in wholly Heideggerian
130 Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice
terms. For my being-in-the-world is already my ‘being-in-question’ (ibid.).71
Thus, when Pascal suggests that ‘the primitive model for the usurpation of
the whole earth’ lies in the naive and natural exclamation ‘this is my place
in the sun’ (1961: §231),72 Levinas adds that it is to this extreme point that
‘Pascal’s “the I is hateful” must be thought through’ (1999: 22).73 Indeed,
it is in this way that ‘the subjective’ is irrevocably ‘knotted in ethics’ (1992:
95), for, as Caputo rightly notes, Levinas has ‘installed bad conscience as a
kind of structural feature of ethical life’ (2000: 116).74
This is only a preliminary sample of such murderous reflections in
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Are you ashamed because you are alive in place of another? And in
particular, of a man more generous, more sensitive, wiser, more
useful, more worthy of living than you? You cannot exclude this: you
examine yourself, you review your memories, hoping to find . . . that
none of them are masked or disguised; no, you find no obvious trans-
gressions, you did not usurp anyone’s place, you did not beat anyone
. . . you did not steal anyone’s bread; nevertheless, you cannot exclude
it. It is no more than a suspicion, indeed the shadow of a suspicion;
that everyone is his brother’s Cain, that everyone of us . . . has usurped
his neighbour’s place and lived in his stead. It is a suspicion, but it
gnaws at us . . . [that] I might be alive in the place of another, at the
expense of another; I might have usurped, that is, in fact killed.
(1998: 62)76
Levinas puts it: ‘access to the face is straightaway ethical’ (1992: 85).92 The
face does not wait to be deciphered as a collection of distinguishing fea-
tures, for it is not ‘the mere assemblage of a nose, a forehead, eyes, etc.; it
is all that, of course, but takes on the meaning of a face through the new
dimension it opens up in the perception of a being’ (1997a: 8),93 and this is
why ‘the word face must not be understood in a narrow way’ (1998b: 231).
Levinas summarizes: ‘The best way of encountering the Other is not even
to notice the color of his eyes! When one observes the color of the eyes one
is not in social relationship with the Other’ (1992: 85).94 Levinas’s treat-
ment of the face thus not only parallels Wittgenstein’s own, it also deepens
the former’s more general attempt to question the traditional philosophi-
cal prioritization of knowledge over responsibility (or ontology over
ethics).95 Still, in order to situate Levinas’s account of the face within this
broader critical enterprise I would like to draw on some phenomenological
observations Wittgenstein makes in Zettel. Although these passages refer to
the face (specifically the eyes), my initial interest here is methodological –
that is, with Levinas’s broader suspicion of visual metaphors and his sub-
sequent tendency to describe the face in auditory terms.
In Zettel Wittgenstein writes:
We do not see the human eye as a receiver, it appears not to let any-
thing in, but to send something out. The ear receives; the eye looks.
(It casts glances, it flashes, radiates, gleams.) One can terrify with
one’s eyes, not with one’s ear or nose. When you see the eye you see
something going out from it. You see the look in the eye.
(1990: §222)
(I have never yet read a comment on the fact that when one shuts one
eye and ‘only sees with one eye’ one does not simultaneously see dark-
ness (blackness) with the one that is shut.)
(1990: §615)
When one encounters the other’s face, her eyes are not entirely passive;
one experiences ‘the look in the [other’s] eye.’96 (As will become clear
later, a central part of Levinas’s own work is to elucidate the ethical
meaning of this ‘look.’) But what these passages highlight is the wider
Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice 133
97
function of the ocular in Levinas’s work. For while Levinas must –
despite his protestations98 – rely upon visual metaphors simply in virtue of
his emphasis on the face (a face that is both ‘what is seen . . . and also that
which sees’ (Derrida 1997c: 98)) it becomes apparent that this same
metaphor motivates his criticism of philosophy’s misrepresentation of the
other. According to Wittgenstein, the eye might be said to be ravenous for
the world in a way that the ear (or nose) is not,99 and this is why ‘one does
not simultaneously see darkness’ when one eye is closed. This broadly
phenomenological point corresponds to Levinas’s general characteriza-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
The first word of the face is the ‘Thou shalt not kill.’ It is an order.
There is a commandment in the appearance of the face, as if a master
spoke to me. However, at the same time, the face of the Other is desti-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
tute; it is the poor for whom I can do all and to whom I owe all.
(Levinas 1992: 89)110
have not done anything and I have always been under accusation –
persecuted.
(Levinas 1994a: 114)147
That the face ‘calls me into question’ is thus not the clearest way for
Levinas to express himself, as this does seem to imply a prior ‘me’ to which
being ‘called into question’ happens.148 Levinas provides a better formula-
tion when he remarks: ‘One comes not into the world but into question’
(1996b: 81),149 and similarly: ‘Responsibility . . . is not a simple attribute of
subjectivity, as if the latter already existed in itself, before the ethical rela-
tionship. Subjectivity is not for itself; it is . . . initially for another’ (1992:
96).150 The ‘I’ is thus actually ‘defined’ in its exposure to another human
being, for the ‘ethical I is a being who asks if he has a right to be!, who
excuses himself to the other for his own existence’ (1984: 62–3).151
Earlier I discussed Wittgenstein’s remark to Drury that there was ‘a
sense in which’ they were ‘both Christians’ (Drury 1981: 130). Although I
will return to this in Chapter 7, it is here worth noting that Derrida sim-
ilarly recalls Levinas once describe himself as being (in some sense)
‘Catholic’; a remark that would ‘call for long and serious reflection’
(Derrida 1996c: 9). It is reasonable to suppose that this meditation would
involve Derrida considering the place of Guilt (and perhaps confession)
in Levinas’s work.152 But I allude to Levinas’s ‘Catholicism’ because his
treatment of Guilt, though rarely named as such, requires careful negotia-
tion.153 As previously suggested, Levinas does not seek atonement or liber-
ation from his ‘ghosts,’ and thus his preoccupation with Guilt is, contrary
to the intimation above, emphatically not that of Catholic orthodoxy, or of
Christian theology more generally.154 Although both Catholic and Lev-
inasian Guilt recast the self as ethically burdened, for Levinas this burden
is not merely of ancient origin, but immemorial. That is, the Guilt around
which Levinas’s thought revolves remains Heideggerian insofar as it does
not first emerge through specific acts or omissions perpetrated. Neither
can it be subsumed under the rubric of ‘original sin’ or any other archaic
inheritance.155 For although the mark of original sin in its various Chris-
tian formulations may cut deep into human nature, insofar as this notion
maintains an origin – and thereby the potential for nostalgia – it simultan-
eously remains tethered to the possibility of reparation, salvation and
Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice 137
156
eventual good conscience. But it is precisely this ‘promise . . . of the
“Happy End” ’ (1988a: 175) or of ‘divine pardon’ (1998b: 18) that the face
of the other calls into question. In ‘the augmentation of guilt,’ Levinas
thus remarks, ‘there is no rest for the self’ (1996a: 144):
This does not mean simply that you are not to go around firing a gun
all the time. It refers, rather, to the fact that, in the course of your life,
in different ways, you kill someone. For example, when we sit down at
the table in the morning and drink coffee, we kill an Ethiopian who
138 Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice
doesn’t have any coffee. It is in this sense that the commandment
must be understood.
(1988a: 173)165
rebuttal of the ‘acts and omissions’ distinction. For one should again
recall: my responsibility for you does not spring from, and is not simply
proportionate to, our relative material assets or ‘proprietorship’
(Rousseau 1930: 220). Rather, my asymmetrical responsibility precedes the
responsibilities arising from such material inequalities.168 I am responsible,
not in virtue of what I have or can do, but in virtue of the fact that I am.169
In the concluding part of this chapter I want to bring these points
together by: (1) demarcating where the Heideggerian and Levinasian pro-
jects both intertwine and part company, and (2) explaining why Wittgen-
stein remains of crucial importance here.
this land of Moriah that is our habitat every second of every day.
(1995b: 69)181
Well, you are in a desolate condition, ’tis true, but pray remember,
where are the rest of you? Did not you come eleven of you into the
boat? where are the ten? Why were they not saved and you lost? Why
were you singled out? Is it better to be here or there? and then I
pointed to the sea. All evils are to be considered with the good that is
in them.
(Defoe 1985: 80)
In this way Crusoe keeps a tight rein on his ‘melancholy’ (ibid.: 81).
Mindful of Crusoe’s predicament, Levinas’s reading of Genesis 4:9
becomes pertinent:
Insofar as the others’ deaths haunt Crusoe’s own survival, his pragma-
tism is (ontologically speaking) perfectly reasonable 195 – after all, what third
142 Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice
party would contest his motives? Analogously, Cain’s response to God is
hardly exceptional: Abel is not an infant requiring constant supervision.
Still, the responses of Crusoe and Cain are by no means inevitable; that
‘there is only ontology’ here is not, as it were, predetermined. Such prag-
matism is, for example, lacking in Rousseau’s The Confessions. There we are
told how, upon his father’s homecoming from Constantinople, Rousseau
himself became ‘the unhappy fruit of his return.’ An ‘unhappy fruit,’ not
merely due to his being a ‘poor and sickly child’ who was ‘almost born
dead,’ but specifically because this birth ‘cost [Rousseau’s] mother her
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
life’:
I never knew how my father stood up to his loss, but I know that he
never got over it. He seemed to see her again in me, but could never
forget that I had robbed him of her; he never kissed me that I did not
know by his sighs and his convulsive embrace that there was a bitter
grief mingled with his affection . . . When he said to me, ‘Jean-Jacques,
let us talk of your mother,’ I would reply: ‘Very well, father, but we are
sure to cry.’ ‘Ah,’ he would say with a groan; ‘Give her back to me,
console me for her, fill the void she has left in my heart! Should I love
you so if you were not more to me than a son?’
(1953: 19)196
She had given shelter to three Jews fleeing the Nazis, but after some
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
days she asked them to leave because she was involved in a plot to
assassinate Hitler and judged that it would be at risk if she were
caught sheltering Jews. The three were caught within days of leaving
her house and murdered in a concentration camp. She said Hitler
had made a murderess of her.
(1991: 43)
Although the woman clearly ‘was not a murderer: no court would judge
her to be that . . . no one could seriously say to her, nor even of her, that
she was, morally speaking, a murderess’ (ibid.), it is nevertheless meaning-
ful for her to feel remorse for her actions.202 Gaita thus rightly concludes
that it is the ‘tendency to connect moral responsibility too tightly to culpa-
bility’ that ‘leads to a moralistic distortion in much contemporary discus-
sion of moral responsibility’ (ibid.: 44).203 A similar example of this occurs
toward the end of Spielberg’s Schindler’s List. There, the morally ambigu-
ous figure of Schindler realizes that, despite his contribution to the safe-
keeping of ‘his’ Jews, he could nevertheless have done so much more. The
‘Schindler Jews’ attempt to curb what seems to them a perversely harsh
self-condemnation (earlier, Schindler is assured that what he was doing
was an ‘absolute good’). But for Schindler this provides little solace as he
continues to interrogate himself regarding how many more lives could have
been saved had his lifestyle during the war been less opulent – despite the
fact that it was precisely this opulence that had enabled him to safeguard
‘his’ Jews in the first place. Both the Dutchwoman and Schindler thus bear
witness to a remorseful guilt that no third party could ever seriously
endorse. In short, theirs is a guilt marked by its ‘radical singularity.’204 As
Gaita puts it, whatever reassurances are offered by others, it ‘should be no
consolation if what we did was also done by the best of people’ (ibid.: 49),
for ‘there can be only corrupt consolation in the knowledge that others
are guilty as we are’ (ibid.: 47). A final example from Wittgenstein’s own
life illustrates the point well. In the 1930s Wittgenstein delivered a ‘confes-
sion of sins’ to a number of friends.205 One of those recipients, Fania
Pascal, has since confessed her own ‘feeling of guilt’ (1996: 45) for her
‘coldness and for being at a loss what to say’ (ibid.: 49) in response. After
contemplating the possible reasons for Wittgenstein’s confession she pro-
ceeds: ‘These are idle speculations. Yet the question seems relevant:
144 Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice
should he not have realized that many people live with a constant feeling
of guilt?’ (ibid.: 49–50). What is interesting about Pascal’s question is how,
having suggested that Wittgenstein’s confession was unnecessary because
‘many people live with a constant feeling of guilt,’ she does not excuse her
own confession and guilt in the same way. Why? Because while it may be
perfectly natural and justifiable to say to the other ‘Take comfort; you do
not need to confess. After all, we are all similarly guilty,’ to console oneself
with such sentiments could only reveal an indecent and questionable pre-
sumptuousness.206 Recalling Dostoyevsky’s remarks in The Brothers Karama-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
zov, while I might concede that ‘every one of us is responsible for everyone
else in every way,’ this is not to say that such responsibility divides equally
amongst us: I may still be guilty ‘most of all’ (1967: 339). In Heidegger’s
terms, what is being resisted by the Dutchwoman, Schindler and Pascal is
the possibility of falling into the good conscience of the ‘we’; of saying ‘ “I
am good” ’ (1999: 338) because ‘they’ assure me so.207 Here too, then,
guilt functions outside the rules that, according to Heidegger and Levinas,
govern the ‘everyday,’ reparative model. But although their characteriza-
tion may fit a certain legal-judicial model of guilt, it is unlikely that model
adequately represents how moral guilt functions ‘ordinarily’ (ibid.: 314).
In other words, it is unclear that this ‘radical singularity’ or ‘mineness’208 is
not already inscribed into the grammar of moral guilt. If this is correct
then Guilt does not need a ‘new vocabulary’ (Kellner 1992: 209). Rather,
what is required is more attentiveness regarding our ‘ordinary’ language –
a language that is often quite ‘extraordinary’ (Derrida 2000a: 415).209
Although the previous examples dramatize my main point, their lesson
is by no means exceptional. Indeed, such phenomena are so common-
place we often fail to notice them.210 It is not unusual to feel guilty for
having done or said something (or omitted to do so) to someone who is
now long since dead.211 This guilt might persist beyond any possible repa-
ration, haunting us for the rest of our lives212 – even though, as others
remind us, the offended party did not die with any sort of grudge. Indeed,
the offence in question might itself be spectral, having been explicitly for-
given long before the other’s demise. One might, for example, feel an
unshakeable guilt for having omitted to tell a partner ‘I love you’ on the
morning of their death – a morning that lacked any special reason for inti-
macies of this sort. With a variety of such facts others may try and console
us. But this was the morning of their death, and no recourse to circum-
stantial details need ever relieve our bad conscience. Of course, this sense
of guilt is prone to ‘egocentric corruptions’ (Gaita 1991: 52), where one
adorns oneself in the garbs of guilt to wallow in self-pity or play the role of
martyr.213 In this respect the mere recognition of bad conscience can itself
simply disguise a deeper good conscience.214 Piety, or any ritualized activity
that is not ‘as genuine as a kiss’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 8), is something to
be wary of here too,215 as is the descent into narcissistic self-destruction.
Thus, recalling Crusoe, it may sometimes
Trespassing, guilt and sacrifice 145
be a proper rebuke against moral haughtiness and hubris to remind
someone who judges their failings of character too harshly that they
are only human, meaning, that they should gain a perspective on
their failings by remembering they are not alone in such failings.
(Gaita 1991: 49)
people. That is not pride because remorse does not focus on what
kind of person we are: its focus is on what we have become . . . It is
therefore not inaccurate or fanciful to say that the guilty, in recogni-
tion of what they have become, have a sense of being placed else-
where: placed, because of their concentrated radical singularity under
judgement; elsewhere, because their suffering can find no relief in a
humbling acknowledgement of their humanity.
(Gaita 1991: 49–50)
For the first time I began to perceive that true sympathy cannot be switched
on and off like an electric current, that anyone who identifies himself with
the fate of another is robbed to some extent of his own freedom.
S. Zweig, Beware of Pity
If you offer a sacrifice and are pleased with yourself about it, both you and
your sacrifice will be cursed.
L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value
Introduction
In Chapter 3 I argued that characterizing the human body as a ‘moral
space’ facilitates a deeper understanding of the ethical terrain of Wittgen-
stein’s later work.1 What he calls into question is the assumption that
ethics constitutes a subsidiary layer of experience that is essentially para-
sitic on more fundamental philosophical issues.2 This is not to deny
reason its place, but rather to highlight the ‘common behavior of
mankind’ (1958: §206) upon which reason – including ethical-political
deliberation – is hinged. Levinas also questions philosophy’s prioritization
of knowledge and reason over ethical responsibility, and similarly denies
that the latter is ‘superimposed ... as a second layer’ (1998a: 11).3 On this
point the Wittgensteinian and Levinasian projects are in broad agree-
ment. However, this accord comes unstuck at the level of the ‘natural.’
Despite their mutual preoccupation with the face and vulnerability, a
crucial disparity occurs at the precise moment Wittgenstein’s unifying nat-
uralism is revealed. My objective in this chapter is to: (1) elucidate this
tension between the Levinasian and Wittgensteinian projects, and (2)
provide a Wittgensteinian corrective to Levinas’s anti-naturalism. But in
The unreasonableness of ethics 149
order to do this a number of additional Levinasian themes need to be
explored. Thus, developing my previous analysis of the face, I will first
assess the significance of Levinas’s ‘religious’ conceptual vocabulary
(specifically with reference to his account of the ‘third-party’), and then
critique his ‘inhospitality’ toward the non-human animal.
God’s reality ‘cannot be proved.’ Rather, the existence of God ‘is sacred
history itself, the sacredness of man’s relation to man through which God
may pass’ (1984: 54).19 Thus, regarding Picard’s suggestion that ‘the face of
man is the proof of the existence of God,’ Levinas remarks:
Clearly the concern here is not with deductive proof, but with the very
dimension of the divine . . . disclosing itself in that odd configuration of
lines that make up the human face. It is in the human face that . . . the trace
of God is manifested, and the light of revelation inundates the universe.
(1996d: 95)
In the other’s face one does not ‘see’ the face of God.20 Neither does one
infer from it that God exists.21 Rather, the other’s face testifies to the
divine in a way that cannot be assimilated to epistemic categories.22 Obvi-
ously the face can be treated as merely one object among many23 (as can
the other more generally24), and this possibility is why Levinas cautions
that the ‘best way of encountering the Other is not even to notice the
color of his eyes!’ (1992: 85). Estheticizing the other in this way bypasses
the social relation and results in an essentially pornographic encounter.
But while Levinas avoids speaking of the face in purely surface terms, so
too does he want to avoid any suggestion that the face is a material obs-
tacle to the divine.25 It is not that the phenomenal appearance of the face
(including the other’s capacity to use it as a ‘mask’) is irrelevant to the
social relation – how could it be? What Levinas is resisting is the reduction
of its meaning to these material features.26 But a familiar problem re-
emerges here, for opposing the tendencies of reductionism does not
necessarily liberate us from the categories of knowledge – assuming we
seek such liberation. Even if we concede that the face should not be
‘understood’ solely in terms of its surface qualities,27 it remains unclear
whether Levinas’s point is not fundamentally epistemological. Again, how
is it possible to think the transcendent without a more-or-less implicit
appeal to knowledge – albeit the impotence of knowledge and ontological
language here?28 Thus, one might say, Levinas’s negative theology of the
face is – like all negative theologies perhaps – not sufficiently negative.29
Still, Levinas’s denial that the face provides a ‘proof of the existence of
God’ but rather represents ‘the indispensable circumstance of the meaning of
The unreasonableness of ethics 151
30
that word’ (1993: 94) opens another possible avenue for exploring his
intermingling of philosophy and religion. The intimate relation between
the face and language is clearly insinuated in Levinas’s remarks on
‘prayer’ and ‘liturgy’ cited above. But why should he mention these spe-
cific discourses? As previously suggested, one potentially fruitful way of
approaching this question would be through Wittgenstein’s remarks on
religious belief. That the face testifies to the Infinite (that it is ‘the locus of
the [“Thou shalt not kill”] of God’ (Levinas 1999: 104)) could then be
understood in terms of its ‘imperative’ (1993: 158), commanding author-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
ity.31 That is, the face of the other in Levinas’s work functions in much the
same way as God’s command does in Wittgenstein’s observation that one
can only ‘hear God speak’ if one is ‘being addressed’ (1990: §717) – a
point Levinas himself makes.32 Indeed, the authority Levinas claims on
behalf of the face mirrors Wittgenstein’s more general remarks on the cat-
egorical nature of genuinely religious utterances.33 A further correlation
between Levinas and Wittgenstein emerges here insofar as the face of the
other alludes to killing in the twofold sense that I am both ‘straightaway’
(Levinas 1992: 85)34 commanded not to kill and simultaneously accused of
having killed (and indeed of continuing to be an ‘accomplice’ (1998b:
186) to murder) through my very being-in-the-world.35 The face’s
command ‘thou shalt not kill’ (ibid.: 168) is, like Wittgenstein’s example
in Culture and Value,36 an impossible command; a mandate I have necessarily
already violated and continue to violate with every breath, word and deed.
The face both warns and accuses me of crimes already committed, and this
is why ‘in approaching the neighbor’ I am ‘always late for the appointed
time’ (Levinas 1996a: 106).37 In short, there is an important and telling
concurrence between the ‘depth grammar’ of religion and the face.38
With these points in mind, we are now better placed to understand
Levinas’s remarks that:
And similarly:
I am a testimony . . . The Infinite is not ‘in front of’ me; I express it,
but precisely by giving a sign of the giving of signs, of the ‘for-the-
other’ in which I am dis-interested: here I am (me voici)! The
accusative here is remarkable: here I am, under your eyes, at your
152 The unreasonableness of ethics
service, your obedient servant . . . The religious discourse that pre-
cedes all religious discourse is not dialogue. It is the ‘here I am’ . . .
(1996a: 146)39
The meaning of the ‘here I am’ is therefore similarly twofold: (1) ‘here I
am’ offering myself to you, ‘at your service,’40 and (2) ‘here I am’ accused
and guilty. Situated before the other’s face the ‘I’ is at once both submis-
sive to her demands and confessional regarding the violence of its own
being-in-the-world. In this second sense the ‘here I am’ constitutes a ‘testi-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
In other words, even if one were to take the face in its ‘plasticity’54 as merely
another ‘cultural Object,’ its sense as such refers us to other others in its being
part of a ‘common surrounding world’ (Husserl 1989: 201).55 However,
constituting the other others in such a way would, for Levinas, still be too
154 The unreasonableness of ethics
ontological56 in its safely housing the ‘I’ in a community of observers.57 This
broadly phenomenological point Levinas thus ethicalizes as follows:
The problem that now emerges is how ‘to reconcile . . . the infinite ethical
requirement of the face that meets me . . . and the appearance of the
other as an individual and as an object’ (1998b: 205).58 According to the
passage above the relation to both the singular other and the third party
must be understood in terms of the demand for worldly justice.59
Although, as discussed in Chapter 5, Levinas tends to focus on the rela-
tionship with the singular other, here he insists that such a relationship is
(though in a rather specific sense) a fiction; ‘in reality, the relationship
with another is never uniquely the relationship with the other.’60 Levinas’s
preoccupation with the ‘uniqueness of the other man’ is not therefore ‘a
repudiation of politics’ (ibid.: 195).61 For if
there was only the other facing me, I would say to the very end: I owe
him everything. I am for him . . . I am forever subject to him. My resis-
tance begins when the harm he does me is done to a third party who is
also my neighbor. It is the third party who is the source of justice, and
thereby of justified repression; it is the violence suffered by the third
party that justifies stopping the violence of the other with violence.
(1998a: 83)
[T]here arose rivalry and competition on the one hand, and conflicting
interests on the other . . . All these evils were the first effects of property
. . . Usurpations by the rich, robbery by the poor, and the unbridled pas-
sions of both, suppressed the cries of natural compassion.
(Rousseau 1930: 218–19)
the respective emphases of Rousseau and Levinas differ in one very import-
ant sense: Rousseau’s interest lies with the life experienced by ‘infant man’
(1930: 207) in glorious isolation from others (or at least in a primitive, pre-
linguistic, pre-rational form of sociality86), whereas Levinas would question
Rousseau’s valorization of this state of natural ‘self-preservation’ (ibid.). (I
will return to the latter.) These differences aside, it is nevertheless striking
that both philosophers stress the inherently problematic nature of being-
with-(other)-others. To what (if any) extent then does Levinas share
Rousseau’s nostalgia? As Derrida has recently inquired,87 might Levinas’s
claim that ‘there wouldn’t be any problem’ (1998b: 106) if there were only
two of us constitute a lamentation regarding the way the third party becomes
a ‘complication’ (1997b: 82) to the face-to-face relation? These important
questions can, I think, be answered with reference to the following pas-
sages from Otherwise than Being:
In the proximity of the other, all the others than the other obsess me,
and already this obsession cries out for justice, demands measure and
knowing . . . The other is from the first the brother of all the other
men. The neighbor that obsesses me is already a face, both compara-
ble and incomparable, a unique face and in relationship with faces,
which are visible in the concern for justice . . . The relationship with
the third party is an incessant correction of the asymmetry of proxim-
ity in which the face is looked at. There is weighing, thought, objectifi-
cation, and thus a decree in which my anarchic relationship with
illeity is betrayed . . .
(Levinas 1994a: 158)
This ‘Thanks to God’ (or similarly ‘ “with the help of God” ’ (ibid.: 160))
could be variously interpreted. So, for example, Critchley suggests that
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
But Levinas reads much more into this encounter. Having described the
‘sounds and noises of nature’ as ‘words that disappoint us’ (and again
warned philosophy of its neglect of the ‘direct social relations between
persons speaking’103), he thus remarks:
The unreasonableness of ethics 161
But this is a disdain that cannot gainsay a situation whose privileged
nature is revealed to Robinson Crusoe when, in the tropical splendor
of nature, though he has maintained his ties with civilization through
his use of utensils, his morality, and his calendar, he experiences in
meeting Man Friday the greatest event of his insular life – in which a
man who speaks replaces the ineffable sadness of echoes.
(1993: 148)
tion, servitude, and submission’ (Defoe 1985: 209) at the hands of Crusoe.
Indeed, this apparent nonchalance toward the colonialism at the heart of
Defoe’s narrative is manifest in Levinas’s silence concerning Friday’s sub-
sequent ‘education’ – and, not least, that the second word Crusoe would
teach him was ‘Master’ (ibid.).104 Rather, what preoccupies Levinas is the
way Friday’s utterances despite their unintelligibility figure as the most
momentous ‘event’ in Crusoe’s ‘silent life’ (ibid.: 81).105 Putting this in
more theoretical terms, what concerns Levinas is that:
Beyond the thematization of the Said and of the content stated in the
proposition . . . The proposition is proposed to the other person . . . It
is communication not reducible to the phenomenon of the truth-that-
unites: it is a non-indifference to the other person, capable of ethical
significance.
(1993: 142)106
Most of the time my life is dearer to me, most of the time one looks
after oneself. But we cannot not admire saintliness . . . that is, the
person who in his being is more attached to the being of the other
than to his own. I believe that it is in saintliness that the human
begins; not in the accomplishment of saintliness, but in the value. It is
the first value, an undeniable value . . . I maintain that [the] ideal of
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
The universality of this ‘ideal’ is reiterated where Levinas claims that the
‘only absolute value is the human possibility of giving the other priority
over oneself. I don’t think that there is a human group that can take
exception to that ideal, even if it is declared an ideal of holiness’ (1998b:
109),113 and likewise:
pure being before or without ethics’ that is ‘already a metaphor for the
cruelty of the cruel in the struggle for life and the egotism of wars’
(1998b: 201–2).121 More notable, however, is where Levinas proposes a
certain complicity between Heideggerian ontology and Darwinism insofar
as both (allegedly) allude to a being that ‘is something that is attached to
being, to its own being . . . a struggle for life.’ He proceeds: ‘Dasein is a
being who in his being is concerned for this being itself. That’s Darwin’s
idea: the living being struggles for life. The aim of being is being itself’
(1988a: 172).122 What distinguishes the truly human from such a character-
ization is that here it first becomes possible to speak of there being ‘some-
thing more important’ than myself; namely, ‘the life of the other’
(ibid.).123 Ethics is ‘against nature because it forbids the murderousness of
my natural will to put my own existence first’ (1984: 60).124 With the ‘awak-
ening to the human’ thus comes an ‘ideal of holiness contrary to the laws
of being’ (1998b: 114). Indeed, this is why the human – insofar as it ‘inter-
rupts the pure obstinacy of being and its wars’ (ibid.: 231) – is nothing less
than ‘a scandal in being’ (ibid.: 115).125 The orientation of such passages
is clear enough. But although Levinas is candid regarding what this break
with ‘pure being’ (1988a: 172) inaugurates (namely, the possibility of
saintly self-sacrifice), it remains unclear precisely how this rupture is sup-
posed to occur.126 While Levinas is ‘not saying men are saints, or moving
toward saintliness,’ but rather that ‘the vocation of saintliness is recog-
nized by all human beings as a value, and that this recognition defines the
human’ (1999: 171), there here lies an ambiguity concerning the extent
to which his point is essentially descriptive or prescriptive (or both). Do all
human beings actually recognize ‘the vocation of saintliness . . . as a value,’
or is this the criterion for ‘genuine’ humanity? Is Levinas alluding to a fact
about human beings qua human beings, and if so is he identifying a more-
or-less latent capacity on the part of human beings for ‘saintliness’? On
this latter reading Levinas’s point may be both descriptive (human beings
do possess the capacity to transcend their animal nature) and prescriptive
(human beings should pursue such ‘saintliness’), but the constitution of
this ‘capacity’ still remains obscure. It presumably cannot be a rational
capacity as this would make being-for-the-other essentially a matter of
deliberation, and thus relative to the subject’s own cognitive powers.127 If
it is a natural capacity then can one be so assured that it is peculiar to
164 The unreasonableness of ethics
human beings? If it is neither rational nor natural then how does it arise?
– presumably not from God mysteriously endowing the human with a
spark of the divine. Given that Levinas is ‘not saying men are saints, or
moving toward saintliness’ (1999: 171), it would seem that he does not
want to suggest that human beings are essentially constituted by ‘saintli-
ness’ – as though saintliness were somehow unavoidable. But even here
things are not straightforward. For Levinas does suggest that something
‘saintly’ precedes (or is at least co-extensive with) every encounter with the
other – even encounters of an explicitly violent sort. (To put this differ-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
ently, the Saying remains ‘saintly’ regardless of what transpires in its being
Said.) Levinas provides no clear answer to these questions, but his general
motivation is patently exclusivistic: that only we (that is, not the non-human
animal) possess the capacity to even aspire to such saintliness.128 Much like
Heidegger’s descriptive-prescriptive account of authenticity, insofar as we
are constituted by an ineliminable Guilt, ‘pure’ saintliness is necessarily
impossible. Nevertheless, in our practical dealings with others we can
approach the saintly more-or-less adequately. The ‘human’ in Levinas’s
work thus appears to be more an ethical than biological category. In other
words, the ‘break’ with the natural realm is not something that has, in any
determinate sense, ‘occurred,’ but is rather something that we need
continually to attempt. For Levinas, being (biologically) human is there-
fore the necessary condition for (ethical) saintliness. It is not, however, a
sufficient condition.
According to Levinas then, it is the potential for self-sacrifice that con-
stitutes the ‘meaning of the human adventure’ (ibid.: 227):
In the realm of pure animality one’s interests move circularly from self to
world and back again. Like a love, gift or confession that ultimately seeks
its own satisfaction, Being is marked by its continual recuperation, replen-
ishment and nostalgic homeward-ness.130 Such a model is thus marked by
what Levinas describes as the interestedness of ‘need’ (1996a: 51).131 But
the other disrupts this economy of satisfaction, interjecting the exuber-
ance of ‘desire’ (ibid.)132 into an otherwise egological narrative.133 Hence-
forth the inter-human relation can be ‘considered from another
perspective’:
[As] concern for the other as other, as a theme of love and desire
which carries us beyond the finite Being of the world . . . God, as the
The unreasonableness of ethics 165
God of alterity and transcendence, can only be understood in terms of
that interhuman dimension which, to be sure, emerges in the phe-
nomenological-ontological perspective of the intelligible world, but
which cuts through and perforates the totality of presence and points
towards the absolutely Other.
(1984: 56–7)
It is not the softness or warmth of the hand given in contact that the
caress seeks. The seeking of the caress constitutes its essence by the
fact that the caress does not know what it seeks. This ‘not knowing’,
this fundamental disorder, is the essential. It is like a game with some-
thing slipping away, a game absolutely without project or plan, not
with what can become ours or us, but with something other, always
other, always inaccessible, and always still to come . . .
(1997b: 89)137
ejects from himself all his denial of himself, of his nature, naturalness,
and actuality, in the form of an affirmation . . . as God, as the holiness
of God, as God the Judge . . . as torment without end, as hell, as the
immeasurability of punishment and guilt.
(Nietzsche 1992b: §22)
Here we thus find a certain ‘madness of the will’ to judge ourselves ‘guilty
and reprehensible to a degree that can never be atoned for’; to be ‘pun-
ished without any possibility of the punishment becoming equal to the
guilt’ (ibid.).153 Such Judaic-Christian virtues as neighborly love are, Niet-
zsche insists, ‘always something secondary . . . when compared with fear of
one’s neighbor’ (1987: §201).154 That is, ‘the emancipated are . . . the under-
privileged whose deepest instinct is revenge’ (1992a: p. 46).155 While more
‘noble cultures’ judge neighborly love, pity and selflessness to be ‘some-
thing contemptible’ (1972a: p. 91), we have taken cruelty and transformed
it into ‘tragic pity, so that it is denied the name of cruelty’ (1968: §312).
168 The unreasonableness of ethics
And it is for these reasons that Nietzsche questions the teleology of
Darwinism:
Continuing his assault on the naive belief (or apparent need to believe156)
that ‘we have really grown more moral’ (ibid.: p. 89), Nietzsche proceeds to
condemn our ‘modern’ era as ‘a weak age.’ Indeed, these virtues are
‘demanded by our weakness’ (ibid.: p. 91). Thus, our ‘belated constitution,
a weaker, more delicate, more vulnerable one, out of which is necessarily
engendered a morality which is full of consideration’ does not betoken any
moral advancement. On the contrary, it ‘represents . . . our general decay
of vitality,’ for here, where ‘everyone helps everyone else . . . everyone is
. . . an invalid and everyone a nurse.’ Among those ‘who knew a different
kind of life, a fuller, more prodigal, more overflowing life,’ this alleged
virtue ‘would be called something else: “cowardice”, perhaps, “pitiable-
ness”, “old woman’s morality”.’ In short: ‘Our softening of customs . . . is a
consequence of decline’ (ibid.: p. 90).
Mindful of these passages, one can imagine what a Nietzschean critique
of Levinas would look like, for each account represents the pathological
shadow of the other. Indeed, given Levinas’s emphasis on Guilt and asym-
metrical responsibility (in Nietzschean terms, given Levinas’s profound
‘condemnation of [the] instincts’ (1972a: p. 45) or ‘tyranny against
“nature” ’ (1987: §188)) Nietzsche’s critique of Christianity would become
even more caustic. In this respect it is notable that Nietzsche refers to the
‘madness’ of ‘man’ having judged ‘himself guilty . . . to a degree that can
never be atoned for’ (1992b: Dialogue 2, §22). (Indeed, Levinas not only
refers to one’s being accused by the other as ‘a seed of madness . . . a psy-
chosis’ (2000: 188),157 he suggests that his conception of ethics is in some
sense ‘masochistic’ (2001: 46).) Both Nietzsche and Levinas could agree
that morality is fundamentally against the (allegedly) most primitive of
human drives toward self-assertion, and thereby ‘[a]nti-natural’ (Nietzsche
1972a: p. 45). Likewise, there is a sense in which Nietzsche’s claim that
morality ‘is the judgement of the judged’ (ibid.: p. 46) might also ring
true for Levinas.158 Indeed, Levinas could even accept that ‘Man is fin-
The unreasonableness of ethics 169
ished when he becomes altruistic’ (ibid.: p. 87), if by this one means
natural ‘man’ immersed in the egotistic ‘instinct of life’ (ibid.: p. 45). Both
philosophers therefore demand that we become more human, but while
for Levinas this requires a radical break from the natural instinct of self-
preservation, according to Nietzsche we need rather to rediscover our nat-
uralness and thereby be liberated from our ‘unnaturalness,’ our
degenerate, otherworldly ‘spirituality’ (ibid.: p. 23). What Nietzsche’s
untimely vision thus bears witness to is precisely what Levinas most fears of
the natural realm – namely, the subject’s primitive drive toward self-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
the lion’s ‘form of life’ is not radically different from the human. Indeed,
we already (without the lion’s ‘speaking’) perceive such connections, so
why assume that its acquisition of language would not extend these
further? (What Wittgenstein perhaps ought to have said is: ‘If a stone could
talk, we could not understand it.’) With this in mind Wittgenstein’s occa-
sional remarks on other humans being ‘a complete enigma’ (1958, p. 223)
– and similarly: ‘ “These men . . . have nothing human about them” ’
(1990: §390) – should be treated with caution. But a further point can be
drawn from §284 of Philosophical Investigations regarding Levinas’s
emphasis on the ‘otherness’ of the other. For Levinas must presuppose
some sort of recognition of (or, more naturalistically, reaction to) the
human qua human in order to assert that ‘the prototype . . . is human
ethics’ (1988a: 172) and ‘[t]he human face is completely different and
only afterwards do we discover the face of the animal’ (ibid.: 171–2).168 In
other words, Levinas must already presuppose that the ‘human’ is signific-
antly distinguishable from the realm of either inert nature or ‘mere’ ani-
mality.169 As such, his emphasis upon the radical otherness of the other
(who, we are repeatedly told, transcends all traditional philosophical cat-
egories) turns out to be not so ‘radical’ after all. As I suggested in Chapter
3 and earlier in this chapter (and as Derrida himself intimates170), for
another to be absolutely ‘other’ would mean that that other remained
wholly unrecognizable even as an other to whom one was ethically
bound.171 Indeed, without this identification we would be forever ‘at a
loss’ as to whether such an encounter was taking place, or had ever taken
place.172 In short, this would plunge Levinas into the most extreme form
of ethical skepticism or Pyrrhonian quietism.173 Thus, his recurrent claim
that the ‘human community . . . does not constitute the unity of genus’
(1996c: 213–14),174 or that the other is ‘irreducible . . . to the individual of
the human race’ (1998a: 10) must be treated with the same degree of cir-
cumspection as Surin’s, Lyotard’s and Readings’s (not to mention
Levinas’s own175) suspicion of positing a human ‘we.’ It is, of course,
correct to insist that the singular other (here, face to face with me) is not
experienced merely as a specific incarnation of the ‘human race as a bio-
logical genus’ (Levinas 1996c: 213),176 or a specific ‘instance of humanity’
(Winch 1987: 174), for such a picture of intersubjectivity would be
absurdly deliberative. It is also correct to highlight the ethical significance
The unreasonableness of ethics 171
of our ‘involvement with . . . particular human beings’ (ibid.: 172), each
with ‘his own nature and history’ (ibid.: 174).177 Yet while the other should
not be construed as merely one replaceable (and to that extent more-or-
less anonymous) sample of ‘the human,’ neither is her specificity radically
separable from ‘the human.’ This is why the minimal naturalism I have
been drawing from Wittgenstein is important, for without it sensitivity
toward the singular other would be rendered a fundamentally mysterious
phenomenon.178
If we recall, Levinas is concerned with language as a medium through
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
which the ethical passes.179 The face, after all, addresses me in its ‘mute
and accusatory eloquence’ (Derrida 1992b: 117).180 Here Levinas decom-
poses language into its dual function as: (1) informational-communicative
content (Said), and (2) quasi-performative offering or gift (Saying),181
thus extending the ethical significance of language beyond a mere ‘truth-
that-unites’ (1993: 142).182 Consequently the linguistic realm is demarcated
from the ‘sounds and noises of nature’ that merely represent ‘words that
disappoint us’ (ibid.: 148). In order to explore this demarcation I want to
turn to Levinas’s brief discussion of ‘Bobby,’ a stray dog who (albeit tem-
porarily) reconfirmed Levinas’s humanity during his wartime incarcera-
tion.
While both Wittgenstein and Levinas agree that ethics does not ulti-
mately have a rational ground, Levinas’s error is to conflate what is reason-
able with what is natural.197 For Levinas ethics cannot be grounded in the
natural because he assumes that the realm of the natural is saturated with
the egological ‘instinct of life’ (Nietzsche 1972a: p. 45). It thus only
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
becomes possible to speak of ethics when this natural drive toward being-
for-oneself is disrupted by concern for another.198 And this, we should
recall, is precisely what Levinas claimed was missing from Cain’s response
to God (‘Am I my brother’s keeper?’) for here ‘[e]thics is the only thing
lacking in his answer; there is only ontology: I am I, and he is he’ (1998b:
110). In other words, for Levinas, Cain’s response is entirely rooted in his
animal nature.199 It does not seem significant to Levinas that it is also ‘a
primitive reaction to tend, to treat, the part that hurts when someone else is
in pain; and not merely when oneself is’ (Wittgenstein 1990: §540, my
emphasis).200
Earlier I discussed how, on Levinas’s account, the other’s face embod-
ies the commandment ‘thou shalt not kill’ (1992: 87–8), and thereby con-
stitutes ‘the categorical imperative’ (1993: 158) or ‘order issued to me not
to abandon the other’ (ibid.: 44). All this lies in the face that faces me.
But, as I also noted, Levinas contrasts these more active determinations by
suggesting that the face is simultaneously ‘exposed, menaced, as if inviting
us to an act of violence. At the same time, the face is what forbids us to
kill’ (1992: 86). The face is thus the very junction at which authority and
vulnerability meet – indeed, its authority is its fragility. For Levinas all
these characterizations pertain explicitly to the human face.201 But here I
want to suggest that the vulnerability he attributes to the face of the other
lies not in their humanity but in their animality – that is, in their elemen-
tary needs for sustenance, shelter and care.202 Thus, where Levinas dis-
cerns a spark of the ‘divine’ in the eyes of the other, we should instead
rediscover the animal in the other’s eyes.203 With this in mind, it is interest-
ing that Derrida should draw attention to a passage in Baudelaire, where a
beggar’s gaze of ‘ “mute eloquence” ’ is explicitly associated with ‘ “the
tear-filled eyes of a dog being beaten”.’ Why should Baudelaire make this
comparison? Perhaps, as Derrida suggests, because the ‘poor man is a dog
of society, [and] the dog is the fraternal allegory of social poverty, of the
excluded, the marginal, the “homeless” ’ (1992b: 143). But Derrida goes
further than Baudelaire, declaring that ‘[n]othing is less stupid, less beast-
like than “dogs being beaten” and whose “tear-filled eyes” speak the infi-
nite demand’ (ibid.: 167).204 Must one take these latter remarks
metaphorically and thereby conclude that such sentiments are (as Levinas
maintains) only possible because the ‘prototype . . . is human ethics’ and
The unreasonableness of ethics 175
concern for non-human animals ‘arises from the transference to [them]
of the idea of suffering’ (1988a: 172)? In short, what is to be gained by
endorsing Levinas’s claim that ‘[i]n my relation to the other, I hear the
Word of God. It is not a metaphor . . . it is literally true’ (1998b: 110),
rather than evacuating the unnecessary metaphysics?205
In Chapter 2 I explored Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘trust’ in On Cer-
tainty, and specifically how distrust belongs to ‘a fairly advanced stage of
human relations’ (Hertzberg 1988: 318). The child thus displays a ‘primi-
tive’ trusting toward its principal carers, only upon which subsequent (and
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Now, Levinas accepts that the child ‘is a pure exposure of expression’ or a
‘pure vulnerability,’ not least because she ‘has not yet learned . . . to
deceive, to be insincere’ (1984: 64).206 It is, one might say, through the
inherent vulnerability of the child that her unconditional trust is manifest,
and that this primitive (pre-linguistic, pre-rational) trusting demands the
responsibility of others.207 But if this is true regarding the human infant,
then it also pertains to non-human animals. Moreover, Hertzberg’s
remarks enable us to say something, not only about the natural vulnerabil-
ity of the other but also about the subject who responds to the vulnerable
other. In short, the minimal naturalism I have been defending cuts both
ways in the ethical relation. Thus, at a primitive level, the dog (for
example) is the very epitome of Levinasian responsibility; that is, of an
unconditional ‘love without reward’ (or ‘gratuitous gift of . . . friendship’
(Gaita 2003: 10)), even in the face of violence. Pure animality is pure
trust, faith and obedience to the demands of another who is absolute
authority. The dog responds without concern for reciprocity, for, as
Levinas remarks of Bobby, he lacks ‘the brain needed to universalize
maxims’ (1997a: 153). Of course, this rational incapacity excludes the
non-human animal from playing an active208 role in the realm of justice –
where, for the sake of the third party, reciprocity, equality and calculation
become necessary. But this should not blind us to the fact that the
complex, often agonizing decisions justice requires can only arise as such
against a backdrop of primitive, natural behaviors – many of which we
share with non-human animals.209 Thus, when Levinas claims that the
176 The unreasonableness of ethics
‘Here I am!’ constitutes the ‘religious discourse that precedes all religious
discourse’ (1996a: 146),210 this casts things in the wrong light. It would, I
believe, be better to say that the ‘Here I am!’ is in fact the natural ‘dis-
course’ that precedes all discourse, including the ‘religious.’ In this regard
it is notable that Levinas (again, like Rousseau211) should allude to ‘the
original language, a language without words or propositions . . . a commu-
nication without phrases or words’ (1987: 119–20). For, as previously
noted, he is adamant that the ‘sounds and noises of nature’ merely repre-
sent ‘words that disappoint us’ (1993: 148). To reiterate my earlier ques-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
It is true that the raven croaks, the dog barks, and the lion roars. But
animal voices are only chinks in the silence. It is as though the animal
were trying to tear open the silence with the force of its body.
‘A dog barks today exactly as it barked at the beginning of Cre-
ation’, said Jacob Grimm. That is why the barking of dogs is so desper-
ate, for it is the vain effort, since the beginning of creation until the
present day, to split the silence open, and this attempt to break the
silence of creation is always a moving thing to man.
(1948: 111)212
order of the political’ (1999b: 49).221 Although this claim is not wholly
improvident (Levinas does indeed speak of a ‘prior non-indifference to
the other man’ (1998a: 141), the ‘religious discourse that precedes all . . .
discourse’ (1996a: 146), and so on222), Derrida’s reading nevertheless
underestimates Levinas’s anti-naturalism. Indeed, later in his commentary
Derrida compounds this oversight by suggesting that ‘there is no concept
of nature or reference to a state of nature in Levinas . . . and this is of the
utmost importance.’ He then proceeds to reiterate the significance of this
(alleged) omission in the Levinasian project:
As I said, this reading is not without some legitimacy, for Levinas does
place ethics before (or ‘above’) ontology. Nevertheless, given what
Levinas says about the radical ‘break’ humanity makes with natural ani-
mality – not to mention the anomaly between genuine language and the
disappointing ‘sounds and noises of nature’ (1993: 148)224 – Derrida’s
claim that the former lacks a ‘concept of nature’ is mistaken. While we
might accept that there is no analysis of ‘the natural’ in Levinas’s work,
this is precisely the problem insofar as his treatment of the natural hinges
on a number of misguided assumptions. Derrida’s oversight is thus
perhaps due more to an ambiguity within Levinas’s work. But what pri-
marily interests me is how this oversight again raises the question whether
goodness (generosity, hospitality, and so on) can be said to have its roots
in the natural realm? Earlier in his exposition Derrida makes a very perti-
nent remark in this regard. There, referring to Levinas’s account of inter-
subjectivity, he speculates: ‘It is as if the welcome, just as much as the face,
just as much as the vocabulary that is co-extensive and thus profoundly
synonymous with it, were a first language, a set made up of quasi-primitive
. . . words’ (1999b: 25).225 I have already alluded to the notion of a ‘first
The unreasonableness of ethics 179
language’ in Levinas’s work, and specifically how this might be thought of
in more naturalistic terms. Nevertheless, Derrida’s allusion to the ‘quasi-
primitive’ offers something of much broader significance for my argu-
ment. Of course, one is here faced with a slight equivocation: it is as if the
welcome, generosity and hospitality consisted of something ‘primitive’
before or beneath culture, society and politics. Although the ‘as if’ (and
the ‘if there is’) has a crucial and unequivocal function in Derrida’s
work,226 on this point such a qualification seems to me unnecessary. To
put it bluntly, why not simply drop the ‘quasi’ and say with Wittgenstein
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
that ‘it is a primitive reaction to tend, to treat, the part that hurts when
someone else is in pain; and not merely when oneself is’ (1990: §540), and
likewise that ‘this sort of behavior is pre-linguistic: that a language-game is
based on it, that it is the prototype of a way of thinking and not the result
of thought’ (ibid.: §541).227 Why posit a mysterious pre-natural dimension
of hospitality228 when the natural itself proves adequate to the ethical
task?229 Interestingly, in another recent text (concerned with issues of ‘for-
giveness’), Derrida addresses ‘the question of the animal’ as follows: ‘it
would be very imprudent to deny all animality access to forms of sociality
in which guilt, and therefore procedures of reparation, even of mercy –
begged or granted – are implicated in a very differentiated way.’ Derrida
then suggests that, just as there is an animal ‘act of war,’ there is ‘no
doubt’ an animal ‘thank you,’ ‘shame, discomfort, regret, anxiety’ and
‘remorse’ – indeed, in the realm of the animal one can also witness ‘rites
of reconciliation, of the interruption of hostility, of peace, even of mercy’
(2001b: 47).230 In short, without wanting to deny the significance of
‘verbal language’ for these complex phenomena, the ‘possibility, even
[the] necessity of extra-verbal forgiveness’ (ibid.: 48) must be acknow-
ledged. If there is such a thing as a ‘pure’ gift, hospitality and generosity,
and if there is such a thing as giving without calculation or the expectation
of return (and I take Derrida’s point to be that one can only have faith
that such things occur231), then I want to say that they happen blindly every
day as a ‘ “goodness without thought” ’ (Levinas 1999: 108).232 In other
words, these occurrences are – like the violence of being itself – so ordin-
ary, so banal that one does not even designate them as such. The ‘imposs-
ible’ that Levinas invests so much faith in has ‘already occurred’ (Derrida
1997c: 80) as an entirely natural phenomenon – that is, as ‘something
animal’ (Wittgenstein 1999: §359).
8 Contaminations
Levinas, Wittgenstein and Derrida
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Hearts open very easily to the working class, wallets with more difficulty.
What opens with the most difficulty of all are the doors of our own homes.
E. Levinas, Nine Talmudic Readings
Introduction
In the preceding chapters we have been concerned with ‘hauntings’ of
various sorts; of knowledge by doubt, reason by rhetoric, politics by ethics,
justice by violence, good conscience by Guilt, and the human by ‘the
animal.’1 Throughout these analyses I have referred to Derrida’s work on
numerous occasions. In this final chapter I want to bring the aforemen-
tioned themes together by releasing Derrida from his (as yet) somewhat
spectral presence. In particular I want to explore: (1) the extent to which
Derrida’s work has become increasingly possessed by Levinasian themes,
and (2) how Wittgenstein might in turn be invited to ‘haunt’ Derrida.2 In
a number of recent texts the influence of Levinas on Derrida’s thinking is
prominent – most notably where Derrida focuses on the aporetic demands
of ‘hospitality.’3 As we will see, these ‘quasi-prophetic’ (Caputo 1993: 91)
interventions demonstrate that there is perhaps nobody more attuned to
the question of what Levinas’s thinking might mean for contemporary
ethical-political theorizing.4 Of course, the precise degree of proximity
between Levinas and Derrida remains contentious.5 Nevertheless, the con-
tinual reformulation of Levinasian motifs in Derrida’s writings is, I believe,
undeniable.6 In the following discussion I will summarize how Derrida has
Contaminations 181
developed and politicized Levinas’s work. More specifically, what interests
me here are: (1) what Derrida’s explicit reflections on hospitality owe to
Levinas’s phenomenology of ‘home’ (outlined in Totality and Infinity7), (2)
how the question of hospitality figures as a backdrop to Derrida’s work on
‘iterability,’ and (3) how his remarks on testimony, trust and faith might
be read along broadly Wittgensteinian lines. As we will see, these three
topics are intimately connected.
and therefore can sanction possession itself.’ That is, in the ‘face of
another being’ (ibid.: 162) the subject’s home (and all ‘possession’ mani-
fest therein) is called ‘in question’ (ibid.: 163),16 and this is why the ‘some-
where of dwelling’ constitutes ‘a primordial event’ (ibid.: 168).
It is at this point that the question of hospitality arises – or, more accu-
rately, shows itself to have already arisen. For now the issue is not primar-
ily about the home as ‘hospitable for its proprietor’ (ibid.: 157) but rather
about the ‘welcome [that] the Home establishes’ (ibid.: 170–1), or my
knowing how to ‘give what I possess’ and thereby ‘welcome the Other who
presents himself in my home by opening my home to him’ (ibid.: 171).
Levinas thus concludes:
[N]o face can be approached with empty hands and closed home. Rec-
ollection in a home open to the Other – hospitality – is the concrete
and initial fact of human recollection and separation; it coincides with
the Desire for the Other absolutely transcendent. The chosen home is
the very opposite of a root . . . The possibility of the home to open to
the Other is as essential to the essence of the home as closed doors and
windows. Separation would not be radical if the possibility of shutting
oneself up at home with oneself could not be produced without
internal contradiction as an event in itself, as atheism.
(1996c: 172–3)17
ship’ (1997e: 14)27), he seems more willing than Levinas28 to cast this in
quasi-epistemological terms. So, for example, Derrida remarks that this
‘nonknowledge is the element of friendship or hospitality for the trans-
cendence of the stranger, the infinite distance of the other’ (1996c: 6).29
This reference to ‘hospitality’ is significant, not only because I previously
identified a certain Levinasian ‘inhospitality’ toward the animal but more
particularly because it is around this Levinasian theme that Derrida devel-
ops a number of ethical, political and quasi-religious concepts.30 Employ-
ing Derrida’s conceptual vocabulary, intersubjectivity can be cashed out as
follows: The other qua other (that is, if she is not merely a reflection of
myself31) can always surprise me.32 That is, for ‘the other to happen, to
come to me’ (1997a: 5) means that I find myself in the domain of the
‘unforeseeable’ (2002a: 361) or ‘perhaps’ (1997a: 5).33 (Levinas similarly
remarks that the ‘perhaps’ is ‘the modality of an enigma, irreducible to
the modalities of being and certainty’ (1996a: 75).34) As discussed in
Chapter 3, Wittgenstein makes a number of related points when contrast-
ing ‘fixed’ behaviors with a natural ‘liveliness’ (1958: §420),35 ‘incalculabil-
ity’ (1994a: 73) and ‘unpredictability of human behavior’ (1990: §603).36
But Derrida’s emphasis on the other’s unforeseeableness takes on more
explicitly political overtones when he proceeds to distinguish between the
‘invitation’ and ‘visitation’ (or hospitality).37 In the invitation – by which
Derrida is primarily referring to the closed invitation (‘Come at 4
o’clock’), not the open invitation (‘Come whenever you want’38) – the
coming of the other is brought under regulatory control; you are invited
and I am therefore ‘expecting you and am prepared to meet you’ (1999a:
70).39 Though even here there remains a necessary possibility (otherwise
this would be mere coercion40) that the other will surprise me by coming
sooner or later than requested – or even not at all41 – the function of the
invitation is to inhibit such possible interruptions of my being-at-home.42
The grammar of the invitation thus shows it to be infused with condition-
ality insofar as it neither stands indefinitely nor precludes its later amend-
ment or withdrawal.43 More specifically, this conditionality is ultimately
founded upon notions of property rights; my being ‘at home’ (Derrida
2000b: 51).44 What the invitation effectively says is: You are permitted
to come and I will thereby grant you some of ‘my’ space and time, for I
rightfully belong here; I am not (and here cannot be) a trespasser.45 These
184 Contaminations
presuppositions are clearly problematic on Levinasian grounds, for, as
previously discussed, ‘the Other . . . calls me into question’ and ‘paralyzes
possession, which he contests by his . . . face’ (Levinas 1996c: 171).46 Given
this fundamentally ‘accusative’ (Levinas 1998b: 111) structure of intersub-
jectivity, one is never simply or unproblematically ‘at home.’ Rather, as
Derrida puts it, one is always the ‘stranger at home’ (1993b: 10), for ‘my
home’ undergoes a continual haunting by the other: ‘[h]ospitality is the
deconstruction of the at-home’ (2002a: 364).47 In contrast to the eco-
nomics of the invitation (though, as we will see, this demarcation is neces-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Outside and inside are both intimate – they are always ready to be
reversed, to exchange their hostility. If there exists a border-line
surface between such an inside and outside, this surface is painful on
both sides . . . The center of ‘being-there’ wavers and trembles.
(Bachelard 1994: 218)66
‘writing’ and ‘iterability.’70 Thus, the necessary threat of death can be seen
to haunt language in general insofar as: (1) the human (linguistic) subject
is vulnerable and mortal, and (2) language, in its structure, transcends the
empirical conditions of this mortality.71 It is to the relationship between
language and finitude that I now want to turn.
word from the world. (One might further imagine that her death obliter-
ates the memories of others concerning anything she may have written
during her lifetime.87) The point of this thought experiment is to illustrate
not only how strange the world would be were language confined by
human finitude but, more radically, whether the concepts of ‘language,’
‘writing’ and ‘communication’ (and, not least, the very distinction between
‘author’ and ‘text’) could even get a foothold.88 That the mortality of the
(linguistic) subject needs to be contrasted with the immortality of the lan-
guage she ‘uses’ is, to borrow Wittgenstein’s words, something about ‘the
natural history of human beings’ (ibid.: §415) which does ‘not strike us
because of [its] generality’ (ibid.: p. 230).89 It is doubtless this ‘generality’
that has contributed to the ill reception of Derrida in certain philosophical
circles (and specifically to his being charged with making ‘trivial’ (1995a:
420) propositions). Of course, were Derrida’s point left in the stark
formulation ‘language is . . . “immortal” ’ (2000a: 402) then it would indeed
appear to be of little philosophical interest.90 What is significant is the way
such general ‘observations which no one has doubted’ (Wittgenstein 1958:
§415) – once their implications are pursued – necessarily effect other,
more specific areas of philosophical, political and ethical concern. Recall-
ing my earlier remarks on Levinas’s preoccupation with Guilt, and the
seemingly ‘trivial’ assertion (made above) that I will some day utter my ‘last
words,’ we can now bring these two themes together: With each word I
testify to my mortality,91 and, by implication, to my having escaped death thus
far. As Derrida puts it, I write, speak, act (and so on) in the name of my
‘survival’ (1995a: 346),92 and as such my activities (linguistic or otherwise)
constitute a ‘living death liturgy’ (1993a: 137).93 But as I argued in Chapter
6, my ‘survival’ is problematic insofar as to be is ‘already an ethical problem’
(Levinas 1993: 48).94 Granted, I am now surviving; this is the condition of
possibility of being an ‘I.’ But, as Levinas inquires, at ‘whose cost’ (1999:
179) is this survival?95 To the extent that my activities (or ‘writing’ in the
broader sense Derrida assigns that term) testify to my survival, they
simultaneously testify to my Guilt for surviving,96 and in doing so betray
their inherently confessional, apologetic nature.97 Levinas thus speculates:
I wonder whether there has ever been a discourse in the world that
was not apologetic, whether . . . our first awareness of our existence is
188 Contaminations
an awareness of rights, whether it is not from the beginning an aware-
ness of responsibilities, whether, rather than comfortably entering
into the world as if into our home, without excusing ourselves, we are
not, from the beginning, accused.
(1994b: 82)
confessing’ (2002a: 383).98 Indeed, he explicitly links this request for for-
giveness to the fact that ‘one is always failing, lacking hospitality . . . one
never gives enough’ (ibid.: 380),99 and, more significantly, to the ‘guilt . . .
for living, for surviving . . . for the simple fact of being there’ (ibid.: 383).
‘knowledge’ and ‘doubt,’116 Derrida reminds us that the possibility for sin-
cerity, authenticity, success, truthfulness (and, not least, hospitality, friend-
ship and goodness) necessarily depends upon the ineliminable potential
for insincerity, inauthenticity, failure, lying (hostility, enmity and evil). In
short, there is a necessary ‘reciprocal contamination’ (1984: 122) between
the grammar of these concepts.117 (As Wittgenstein suggests in Philosophi-
cal Investigations, this is why one cannot, without a certain distortion,
describe the ‘unweaned infant’ (1958: §249) – or many non-human
animals118 – as ‘sincere,’ ‘honest’ or ‘truthful.’119) Of course, circum-
stances may indicate that danger is at hand, be it in the form of physical
violence or mere insincerity. But even here ‘transcendent certainty’
(Wittgenstein 1999: §47)120 is neither available nor required, and thus
cannot be an object of philosophical nostalgia. There is no way of deter-
mining a ‘total context,’121 not least because one ‘cannot precisely
describe’ what constitutes ‘normal circumstances’ (ibid.: §27).122 After all,
what possible contextualization could provide quarantine against any
utterance being used ironically or in quotation?123 Indeed, to this extent
Derrida’s misgivings concerning the simple demarcation between ‘ordin-
ary’ and ‘extraordinary’ language (because what he is ‘trying to find . . .
[is] the production of the extraordinary within the ordinary, and the way
the ordinary is . . . “vulnerable” to or not “immune” to what we understand
as extraordinary’ (2000a: 415)124) are in line with much of Wittgenstein’s
later work. Thus, recalling Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘trust’ and ‘founda-
tional propositions’ in On Certainty, we can re-cast a number of Derrida’s
points on iterability as follows: I have to trust what the other says to me –
or at least trust my own judgement that she is not to be trusted.125 Like-
wise, I trust that what I say will be believed and understood as it was
intended.126 More radically perhaps, I must even trust that I will survive to
the end of this sentence,127 and that you will survive too, no matter how
undetermined the ‘you’ is here.128 (In other words, I trust that the Apoca-
lypse will not arrive in the meantime.129) Such ‘primitive’ (Wittgenstein
1999: §475),130 ‘elementary faith’ (Derrida 1998b: 45) is not therefore
‘hasty but excusable’ (Wittgenstein 1999: §150), for without it one would
simply be ‘incapable of learning,’ and subsequently engaging in ‘language
games’ (ibid.: §283).131 In this crucial sense then, trust is not one
language-game among others.132 Rather, it constitutes that which all
190 Contaminations
language-games133 are hinged upon.134 As Derrida remarks, there could be
‘no society . . . without trust in the other . . . [without] this minimal act of
faith’ (1997e: 23), or, in Winch’s words, the ‘notion of a society in which
there is a language but in which truth-telling is not regarded as the norm
is a self-contradictory one,’ and therefore it would ‘be nonsense to call the
norm of truth-telling a “social convention”, if by that were meant that
there might be a human society in which it were not generally adhered to’
(1960: 242–3).135 That is, ‘some concern with the virtue of truthfulness is a
necessary background condition in any society in which it is possible for
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
anyone to make true statements’ (ibid.: 244).136 At its root such trust is
neither reasonable nor unreasonable,137 not least because ‘it may never
have been expressed’ or even ‘thought’ (Wittgenstein 1999: §159).138 On
this point, I want to suggest, the Wittgensteinian naturalism I have hith-
erto been defending is itself minimal enough to be read into Derrida’s
remarks on ‘testimony’ and ‘trust.’139 Thus Derrida variously remarks:
‘Testimony, which implies faith or promise, governs the entire social space
. . . theoretical knowledge is circumscribed within this testimonial space’
(1999a: 82):
[O]ne can testify only to the unbelievable. To what can, at any rate,
only be believed; to what appeals only to belief and hence to the given
word, since it lies beyond the limits of proof, indication, certified
acknowledgement . . . and knowledge . . . when we ask others to take
our word for it, we are already in the order of what is merely believ-
able. It is always a matter of what is offered to faith and of appealing to
faith . . . Such is the truth to which I am appealing, and which must be
believed, even, and especially, when I am lying or betraying my oath.
(1998c: 20–1)
yes to who or what turns up, before any determination . . . before any
identification, whether or not it has to do with a foreigner, an immi-
grant, an invited guest, or an unexpected visitor, whether or not the
new arrival is the citizen of another country, a human, animal, or
divine creature, a living or dead thing, male or female.
(Derrida 2000b: 77)
That I choose you over her, friends over strangers, my family or commun-
ity (or even species) over ‘foreigners’ – all this I routinely justify. But that
in this very process of justification I apply this set of criteria over another, I
cannot justify.190 In short: ‘I will never know that I have made a good
decision’ (Derrida 2001b: 62). We must of course ‘calculate’191 between
possible choices; Derrida is not advocating random192 or arbitrary action,
neither of which would constitute a ‘decision.’193 Likewise, we have a
responsibility to accumulate as much knowledge as possible in order to
make judgements.194 We must not be willfully anti-rational (after all, how
could this be justified without appealing to another rationality?195). But
the decision to calculate is not itself ‘of the order of the calculable’
(Derrida 1990: 963).196 More specifically, the ‘decision between just and
unjust is never insured by a rule’ (ibid.: 947) because the justice of the rule
– and there might always be a better justice and a better rule197 – would
thereby have to be assumed. Recalling the paradox of Pyrrhonian qui-
etism discussed in Chapter 1, we are always already within the decision:
‘[t]he decision takes place’ (2002f: 312). Even when I am indecisive (even
when I say ‘No!’ to the incessant demands of decision) I have already said
‘Yes’ to indecision.198 This being-in-the-decision is not itself deliberative or
quasi-contractual, but due to the very structure of human finitude.199 In
this way, then, Derrida is not advocating a voluntaristic decisionism but
rather attempting to articulate (which is difficult, if not impossible, insofar
Contaminations 195
as every discourse or meta-discourse presupposes the pre-performative
‘Yes’ for itself200) the affirmative backdrop against which all particular
deliberations occur.201
Despite this ‘always already’ of one’s being-in-the-decision – and some
avowedly ‘hazardous’ reflections regarding Heidegger’s ‘inexcusable
silence’ on ‘Auschwitz and many other topics’ (1988a: 147)202 – Derrida
does not (as Heidegger seems to203) cast suspicion upon apologetic-
confessional practice per se. Rather, what he emphasizes is the necessary,
though again impossible, vigilance demanded by such practices;204 a vigi-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
lance that would both maintain bad conscience and yet also ensure that
such bad conscience never simply masked a deeper good conscience.205
(Though even in this risky formulation Derrida would question the ethi-
cality of a bad conscience that could be ‘ensured.’) There may seem to be
something ‘terrible’ (1997b: 20)206 about all this, but, let us recall, these
aporias do not delineate a ‘trap.’ Rather, they are the very ‘condition of a
decision’ (1999a: 69) and thus of responsibility itself. What characterizes
the experience of the impossible is a ‘perpetual uneasiness’ (1984: 120) in
acknowledging that my worldly activities – insofar as they are necessarily
sacrificial207 – are never wholly just(ifiable).208 As such, ‘remorse’ becomes
‘an essential predicate of the relation we have to any decision’ (1998a:
37), for ‘in our relations with others . . . we should never be sure of having
done the right thing’ (1997b: 23):209
Enduring faith
As noted previously, Wittgenstein maintains that the ‘tendency’ of those
who attempt ‘to run against the boundaries of language’ when talking
about ethics and religion ‘is perfectly, absolutely hopeless’ (1993: 44).
Though worthy of respect, such endeavors nevertheless attempt the
impossible. But, as discussed in Chapter 5, Wittgenstein does not leave us
stranded in the silent landscape of the Tractatus. Despite his claim that
‘Ethics, if it is anything, is supernatural’ (ibid.: 40), Wittgenstein provides
some clues as to the terrestrial dimension of ethical life in his subsequent
references to ‘shame’ and feeling ‘guilty’ (ibid.: 40). Although for both
Levinas and Derrida the ‘desire for the impossible’ is more directly linked
to the question of good conscience and Guilt, to what extent Derrida
shares Levinas’s religiosity is difficult to determine. Thus, in keeping with
both Levinas and the later Wittgenstein, Derrida cautions: ‘We should
stop thinking about God as someone, over there, way up there, transcend-
ent,’ and instead ‘think of God and of the name of God without such idol-
atrous stereotyping or representation’ (1995b: 108). But, we might ask,
what then can be said about God? What viable function can this term now
have? Interestingly, in ‘Circumfession’ Derrida claims that ‘nobody under-
stands anything’ about his ‘religion’ (1993a: 154) – not even his mother
‘who asked other people a while ago, not daring to talk to me about it, if I
still believed in God.’ He proceeds: ‘but she must have known that the
concept of God in my life is called by other names, so that I quite rightly
pass for an atheist’ (ibid.: 155). As Caputo notes, to ‘pass for an atheist’
seems a rather cryptic formulation218 – one might – like the culturally
assimilated Pyrrhonist – ‘pass for’ many things without that determination
getting to the heart of the matter. Here we might recall Wittgenstein’s
Contaminations 197
own remarks concerning the ‘sense in which’ (Drury 1981: 130) he could
be called ‘a Christian.’ Conversely, there is a ‘sense in which’ Derrida
‘quite rightly’ passes for an atheist because ‘God’ goes relatively unnamed
(or at least ‘by other names’) in his life and work. The situation is compli-
cated, not least because Derrida wonders whether it is even ‘possible to
think of responsibility, decision, remorse, and so on . . . outside of a Chris-
tian tradition’ (1997b: 21).219 But it is not difficult to see what ‘other
names’ might pertain to the divine in Derrida’s writings. His preoccupa-
tion with confession, negative theology, the messianic and even prayer220
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
For me, there is no such thing as ‘religion’ . . . Within what one calls
religions . . . there are again tensions, heterogeneity, disruptive volca-
noes, sometimes texts, especially those of the prophets, which cannot
be reduced to an institution, to a corpus, to a system.
(1997e: 21)
[W]hat I call faith in this case is like something that I [say] about
justice and the gift, something that is presupposed by the most radical
deconstructive gesture. You cannot address the other, speak to the
other, without an act of faith, without testimony . . . This ‘trust me, I
am speaking to you’ is of the order of faith, a faith that cannot be
reduced to a theoretical statement . . . So this faith is not religious,
strictly speaking; at least it cannot be totally determined by a given
religion. That is why faith is absolutely universal.
(1997e: 22)
Like Wittgenstein, Derrida does not commit himself to any specific reli-
gious world-picture, and to this extent his position might be described as
atheistic. However, insofar as all world-pictures – indeed, every human
(and perhaps animal) activity, including deconstruction – are governed by
a ‘minimal’ (ibid.: 23) faith, this hesitancy regarding the religious is not
straightforwardly atheistic.222 Indeed, that religious faith is itself dependent
upon a more ‘elementary faith’ (1998b: 45) is consistent with my own sug-
gestion that the absolute ‘trusting’ (Wittgenstein 1994a: 72) demanded by
religion finds a natural counterpart in the ‘primitive’ trusting manifest in
(for example) the parent–child relation.223 In short, the ‘testimonial
space’ Derrida maintains ‘governs the entire social space’ (1999a: 82) is a
natural horizon which, as Wittgenstein might put it, is ‘given’ (1958:
p. 226), or ‘there – like our life’ (1999: §559).224
Synopsis
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Introduction
1 See Kerr 1997: Chs 1–6.
2 See Chapter 2.
3 See also Wittgenstein 1993: 40–4; 1996b: 94–5. As I explain in later chapters, a
‘desire for the impossible’ preoccupies both Levinas and Derrida.
4 Although Derrida’s earlier work is intimately related to these recent preoccu-
pations, I only indicate some of their more striking correlations (see also Bern-
stein 1991: 172–98). The tendency of some commentators (notably Baker
1995: 97–116; Patrick 1997: 71–90) has been to examine the ‘ethics’ of decon-
structive practice. Interesting though these analyses are, their broad methodo-
logical focus often obscures the ethical terrain of Derrida’s thinking.
5 See Caputo 1993; Bernasconi 1997; Critchley 1999a, 1999b; De Vries 1999;
Bennington 2000b: Ch. 3; Llewelyn 2002.
6 See Staten 1986; Garver and Lee 1994; Glendinning 1998; Wheeler 2000.
7 Greisch (1991: 69–74) and Werhane (1995: 61–3) suggest some possible corre-
lations between Wittgenstein and Levinas.
8 Clack (1999) is a notable exception.
9 For his later work Wittgenstein chose ‘ “I’ll teach you the differences” ’ as his
preferred ‘motto’ (Drury 1981: 171).
10 Although I allude to a number of biographical details (on both Wittgenstein
and Levinas), nothing philosophical ultimately turns on them.
11 Though this multiplicity is ‘not . . . fixed, given once for all’ (Wittgenstein
1958: §23).
12 In Chapter 8 I develop this point in relation to Derrida’s remarks on ‘testi-
mony’ and ‘faith.’
13 See also Schutz 1964: 234.
14 See Nielsen 1967; Clack 1999: 78–89. That is, the view that the ‘internal’ rule-
bound religious practices of specific communities are quarantined from the
critical assessment of those ‘outside.’
15 See Nielsen 1967: 193, n. 1.
16 See Trigg 1999: 178.
17 See Nielsen 1967: 191.
18 Unlike Wittgenstein, Frazer’s use of this term is pejorative.
19 See also Wittgenstein 1996a: 64–6, 68, 70, 72–4.
20 As will become clear in later chapters, I would here add ‘vulnerability’ and ‘suf-
fering.’
21 As I argue in Chapter 3, this is why Wittgenstein has interested ‘radical’ plural-
ists like Lyotard.
22 I develop this in Chapters 2 and 3.
202 Notes
23 Similar ideas emerge in Wittgenstein’s suggestion that God’s having ‘com-
manded’ something does not entail that it is even ‘possible’ (1994a: 77) to
meet that demand. I explore this in Chapter 5.
24 As Derrida remarks of his own work: ‘What I am trying to do is to find . . . the
production of the extraordinary within the ordinary’ (2000a: 415).
25 This has partly been due to Levinas (and Derrida) frequently being described
as ‘postmodernists’ – an unhelpfully vague term that tends to be used as a
synonym for ‘skepticism’ and ‘relativism’ (Gellner 1993: 22–4; Gaita 2000:
15–16, 184–5, 258; Graham 2001: 21, 47, 203–4).
26 See Gellner 1993: 23; Davis 1996: 3.
27 See, for example, the essays collected in Campbell and Shapiro 1999. I refer to
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
1 Peaceful thoughts
1 For a condensed version of the present chapter see Plant 2004b.
2 See Drury 1981: 161.
3 See Derrida’s criticism of Wittgenstein (1993a: 62–3), and the former’s more
recent ‘confession’ of his ‘failure’ (2000a: 351) to address Wittgenstein’s work
properly.
4 See Wittgenstein 1993: 462. For some notable exceptions see Drury 1981:
102–8.
5 I here take my lead from Fogelin’s remarks on Wittgenstein and Pyrrhonism
(1986, 1987: Ch. XV; see also Hardwick 1971: 24; Hookway 1990: 16). Fogelin
suggests that this correlation has been overlooked due to the seeming
perversity of reading Wittgenstein alongside any form of skepticism, given
his persistent attempts to undermine the ground upon which the
skeptic stands (1987: 226). But what is at stake here is not whether Wittgen-
stein was ‘really’ a Pyrrhonist (actually familiar with their writings, and so on),
but whether Wittgenstein’s methods and motives exhibit Pyrrhonian tend-
encies.
6 See Drury 1981: 97, 99.
7 See Nussbaum 1991: 521–2, 536, 538, 541.
8 See Nussbaum 1991: 527.
9 Stated otherwise ‘unperturbedness’ (Hookway 1990: 4) or ‘freedom from dis-
turbance’ (Nussbaum 1991: 529). Pyrrho of Elis is thought to have visited
India (Diogenes 1925: 475; Hankinson 1995: 58ff.), which raises interesting
questions about the relationship between Pyrrhonism and Eastern philo-
sophy.
10 See Nussbaum 1991: 538; Sextus 1996: 1:13–17.
11 See also Nussbaum 1991: 540, 545. As we will see, while the strength of treat-
ment may alter, there remains an essential methodology of oppositional argu-
mentation here. As such it is misleading for Sextus to claim that Pyrrhonism
lacks a definitive method.
12 See Diogenes 1925: 491; Hookway 1990: 1; Nussbaum 1991: 548.
Notes 203
13 See Sextus 1996: 1:3–4.
14 On philosophical ‘dogmatism’ see Wittgenstein 1958: §131; 1994b: 72; Niet-
zsche 1968: §446.
15 See Nietzsche 1968: §455.
16 There remains a question as to whether she must implicitly allude to ‘truth.’
On a related point see Derrida 1992a: 257, 265, 288, 296–8; 1996b: 82; 1998b:
18, 26–8, 30, 44–5, 47, 63–4.
17 See Diogenes 1925: 515–17. This is not a trivial maneuver, for ‘[w]hen lan-
guage-games change, then there is a change in concepts, and with concepts
the meaning of words change’ (Wittgenstein 1999: §65; see also 1990: §438).
Note also Rorty’s voluntarism on this matter (1999: pp. xviii–xix, xxii, 176),
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
75 I use the term ‘categorical’ in Kant’s sense (1976: 78ff.), to which I will return
in Chapter 5 with reference to Wittgenstein.
76 See Rhees 1969: 171; Wittgenstein 1993: 161.
77 Both Wittgenstein (1958: §106; 1993: 183; 1994a: 74) and Freud use the
metaphor of untying a knot to characterize their respective projects. Note also
a certain ‘entanglement’ both within and between psychoanalysis and decon-
struction (Derrida 1998a: 1–38).
78 On Wittgenstein’s remarks on the ‘trivial,’ see Moore 1993: 114.
79 On Wittgenstein’s fear of his work leading him ‘to insanity,’ see 1993: 468.
80 See Luckhardt 1991: 255–72. Neither Rhees nor Luckhardt mention Pyrrhon-
ism.
81 See Drury 1981: 96.
82 See Drury 1981: 136; Monk 1991: 334ff.; Shusterman 1997: 21.
83 In this sense Wittgenstein maintains a highly teleological view of philo-
sophical practice in general (and philosophical argument in particular) as
he seems not to address the possibility of someone simply enjoying philo-
sophical perplexity and argumentation. On the possibility and value of non-
teleological argumentation, see Bennington 2000.
84 Philosophy-as-therapy is thus a profoundly ‘counter-institutional institution’
(Derrida 1992a: 58, see also 36; 1995a: 327–8, 346, 376; 2002f: 74–5) insofar as
it both laments its own existence and dreams of its own demise.
85 See also Moore 1993: 114.
86 See Wittgenstein 1958: §93.
87 See Monk 1991: 335, 356–7. Like psychoanalysis, Wittgenstein’s work stresses
the importance of ‘discussion’ (Moore 1993: 113).
88 See Nussbaum 1991: 538, 540, 545; Sextus 1996: 3:280.
89 See Rosenzweig 1999: 55. Putnam (1999, 1–20) here likens Rosenzweig’s posi-
tion with Wittgenstein’s.
90 See also Derrida 1998a: 3, 17.
91 Wittgenstein also speaks of one’s being ‘calmed’ regarding what makes us ‘so
profoundly uneasy’ (1993: 173), that the ‘disorder in our concepts’ can be
remedied in such a way that ‘certain troubles . . . disappear’ (at which point
we reach ‘complete satisfaction’ (ibid.: 181–3)), and that ‘[o]ur object is to
get rid of certain puzzles’ by ‘pulling ordinary grammar to bits’ (1979b: 31).
92 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§25, 244, 343, 415; 1990: §§391, 540–1, 545; 1994a:
31.
93 See Wittgenstein 1996a: 61–81. On the similarities between Wittgenstein’s
work and Tolstoy’s Confessions, Thompson notes their shared emphasis on: (1)
the ‘dissolution’ of life’s problems (1997: 101–7, 109, 111), (2) action over
theory (ibid.: 110), and (3) the non-eschatological nature of religious belief
(ibid.: 104–5). Thompson also alludes to Tolstoy’s naturalistic ‘nostalgia,’ as
does Sontag (1995: 125).
94 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §109; 1990: §690; 1999: §435.
206 Notes
95 See Wittgenstein 1993: 183–7.
96 See also Wittgenstein 1990: §405.
97 See also Wittgenstein’s remarks on the relation between the ‘instinct’ to ask
certain questions and what ‘leads children to ask “Why?” ’ (Moore 1993: 114).
98 In his own commentary on Wittgenstein, Wood mistakenly suggests that it is
traditional philosophy’s ‘attempts to make language behave in artificial ways
that generate philosophical problems’ (1990: 55, my emphasis; see also Rorty
1999: xxi–xxii).
99 Staten’s deconstructive reading of Wittgenstein overlooks his naturalism (see
especially Staten 1986: 75).
100 Wittgenstein suggests that our tendency toward confusion (and the mistaken
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
124 See Wittgenstein 1995: 6.41–445, 6.522. As will become clear in Chapter 2, the
saying/showing distinction re-emerges in On Certainty (Clack 1999: Chs 1–2).
125 Indeed, Wittgenstein claims that the ‘point of the book is ethical,’ and his
concern is with the (absent) book the Tractatus renders impossible to write
(Monk 1991: 178). I will return to this in Chapter 5.
126 Compare with Wittgenstein 1958: §§128–9, 415; 1994a: 63.
127 Compare with Wittgenstein 1958: §§89, 109.
128 See Wittgenstein 1993: 183. This is not, for example, to deny the reality of
free will, but rather to acknowledge that the choices one can make are always
framed within given natural and cultural horizons.
129 See Monk 1991: Chs 8–9. Wittgenstein identifies his happiest times as those
spent away from philosophy (see his letter to Fouracre in Monk 1991: 494).
130 See Drury 1981: 92, 186 n. 9. This is not entirely accurate; one only has to
consider his brief excursion into architecture to see his abilities in other fields
(Monk 1991: 235–8). It would thus perhaps be better to say that Wittgenstein
failed to find anything that captivated him so intensely as philosophy.
131 See also Burnyeat 1983: 123–4; Hookway 1990: 2; Nussbaum 1991: 539, 548.
132 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§23, 114.
133 Recalling the Pyrrhonist’s emphasis on the need to bend with the vacillations
of the world, what Wittgenstein effectively does in Philosophical Investigations is
replace the methodological assumption that ‘the world must fit the theory’
with non-theorizing, descriptive procedures.
134 See Fogelin 1996: 34.
135 On this point, Cioffi’s suggestion (1998: 155–81) that, despite appearances,
Wittgenstein’s anti-instrumentalist reading of Frazer ought not to be taken as
wholesale is in keeping with this warning. I will return to ‘Remarks on Frazer’s
Golden Bough’ in Chapters 3 and 5.
136 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §§103, 115, 133, 255; 1994a: 63; Genova 1995: 33;
Fogelin 1996: 34.
137 See Wittgenstein 1958: §656, p. 200.
138 See Wittgenstein 1958: §133; 1994a: 9.
139 See McGinn 1997: 25.
140 See Burnyeat 1983: 121.
141 See Derrida’s remarks on the relation between the ‘fragment’ and ‘system’
(1999c: 181).
142 See Feyerabend 1988: 281.
143 See Rhees 1969: 170.
144 There is doubtless something to be said about more orthodox confessional
practices and Wittgenstein’s frequent use of an interrogative interlocutor in
his later writings. I will return to confession in Chapter 8 with reference to
Derrida.
145 See Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘confession’ (1994a: 18) and Derrida’s remarks
on the ‘futurity’ of confession and guilt (1997b: 19–21).
208 Notes
146 See Shields 1997: 55–6.
147 I will argue in Chapter 5 that it is this lack of institutional allegiance (and not,
as Holland maintains, Wittgenstein’s alleged incapacity to pray) that lies
behind his claim: ‘ “I am not a religious man . . .” ’ (Drury 1981: 108, 117, 144,
162, 179–80). Holland attempts to address the apparent discrepancy between
the previous remark and Wittgenstein’s comment that ‘I cannot kneel to pray
because it’s as though my knees were stiff’ (1994a: 56). Using Taylor’s ‘The
Faith of the Moralist’ for comparison, Holland concludes that ‘the point
above all which differentiates Taylor’s position from Wittgenstein’s is that a
person in Taylor’s shoes gets down on his knees and prays’ (1990: 28). But
Holland makes no mention of the fact that upon his return from Norway
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Wittgenstein claimed to have there ‘spent his time in prayer’ (Drury 1981:
135), or that on another occasion he remarked that there was ‘a sense in
which’ both he and Drury were ‘both Christians’ (ibid.: 130).
148 See Wittgenstein’s remarks on being ‘obsessed by a certain language form’
(1979b: 98).
149 See Moore 1993: 113.
150 Although Wittgenstein criticizes Freud’s essentialism (1994b: 47–8, 50) and
his failure to show ‘how we know where to stop – where is the right solution’
(ibid.: 42, see also 51; 1994a: 16, 34), Wittgenstein is not unduly perturbed by
Freud’s attempt to develop a new ‘way of thinking’ that makes ‘certain ways of
behaving and thinking natural’ for people (1994b: 45) (see also Wittgen-
stein’s remarks on Darwin and Copernicus (1994a: 18)). But how could he
object, given that – on Wittgenstein’s own admission – this is precisely what he
is attempting to do?
151 See Rhees 1969: 170.
152 See Wittgenstein 1958: p. x.
153 Although one might have to start with oneself before helping others (Wittgen-
stein 1994a: 44).
154 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 32, 53, 64, 86.
155 See Monk 1991: 334ff.; Pascal 1996: 34ff.; Shusterman 1997: 21.
156 See Wittgenstein 1999: §§65, 256.
157 As will become clear in Chapter 3, this emphasis on multiplicity (Wittgen-
stein’s alleged ‘pluralism’) is tempered by his naturalism.
158 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§23, 97, 114; 1999: §321.
159 We should note that in §133 of Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein speaks
of the ‘discovery’ that makes him ‘capable of stopping doing philosophy’ when
he ‘wants to.’
160 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 48. In the preface to Philosophical Investigations
Wittgenstein remarks: ‘Up to a short time ago I had really given up the idea of
publishing my work in my lifetime. It used, indeed, to be revived from time to
time: mainly because I was obliged to learn that my results (which I had com-
municated in lectures, typescripts and discussions), variously misunderstood,
more or less mangled or watered down, were in circulation. This stung my
vanity and I had difficulty in quieting it’ (1958: pp. ix–x, my emphasis).
161 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§105–8. As will become clear in Chapter 5, while
Wittgenstein rejects the linguistic-conceptual perfectionism of his early work,
he maintains a certain ethical perfectionism – something which is perhaps
most apparent in his confession of ‘sins’ to (amongst others) Fania Pascal
(1996: 45–50). I will return to the latter in Chapter 6.
162 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§24, 79–80, 179, 203, 304, p. 224; 1990: §17; 1999:
§§348, 432.
163 See Wittgenstein 1993: 183.
164 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§108, 132, 271.
Notes 209
165 One must distinguish this from the biographical question regarding Wittgen-
stein’s own – often naïve – political sympathies (Monk 1991: 178, 342–4;
Pascal 1996: 55–7).
166 Nyíri focuses on the conservatism elucidated by (amongst others) Kaltenbrun-
ner, Oakeshott, Mannheim, Mohler and Grabowsky.
167 See also Nyíri 1982: 54.
168 See also Nyíri 1982: 45.
169 See Derrida’s remarks on Wittgenstein’s silence and the ‘mystical’ founda-
tions of law (1990: 943).
170 Phillips takes issue with this conservative reading, claiming that ‘[l]eaving
everything where it is involves taking account of cultural turmoil as much as
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
cultural stability’ (1986: 49). But this compounds the problem, for the ques-
tion is not whether the descriptive method (coupled with Wittgenstein’s prin-
ciple of non-interference (1958: §§126, 226)) is ‘conservative’ due to its
selectivity, but whether this approach is conservative insofar as it is descriptive.
171 As will become clear in later chapters, Wittgenstein remained suspicious of
our obsession with ‘reason’ and neglect of more natural ‘phenomena’ and
behavioral ‘patterns’ (1993: 389).
172 See Popkin 1979: 1–17, 49, 70ff.
173 See Nielsen 1967.
174 See also Wittgenstein 1999: §559. Concerning ‘lifestyles, customs and laws’
Philo remarks that ‘since among different people these things are not just
slightly different but utterly discordant, so as to compete and conflict,
necessarily the appearances experienced will differ and the judgments be at
war with one another. This being so, who is so senseless and idiotic as to say
steadfastly that such-and-such is just or intelligent or fine or advantageous?
Whatever one person determines to be such will be nullified by someone else
whose practice from childhood has been the contrary’ (quoted in Annas and
Barnes 1985: 155). I will return to (apparently) similar remarks in On Certainty
in Chapters 2 and 3.
175 Regarding this alleged ‘conservative’ element in Wittgenstein’s work, see also
Jones 1986: 282; Wittgenstein 1993: 407.
176 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§126, 226. With reference to a specifically political
question (the survival of the Irish language), Drury recalls Wittgenstein claim
that: ‘ “It is always a tragic thing when a language dies. But it doesn’t follow
that one can do anything to stop it doing so. It is a tragic thing when the love
between a man and wife is dying; but there is nothing one can do. So it is with
a dying language . . .” ’ (Drury 1981: 152). On a related point, see Derrida
1998c: 30.
177 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 4, 27.
178 For a critique of Nyíri’s ‘conservative’ reading, see Jones 1986; Schulte 1986.
179 Interestingly, when referring to ‘training’ Wittgenstein frequently employs the
German word abrichten; a term normally associated with the ‘conditioning’ of
animals. I thank Peter Baumann for bringing this to my attention.
2 Trusting in a world-picture
1 Parts of this chapter have appeared in Plant 2003a and 2003b.
2 See Pitkin 1993: 325; Scheman 1996: 384.
3 On Certainty was never intended for publication, but rather represents ‘first-
draft material’ Wittgenstein ‘did not live to excerpt and polish’ (1999: p. vi).
Nevertheless, I would suggest that it is precisely the ‘rough edges’ of this text
that make it so provocative (Hudson 1986a: 123–4; Plant 2003b). Indeed,
Wittgenstein’s suggestion that ‘[o]ne could teach philosophy solely by asking
210 Notes
questions’ (1979b: 97) seems especially pertinent when reading On Certainty
(Bambrough 1992: 242).
4 Wittgenstein appears to substantiate Edwards’s reading when he remarks: ‘On
all questions we discuss I have no opinion; and if I had, and it disagreed with
one of your opinions, I would at once give it up for the sake of argument
because it would be of no importance for our discussion’ (Wittgenstein
1979b: 97). But Wittgenstein’s point here is methodological; that he is not
concerned with offering theoretical solutions, but rather with providing gram-
matical reminders concerning the actual use of words.
5 Edwards does not make this Pyrrhonian connection.
6 As I will discuss in later chapters, radically ‘nonfoundationalist’ interpreta-
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
112 See also Wittgenstein 1990: §320; 1999: §§141, 554, 620.
113 See Malcolm 1972: 208; Wittgenstein 1999: §§110, 130. Note also Derrida’s
remarks on the groundlessness of law (1992a: 192, 202–5, 208).
114 It is thus false to say that philosophy begins with doubt (Wittgenstein 1993:
399). On a related point see Derrida’s remarks on the ‘pre-originary pledge’
or ‘faith’ before any ‘question’ (1989: 129–30, n. 5).
115 See Wittgenstein 1999: §110. It is Wittgenstein’s recurrent emphasis on a ‘way
of acting’ that not only discloses his naturalism but also problematizes the
nonfoundationalist reading of his work. As will become clear in Chapters 3
and 5, although Wittgenstein is nonfoundationalist if one means ‘rational’
foundationalism, he nevertheless emphasizes the instinctive, primitive founda-
tions of human life.
116 See Wittgenstein 1958: p. 200; 1999: §475. In this sense there can be no meta-
discourse on trust that would not thereby enact (show) what it aspired to eluci-
date (say). Again, I will return to this in Chapter 8 with reference to Derrida.
117 See Wittgenstein 1958: §116, p. 200; 1999: §§164, 192, 212, 370, 375, 519, 620.
118 See Wittgenstein 1999: §§495, 513, 526, 616, 619, 657.
119 Some notable exceptions include Malcolm 1972; Gill 1974: 282, 290; Martin
1984; Hudson 1986a: 127; 1986b: 175–83; Phillips 1988: 38ff.
120 This is not to say that all types of religious belief are entirely non-hypothetical
(Hudson 1986b: 177).
121 See also Drury 1981: 105.
122 See Martin 1984: 608–13.
123 See Hudson 1986b: 176.
124 See Wittgenstein 1994b: 61.
125 See also Wittgenstein 1994b: 53, 55.
126 See Nietzsche 1968: §161. It would, for example, prove more difficult to
demarcate so sharply between belief in the Last Judgment and the Marxist’s
belief in the coming Revolution.
127 See also Kierkegaard 1973: 255.
128 See Hudson 1986b: 179–80; Wittgenstein 1999: §199.
129 This is an adaptation of one of Sartre’s examples (1977: 35–8). That ‘it is I
myself . . . who have to interpret the signs’ is again brought out by Sartre when
he comments on a ‘remarkable’ Jesuit, who, having experienced ‘a succession
of rather severe [personal] setbacks’ interpreted all this ‘as a sign that he was
not intended for secular successes, and that only the attainments of religion,
those of sanctity and of faith, were accessible to him.’ But of course, this inter-
pretation was not dictated by the phenomena themselves; ‘[o]ne could have
drawn quite different conclusions’ (ibid.: 38). We should here note that
another’s suffering constitutes one ‘phenomenon’ that does not require inter-
pretation, but rather commands us immediately to offer help. I will expand on
this in Chapters 3, 7 and 8.
130 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§5, 630; 1990: §419; 1999: §128.
216 Notes
131 See Wittgenstein 1958: p. 224. Should ‘an irregularity in natural events . . .
suddenly occur’ even that ‘wouldn’t have to throw me out of the saddle’
(Wittgenstein 1999: §619).
132 See Kober 1996: 422.
133 It is possible that a response to such an occurrence would not involve any
deliberation at all – one would instead ‘obey [a] rule blindly’ (Wittgenstein
1958: §219).
134 ‘For me to question my world-picture in this way is already for me to disown it
in the face of a new conviction about how things are’ (Morawetz 1978: 132).
Sartre similarly remarks: ‘if you seek counsel – from a priest, for example –
you have selected that priest; and at bottom you already knew, more or less,
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
While I agree with much of Morawetz’s analysis (and specifically his emphasiz-
ing the stakes involved in questioning one’s own world-picture (ibid.: 132–7)),
I remain unconvinced that one can so easily sidestep the relativism of On Cer-
tainty on these epistemic grounds – that is, without reference to moral consid-
erations. As I will argue in Chapters 3 and 5, other of Wittgenstein’s writings
open the way to a more ethical challenge to relativism.
234 See Kuhn 1996: 151.
235 Kuhn similarly alludes to the ‘conversion experience’ that occurs in the
‘transfer of allegiance from paradigm to paradigm’ (1996: 151). For a more
sympathetic interpretation of this aspect of Kuhn’s work see Hoyningen-
Huene 1993: 221, 252–8.
236 Which is not to say that silence can be adequately characterized as a mere
absence or lack (Lyotard 1988: p. xii, 29; Derrida 1988a: 145–8; 2000b: 135;
Levinas 1989: 487; Heidegger 1999: 208–9).
237 See Bambrough 1992: 243. Note also Derrida’s remarks on ‘forgiveness’
(1992b: 164–8).
238 See James 1985: 209.
239 This terminology is steadily replacing previous discussion of ‘cults’ and ‘brain-
washing.’ For an overview of these ‘new’ religions see Barker 1990: 31–40.
240 This parallels what James says of Revivalism’s understanding of religious con-
version (1985: 228).
241 See Wittgenstein 1999: §262.
242 This might be contrasted with the more formal recruitment procedures of Sci-
entology, where an individual can (allegedly) ‘convert’ themselves (Nelson
1987: 139). From a Wittgensteinian perspective such groups would doubtless
fail the criteria demanded of genuine religiosity. It is perhaps significant that
the ‘religious’ status of Scientology has indeed been contested by a number of
governments (Barker 1990: 40, n. 6).
243 See also Drury 1981: 114.
244 See Wittgenstein 1999: §609.
245 See Wittgenstein 1999: §5. One might be tempted to claim that A’s position
is superior insofar as it can accommodate B’s, whereas B’s position
cannot accommodate A’s (Morawetz 1978: 130–1). But this is questionable.
After all, it is hardly self-evident that B’s position could not accommodate A’s.
One’s temptation to assume this simply reveals a deeper obsession with a
specific, empirical-scientific account of what constitutes genuine ‘accommo-
dating.’ A could doubtless provide a compelling account (to her community)
of B’s activities. But so could B likely provide a compelling account (to
his community) of A’s. The question here is whether cashing out ‘superiority’
in terms of ‘accommodating’ (or ‘being capable of explaining’) is itself
the product of a specific scientific world-picture (ibid.: 124; Wittgenstein
1999: §298)? Moreover, the very notion of being able to ‘embrace and
include’ an alien world-picture and ‘say what they believe’ (Morawetz 1978:
222 Notes
130) is itself problematic (Wittgenstein 1994b: 55). I will return to the latter
in Chapter 5.
246 See Johnston 1991: 142–3; Plantinga 1998: 187–209.
247 This relates to Wittgenstein’s distinction between judgements of ‘relative’ and
‘absolute’ value. I will discuss this in Chapter 5.
248 This is why Rorty simply begs the question when he asserts that ‘the benefits
of modern astronomy and space travel outweigh the advantages of Christian
fundamentalism’ (1999: p. xxv).
249 See Feyerabend 1988: 258.
250 See Plantinga 1998: 131.
251 This point can be seen as a development of Wittgenstein’s remark that ‘[y]ou
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
must ask yourself: what does one accept as a criterion for a medicine’s helping
one?’ (1993: 403). The situation concerning Jehovah’s Witnesses’ rejection of
blood transfusions is pertinent here, for even enforced transfusions fre-
quently make the recipient feel as though they have committed (or at least
been instrumental in) an act of blasphemy.
252 See Wittgenstein 1993: 377.
253 Even on the broadly scientific criteria of theory-simplicity (Kuhn 1996: 206),
B’s account may prove the ‘better’ option (Morawetz 1978: 124).
254 To this extent Wittgenstein’s claim that, through such descriptive procedures,
the other will be ‘convinced’ (1999: §671), is questionable. Regarding A’s
‘explaining’ to B what she is doing – and even showing him microscopic ‘evid-
ence’ in support – we should note Feyerabend’s remarks on Galileo’s argu-
ment with the Church concerning his telescopic findings. Feyerabend
considers the Church’s response to have been ‘scientifically correct’ and also
as having ‘the right social intention, viz. to protect people from the machina-
tions of specialists’ (1988: 137). One of the reasons he draws this conclusion is
Galileo’s failure to substantiate his findings theoretically by volunteering any
cogent reason why the telescope offered ‘better’ observational data than the
unaided eye (ibid.: 89–105, 131–8). Likewise, in my example, B’s coming to
accept A’s ‘evidence’ does not rest on the data presented but rather on B’s
having been trained in A’s world-picture. There is no reason why B should
accept A’s procedures (and microscopic data in particular) as providing ‘evid-
ence’ for anything at all.
255 Preston summarizes Feyerabend’s position on the alleged superiority of
Western medicine as follows: ‘By the very different standards of another tradi-
tion, the “achievements” of Western science may seem piffling’ (Preston 1997:
201). Presumably Preston does not mean that the achievements of Western
science seem ‘piffling’ in the sense that they are only small achievements, but
rather that they are not seen to be ‘achievements’ at all.
256 See Morawetz 1978: 128.
257 And the additional point here is that the criterion of ‘effectiveness’ is also
accepted. The context of my assertions here should make it clear that I am
not advocating an uncritical attitude toward Western medicine per se.
258 See Levinas 1988b: 158.
259 See Caputo 1993: 32–3, 54. The frequent accusation that television news
betrays a deep morbidity in its preoccupation with ‘bad’ news is in this sense
itself morally questionable. For it is precisely the ‘disasters’ that highlight our
shared humanity. The same objection could be made against Rousseau’s
lamentations concerning the tendency of historians to focus on ‘catastrophes’
(1973: 107).
260 See Wittgenstein 1999: §609.
261 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §656.
Notes 223
3 Pluralism, justice and vulnerability
1 See Wittgenstein 1999: §9.
2 See Wittgenstein 1995: 4.121.
3 It is here worth noting the ontological wonder expressed in the Tractatus, ‘A
Lecture on Ethics’ and ‘On Heidegger on Being and Dread.’ Interestingly, in
‘A Lecture on Ethics’ Wittgenstein adds that ‘the right expression in language
for the miracle of the existence of the world . . . is the existence of language
itself’ (1993: 43–4). On this point see Derrida’s remarks on the ‘telephonic yes
. . . which recalls the origin of the universe’ (1992a: 271, see also 260, 270,
273), and the givenness of language (1992b: 27, 80–1; 1998c: 40, 64, 67–8) –
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
including any discourse on the nature of ‘the gift’ and ‘giving’ in general
(1992b: 62, 80, 82, 90–2, 99; 1999c: 58, 66–7, 71). I return to a number of
these themes in Chapter 8.
4 This is a contentious point, and, as will become clear, I favor a minimally nat-
uralistic interpretation of such concepts.
5 See also Sextus’ remarks, cited in Schopenhauer 1995: 122.
6 This relates to Winch’s reflections on the need to contextualize the concepts
of ‘decision’ (1960: 235–7), ‘facts’ (ibid.: 237–8), ‘objective reality’ (1964:
308–9, 313; 1970: 253), and the possibility of ‘different rationalities’ (1964:
316–18; 1960: 236). The extent to which the moral realm is actually frag-
mented in the way Feyerabend (and others) suggest is debatable (Graham
2001: 8–9).
7 Without some appeal to universal criteria Feyerabend could not justify this
use of ‘reasonable’ and ‘civilized,’ for what constitutes each of these will be a
matter of contention between traditions.
8 See Wittgenstein 1958: §23; 1999: §609.
9 See Feyerabend 1987: 106ff.
10 Winch likewise alludes to the mutability of scientific concepts (1960: 234). For
his reflections on scientism, see 1964: 308–9, 321; 1970: 250, 253–4, 258–9.
11 See also Morris 1990: 194. Compare Feyerabend’s remarks with Rousseau’s
advice concerning religious education (1973: 115–16).
12 Concerning Feyerabend’s political agenda, see Preston 1997: 191–211.
13 A similar problem arises when Critchley asserts that ‘the problem of politics is
that of delineating a form of political life that will repeatedly interrupt all
attempts at totalization’ (1999a: 223; see also Campbell 1999: 42, 51), for even
this imperative must thereby enact something of a ‘totalizing’ gesture. Much
the same could be said of Derrida’s claim: ‘This is what must be avoided –
dogmatic theses – this is a categorical imperative; dogmatism . . . must be
avoided at any price’ (2002f: 213).
14 See Johnston 1991: 143.
15 Bernstein (1991: 222) makes a similar point regarding Lyotard.
16 Since 9/11 and the so-called ‘War on Terror’ the themes I will discuss in
this chapter have become even more pressing. Likewise, my discussion of
Levinas and Derrida in Chapter 8 (specifically on the question of ‘hospitality’)
is especially relevant in the current political climate of anxiety about immi-
gration.
17 I will refer primarily to The Rainbow of Faiths where Hick explicitly responds to
his critics (1995).
18 See Hick 1995: 31. Hick suggests that his own pluralism does not claim a ‘priv-
ileged vantage point’ (ibid.: 49) but ‘is arrived at inductively, from ground
level’ (ibid.: 50), and, further, that his hypothesis is ‘offered as the “best
explanation” . . . from a religious point of view, of the facts of the history of
religion’ (ibid.: 51).
224 Notes
19 See Hick 1995: 34–7. A distinction should be made between pluralism and the
mere recognition of plurality (Surin 1990: 117) – a distinction lacking in, for
example, Sugden’s ‘informed evangelicalism’ (1990: 148, see also 150–2).
Pluralism, as Sugden construes it, amounts only to a certain patience and
non-coerciveness regarding the non-evangelical (that is, yet-to-be-converted)
world. Refer also to Derrida 1998b: 21–2; 1998c: 37–8; 2001a: 62–3.
20 See Hick 1995: 34.
21 See Hick 1995: 16, 125.
22 See also Caputo 2001: 20.
23 See Hick 1977: 167–84; 1995: 87.
24 The ‘quasi’ is important here, for although Hick alludes to Wittgenstein’s
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Any society (or individual) inclined to affirm its (or their) moral rectitude is
either dangerously naive or despotic (Caputo 2000: 112, 115). As we will see
in Chapters 7 and 8, both Levinas and Derrida make similar claims.
67 See also Derrida’s remarks on the silencing of madness (1998a: 80–1).
68 Hick seems to think his pluralistic hypothesis constitutes a natural extension
of this implicit pluralism.
69 See Hick 1995: 19.
70 See Readings 1991: 109; Lyotard 1997a: xxiv–xxv.
71 See Lyotard 1988: xiii; 1997a: 82.
72 See also Derrida 1990: 951.
73 For a rather unconvincing account of radical cultural ‘otherness’ regarding
methods of spatialization see Shapiro 1999: 62.
74 See Readings 1992: 181–2. Note also Winch’s remarks on ‘magical influence’
and ‘causation’ (1964: 320).
75 Readings insists that any notion of ‘common humanity’ (or ‘human nature’)
is by definition totalitarian (1992: 174–6, 184, 186). I contest this claim later.
76 See Derrida 2000b: 15, 27, 135. Readings later remarks that the ‘injustice per-
petrated on indigenes is not a racism accidental to modernism which might
be prevented by including them within a wider concept of human nature.
Rather, the assumption of universal human nature, like all modernist meta-
narratives, lights the way to terror even as it upholds the torch of human
rights’ (1992: 186).
77 Here we might recall the Pyrrhonist’s ‘being-at-a-loss,’ discussed in Chapter 1.
Compare these passages with Morawetz’s remarks on On Certainty (1978: 123).
78 See also Pitkin 1993: 325–6; Greisch 1999: 50. Note Husserl’s remarks on
‘empathy’ (1982: 134–5; 1989: 84).
79 Although I will not pursue this here, there is doubtless a story to be told about
Wittgenstein and Hume at this juncture (Clack 1999: 11–24).
80 Similarly, Werhane has misplaced ‘Levinasian’ reservations concerning
Wittgenstein’s later work – specifically his (alleged) inability to develop a
‘notion of the self or of interrelationships between selves’ (1995: 62).
81 See Cockburn 1990: 6, 76; Tilghman 1991: 98.
82 This passage should be contrasted with Wittgenstein’s remark that others are
sometimes ‘a complete enigma’ (that ‘[w]e cannot find our feet with them’),
especially when entering ‘a strange country with entirely strange traditions’
(1958: p. 223; see also Glendinning 1998: 71). The claim that such others are
a complete mystery is misleading. Indeed, these remarks are immediately fol-
lowed by Wittgenstein’s equally deceptive remark that ‘If a lion could talk, we
could not understand it’ (ibid.). I return to the latter in Chapter 7.
83 See Wittgenstein 1990: §567.
84 Even applying the term ‘colony’ presupposes some minimally identifiable form
of social – though not necessarily human – structure (Derrida 2000a: 405).
85 See Winch 1987: 144; Cockburn 1990: 119.
Notes 227
86 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §415; Tilghman 1991: 100–1; Gaita 2000: 269. A
related point is made in Merleau-Ponty 1996: 353.
87 See Cockburn 1990: 77.
88 Wittgenstein also remarks: ‘Only of what behaves like a human being can one
say that it has pains’ (1958: §283), and ‘only of a living human being and what
resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations;
it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious’ (ibid.: §281, see
also §360; Cockburn 1990: 66, 70; Gaita 2003: 44, 59).
89 Wittgenstein’s remarks on slavery illustrate something of the disingenuous-
ness of treating others as mere machines (1990: §§108, 528–30; see also Cavell
1979: 376; Gaita 2000: 48–9, 54–5, 68). One might say that even in ‘hatred’
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
one exhibits a certain ‘form of desire’ (Derrida 1995c: 47) for the other; that
in my saying ‘no’ to the other there lies an indelible trace of a ‘yes’ (Derrida
1996b: 82). I return to these suggestions in Chapters 7 and 8.
90 Gaita alludes to the ‘face’ on a number of occasions (2000: 15, 61–2, 266–8),
though fails to explain its significance. I pursue this in later chapters with ref-
erence to Levinas.
91 See Wittgenstein 1990: §220; Merleau-Ponty 1996: 351.
92 See Wittgenstein 1958: §286; Cockburn 1990: 66–7, 70–1, 77; Rose 1997: 61,
67.
93 See Wittgenstein 1990: §506.
94 Wittgenstein’s allusions to the face may be surprising from a biographical
perspective insofar as he is thought to have suffered from Asperger’s syn-
drome (Guardian Education supplement, 20/2/01: 45).
95 See Tilghman 1991: 97–8; Gaita 2000: 270.
96 See Wittgenstein 1958: p. 179; Winch 1987: 147, 151–2; Kerr 1997: 80; Gaita
2000: 264–6.
97 Eye contact is especially significant here (Cockburn 1990: 5).
98 See Wittgenstein 1958: §537.
99 Although Husserl similarly insists that one does not make an ‘inference from
analogy’ (1982: 111), he nevertheless maintains this general ‘from-me’ struc-
ture insofar as ‘the body over there, which is . . . apprehended as an animate
organism, must have derived this sense by an apperceptive transfer from my
animate organism’ (ibid.: 110; see also Schutz 1964: 22–4, 37; 1974: 62, 104).
For a more sympathetic reading of Husserl on this point, see Derrida 1997c:
123ff.
100 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §285; Dilman 1987: 31.
101 See also Wittgenstein 1969: 162.
102 Compare this with Schopenhauer 1995: 143, 147, 148.
103 Regarding the natural priority of the human face, see Wittgenstein 1958:
§§281, 283, 583.
104 See Descartes 1976: 73–4.
105 See Hume 1988: 159; Tilghman 1991: 98ff.; Gaita 2000: xxviii.
106 See Wittgenstein 1996a: 69; 1994a: 37.
107 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 4. This is perhaps akin to the sense of wonder at
one’s own body (ibid.: 11).
108 See Bergson 1911: 30.
109 By ‘unmechanical’ I do not mean random, which would itself likely generate
an ‘uncanny feeling.’
110 Or better, a degree of iterability (repetition-without-sameness (Derrida 2001d:
76; 2002d: 24)), thus allowing for the possibility of distinguishing between
natural behavioral repetition and catatonia.
111 See Wittgenstein 1990: §§603–4.
112 See Bergson 1911: 32, 34. The history of film bears witness to the fact that
228 Notes
madness, possession and the alien are most effectively portrayed by stunted,
repetitive movements, lifeless speech, limited and inapt facial expressions
(ibid.: 24, 56). Of this repertoire of cinematic devices the ‘fixed look’
(Wittgenstein 1958: §420) stands out. On the role of the face in cinema, see
Balázs 1985: 255–64.
113 See also Cockburn 1990: 119.
114 Bergson’s analysis of comedy is essentially an extended meditation on this
point (1911: 8–10, 16, 18, 20, 24–5, 29–34, 36–7, 43, 48, 57–9, 69, 72–3, 77, 79,
87, 101–2, 109).
115 What does change between each listening is oneself; one’s circumstances,
memories, anticipations, and so on (Derrida 2000d: 65–6). Note also Schutz’s
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
135 See Winch’s remarks on ‘truth-telling’ (1960: 242–6, 250) and Wittgenstein’s
remarks on lying (1958: §249).
136 See also Wittgenstein 1958: p. 223. Of course, none of this is to deny that we
also possess a natural capacity for violence (indeed, Wittgenstein sometimes
appears overly fatalistic regarding this (Drury 1981: 131)). The point is that –
contrary to philosophers like Levinas who judge ‘the natural’ to be essentially
egoistic – it is also natural to care for others. As will become clear in Chapters
6 and 7, the problem with Levinas’s anti-naturalism is that it makes any other-
oriented acts seem like a ‘miracle’ (Greisch 1999: 51; Caputo 2001: 139).
137 See also Wittgenstein 1999: §§391–2, 458.
138 See also Cavell 1979: 110–11; Wittgenstein 1990: §391; Cockburn 1990: 76.
139 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§244, 343; Kerr 1997: 85.
140 It is not incidental that children do not generally display the same sort of
curiosity (‘is this suffering?’) with regard to stones, carpets or iron filings.
141 Despite Tilghman’s later comments (1991: 113), in emphasizing beliefs ‘that
“stand fast” for us’ (ibid.: 104) he does not give due weight to Wittgenstein’s
naturalism.
142 See also Nietzsche 1992b: Essay 2, §7. Caputo makes too much of the possibil-
ity for a ‘genealogy’ of pain (1993: 208–9). Indeed, such a genealogy would
severely problematize Caputo’s forthright condemnation of ‘cruelty or the
causing of useless suffering’ (2003: 177). In a similar vein, Foucault remarks:
‘We believe in the dull constancy of instinctual life and imagine that it con-
tinues to exert its force indiscriminately in the present as it did in the past.
But historical knowledge easily disintegrates this unity . . . We believe, in any
event, that the body obeys the exclusive laws of physiology, and that it escapes
the influence of history, but this too is false. The body is molded by a great
many distinct regimes . . . Nothing in man – not even his body – is sufficiently
stable as the basis for self-recognition or for understanding other men’ (2000:
379–80; see also Derrida 2001c: 262; 2002f: 204, 210). Needless to say, I think
these claims are fundamentally misguided.
143 See Caputo 1993: 196, 216. My suggestions here correlate with Winch’s ‘limit-
ing notions’ of ‘birth, death’ and ‘sexual relations’ (1964: 322) (categories
echoed in Wittgenstein 1996a: 66–7) which ‘are inescapably involved in the
life of all known human societies in a way which gives us a clue where to look,
if we are puzzled about the point of an alien system of institutions.’ For
Winch, then, ‘the very notion of human life is limited by these conceptions’
(1964: 322, see also 324), and in this crucial sense his position is not relativis-
tic (ibid.: 308, 320–1; 1960: 232–3, 238, 244, 250; 1970: 249). With Winch’s
‘limiting notions’ in mind, note also Derrida’s remarks on the transcultural
preoccupation with death (1993b: 24, 42–4, 60–1).
144 See Tilghman 1991: 113; Caputo 2000: 111.
145 See Winch’s remarks on the necessary presuppositions for understanding
another human being and/or culture (1960: 232–3; 1970: 250). Wittgen-
230 Notes
stein’s remarks on ‘agreement . . . in form of life’ (1958: §241) should likewise
be read in this minimally naturalistic light.
146 See also Schopenhauer 1995: 139.
147 See Mates 1996: pp. 30–1.
148 I am not denying that genuine amoralism and/or ‘moral blindness’ are pos-
sible (Gaita 2003: 167ff.). My point is to caution against applying these cat-
egories too hastily.
149 Wittgenstein’s reflections on ‘free will’ are interesting here, particularly his
suggestion that determinism is a form of ‘fatalism’ (1993: 431) and signifies
‘that you don’t want to make [the other] responsible, or be harsh in your
judgment’ (ibid.: 433) (‘It is the way in which we look at a case when we don’t
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
(Levinas 1988b: 162; Peukert 1998: 156; Gaita 2000: 111, 141).
197 Winch is unclear on this point, for while he also alludes to ‘radical disagree-
ment’ (1987: 186), in his subsequent remarks on Orwell and Ghandi he seems
to imply that such a degree of conflict would be impossible (ibid.: 187–8).
198 See Davidson 1984: 184–5, 192, 197; Bambrough 1992: 247–50; Wittgenstein
1999: §156.
199 See Caputo 1993: 29, 54.
200 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 45–6. Tilghman similarly concludes that ‘the human
body and especially the human face [is] a moral space, that is . . . the locus of
the possibility of all those expressions that are at the basis of moral life’ (1991:
115; see also Caputo 1993: Ch. 9; Gaita 2000: 283). I return to these points in
Chapters 6 and 7.
201 One commentator remarks of the Habermasian agenda: ‘If there is a univer-
sal moral community, it is constituted by a relatively narrow set of norms,’ and
proceeds: ‘Because the forms of the good are plural and because all humans
are subject to common vulnerabilities, the solidarity projected by a discourse
ethics must be based largely on a vision of the “damaged life” rather than an
affirmative view of the “good life” ’; ‘To the extent that all humans are vulner-
able in similar ways, it is plausible to suppose that there are “generalizable
interests” that could provide the basis for norms that would command univer-
sal assent’ (Moon 1995: 152; see also Caputo 1993: 41). However, Habermas
clarifies that he is primarily concerned with vulnerabilities of socialization
(1983: 120–2; 1996: 196–7), not those of ‘biological’ (1983: 120) fragility.
4 Interlude
1 This would hold even on a differential account of meaning where the absent
(excluded) terms play a constitutive role in the production of meaning.
2 Of course, we are dealing also with the practices within which words have their
life (Wittgenstein 1990: 144; 1994a: 85; 1994b: 55). The point I am drawing
from this passage might usefully be correlated with Heidegger’s remarks on
‘equipment’ that becomes ‘conspicuous’ due to its breaking or otherwise being
rendered ‘unusable’ (1999: 104–5).
3 Interestingly, Winch remarks that ‘human beings are essentially potential critics
of each other’ to the point where even another’s presence can constitute ‘an
implicit criticism’ of one’s ‘views of life’ and ‘roles in life’ (1987: 180, see also
146–7, 150). The Levinasian significance of such claims will become clear in
Chapter 6.
4 See Handelman 1991: 195.
5 This, of course, constitutes the problem at the root of every naive contractual-
ism. See also Levinas 2000: 164.
6 See Winch’s remarks on the Good Samaritan (1987: 174) and tolerance (ibid.:
190).
Notes 233
7 See Winch 1987: 174; Caputo 1993: 126–7; Schopenhauer 1995: 126, 130, 138,
144; Levinas 1998a: 163; 1998b: 227.
8 As I discuss in Chapter 8, the notion of pure self-sacrifice is complicated on
Derrida’s account (1992b: 7, 10, 12, 27, 29–30, 76, 104, 123; 1993b: 38–9, 79;
1995b: 42–5). Nevertheless, he would concede that a certain desire for ‘the
impossible’ remains essential to moral life (1992b: 8, 31, 36; 1999c: 59, 72).
9 See Derrida 1992a: 68; Bennington 1993: 310.
discussed in Chapter 3.
2 See also Caputo 1993: 120.
3 See also Derrida 1990: 927, 1015; 1997c: 117, 125.
4 It thereby constitutes both the conditions of possibility and impossibility of
ethical responsibility: Conditions of possibility insofar as any relationship with
the other demands such a prior identification of them as ‘other.’ Conditions of
impossibility because this identification means that any subsequent relation will
never be wholly uncontaminated by such a primary ‘violence’ (Derrida 1971:
328; 1992b: 12; 1997c: 132, 137–8, 140–1, 143, 152; 2002c: 135; 2002f: 298,
300; Caputo 1993: 74–5, 80–3; Levinas 2001: 51). I return to this in Chapter 8.
5 See Wittgenstein 1994b: 63, 71–2. One’s having no ‘clear idea’ here does not
necessarily mean that the utterance is absurd, but rather that one would not
know how to make such an assessment (Winch 1964: 311–12, 319; 1970: 256–7).
6 See Drury 1981: 162; Wittgenstein 1994a: 48.
7 See Mates 1996: pp. 30–2.
8 See Engelmann 1967: 77.
9 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 33. Only if such dissent involved a denial of the truth
of the believer’s utterance would such a pre-understanding be assumed. As
noted in Chapter 1 with reference to Pyrrhonism, such pre-understanding
would not be assumed if one denied that the believer’s utterance had
meaning. It is therefore striking that Wittgenstein does not merely dismiss the
believer’s utterances as meaningless. One of the reasons he invests so much
time in reaching a sympathetic understanding of religious concepts must be
located in the fact that people do profess such beliefs and that these beliefs do
play a pivotal role in their lives. While a specific belief may be ‘mistaken,’ how
an entire way of life could be ‘mistaken’ is significantly less clear (Wittgenstein
1996a: 61).
10 For a similarly striking example see Kierkegaard 1965: 69–78.
11 See Tolstoy 1987: 66, 68. As Wittgenstein remarks: ‘everything will be different
and it will be “no wonder” if you can do things that you cannot do now’
(1994a: 33).
12 This is not to say that the believer is necessarily better placed to understand
and represent another’s non-belief.
13 See Phillips 1970: 69; Cavell 1979: 371–2.
14 See Wittgenstein 1993: 181; 1994b: 72.
15 See also Wittgenstein 1994b: 56, 61–2, 71; 1999: §361.
16 See also Wittgenstein 1996a: 61. Note also Winch’s remarks on contradiction
(1960: 234; 1964: 312, 314–15; 1970: 254, 257–8). Wittgenstein once claimed
that ‘many controversies about God could be settled by saying “I’m not using
the word in such a sense that you can say . . . ”, and that different religions
“treat things as making sense which others treat as nonsense, and don’t
merely deny some proposition which another religion affirms” ’ (Moore 1993:
103).
234 Notes
17 See also Wittgenstein’s distinction between secular and sacred history (1994a:
31–2; 1994b: 53–4, 56–7). This might usefully be compared with Derrida’s
own distinction between the ‘future’ and that which is ‘to come’ (1990:
969–71; 1992a: 37–8; 1997a: 2, 9; 1997b: 19–20, 30; 1998b: 7, 47; 1999a: 79;
2001d: 67).
18 See Wittgenstein 1994b: 61. Note also my discussion of blasphemy in Chapter
2.
19 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§109, 126. Of course, after such analysis another’s
professed belief may show itself to be merely hypothetical – and thus, for
Wittgenstein, not ‘genuinely’ religious.
20 See Winch 1987: 198, 200; Wittgenstein 1994a: 85; 1994b: 55. For a similar
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
modern science has rendered such natural phenomena any less awe-inspiring
(Wittgenstein 1994a: 5; 1996a: 67). Indeed, we might recall our own ritualized
fascination with such phenomena, the decline of which is neither inevitable
nor prerequisite for one’s immersion into secular world-pictures (Winch
1987: 202–4). Note also Levinas’s phenomenology of ‘enjoyment’ (1996c:
110ff.).
42 Frazer would have to concede this in order to assess the superiority of one
over the other (Drury 1981: 134).
43 This point cuts both ways: the charge – often made from a misplaced self-
deprecation by Westerners – that the West is spiritually barren, is similarly
superficial. See Derrida’s remarks on the ‘secular’ (2001b: 67).
44 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 16.
45 See Bambrough 1992: 249–50.
46 See Wittgenstein 1996a: 61.
47 While the existential complexities of (for example) Kierkegaard’s troubled
relationship with Regina Olsen (Kierkegaard 1965: 69–78) can only begin to
be understood by virtue of our naturally shared orientation to seek compan-
ionship and sexual partners, to hope to illuminate this specific episode by a
study of (for example) primate behavior would clearly be misguided. Wittgen-
stein’s accusation that ‘Frazer is much more savage than most of his savages,
for they are not as far removed from the understanding of a spiritual matter
as a twentieth-century Englishman’ (1996a: 68) is not reductive in this sense.
For Frazer’s ‘savagery’ is not only not inevitable (he could be attuned to such
‘spiritual matter[s]’), it is also anomalous with a genuinely ‘anthropological’
attitude.
48 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 78; 1996a: 80.
49 See Derrida 1995c: 3.
50 The square brackets and enclosed text are present in the translation. I have
added emphasis to suggest that, although Wittgenstein can begin to identify
what ‘consequences’ might follow from such a statement (‘ethical ideas of
responsibility’), he is not sure that the person who makes such a claim
necessarily has these in mind.
51 Similar analyses could be offered of the lover’s pronouncement ‘I have always
loved you’ or ‘I will always love you.’ The ‘always’ here is not empirical-histor-
ical; ‘I will always love you’ does not mean that, if our relationship ends, I have
thereby been proved an opportunist or disingenuous. Neither does it commit
me to believing that our relationship will continue post mortem in some spir-
itual realm. The ‘always’ here is rather a performative pledge of commitment.
52 The square brackets and enclosed text are present in the translation.
53 Gaita’s position on the religious and non-religious is interesting here. On the
one hand, he claims that religious language (concerning, for example, the
‘sacredness’ of others) is a superior form of expression than its ‘secular
equivalent’ (2000: 23; see also Nielsen 1967: 196). On the other hand, Gaita
236 Notes
not only makes much of ‘non-religious’ ritual (2000: 219–21) but also suggests
of the ‘soul’ that the ‘religious or metaphysical conception . . . depends on the
conception expressed in the more natural ways of speaking’ (ibid.: 239, my
emphasis). His point would thus seem to be twofold: (1) we should not con-
flate ‘secular’ with ‘natural’ ways of speaking, and (2) the religious is closer to
the ‘natural’ than the scientific and philosophical.
54 See James 2:17–18. In response to a letter received from a pupil telling him of
their conversion to Catholicism, Wittgenstein pithily remarked: ‘ “If someone
tells me he has bought the outfit of a tight-rope walker I am not impressed
until I see what is done with it” ’ (Drury 1981: 103).
55 Regarding Tolstoy’s A Confession, Greenwood remarks: ‘What he leaves us
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
with, in the end, is an overwhelming feeling of his need for God to exist and
his sense that many among the people possess an enviable faith in the reality
of that existence which he himself lacks’ (1975: 121). Much the same could be
said of Wittgenstein (Drury 1981: 162, 182) – indeed, Greenwood’s allusion to
‘envy’ (a word Tolstoy himself uses (1987: 73)) goes some way toward explain-
ing why Wittgenstein cannot adequately be described as ‘agnostic.’
56 As will become clear in Chapters 6 and 7, this formulation similarly applies to
Levinas’s work.
57 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 86.
58 See Breton 1984: 98.
59 See also Wittgenstein’s remarks on the need for one’s ‘soul . . . to be saved,’
not one’s ‘abstract mind’ (1994a: 33), and the marginal value of ‘sound doc-
trines’ (ibid.: 5) for the religious life.
60 See Malcolm 1958: 20; Engelmann 1967: 77–8.
61 In this regard it is significant that, like Nietzsche, Wittgenstein suggests that
‘even our more refined, more philosophical doubts have a foundation in
instinct’ (1994a: 73).
62 A reverence perhaps more obvious in Heidegger’s work. Interestingly, in his
own brief remarks on Heidegger, Wittgenstein again refers to ‘the astonish-
ment that anything exists’ (1978: 80).
63 See also Wittgenstein 1993: 44.
64 See also Derrida’s comments on his own preoccupation with negative theo-
logy (1995c: 69) and the ‘impossible’ more generally (1990: 981; 1995c: 81). I
return to the latter in Chapter 8.
65 See Wittgenstein 1993: 40.
66 See also Picard 1948: 227.
67 As discussed in Chapter 3, the traditional is/ought distinction maintained in
both the Tractatus and ‘A Lecture on Ethics’ is problematized by Wittgen-
stein’s later phenomenology of the body. Regarding Wittgenstein’s attitudinal
emphasis on the ontological question, see also his remarks on belief in pre-
destination (1994a: 30), fate (ibid.: 61) and free will (ibid.: 63).
68 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 32, 53, 61, 63; 1994b: 53–4.
69 See Phillips 1970: 44–5.
70 See Malcolm 1972: 214. This is why any alleged religious movement which
does not aim at the transformation of the moral character of the convert
might be referred to as ‘religious’ in only an attenuated sense (ibid.: 211).
71 See Wittgenstein 1958: §109.
72 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§38, 132. Note also Wittgenstein’s remarks on
Socrates (Drury 1981: 131) and Hegel (ibid.: 171).
73 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 41.
74 Passages like this – where Wittgenstein appears to advocate a change in the way
we speak – clearly threaten the ‘conservative’ interpretation of his work dis-
cussed in Chapter 1 (Jones 1986: 282).
Notes 237
75 See also Moore 1993: 109–10.
76 See Wittgenstein 1969: 18.
77 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 22.
78 See Phillips 1970: 49. In response to Drury’s admission that he thought of
‘death as the gateway to a permanent state of mind,’ Wittgenstein ‘seemed
disinclined to continue with this conversation’ – Drury having ‘the feeling
that [Wittgenstein] thought what [Drury] had said was superficial’ (1981: 147,
see also 183). Analogously, the same might be said of confession, for this
cannot be adequately understood as an exercise in personal reportage
(Derrida 1993a: 16–18, 48, 56; 1995c: 38–9; 1999c: 98–9). What differentiates
confession from the ‘merely’ autobiographical is the way the former ‘has to be
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
to Levinas).
92 Though they are always susceptible to becoming ‘complete automatism’
(Bergson 1911: 46, see also 44–5; Derrida 1995c: 132–3). Here again one
might talk of a certain iterability (I return to this in Chapter 8).
93 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 30. One sees this lower level of religiosity emerge in
Wittgenstein’s markedly Pyrrhonian advice to Drury to ‘try experiments in
religion. To find out, by trying, what helps one and what doesn’t’ (Drury
1981: 179).
94 While in Norway Wittgenstein ‘spent his time in prayer’ and had also ‘felt it
necessary to write out a confession’ (Drury 1981: 135) – the latter was eventu-
ally offered to, amongst others, Moore and Fania Pascal (ibid.: 190–218;
Pascal 1996: 45–50).
95 Likewise, when Wittgenstein remarks to Drury that ‘the religion of the future’
will perhaps be ‘without any priests or ministers,’ he proceeds to suggest that
‘one of the things you and I have to learn is that we have to live without the
consolation of belonging to a church’ (Drury 1981: 129, my emphasis).
96 Recalling my discussion of Rhees in Chapter 1, emphasizing this terminology
tends to make Wittgenstein’s view of philosophy look overly categorical.
97 This is most evident in Wittgenstein’s ‘A Lecture on Ethics.’ Moreover, the
notion of absolute dependence relates to what I said in Chapter 2 concerning
the role of unconditional trust in On Certainty (indeed, both Hertzberg (1988:
309–10) and Shields (1997: 48) allude to Abraham and Isaac in this respect).
See also Derrida 1995b: Chs 3–4.
98 See also Wittgenstein 1979a: 74.
99 See also Shields 1997: 65; Gaita 2000: 219–20.
100 See also Shields 1997: 70.
101 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 29, 32, 45, 53; 1994b: 56, 58.
102 See Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘How God judges a man’ (1994a: 86), and
Derrida’s comments on God not having ‘to give his reasons or share anything
with us’ (1995b: 57).
103 As Hertzberg remarks of ‘reliance’ and ‘trust’: ‘In relying on someone I as it
were look down at him from above. I exercise my command of the world. I
remain the judge of his actions. In trusting someone I look up from below’
(1988: 315, my emphasis). Of course, even in Abraham’s example, God did
not demand what was practically impossible (Kierkegaard 1985: 44–6). Wittgen-
stein’s remarks thus seem to move beyond even Abraham’s example; namely,
that God could demand of me not merely something I cannot justify (beyond
the fact that He has commanded it) but something I could not do even if I had
the will to do it. As will be seen in Chapter 8, Derrida’s remarks on respons-
ibility and im/possibility are pertinent here.
104 See also Phillips 1970: 68–9.
105 Interestingly, Tolstoy remarks: ‘the essence of any faith consists in giving a
meaning to life that will not perish with death’ (1987: 68).
Notes 239
106 That is, in this primitive experience of bad conscience one undergoes a
certain ‘haunting’ by the other (Levinas 1984: 63; Derrida 1993a: 260–3;
1993b: 20). I return to this in Chapter 6.
107 For a detailed analysis of the relationship between ‘A Lecture on Ethics’ and
the Tractatus, see Edwards 1985: 75–101.
108 See Kant 1976: 78ff.
109 See Wittgenstein 1993: 38–9; Derrida 1995a: 273, 276.
110 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 3; 1995: 6.42; Levinas 1998a: 154.
111 See Wittgenstein 1978: 80–1.
112 See also Engelmann 1967: 74–5.
113 See also Derrida 1995c: 17–21. Wittgenstein similarly remarks that he should
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
like to ‘put an end to all the idle talk about Ethics – whether there be know-
ledge, whether there be values, whether the Good can be defined, etc.’ (1978:
80–1).
114 See Wittgenstein 1995: 6.4–6.421.
115 In one of his more caustic moments Levinas remarks: ‘Those who have
worked on methodology all their lives have written many books that replace
the more interesting books that they could have written. So much the worse
for the philosophy that would walk in sunlight without shadows’ (1998a: 89).
The extent to which Wittgenstein’s remarks on ethics here correspond to
Levinas’s own textual practice is discussed in Chapter 6.
116 This relates to what I said in Chapters 1 and 2 regarding the need for shared
criteria in judgement. See also Drury’s remarks concerning his first meeting
Wittgenstein at the Moral Sciences Club (Drury 1981: 114).
117 See Phillips 1970: 47.
118 See Winch 1987: 176. The distinction between the ‘relative’ and ‘absolute’ is
not straightforward. One might argue that ‘You ought to want to play tennis
better because your partner will then get more enjoyment out of the game,
and her enjoyment is of greater ethical significance than your own content-
ment to play badly.’ Here playing tennis is thus the means by which a deeper
ethical obligation toward increasing the happiness of others becomes realiz-
able.
119 In Chapter 6 I discuss Levinas’s work under the rubric of the ‘guilt of the sur-
vivor’ with specific reference to the impact of the Holocaust on his work. On a
biographical note, Wittgenstein might also have experienced something of
this ‘guilt’ regarding the suicide of three of his brothers (Monk 1991: 11ff.).
Interestingly, although Wittgenstein himself contemplated suicide many
times, he nevertheless judged this to be ‘the elementary sin’ (1979a: 91; see
also Gaita 2000: 221–2).
120 Likewise, the question ‘What’s the point in friendship?’ is misplaced (assum-
ing it is not really a cry of despair). There is no essential ‘point’ to friendship,
although doubtless one can retrospectively identify certain benefits of having
friends. The initial question erroneously assumes that there are good reasons
upon which friendship is ‘founded.’ See also Derrida’s remarks on ‘forgive-
ness’ (2001e: 27).
121 See also Caputo 2000: 121; 2001: 4, 12–13.
122 See Derrida 1999e: 132–3.
123 See Schopenhauer’s remarks on how religion does not combat egoism but
rather shifts it to ‘another world’ (1995: 137).
124 On the anthropological ‘principle of loss,’ see Bataille 1996: 116–23.
125 See also Nietzsche 1968: §§172, 246; 1992b: First Essay §§14–15. Kierkegaard
remarks: ‘Official preaching has falsely represented religion, Christianity, as
nothing but consolation, happiness etc. And consequently doubt has the
advantage of being able to say in a superior way: I do not wish to be made
240 Notes
happy by an illusion. If Christianity were truthfully presented as suffering,
ever greater as one advances further in it: doubt would have been disarmed’
(1965: 209). This sentiment is echoed in Wittgenstein’s conversations with
Drury (1981: 110). King similarly recalls Wittgenstein having claimed: ‘ “of
one thing I am certain – we are not here in order to have a good time” ’
(1981: 90).
126 See Derrida 1990: 953; 1996b: 86.
127 See Malcolm 1958: 52; Redpath 1990: 50; Sontag 1995: 57, 64; Pascal 1996: 32.
128 See also Drury 1981: 101, 117–18.
129 There is a correlation between this passage and Wittgenstein’s own remark
that: ‘ “You can’t hear God speak to someone else, you can hear him only if
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
you are being addressed”. – That is a grammatical remark” ’ (1990: §717). The
‘grammatical’ point here concerns the impossibility (at least in the Judeo-
Christian tradition) of coolly witnessing God addressing an other, for to hear
God is always to have oneself implicated. See also Levinas’s endorsement of
Halevy’s suggestion that ‘God speaks to each man in particular’ (Levinas
1994a: 184), and Derrida’s remarks on ‘speak[ing] with God’ (1995b: 57).
130 The sentiments of this passage are repeated a number of times in The Bothers
Karamazov, particularly in ‘From the Discourses and Sermons of Father
Zossima’ (Dostoyevsky 1967: 376–9).
131 See also Wittgenstein 1994a: 86.
132 See Derrida 1993b: 19–20; 1997b: 20–1; 1999: 67.
133 See Engelmann 1967: 80. Again, Wittgenstein’s Jewish heritage may be rele-
vant here (Drury 1981: 175).
134 See Glendinning 1999, 2000.
135 See Davis 1996: 129–41.
136 According to Levinas this was his ‘main theme’ (1999: 179; see also 2000: 12,
17).
6 Trespassing
1 Parts of the present chapter have appeared in Plant 2003c.
2 See also Derrida 1997c: 90–1. Levinas claims that ethics is ‘unintelligible
within being’ (2000: 172).
3 See Levinas 1994a: 94.
4 See Greisch 1991: 71.
5 According to Greisch, what Levinas provides (specifically in his remarks on
the ‘here I am’ that precedes discourse) is an ‘answer to the question of the
essence of language’ (1991: 69), or ‘the condition of possibility of all . . . lan-
guage games’ (ibid.: 70). Greisch’s remarks on ‘sincerity’ (ibid.: 69; see also
Levinas 2000: 190–4) might usefully be read alongside Wittgenstein’s reflec-
tions on trust discussed in Chapter 2.
6 By focusing on Wittgenstein’s earlier ‘transcendental’ (Greisch 1991: 72) view
of ethics, Greisch overlooks how Wittgenstein’s naturalism problematizes the
‘nonfoundationalist’ reading. As will become clear, although Levinas denies
that he is seeking ‘the “transcendental foundation” of “ethical experience” ’
(1994a: 148; see also 2000: 200), the face of the other ‘accusing’ me is
emphatically not proffered as a hypothesis. On the contrary, insofar as the
‘flesh-and-blood’ (Nuyen 2000: 415) face makes demands on me immediately,
one might say that the other’s face is the indisputable ‘given’ of Levinas’s
work.
7 See Handelman 1991: 258; Levinas 1992: 22; 2001: 24, 28, 81, 89; Stone 1998:
5.
8 See Levinas 1992: 98, 101; 1993: 44; 1994a: 146; 1996a: 102; 1998b: 105; 2001:
Notes 241
72, 133. According to Robbins (1999: 147) this citation appears at least twelve
times in Levinas’s work.
9 See Levinas 1999: 101.
10 See also Levinas 2000: 175.
11 For the Heideggerian–Levinasian application of these terms I will, where pos-
sible, capitalize ‘Conscience’ and ‘Guilt.’
12 See also Levinas 1984: 51–2; 1989: 487–8; 1992: 38, 42; 1997a: 281; 2001: 141.
Levinas’s explicit reference to Heidegger’s remarks on Guilt are extremely
negative (Levinas 2001: 141). As will become clear, I believe that Levinas
remains blind to the affinities between his own work and Heidegger’s on this
topic.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
82 With this passage in mind, see Melville’s short story ‘Provenance of a face’
(1999: 169–77).
83 See Caputo 1993: 32.
84 Although Levinas provides a number of qualifications as to what he means by
this term, he is explicit that his primary concern is the other human being
(1998a: 88; 1998b: 10). I return to this in Chapter 7.
85 See Levinas 1984: 50.
86 See Levinas 1992: 61.
87 See also Levinas 1988a: 176. Here one might also recall Exodus 33:20–3.
88 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 82.
89 See Wittgenstein 1958: p. 179.
90 See also Levinas 1996c: 66; Robbins 1999: 23–5.
91 See Levinas 1988a: 171; 1992: 57, 61; 1993: 158; 1996a: 22, 92. As will become
clear later, the face is not Levinas’s only route of access to the ethical (1992:
87, 117; 1993: 94, 103).
92 See also Levinas 1992: 87; 2001: 48–9, 135, 204, 208, 215.
93 See also Levinas 1992: 96; 1993: 35, 44; 1996a: 22; 1998b: 232.
94 See also Levinas 2000: 196.
94 See Handelman 1991: 209; Levinas 1992: 60; 1993: 39; 1998a: 154.
96 See Derrida 1993c: 122; 1995b: 99.
97 See Jay 1993: 555–60.
98 See Levinas 1996c: 50–1.
99 See Caputo 1993: 199–200.
100 See Levinas 1992: 75–6; Derrida 1997c: 118.
101 See also Handelman 1991: 211; Levinas 1998a: 138.
102 See Peperzak 1993: 162–3; Levinas 1996c: 295–6; Derrida 1997c: 99–100.
103 See Handelman 1991: 210.
104 See Levinas 1996c: 191; 2000: 163, 165–6.
105 See Wittgenstein 1990: §222. Of course, the ear is not entirely passive, for
there is a difference between hearing and listening (a distinction Levinas some-
times understates (2000: 201)).
106 See Handelman 1991: 220. While one can be selective regarding what one
chooses to look at, one cannot be similarly selective about what one hears (or
smells) – though one can choose to ignore what one hears (Levinas 1996a:
54). This is why it would be better to say that for Levinas the other’s face is
heard more than it is seen (2000: 173).
107 See also Levinas 1998a: 170; 1998b: 145.
108 See Handelman 1991: 211; Levinas 1996a: 76; 1998b: 96, 186; Derrida 1997c:
100.
109 See Levinas 1988a: 174; Robbins 1999: 23, 57. Barthes’s analysis of the photo-
graphic image – and specifically its power to awaken a sense of ontological
guilt in the viewer (2000: 84) – might usefully refine Levinas’s rather dismis-
sive attitude to the face in its ‘plasticity.’
Notes 245
110 See also Levinas 1998b: 168–9, 186.
111 See Levinas 1998b: 104; Robbins 1999: 64.
112 See also Derrida 1990: 929.
113 A qualification needs to be made here, for the ‘face is not a force. It is an
authority. Authority is often without force.’ Likewise, on the punitive interpre-
tation of God, Levinas proceeds: ‘That is a very recent notion. On the con-
trary, the first form, the unforgettable form, in my opinion, is that, in the last
analysis, he [God] can not do anything at all. He is not a force but an author-
ity’ (1988a: 169).
114 See Levinas 1992: 89, 86; 1998b: 108; Derrida 1997c: 104.
115 See also Levinas 1996a: 17, 54; 1998b: 105. Levinas also remarks that ‘the face
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
immanence’ (ibid.: 59, see also 69), and that ‘[o]nly the meaning of the other
is irrecusable, and forbids the reclusion and reentry into the shell of the self’
(1994a: 183).
142 See also Levinas 2000: 187; 2001: 50, 55.
143 See Robbins 1999: 16–19; Levinas 2000: 193. Levinas does occasionally refer
to ‘violence’ (2000: 187) in this regard, but such allusions must be treated
with caution.
144 See Derrida 1998a: 21; 1999a: 69; Levinas 2000: 152. Derrida characterizes the
relation to the other as necessarily involving a ‘preethical violence’ (1997c:
125) insofar as the other must first appear (and thus be minimally assimilated
to consciousness) as an ‘other’ for Levinas’s ethics to get off the ground
(see also Merleau-Ponty 1996: 359, 361). In reference to the need for
judgement between competing responsibilities Levinas himself acknowledges
that ‘[t]here is a certain measure of violence necessary in terms of justice’
(1998b: 105; see also 2001: 167, 221; Derrida 1996a: 63; 1997b: 25, 32; 1999a:
72–3).
145 See Sartre 1993: 252ff.; Levinas 1984: 52–3. On the relationship between
Sartre and Levinas, see Howells 1988.
146 This is an important point, for otherwise Levinas’s frequently shocking termi-
nology of being ‘hostage’ and ‘persecuted’ (1996a: 80–95) could be miscon-
strued. Nevertheless, there is a sense in which Levinas himself relies on just
such a ‘mythical past’ in his holding justice accountable to the preoriginal
ethical relation, and thereby maintaining the possibility of legitimate violence
on behalf of another. I return to this in Chapter 7.
147 See also Levinas 2000: 195–6; 2001: 52, 55–6, 192, 204, 225.
148 Here one might recall Wittgenstein’s cautionary remarks concerning the
‘temporality’ that is ‘embedded in grammar’ (1994a: 22).
149 See also Levinas 1996a: 17, 94.
150 See also Levinas 1996a: 144–5.
151 See also Levinas 2000: 196.
152 This gains support from Derrida’s earlier remarks (1996c: 5–6; see also 2002a:
383–91). On Derrida’s own preoccupation with confession see 1992a: 34–35;
1998c: 60.
153 See Levinas 1996a: 144. Aside from the Heideggerian overtones of the term
‘guilt’ (Levinas 1996a: 18), there is an issue of translation here, for the French
culpabilité refers to notions of fault or blame. Levinas would want to avoid such
connotations insofar as they imply more-or-less specifiable transgressions vol-
untarily perpetrated (1996b: 83–4; 1998a: 170; 1999: 106).
154 See Levinas 2000: 203–4.
155 See Derrida 1993b: 77; Levinas 1997a: 225.
156 See Levinas 1998a: 169–70; 1999: 179; Derrida 2001b: 26, 56. Note also
Lyotard’s remarks on eschatology (1997b: 96, 98).
157 See also Levinas 1999: 106; 2000: 195–6, 208–9.
Notes 247
158 See Levinas 1998a: 152, 175. As Derrida puts it, I am ‘a priori guilty’ (2002a:
384).
159 See also Levinas 2000: 12, 20, 138, 161, 193, 195.
160 See also Levinas 1996c: 84.
161 See also Derrida 1993b: 19–20; 1995a: 184, 194, 286–7, 361–2; 1996b: 86;
1997b: 20–1; 2001d: 87. In this sense Levinas’s remark that ‘I am placed in the
accusative case, in the place of the one accused – I lose all place’ (2000: 161)
is potentially misleading. For it is not that I have no place before the other but
rather that I have no rightful place.
162 See Culler 1976: 26.
163 See Derrida 1993a: 255. Levinas did once remark that the fact that I am ‘in
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
one place in space and the other is at another place in space . . . is not the
alterity that distinguishes you from me. It is not because your hair is unlike
mine or because you occupy another place than me – this would only be a dif-
ference of properties or of dispositions in space, a difference of attributes’
(2001: 49). While I am not suggesting that the other’s ‘otherness’ can be
reduced to such ‘spatial differences,’ I nevertheless believe (and numerous
passages in Levinas’s work bear this out) that these cannot be dismissed as
mere differences ‘of attributes.’
164 See also Derrida 1993b: 39, 61, 76.
165 For similar remarks concerning the ‘Third World’ see Levinas 1999: 23, 30,
179; Derrida 2003: 121–2. Derrida rejects the suggestion that his own concep-
tion of ethics is reducible to a ‘distributive justice’ (2002f: 105).
166 Rousseau there refers to the ‘first man who, having enclosed a piece of
ground, bethought himself of saying This is mine’ (1930: 207) – an event along
with which came the notion of ‘property’ and ‘a thousand quarrels and con-
flicts’ (ibid.: 210), ‘slavery and misery’ (ibid.: 215). On such a reading
Rousseau’s own vocabulary of trespassing (the ‘usurpations’ of the rich, the
injustice of ‘proprietorship,’ and his reminder: ‘Do you not know that
numbers of your fellow-creatures are starving, for want of what you have too
much of?’ (ibid.: 219–20)) takes on renewed significance. Interestingly, De
Sade makes a similar point about ‘usurpation’ (1969: 173).
167 On the possible significance of Levinas’s work for politics see Derrida 1999b:
20, 70–1, 78–83, 197; Critchley 1999b: 274ff. I return to this in Chapter 8.
168 Recalling Derrida’s allusion to ‘mourning’ see Levinas’s remarks on Pascal
(Levinas 1999: 179).
169 See Blanchot 1995: 245; Levinas 1999: 23. In some astonishing passages
Levinas says of this non-symmetrical relation that ‘I am responsible for the
Other without waiting for reciprocity . . . Reciprocity is his affair’ (1992: 98),
and ‘What I say here of course only commits me!’ (ibid.: 114). I return to this
later.
170 Levinas remarks that, insofar as the face of the other ‘demands me, requires
me, summons me’ it might well be aligned with ‘the word of God.’ He pro-
ceeds: ‘Does not God come to the mind precisely in that summons . . . desig-
nating me instead in the face of the other as responsible with no possible
denial, and thus, as the unique and chosen one?’ (1999: 27). I return to this
religious subtext in Chapter 7.
171 See Levinas 1998a: 169–71.
172 See Levinas 1997b: 70; 1999: 19–20.
173 A point contested in Bachelard 1994: 5, 7, 46, 213.
174 As Levinas summarizes: ‘for a being that is always in the possible, it is imposs-
ible to be a whole’ (2000: 32).
175 See Heidegger 1999: 342–3.
176 See Heidegger 1982: 171.
248 Notes
177 See Heidegger 1982: 297–8.
178 See also Levinas 1999: 22.
179 See Levinas 1996a: 88; 1999: 20–3; 2001: 62, 92, 97–8, 128, 132. This trespass-
ing is a violation both against this particular other who faces me and, more
generally, any present or absent other.
180 See also Derrida 2001b: 67; 2001d: 86.
181 See also Derrida 1996b: 86; 2002f: 383.
182 Bernstein is therefore in danger of oversimplifying Levinas’s position when he
summarizes: ‘for Levinas, to acknowledge the supreme ethical imperative
does not mean that we always follow it; but we can obey this command. Ethics
presupposes saintliness not as an accomplishment, but as a value or an ideal. I
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
can always act in such a manner as will give ethical priority to the life of the
other’ (Bernstein 2002: 179, see also 181).
183 See also Heidegger 1982: 298; Husserl 1989: 427. Heidegger’s remarks on ‘my
having the responsibility for the Other’s becoming endangered in his exist-
ence, led astray, or even ruined’ (1999: 327) should be read with this in mind.
184 See Macann 1992: 214; Kellner 1992: 206.
185 See also Levinas 1998b: 148; 1999: 23, 28, 30. Recalling Wittgenstein’s
remarks on the ontological question (1994a: 85), one might say that even in
its asking the question of Being Dasein thereby sacrifices other questions
(Lyotard 1988: xii; Bennington 1993: 105; Derrida 2000b: 29). That is, in pur-
suing the issues of fundamental ontology Dasein must overlook the violence
involved in assuming the right to do even this over ‘feeding the hungry and
clothing the naked’ (Levinas 1998b: 116; see also Caputo 1993: 132) – some-
thing that problematizes all theorizing, including Levinas’s own.
186 See Lyotard 1997b: 110.
187 See Levinas 1988a: 175; 2001: 134–5, 197; Derrida 1997c: 95.
188 See Levinas 1984: 63; Derrida 1995a: 381; Mole 1997: 148–9.
189 See Levinas 1992: 89; 1994a: 117; 1996a: 91, 103; 1999: 107; 2000: 138; 2001:
49.
190 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 77; 1994b: 70.
191 Notably Wittgenstein’s moral perfectionism (Pascal 1996: 48).
192 See Levinas 1984: 68; 1996a: 103. On at least one occasion Levinas (like
Rousseau) exalts ‘the goodness of everyday life’ over the failure and corrup-
tion of ‘[e]very [political] attempt to organize the human’ (1999: 107).
193 See Levinas 1993: 148; 1997b: 43; 1998b: 18.
194 Levinas’s allusion to the ‘haughty priority of the A is A’ (1998a: 174) is not, I
think, an attack on logic. Rather, he is highlighting the danger of transferring
the logical principle of identity into the ethical-political realm. For this would
imply that ‘I am I, and he is he’ is the whole story.
195 Regarding the non-reasonableness of love, see Gaita 2000: 27.
196 A similar lamentation appears in Derrida’s own ‘confession’ (1993a: 118–19,
248). See also Derrida’s remarks on murder (ibid.: 297–8; 1999b: 108), and
being guilty without fault (1993a: 300–2, 305).
197 See Rousseau 1953: 25–8, 37, 166.
198 See also Rousseau 1953: 176.
199 See Heidegger 1999: 328.
200 See Heidegger 1999: 327. Note also Heidegger’s warning against ‘idle talk’
(ibid.: 213–14; Macann 1992: 218–19).
201 See Levinas 1993: 135–43; Robbins 1999: 16–19.
202 See Winch 1987: 168. Gaita defines ‘remorse’ as a ‘haunting’ (2000: 32) by –
or ‘pained acknowledgment’ (ibid.: 34) of – one’s guilt. I would assume all
this in what I simply refer to as ‘guilt.’
203 More recently Gaita has claimed that ‘reflection on remorse takes us closer . . .
Notes 249
to the nature of morality and of good and evil, than reflection on rules, prin-
ciples, taboos and transgressions can’ (2000: 32).
204 See Gaita 1991: 48; 2000: 36, 98; 2003: 163ff.
205 See Wittgenstein 1974: 169; Rhees 1981: 190–219; Monk 1991: 367–70;
Malcolm 1993: 12; Pascal 1996: 45–50.
206 See Derrida 2002c: 88, 101, 103.
207 See Heidegger 1999: 312–15; Gaita 2000: 33–4, 128–9. To put this differently,
there is an important disparity between the grammar of innocence and guilt,
for whereas the former ultimately refers to a public realm (a ‘we’), the latter
can be radically singular. The problem with Heidegger’s account is that while
the ‘they’ cannot absolve me of my Guilt, neither can ‘they’ accuse me of it.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Said of the skeptic’s claims clearly render them refutable (‘There is no truth’
is patently self-contradictory), on the level of the quasi-performative Saying
the skeptic can – and does – always return to haunt philosophy (1994a:
167–8). For a summary of this, see Critchley 1999a: 156–69.
112 Of course, Nietzsche vehemently denies that he wants to be ‘pronounced
holy’ or ‘a saint’ (1992a: 96). What is interesting is his subsequent quasi-
prophetic remarks on the potential significance of his own transvaluation of
value: ‘all the power-structures of the old society have been blown into the air
– they one and all reposed on the lie: there will be wars such as there never
yet have been on earth. Only after me will there be grand politics on earth’
(ibid.: 97; see also 101; 1968: §273). Thus, Nietzsche speaks against saintliness
in the name of another saintliness (Derrida 2002f: 223–5, 227).
113 See also Derrida 1999b: 61; Levinas 2001: 90, 111, 170, 183–4, 207, 218, 220.
114 See Rousseau 1930: 213–14. Indeed, according to Levinas, ‘Heideggerian
being-with-one-another’ sounds ‘like a marching together’ (2001: 137).
115 See Levinas 1998b: 229–30.
116 See Gaita’s remarks on loving ‘better’ (2000: 25–7).
117 Levinas remarks that ‘[t]he Desirable does not gratify my Desire but hollows it
out, and somehow nourishes me with new hungers’ (1996a: 52). This passage
is relevant here insofar as the bad conscience inaugurated with the third party
is similarly insatiable insofar as the more I do for this other, the more I have
failed to do for that other. I return to Levinasian ‘desire’ later.
118 And also the conditions of impossibility, for it is precisely this excessiveness
(and thus bad conscience) that prevents me from ever claiming to have ‘ful-
filled’ my responsibilities.
119 See Levinas 1988b: 165. For Levinas’s distinction between the ‘moral’ (or
‘just’) and the ‘ethical’ see 1988a: 171; 1992: 80–1, 90; 1996b: 237–8.
120 See also Derrida 1999b: 112, 115.
121 See also Levinas 1998c: 130–4.
122 See Levinas 1984: 62; 2001: 136, 145, 191. Levinas’s characterization of Dasein
in terms of a ‘struggle for life’ (1988a: 172) is contentious, not only because
Dasein is always being-towards-death (indeed, given Heidegger’s anti-biologism
(Derrida 1988c: 165), this purported complicity between fundamental ontol-
ogy and Darwinian evolution becomes additionally problematic), but also
because his reading of Darwin is questionable (Darwin 1875: 97–145).
123 The implication would thus seem to be that Heidegger’s Dasein is not properly
human. Levinas’s allegation is curious given that the very ‘natural’ relation
between parent and offspring represents a paradigm case of both ‘love
without reward’ and ‘putting the other first.’ I return to this later.
124 See also Picard 1948: 102–4; Levinas 1998a: 164, 171; 2001: 47.
125 See also Levinas 2001: 53, 113, 119, 132. Picard similarly remarks that ‘human
nature’ is so ‘absolutely different’ from the animal that the former ‘could
never have come straight out of animal [nature]’ (1948: 104). Indeed,
Notes 255
‘[a]nimals seem to have dropped out of a human dream’ (ibid.: 103).
Compare this with Levinas 1984: 61.
126 The same ambiguity occurs when Levinas claims that ‘Goodness’ (though a
‘childish virtue’) is ‘already . . . the possibility of sacrifice in which the human-
ity of man bursts forth’ (1998b: 157).
127 Neither can it be a matter of will, as this would subordinate responsibility to
autonomy, and Levinas maintains that ethics calls my freedom into question
(1994b: 37, 85).
128 Even if one accepts the claim that only the human can be saintly, this does not
warrant Levinas’s conclusion that the human ‘breaks’ with the natural. The
advent of the human might mark an unprecedented evolutionary stage, but
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
that does not sever the human from such natural processes (of course, given
Levinas’s comments on Darwinism (1984: 62; 1988a: 172), and more general
suspicions concerning the notion of a ‘human race’ (1998a: 10), it is doubtful
that he has anything ‘evolutionary’ in mind). I will return to some of these
points.
129 Interestingly, Levinas refers to our ‘natural goodness . . . with respect to the
other’ (2001: 55).
130 See Robbins 1999: 3–4.
131 See also Levinas 1996a: 55; 1996c: 117.
132 See also Levinas 1996a: 52, 55, 76; 1996c: 117; Blanchot 1997: 53.
133 Although I return to this point later, one might object that this classification
gets things precisely backwards; that needs are in fact what remain insatiable.
See Derrida 1992b: 158; 1995a: 282.
134 See Derrida 1992b: 7, 12–13, 35, 38, 45–7, 64, 76, 91, 126, 137, 139, 147–8,
156. Of course, the very notion of a pure gift (or absolute expenditure) is itself
caught up in a certain economics of return. For my giving everything could
likewise harbor entirely teleological hopes for a ‘good conscience.’ Somewhat
paradoxically then, sacrificing one’s life for another may not (as Levinas occa-
sionally suggests) be the ‘ultimate’ gift. On this general point see Bernasconi
1997: 258.
135 See Levinas 1992: 92; 1996a: 44–5, 76–7; 1996c: 63; Weil 1987: 86.
136 See also Derrida 2002f: 242.
137 See also Jay 1993: 558–60; Levinas 1998a: 176. There remains an ambiguity
here concerning who/what touches who/what in the caress? That is, do I
here touch the other, or rather touch myself with or through the other?
(Derrida 1993c: 126–7, 133–4, 140). Regarding the ethics of touch, see Benso
2000: 160, 162ff.
138 See Levinas 1992: 32, 61, 67–9.
139 See Levinas’s remarks on ‘justice,’ the ‘liberal state’ and his own ‘utopianism’
(1988a: 177–8).
140 According to Rorty, Levinas’s ethics is ‘pointless hype’ (1996: 42). Rorty’s
objection is, I think, metaphilosophical; namely, that he sees no pragmatic
value in even attempting an ‘ethics of ethics.’ But while Levinas is not con-
cerned with offering a specific ethical-political agenda, this is not to say that
(for example, on the question of moral Guilt) his work lacks ‘practical con-
sequences.’ I have discussed some of these points in Plant 2003d.
141 See Rousseau 1973: 13ff. D’Holbach similarly claims that the ‘compassion in
man is a habitual inclination to feel more or less keenly the ills with which
others are afflicted’ (1969: 66) which is made possible by way of ‘man’s struc-
ture’ (his ‘faithful memory’ and ‘active imagination’ (ibid.: 67)) – in short, his
capacity to ‘transfer’ the pain of an other to himself. However, as I have previ-
ously argued, this deliberative notion of ‘transference’ (Levinas 1988a: 172)
needs to be questioned.
256 Notes
142 See Picard 1948: 105; Levinas 2001: 47, 59, 97, 106, 183, 204, 235.
143 Levinas occasionally refers to Hobbes in this regard (1996a: 51; 1996b: 273).
144 See also De Sade 1991a: Dialogue 5; Nietzsche 1992b: Essay 2, §§5–6. De
Sade’s critique of the Christian ‘invention’ of the notion of brotherhood (a
claim reiterated in his ‘Dialogue entre un Prêtre et un Moribond’ (1991b:
23)) is developed by Nietzsche.
145 Regarding Levinas’s identification of Nietzsche with Nazism, see Bataille 1996:
192–3.
146 There is something quasi-Pyrrhonian about remarks such as this – though for
Nietzsche there is no corresponding ataraxia. For a more striking similarity
between Nietzsche and Pyrrhonism see Nietzsche 1994: pp. 71, 99.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
147 For a powerful literary account of the corruption of pity, see Zweig 2000.
148 See also Nietzsche 1968: §§268, 297.
149 See Nietzsche 1968: §§266, 276, 280, 285, 296; Derrida 2001a: 33–4.
150 See also Nietzsche 1968: §327.
151 See also Nietzsche 1968: §§173–4, 200.
152 See Nietzsche 1992b: Essay 2, §§16, 19.
153 See also Nietzsche 1968: §§245–6. Compare this with Malcolm’s remarks on
guilt and the Judaic-Christian conception of God (1960: 60–1).
154 See also Nietzsche 1968: §176. According to Levinas fear of the other (which is
‘fear for the self’) is subordinate to fear for the other, and he likens the latter
to the ‘mother who fears for the child, or even, each of us who fears for a
friend’ (1998b: 117; see also 1993: 47; 2001: 124, 177). As will become clear in
Chapter 8, Derrida would be more cautious here insofar as one must ask to
what extent fear-for-the-other is also a fear-for-oneself (for one’s own potential loss
or mourning)?
155 In this sense traditional moralities constitute a ‘sign-language of the emotions’
(Nietzsche 1987: p. 92).
156 See Nietzsche 1992b: Essay 1, §13.
157 See also Levinas 2001: 54, 250.
158 The ‘judged’ would here refer to the poor and vulnerable other, while the
‘judgement’ would designate the accusation of my being Guilty.
159 Even Derrida acknowledges that ‘it is not by chance that Nietzsche could be
reappropriated by Nazism’ (Derrida 2002f: 221).
160 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§281, 283, 583; 1990: §506.
161 See also Levinas 1996a: 8, 73.
162 See Derrida 1993b: 35, 75–6, 78; 1995a: 268, 277–9, 284–5. Although Levinas
is critical of Heidegger’s concept of ‘Dasein’ (insofar as it prioritizes the self
over the other), for both philosophers the emphasis remains squarely anthro-
pocentric. On this feature of Heidegger’s work refer to Glendinning 1998:
62–70. I return to this point later.
163 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§250, 357, 650, pp. 174, 229; 1990: §§389, 518.
164 See Glendinning 1998: 71.
165 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§283, 360.
166 See also Wittgenstein 1958: §244, p. 218; 1993: 389; 1994a: 67; 1999: §§359,
475, 538.
167 See Wittgenstein 1996a: 66–7.
168 And similarly: ‘the epiphany of the Other (Autrui) involves a signifyingness of
its own, independent of this meaning received from the world . . . The nudity
of a face is a bareness without any cultural ornament . . . The face enters into
our world from an absolutely foreign sphere’ (Levinas 1996a: 53). On the
relation between concepts, humans and animals, contrast Levinas’s remarks
with Gaita 2003: 60–1.
169 See Caputo 1993: 81; Derrida 1997c: 89, 107. This is not simply a matter of
Notes 257
bodily form, for the ‘behavior one meets is human behavior in the first place
. . . One sees it and responds to it as such’ (Dilman 1987: 29).
170 See Derrida 1997c: 114–16, 121–3, 125, 127, 132, 137–8, 140–1, 143. Of
course, Derrida’s argument is broadly phenomenological rather than natural-
istic.
171 See Caputo 1993: 74–5, 80.
172 See Derrida 1997c: 125. This parallels Derrida’s remarks on the necessary
non-recognition of the gift (1992b: 13–17, 23, 27, 35–6, 47, 56, 91, 101, 147;
1995b: 106–7).
173 See Derrida 1997c: 112, 116–17, 125. To reiterate: this is why Derrida refers to
a ‘preethical violence’ (ibid.: 125, 128) only upon which an ethical relation to
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
the other is possible. That is, although this minimal recognition of the other
as an other (not a thing, ‘not a stone’ (ibid.: 125)) constitutes a ‘violence,’
insofar as such an assimilation is a necessary condition for my being respons-
ible for her, it is therefore ‘preethical.’
174 See also Levinas 1996a: 7, 28, 73; 1998b: 185.
175 See Levinas 1997b: 93.
176 See also Levinas 1994a: 87, 159; Putnam 2002: 55.
177 See also Gaita 2000: 32.
178 Or what Levinas refers to as a ‘miracle’ (2001: 59, see also 106, 111, 113,
216–18, 250). The difficulty Levinas’s anti-naturalism presents is how this sin-
gularity is to be understood given that any commonality enabling the (singu-
lar) face to be recognized as such is condemned as inherently unethical.
179 To what extent Levinas emphasizes verbal communication is contentious.
Thus, Critchley argues against the charge of anthropocentrism (and against
Derrida’s reading of Levinas here (Critchley 1999a: 180)) that Levinas
‘reserves a privileged place for non-verbal communication.’ Critchley then
alludes to a parallel ‘non-verbal language of the skin’ (ibid.: 178–9). But even
if he is right to conclude that ‘the original logos of ethics from which the
experience of obligation derives can be shown to be rooted in the non-verbal’
(ibid.: 181) this simply makes Levinas’s neglect of the animal more bemusing.
180 See also Derrida 1992b: 139, 142, 145; Handelman 1991: 210.
181 See Handelman 1991: 223–5.
182 See also Levinas 1993: 142.
183 See Levinas 1988a: 172.
184 See also Levinas 2001: 41, 90.
185 While Winch does ‘not want to deny that in some attenuated sense one could
speak of allowing a dumb animal to choose and of “respecting” its choice,’ he
nevertheless insists that the ‘sense’ would be ‘attenuated’ (1987: 176–7).
While we might concede Winch’s point concerning deliberative ‘choice,’
there is little reason to accept this general criterion for moral worthiness.
What Winch overlooks here (although he emphasizes it regarding other
matters) is Wittgenstein’s naturalism.
186 Interestingly, Levinas begins the essay by referring to our becoming ‘vegetar-
ian again’ like Adam, and to ‘the butchery that every day claims our “conse-
crated” mouths!’ (1997a: 151).
187 See also Derrida 2002e: 388.
188 See Wittgenstein 1958: §§244, 343.
189 See also Malcolm 1986: 303; Dilman 1987: 49–50.
190 See Wittgenstein 1958: §25.
191 For an example of how Wittgenstein’s remarks on animals have been misap-
plied, see Pinker 1994: 56. Note also Gaita 2000: 240.
192 See Glendinning 1998: 72–5.
193 See Gaita 2003: 61. Certainly one can become deaf to the cry of the
258 Notes
non-human animal – those working in abattoirs presumably do. My point is
that such cases represent an erosion of a more primitive responsiveness to
animals.
194 See also Levinas 1988b: 156–7. In these circumstances even the human is
(albeit temporarily) ‘worldless’ or without a ‘world-picture.’
195 Interestingly, in response to the question ‘Can animals suffer?’ Derrida
claims that there is ‘no doubt. In fact it has never left any room for doubt . . .
it is not even indubitable; it precedes the indubitable, it is older than it’
(2002e: 397).
196 See also Wittgenstein 1993: 381, 383.
197 It is due to this that remarks such as: ‘The great “experiences” of our life have
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
8 Contaminations
1 Parts of the present chapter have appeared in Plant 2003c.
2 That is, beyond the methodological correlations between deconstruction and
Wittgenstein’s later philosophy (Staten 1986).
3 See Derrida 1999c: 57. In a discussion with Ricoeur in 1971 Derrida claims
that his interest is with ‘a type of questioning which has not yet coincided with
the need for ethics’ (1992c: 159). However, the beginnings of the so-called
‘ethical turn’ in Derrida’s work can be identified as early as ‘Violence and
Metaphysics’ where a certain rhetoric of hospitality emerges (1997c: 152–3;
see also Bernstein 1991: 172–229).
4 According to Critchley, Derrida’s recent work represents a ‘quasi-phenomenolog-
ical . . . description and analysis of particular phenomena.’ That is, Derrida is
‘concerned with the particular qua particular . . . with the grain and enigmatic
detail of everyday life’ (Critchley 1996: 32). Of course, what also ‘regulates’
Derrida’s analyses of the gift, hospitality (and so on) is ‘what is inscribed’ in
260 Notes
the ‘heritage’ of these concepts ‘in a number of traditions’ (Derrida 2001b:
53).
5 See Critchley 1999a.
6 Dooley (1999, 2001) has recently attempted to show the fundamental dispar-
ity between Derrida and Levinas. I have criticized this in Plant 2003c.
7 Derrida himself alludes to this section of Totality and Infinity in ‘A Word of
Welcome’ (1999b: 16, 21), although he there focuses on Levinas’s discussion
of the ‘feminine.’ For other analyses of ‘home’ (and related concepts), see
Bollnow 1967; Dovey 1978; Seamon 1979; Seamon and Mugerauer 1985: Bird
et al. 1993; Bachelard 1994; Benjamin 1995; Ingold 2000.
8 See also Bachelard 1994: 47, 51; Levinas 1994b: 107.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
44 See also Derrida 1992b: 126; 2000b: 55; Caputo 1997a: 110–11.
45 See Derrida 1998c: 28; 2000c: 4–5. On ‘giving time’ to others refer to Derrida
1992b: 28.
46 See also Derrida 1999b: 45.
47 See also Levinas 1984: 63; Derrida 1997e: 14; 2003: 95. This is why Derrida
remains suspicious of the notion of ‘tolerance’ (2003: 127–9).
48 See Kant 1976: 79; Derrida 1998c: 67.
49 See Derrida 1999c: 72.
50 See also Derrida 1992b: 7, 12–13, 35, 76, 91, 147, 156; 1997e: 18–19; 2001a:
34, 56; 2001e: 44, 48–51, 55. Regarding the aporia of the gift, compare
Christ’s warning: ‘when you do some act of charity, do not let your left hand
know what your right is doing’ (Matthew 6:3–4) with Derrida’s claim that ‘like
a gift confession must be from the unconscious’ (1993a: 233). I discuss this in
Plant 2004a.
51 Although this cannot be an absolute surprise, for otherwise ‘that would make it
impossible to recognize the surprise as a surprise.’ Indeed, we would not even
know ‘that anything was happening at all’ (Caputo 1993: 74; see also 2000:
113).
52 See Derrida 1993b: 33–4; 1997e: 17; 2000c: 8, 10; 2001a: 83; 2002a: 361, 372,
381. Again, this ‘surprise’ relates to Derrida’s reflections on the gift (1992b:
122–3, 147).
53 See Matthew 24:36, 39, 42–51; Derrida 1997e: 22–4; 2001a: 31; 2002d: 14;
2002f: 94–6; Smith 1998.
54 See also Derrida 1993b: 33; 2001e: 22–3; 2002d: 12, 17; Caputo 2000: 113.
55 See also Luke 14:12–13. Contrast with 2 John 9–11. While Derrida acknowl-
edges that all this is ‘politically unacceptable’ insofar as ‘every nation-state is
constituted by the control of its border’ (2002f: 100, see also 115), he never-
theless maintains that ‘a politics that does not maintain a reference to this
principle of unconditional hospitality is a politics that loses its reference to
justice’ (ibid.: 101).
56 See also Derrida 1992b: 15–16, 82; 1993b: 11; 2000a: 353.
57 See also Derrida 1992b: 9, 35, 45–6, 55; 2002a: 362; Gaita 2000: 105–6. Note
Derrida’s remarks on the ‘madness’ of the gift (1992b: 9, 35, 45–6, 55).
58 See Derrida 1995a: 198; 1995b: 68; 1997a: 10; 1997b: 23, 28–9; 1998b: 31;
1998c: 62; 1999a: 70–1; 1999c: 72; 2001d: 68–9; 2002d: 11, 22, 79–81.
59 See Derrida 1997d: 112; 1998c: 14; 1999b: 35. On this point note also
Derrida’s memories of the Algerian war (1995a: 120).
60 See Baier 1986: 235; Derrida 2000b: 61, 125. Indeed, vulnerability is prerequi-
site for love and friendship in general, and this is why Levinas insists that the
exposed, mortal ‘body is the very condition of giving, with all that giving costs
. . . [giving] implies a body, because to give to the ultimate degree is to give
bread taken from one’s own mouth’ (2000: 188; see also 1994a: 77).
61 See also Derrida 1992b: 12, 53–4, 64; 1995a: 387, 392; 1995c: 143; 1997a:
262 Notes
12–13, 16–17; 1997b: 28–9; 2000a: 352; 2002a: 402; 2003: 101; Bennington
2000a: 341, 348. Freud and Nietzsche are notable in this regard insofar as
each ‘shows himself hospitable to madness’ (Derrida 1998a: 104); that is,
insofar as each attempts a ‘dialogue with madness itself ’ (ibid.: 83; see also
2002f: 217).
62 See Derrida 1999a: 70.
63 See Derrida 1992b: 12, 53–4, 62–4; Gaita 2000: 26–7.
64 See also Wittgenstein 1994a: 8; Levinas 1999: 101; Derrida 2000b: 25, 81–2;
2002c: 134.
65 See also Derrida 1995a: 198, 387; 1999c: 132–3; 2002f: 106, 108, 179, 238. The
force of this ‘must’ is descriptive; radical evil is of necessity a possibility that
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
(natural) and linguistic (cultural) that Rousseau posits – and which feeds his
nostalgia for the former – is effectively ruled out for Wittgenstein.
140 Of course, as Derrida notes, this notion of ‘truth’ is not ‘truth in a theoretical
sense’ insofar as ‘giving a false testimony’ (2000a: 383) is here inscribed as a
necessary possibility (2000d: 27–8, 29–31, 49, 72, 75; 2002c: 173). Note also
Gaita’s numerous references to ‘confessional’ writers (2000: 187–258).
141 See Hertzberg 1988: 309, 313.
142 See Baier 1986: 241–6; Hertzberg 1988: 318; Wittgenstein 1993: 377, 379, 381,
383, 385, 397, 399; 1999: §§115, 160, 341, 354. Bok thus notes how normally
‘[l]ying requires a reason, while truth-telling does not’ (1989: 22).
143 From such passages one might build common ground between Derrida and
Gadamer. I here have in mind their (almost) meeting in 1981, and specifically
Derrida’s suspicions concerning Gadamer’s reference to the necessity of
‘good will’ in conversation (Wood 1990: 118–31). Likewise, Ricoeur’s remarks
on the necessity for sincerity in ‘all the language games which can be con-
sidered acts of discourse’ (and that ‘[a]ll the ways of being committed are
marked by prior ethical structures. We don’t know an ethically neutral world’
(1992: 147)), seem consonant with Derrida’s recent work.
144 See also Derrida 2001d: 97; 2001e: 16–17; 2002a: 362, 364.
145 See Derrida’s remarks on the ‘pledge’ in 1989b: 129–30, n. 5.
146 This qualification is important, for, as discussed in Chapter 2, one can only
doubt x on the grounds of not doubting many other things (Wittgenstein
1999: §§115, 160, 341, 450, 519).
147 See Glendinning 2000: 319, 327–31. Winch similarly claims that one can only
‘mean what [one] says’ if it is also possible to ‘not mean what [one] says’
(1960: 248).
148 See also Derrida 1997e: 22–3; 2000b: 67.
149 Winch’s reflections on the primacy of ‘truth-telling’ (that ‘to act in the
context of a social institution is always to commit oneself in some way for the
future’ (1960: 250)) parallel Derrida’s emphasis on the pre-performative ‘yes,’
‘promise’ and ‘believe me’ (1992a: 38, 70, 74, 257, 265, 272, 276, 279, 288–9,
294, 296–305; 1995a: 171–2, 261, 268, 382–4; 1996a: 68; 1996b: 82; 1996c: 3;
1997a: 16; 1997b: 28, 35; 1998b: 18, 26–8, 30, 44–5, 47, 63–4; 1998c: 21–2,
66–8, 93 n. 11; 1999a: 82; 2002f: 33–4, 247).
150 See Austin 1976: 25–52.
151 See Derrida 1997d: 122, 135; 1999b: 89. Compare also Derrida’s remarks on
the ‘police’ (1997d: 132–4, 138) with Wittgenstein’s remarks on drawing a
‘boundary’ (1958: §499).
152 See Derrida 1995b: 67–71; 1996d: 215; 2000b: 55; 2001b: 49.
153 See Derrida 1992b: 64, 137–8, 142, 146, 162; 1995b: 107, 111–12; 1995c, 74,
133; 1996b: 86; 1997e: 48; 1999b: 48.
154 See Derrida 1995b: 71.
155 Derrida thus resists equating ‘violence’ with ‘evil’ (2001a: 90; see also 2002f: 80).
266 Notes
156 See also Derrida 1992b: 12; 2001b: 22.
157 See Hill 1997: 179–80; Derrida 2000b: 53–4, 59–61. Note also Levinas’s
remarks on ‘wronging the third one’ (1998b: 19).
158 On Derrida’s account of friendship see Bennington 2000b: 110–27.
159 See Weil 1987: 88; Derrida 1997d: 112.
160 See also Derrida 2000b: 147–8; 2001a: 17; 2001e: 44–5.
161 See Gaita 2000: 7.
162 Blanchot suggests that the question ‘Who is the other?’ already perpetrates a
violence insofar as it implies ‘a nature . . . or an essential trait.’ Nevertheless,
he later concedes that while this point ‘must be recalled’ such a ‘precaution is
somewhat ludicrous’ (1997: 70; see also Derrida 2001e: 23). I take Blanchot’s
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
point to be in line with Derrida’s; that such questions have to be asked, dis-
criminations must be made (and so on) for ethics to get off the ground.
163 Moreover, in order to be hospitable and ‘open my home’ (Levinas 1996c:
171) to the other, I must thereby have a ‘home’ of some description (Derrida
1992b: 126; 2000c: 14). Indeed, recalling my previous remarks on Levinas’s
phenomenology of home, part of the tragedy of human destitution might be
said to lie not only in the other’s being without a ‘private domain’ (1996c:
152) in which to ‘withdraw from the elements’ (ibid.: 153) but also in their
being denied the gift of giving hospitality (Derrida 1999b: 41–2).
164 See also Derrida 2001d: 87, 101, 107; 2002f: 92; 2003: 115.
165 See also Levinas 1988a: 177–8; Derrida 2001d: 98.
166 ‘It is necessary to do the impossible. If there is hospitality, the impossible must
be done’ (Derrida 2000c: 14).
167 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 77.
168 See Wittgenstein 1994a: 31.
169 See Derrida 1997e: 21–2.
170 See Derrida 1998a: 37.
171 See also Derrida 1990: 981; 1995c: 43, 81; 1998c: 9; 1999c: 60; 2001e: 31–3,
37–9.
172 See also Derrida 1992b: 8, 31; 1997b: 30; 1999c: 77.
173 See also Derrida 1997d: 116; 2002f: 31; 2003: 134.
174 See also Wittgenstein’s remarks on genuine ritual (1994a: 8). Although I will
not pursue this, there is doubtless much to be said regarding Derrida’s
account of the ‘decision’ and Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘rule following.’ One
wonders, for example, whether Wittgenstein’s notion of following a ‘rule
blindly’ (1958: §219) complicates Derrida’s account of the ‘programmatic’
decision? (note, however, Derrida’s suspicion of the term ‘blind’ in this
context (2002f: 231–2)).
175 See also Winch 1987: 179; Derrida 1999b: 116; 2002f: 229, 231–2; 2003: 118.
176 See also Derrida 1997b: 23; 2001b: 62; 2001d: 63.
177 Winch makes some closely related points regarding ‘judgment’ and ‘risk’
(1979: 60–2) in his critique of Apel.
178 See also Derrida 1995b: 24, 77; 1997a: 10; 1997b: 20, 34; 1997d: 148; 1998a:
113; 1999c: 133–4.
179 The minimal naturalism I have been defending does not undermine
Derrida’s account of the decision. Rather, all meaningful talk of ‘decision’
can only occur within certain natural boundaries. My decision to attend to the
suffering of x rather than y is conditioned by x and y first being the sort of
thing one could ‘attend to’ in this way. As such, when Wittgenstein claims that
‘it is a primitive reaction to tend, to treat, the part that hurts when someone
else is in pain; and not merely when oneself is’ (1990: §540 my emphasis) this is
not a refutation of the possibility (or necessity for) deliberation.
180 See Derrida 1990a: 963; 1997c: 133; 1999c: 133–4.
Notes 267
181 See also Derrida 1990: 967; 1997e: 117; 1999a: 67; 1999b: 117; 2000a: 383,
416; 2002f: 181, 200, 372; Caputo 1997a: 138.
182 See also Derrida 1990a: 965; 2001d: 103.
183 See also Derrida 1995b: 25; 2001a: 22; 2002f: 13–14.
184 Here we might recall Heidegger’s remarks on the ‘they’ discussed in Chapter
6 (there is also more than a little Nietzchean suspicion of ‘morality’ in
Derrida’s work). See Bernstein 1991: 215.
185 See Derrida 1990a: 965; 1997d: 135.
186 See Derrida 1990a: 965.
187 See Levinas 1996c: 157, 170–4.
188 See Levinas 1998b: 20–1.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
also 1993a: 210; 1995a: 346; 1995c: 28; 1996b: 80). This ‘promise’ (1992a: 39)
and ‘power’ to ‘say everything’ (ibid.: 37) is inseparable from those ethical-
political questions pertaining to ‘democracy . . . human rights’ and ‘freedom
of expression’ (1996b: 80; see also 1995a: 10, 86, 213–14; 1995c: 15; 1997b:
31–2; 1999a: 67, 70). And this cardinal verbosity enables the literary establish-
ment (and perhaps philosophy also (Derrida 1995a: 219, 327–8, 376–7)) to
call its own institutionality into question, thus demarcating itself as a ‘counter-
institutional institution’ (1992a: 58, see also 36, 72, 346). In other words, it is
precisely literature’s incessant desire to question the ‘rules’ (ibid.: 37) of its
own institutionality that constitutes its ethical-political power. Of course, there
could be no such transgression were there not some relatively determinate
and regulated institution in the first place – Derrida (like Levinas) is not
‘against’ institutions per se (Derrida 1997d: 132–3, 141; 1997e: 12, 16–17, 21,
27). Nevertheless, the curious nature of the literary institution is constituted
by this reflexive ability to call itself into question and thus, one might say, bear
witness to a certain bad conscience.
215 See Levinas 1998a: 97; 2001: 98; Derrida 2001a: 20.
216 See also Levinas 1993: 44; 1998a: 93; 1999: 30.
217 See Levinas 1988a: 172–3; 1998b: 227.
218 See Caputo 1997b: 288ff. Note also Caputo’s more recent remarks on his own
(apparent) atheism (2001: 32).
219 See also Derrida 1995b: 6; 1999c: 73.
220 See Derrida 1998c: 41.
221 See also Derrida 2001a: 20; 2002c: 111–12, 140, 166, 189; 2002f: 27.
222 See Scanlon 1999: 224. Derrida’s allusion to the ‘absolutely universal’ here
(something Levinas also refers to (1988a: 177; 1994b: 15)) constitutes a direct
challenge to those who judge his thinking to be essentially skeptical or rela-
tivistic (Derrida 2001a: 63–4).
223 As does the possibility of ‘love without reward’ (Levinas 1988a: 176; see also
Derrida 1999b: 72).
224 With reference to §559 of On Certainty, Culler remarks that a Derridean might
here object ‘that one can never be quite certain who is playing [a language-
game], or playing “seriously” ’ (1987: 130–1). This seems to me to rely too
heavily on a quasi-communitarian reading of Wittgenstein that, as I have
argued, neglects his underlying naturalism.
Bibliography
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Annas, J. and Barnes, J. (eds) (1985) The Modes of Skepticism: Ancient Texts and
Modern Interpretations, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Austin, J.L. (1976) How To Do Things With Words, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bachelard, G. (1994) The Poetics of Space, trans. M. Jolas, Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press.
Baier, A. (1986) ‘Trust and Antitrust,’ Ethics 96 (January): 231–60.
Baker, P. (1995) Deconstruction and the Ethical Turn, Gainesville, Fla.: University
Press of Florida.
Balázs, B. (1985) ‘The Close-Up’ and ‘The Face of Man,’ in G. Mast and M. Cohen
(eds) Film Theory and Criticism: Introductory Readings, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 255–64.
Bambrough, R. (1992) ‘Fools and Heretics,’ in P. Griffiths (ed.) Wittgenstein: Cente-
nary Essays, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 239–50.
Barker, E. (1990) ‘New Lines in the Supra-market: How Much Can We Buy?,’ in I.
Hamnett (ed.) Religious Pluralism and Unbelief: Studies Critical and Comparative,
London and New York: Routledge, 31–42.
Barrett, D.V. (1998) Sects, ‘Cults’ & Alternative Religions: A World Survey and Source-
book, London: Blandford.
Barron, A. (1992) ‘Lyotard and the Problem of Justice,’ in A. Benjamin (ed.)
Judging Lyotard, London and New York: Routledge, 26–42.
Barthes, R. (1990) A Lover’s Discourse: Fragments, trans. R. Howard, Har-
mondsworth: Penguin.
—— (2000) Camera Lucida, trans. R. Howard, London: Vintage.
Bataille, G. (1996) Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927–1939, trans. and ed. A.
Stoekl et al., Theory and History of Literature, 14, Minneapolis: University of Min-
nesota Press.
Baudelaire, C. (1996) The Poems in Prose (Vol. II) and La Fanfarlo, trans. and ed. F.
Scarfe, London: Anvil Press Poetry.
Bauman, Z. (1995) Postmodern Ethics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Benjamin, D.N. (ed.) (1995) The Home: Words, Interpretations, Meanings, and Envi-
ronments, USA/Hong Kong/Singapore/Sidney: Avebury.
Bennington, G. (1988) Lyotard: Writing the Event, Manchester: Manchester Univer-
sity Press.
—— (1993) ‘Derridabase,’ in G. Bennington and J. Derrida, Jacques Derrida,
Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
—— (2000a) ‘For the Sake of Argument (Up to a Point),’ in Arguing with Derrida,
Ratio (new series), XIII, 4 (December): 332–54.
270 Bibliography
Bennington, G. (2000b) Interrupting Derrida, London and New York: Routledge.
Benso, S. (2000) The Face of Things: A Different Side of Ethics, Albany: State University
of New York Press.
Bergson, H. (1911) Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic, trans. C. Brere-
ton and F. Rothwell, London: Macmillan.
Bernasconi, R. (1997) ‘What Goes Around Comes Around: Derrida and Levinas in
the Economy of the Gift and the Gift of Genealogy,’ in A.D. Schrift (ed.) The Logic
of the Gift: Toward an Ethic of Generosity, London and New York: Routledge, 256–73.
Bernstein, R.J. (1991) The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Moder-
nity/Postmodernity, Oxford: Polity Press.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Campbell and M.J. Shapiro (eds) Moral Spaces: Rethinking Ethics and World Politics,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 125–53.
Critchley, S. (1996) ‘Deconstruction and Pragmatism – Is Derrida a Private Ironist
or a Public Liberal?,’ in C. Mouffe (ed.) Deconstruction and Pragmatism, London
and New York: Routledge, 19–40.
—— (1999a) The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas, Edinburgh: Edin-
burgh University Press.
—— (1999b) Ethics–Politics–Subjectivity: Essays on Derrida, Levinas and Contemporary
French Thought, London and New York: Verso.
Culler, J. (1976) Saussure, Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.
—— (1987) On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism, London and
New York: Routledge.
Darwin, C. (1875) The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, London: John
Murray.
Davidson, D. (1984) ‘On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme,’ in Inquiries into
Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 183–98.
Davis, C. (1996) Levinas: An Introduction, Oxford: Polity Press.
Defoe, D. (1985) The Life and Adventures of Robinson Crusoe, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Derrida, J. (1971) ‘Signature Event Context,’ in (1982) Margins of Philosophy, trans.
A. Bass, Brighton: Harvester Press, 309–30.
—— (1982) Positions, trans. A. Bass, London: Athlone Press.
—— (1984) ‘Deconstruction and the Other,’ in R. Kearney, Dialogues with
Contemporary Continental Thinkers: The Phenomenological Heritage, Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 107–26.
—— (1985) ‘Racism’s Last Word,’ trans. P. Kamuf, Critical Inquiry 12 (Autumn):
290–9.
—— (1988a) ‘Heidegger’s Silence,’ trans. J. Neugroschel, in G. Neske and E. Ket-
tering (eds) (1990) Martin Heidegger and National Socialism, New York: Paragon
House, 145–8.
—— (1988b) ‘Like the Sound of the Sea Deep within a Shell: Paul De Man’s War,’
trans. P. Kamuf, Critical Inquiry 14 (Spring): 590–652.
—— (1988c) ‘Geschlecht II: Heidegger’s Hand,’ in J. Sallis (ed.) Deconstruction and
Philosophy: The Texts of Jacques Derrida, Chicago and London: University of
Chicago Press, 161–96.
—— (1989a) ‘Biodegradables: Seven Diary Fragments,’ trans. P. Kamuf, Critical
Inquiry 15 (Summer): 812–73.
—— (1989b) Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question, trans. G. Bennington and R.
Bowlby, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
272 Bibliography
Derrida, J. (1990) ‘Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundation of Authority”,’ trans.
M. Quaintance, Cardozo Law Review 11, Nos 5–6, 921–1045.
—— (1991) ‘At This Very Moment In This Work Here I Am,’ trans. R. Berezdivin,
in R. Bernasconi and S. Critchley (eds) Re-Reading Levinas, Bloomington and
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 11–48.
—— (1992a) Acts of Literature, D. Attridge (ed.) London and New York: Routledge.
—— (1992b) Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money, trans. P. Kamuf, Chicago and
London: University of Chicago Press.
—— (1992c) ‘Philosophy and Communication: Round-table Discussion Between
Ricoeur and Derrida,’ trans. L. Lawlor, in L. Lawlor, Imagination and Chance: The
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Difference Between the Thought of Ricoeur and Derrida, Albany: State University of
New York Press, 131–63.
—— (1993a) ‘Circumfession,’ trans. G. Bennington, in G. Bennington and J.
Derrida, Jacques Derrida, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
—— (1993b) Aporias, trans. T. Dutoit, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
—— (1993c) ‘Le toucher: Touch/To Touch Him,’ Paragraph, Vol. 16, No. 2 (July):
122–57.
—— (1995a) Points . . . Interviews, 1974–1994, trans. P. Kamuf et al., E. Weber (ed.),
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
—— (1995b) The Gift of Death, trans. D. Wills, Chicago and London: University of
Chicago Press.
—— (1995c) On the Name, trans. D. Wood et al., T. Dutoit (ed.), Stanford, Calif.:
Stanford University Press.
—— (1996a) Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression, trans. E. Prenowitz, Chicago and
London: University of Chicago Press.
—— (1996b) ‘Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism,’ trans. S. Critchley, in
C. Mouffe (ed.) Deconstruction and Pragmatism, London and New York: Rout-
ledge, 77–88.
—— (1996c) ‘Adieu,’ trans. P.A. Brault and M. Naas, Critical Inquiry 23 (Autumn):
1–10.
—— (1996d) ‘As If I Were Dead: An Interview with Jacques Derrida,’ in J. Branni-
gan, R. Robbins and J. Wolfreys (eds) Applying: To Derrida, Basingstoke: Macmil-
lan, 212–26.
—— (1996e) ‘By Force of Mourning,’ trans. P.A. Brault and M. Naas, Critical
Inquiry 22 (Winter): 171–92.
—— (1997a) ‘Perhaps or Maybe’ (interview with A.G. Düttmann), in J. Dronsfield
and N. Midgley (eds) Responsibilities of Deconstruction, Warwick Journal of Philosophy
6 (Summer): 1–18.
—— (1997b) ‘On Responsibility’ (interview with J. Dronsfield and others), in J.
Dronsfield and N. Midgley (eds) Responsibilities of Deconstruction, Warwick Journal
of Philosophy 6 (Summer): 19–35.
—— (1997c) ‘Violence and Metaphysics: An Essay on the Thought of Emmanuel
Levinas,’ trans. A. Bass, in Writing and Difference, London and New York: Rout-
ledge, 79–153.
—— (1997d) Limited Inc. (trans. various), Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University
Press.
—— (1997e) ‘The Villanova Roundtable: A Conversation with Jacques Derrida,’ in
J.D. Caputo (ed.) Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jacques Derrida,
New York: Fordham University Press, 3–28.
Bibliography 273
—— (1997f) Politics of Friendship, trans. G. Collins, London: Verso.
—— (1998a) Resistances of Psychoanalysis, trans. P. Kamuf et al., Stanford, Calif.:
Stanford University Press.
—— (1998b) ‘Faith and Knowledge: the Two Sources of “Religion” at the Limits
of Reason Alone,’ trans. S. Weber, in J. Derrida and G. Vattimo (eds) Religion,
Oxford: Polity Press, 1–78.
—— (1998c) Monolinguism of the Other; or, The Prosthesis of Origin, trans. P. Mensah,
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
—— (1998d) Of Grammatology, trans. G.C. Spivak, London: Johns Hopkins Univer-
sity Press.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Habermas and Jacques Derrida, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press,
85–136.
Descartes, R. (1976) Philosophical Writings, trans. E. Anscombe and P.T. Geach,
Middlesex: Nelson’s University Paperbacks, Open University.
De Vries, H. (1999) Philosophy and the Turn to Religion, Baltimore, Md and London:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Dilman, I. (1987) Love and Human Separateness, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Diogenes, L. (1925) Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, trans. R.D. Hicks, London:
Heinemann.
Dooley, M. (1999) ‘The Politics of Exodus: Derrida, Kierkegaard, and Levinas on
“Hospitality”,’ in R.L. Perkins (ed.) International Kierkegaard Commentary: Works of
Love, Macon, Ga.: Mercer University Press, 167–92.
—— (2001) ‘The Civic Religion of Social Hope: A Response to Simon Critchley,’
in Philosophy and Social Criticism, Vol. 27, No. 5: 35–58.
Dostoyevsky, F. (1967) The Brothers Karamazov I, trans. D. Magarshack, Har-
mondsworth: Penguin.
Dovey, K. (1978) ‘Home: An Ordering Principle in Space,’ Landscape, Vol. 22, No.
2: 27–30.
Drury, M. (1981) ‘Some Notes on Conversations with Wittgenstein’ and ‘Conversa-
tions with Wittgenstein,’ in R. Rhees (ed.) Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollec-
tions, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 91–189.
Dufourmantelle, A. (2000) ‘Invitation,’ in J. Derrida and A. Dufourmantelle, Of
Hospitality: Anne Dufourmantelle Invites Jacques Derrida to Respond, trans. R. Bowlby,
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Edwards, J.C. (1985) Ethics Without Philosophy: Wittgenstein and the Moral Life,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Engelmann, P. (1967) Letters from Ludwig Wittgenstein, with a Memoir, B.F. McGuin-
ness (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Fann, K.T. (1969) Wittgenstein’s Conception of Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Feyerabend, P. (1987) Science in a Free Society, London: Verso.
—— (1988) Against Method, London: Verso.
Finch, H.R. (1975) ‘Wittgenstein’s Last Word: Ordinary Certainty,’ International
Philosophical Quarterly 15: 383–95.
Flew, A. (1971) ‘Theology and Falsification: A Symposium’ (with R.M. Hare and B.
Mitchell), in B. Mitchell (ed.) The Philosophy of Religion, Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 13–22.
Fogelin, R.J. (1986) ‘Wittgenstein and Classical Skepticism,’ in S. Shanker (ed.)
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Critical Assessments (Vol. II), London: Croom Helm, 163–75.
—— (1987) Wittgenstein, London and New York: Routledge.
Bibliography 275
—— (1996) ‘Wittgenstein’s Critique of Philosophy,’ in H. Sluga and D.G. Stern
(eds) The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 34–58.
Foucault, M. (2000) Aesthetics: Essential Works of Foucault 1954–1984 (Vol. 2),
London: Penguin.
Frazer, J. (1993) The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic and Religion, Ware, Herts:
Wordsworth.
Gaita, R. (1991) Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
—— (1998) Romulus, My Father, London: Headline Book Publishing.
—— (2000) A Common Humanity: Thinking about Love and Truth and Justice, London
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
Routledge.
—— (1999) Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Heller, J. (1961) Catch-22, London: Corgi.
Helvétius, C.A. (1969) ‘On Man’ (excerpt from De L’Homme), in L.G. Crocker
(ed.) The Age of Enlightenment, New York: Harper and Row, 45–7.
Hertzberg, L. (1988) ‘On the Attitude of Trust,’ Inquiry 31: 307–22.
Hick, J. (ed.) (1966) Faith and the Philosophers, New York: St Martin’s Press.
—— (1977) ‘Jesus and the World Religions,’ in J. Hick (ed.) The Myth of God Incar-
nate, London: SCM Press, 167–85.
—— (1988) God and the Universe of Faiths: Essays in the Philosophy of Religion, Bas-
ingstoke: Macmillan.
—— (1995) The Rainbow of Faiths: Critical Dialogues on Religious Pluralism, London:
SCM Press.
Hill, L. (1997) Blanchot: Extreme Contemporary, London and New York: Routledge.
D’Holbach, P.H.D. (1969) ‘Universal Morality, or the Duties of Man Founded on
His Nature’ (excerpt from La Morale Universelle), in L.G. Crocker (ed.) The Age of
Enlightenment, New York: Harper and Row, 66–8.
Holland, R.F. (1990) ‘Not Bending the Knee,’ Philosophical Investigations Vol. 13,
No. 1 (January): 18–30.
Hookway, C. (1990) Skepticism, London and New York: Routledge.
Howells, C. (1988) ‘Sartre and Levinas,’ in R. Bernasconi and D. Wood (eds) The
Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other, London and New York: Routledge, 91–9.
—— (1999) Derrida: Deconstruction from Phenomenology to Ethics, Oxford: Polity
Press.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993) Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s
Philosophy of Science, trans. A.T. Levine, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hudson, W.D. (1986a) ‘Wittgenstein on Fundamental Propositions,’ in S. Shanker
(ed.) Ludwig Wittgenstein: Critical Assessments (Vol. IV), London: Croom Helm,
116–28.
—— (1986b) ‘The Light Wittgenstein Sheds on Religion,’ in S. Shanker (ed.)
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Critical Assessments (Vol. IV), London: Croom Helm, 167–84.
Hume, D. (1988) Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Prin-
ciples of Morals (rev. P.H. Nidditch), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Husserl, E. (1970) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology:
An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy, trans. D. Carr, Evanston, Ill.: North-
western University Press.
—— (1982) Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology, trans. D. Cairns,
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Bibliography 277
—— (1989) Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philo-
sophy (Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution), trans. R. Rojcewicz
and A. Schuwer, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Ingold, T. (2000) The Perception of the Environment: Essays in Livelihood, Dwelling and
Skill, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Inwood, B. and Gerson, L.P. (trans.) (1988) Hellenistic Philosophy: Introductory Read-
ings, Indianapolis, Ind./Cambridge, Mass.: Hackett.
James, W. (1985) The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature, Har-
mondsworth: Penguin.
Jay, M. (1993) Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century French
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
168–80.
—— (1988b) ‘Useless Suffering,’ trans. R. Cohen, in R. Bernasconi and D. Wood
(eds) The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other, London and New York:
Routledge, 156–80.
—— (1989) ‘As if Consenting to Horror,’ trans. P. Wissing, Critical Inquiry 15
(Winter): 485–8.
—— (1992) Ethics and Infinity: Conversations with Philippe Nemo, trans. R.A. Cohen,
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
—— (1993) Outside the Subject, trans. M.B. Smith, London: Athlone Press.
—— (1994a) Otherwise Than Being Or Beyond Essence, trans. A. Lingis, Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
—— (1994b) Nine Talmudic Readings, trans. A. Aronowicz, Bloomington and Indi-
anapolis: Indiana University Press.
—— (1995) ‘Philosophy and the Idea of the Infinite,’ in A. Peperzak, To The Other:
An Introduction to the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas, Indiana: Purdue University
Press, 88–119.
—— (1996a) Basic Philosophical Writings, A. Peperzak et al. (eds), Bloomington and
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
—— (1996b) The Levinas Reader, S. Hand (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
—— (1996c) Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. A. Lingis, Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press.
—— (1996d) Proper Names, trans. M.B. Smith, London: Athlone Press.
—— (1997a) Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism, trans. S. Hand, Baltimore, Md.:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
—— (1997b) Time and the Other, trans. R.A. Cohen, Pittsburgh: Duquesne Univer-
sity Press.
—— (1998a) Of God Who Comes To Mind, trans. B. Bergo, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford
University Press.
—— (1998b) Entre Nous: Thinking-of-the-Other, trans. M.B. Smith and B. Harshav,
New York: Columbia University Press.
—— (1998c) Discovering Existence with Husserl, trans. R.A. Cohen and M.B. Smith,
Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press.
—— (1999) Alterity & Transcendence, trans. M.B. Smith, London: Athlone Press.
—— (2000) God, Death, and Time, trans. B. Bergo, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford Uni-
versity Press.
—— (2001) Is It Righteous To Be? Interviews with Emmanuel Levinas, J. Robbins (ed.),
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Llewelyn, J. (1991) The Middle Voice of Ecological Conscience: A Chiasmic Reading of
Responsibility in the Neighborhood of Levinas, Heidegger and Others, London: Macmillan.
Bibliography 279
—— (2002) Appositions of Jacques Derrida and Emmanuel Levinas, Bloomington and
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Love, N.S. (1995) ‘What’s Left of Marx?,’ in S.K. White (ed.) The Cambridge Com-
panion to Habermas, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press:, 46–66.
Luckhardt, C.G. (1991) ‘Philosophy in the Big Typescript,’ in J. Hintikka (ed.)
Wittgenstein in Florida (Proceedings of the Colloquium on the Philosophy of
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Florida State University, 7–8 August 1989),
Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 255–72.
Lyotard, J.F. (1985) Just Gaming, trans. W. Giodzich, Manchester: Manchester Uni-
versity Press.
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
All biblical quotations are from The New English Bible, Oxford and Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1970.
Index
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012
differences 3–7, 75–6, 80, 92, 95 103–4, 110, 113; Wittgenstein 109, 110–11,
Diogenes 15, 16 115, 206n107, 240n129
disasters 69, 222n259 goodness 96, 119
disfigurement 82–3 Graham, G. 214n98
dissensus 4, 71, 78, 79 grammar, surface/depth 105, 206n101
dogmatism 218n174; Derrida 223n13; Greisch, J. 6, 70, 81–2, 101, 240n5, 240n6
Pyrrhonian Skepticism 17; religion 58; Sextus guilt: confession 143–4; conscience 123, 125–8;
43; skepticism 19; Wittgenstein 41, 104 Derrida 136, 140; ethics 121; Gaita 249n219;
Dostoyevsky, Fyodor: The Brothers Karamazov Heidegger 102, 140, 141, 241n12; innocence
120–1, 123, 144; Crime and Punishment 120 249n207; Levinas 1, 102, 120–1, 123, 136,
doubt 18, 43, 44–5, 51–2 140, 141, 147, 164, 187, 199–200; On Certainty
Drury. M. 12–13, 106, 107, 113, 136, 209n176, 81; punishment 167; radical singularity 143,
237n78 145–6, 147; responsibility 116, 120–1, 143,
195; shame 196; suffering 145; survivor 7, 8,
education 65, 98 129, 130–1, 141–2, 187–8; value judgements
Edwards, J.C. 42, 210n4 117–19; Wittgenstein 119, 123
Enlightenment 80, 166
epistemology 99 Habermas, J. 232n201
equipollence 17, 18, 19, 32 Harvey, I.E. 133
ethical approach xiii, 2, 131–2 haunting 128, 182, 194
ethical/political factors 18–21, 41 Heidegger, Martin: Auschwitz 195; Being and
ethics: animals 9; epistemology 99; guilt 121; Time 8, 123–7; clothing example 124; Dasein
language 122–3, 171; naturalism 8–9; On 123–8, 134, 138–9, 241n25, 254n123; good
Certainty 81; Philosophical Investigations 82; conscience 144; guilt 102, 140, 141, 241n12;
politics 18–21; predator 166; reason 9, 173–4; hesitancy 18; Levinas 7–8, 129–30, 139–40;
religion 6–7, 158, 159–60; responsibility 109, ontology 7–8, 163; sacrifice 127; silence
233n4; skepticism 254n111; social relations 262n69
99–100; subjectivity 2, 135; supernatural Heller, Joseph 20, 37
116–17, 196; Winch 232n3; world-book 116–17 Helvétius, C.A. 166
evil 184–5, 191, 214n98 Hertzberg, L. 48, 54, 55, 175, 213n77, 238n103
evolution, theory of 217n170 Herzog, Werner 79–81
expression, facial 84–5, 134 Hick, J.: Christianity 74–5; God 74; religion 77;
religious exclusivism 78–9; religious
face: animality 177; body 131; Derrida 152–3; pluralism 71, 73–4, 75, 76, 81, 223n18
disfigurement 82–3; ethical approach 131–2; history 214n90, 234n17
expression 84–5, 134; God 150–1; humanity D’Holbach, P.H.D. 255n141
132, 153; language 151, 160; Levinas 7, 9, holiness 162, 196, 254n112; see also saintliness
131–5, 149, 151–3, 245n113, 251n49; other Holland, R.F. 208n147
132, 134, 153–4, 219n198, 247n170, 258n202; Holocaust 128
‘Thou shalt not kill’ 137–8; visitation 250n6; home 181–2, 186, 259n229
vulnerability 174; Wittgenstein 83 hospitality: Derrida 178, 179, 180–1, 183–4,
faith: crisis of 53, 107; Culture and Value 56; 192, 200, 262n67, 266n163; evil 191;
Kierkegaard 217n153; Levinas 159–60, 179; language 262n67; Levinas 178, 266n163;
love 56; sacrifice 104; trust 47, 56; world- radical indifference 192; refuge 181–2; third
pictures 198 party 191–2; trespassing 185–6; trust 190–1;
Feyerabend, P. 71–3, 77, 222n254 vulnerability 183–5
von Ficker, Ludwig 117 host 183
fideism 5, 63, 106, 197, 199, 224n24 hostage 130–1, 183, 246n146
Fogelin, R.J. 202n5 house keys analogy 49–50
forgiveness 243–4n75 Hudson, W.D. 50, 54–5, 216n138
Frazer, James 91–3, 106, 108, 231n181; see also human behavior 183, 264–5n139
Wittgenstein, ‘Remarks on Frazer’s Golden human nature 169, 254–5n125
Bough’ humanism 161–2, 162–3, 177
288 Index
humans: Aboriginal peoples 95; animals Last Judgement 52–3, 57, 58, 104, 110
169–70, 170–1, 174–5, 174–6, 189; automata learning 47, 50–2, 57, 81
83–4; body 86; commonality 80–1, 92; Levi, P. 130–1, 243–4n75
disasters 222n259; face 132, 153; Levinas Levinas, Emmanuel 136, 239n115; anti-
170–1; lost 94–5; non-humanity 82; sacred naturalism 8–9, 148–9, 166, 173–4, 178, 200,
objects 80 257n178; Caputo 130, 180, 230n153;
humour 231n178 confession 152; conscience 137; Dasein
Husserl, Edmund 81–2, 85, 149, 153 254n122; Derrida 2–3, 8, 149–50, 177–8;
desire for other 165–6, 182, 254n117; face 7,
ideal 31 9, 131–5, 149, 151–3, 245n113, 251n49; faith
imagination 211n40 159–60, 179; God 149, 150, 151, 159–60; guilt
immorality 121 1, 102, 120–1, 123, 136, 140, 141, 147, 164,
immortality 262n72; responsibility 6–7; 187, 199–200; Heidegger 7–8, 129–30,
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 102–3; 139–40; home 181–2, 259n229; hospitality
Downloaded by [Nanjing University] at 08:34 06 December 2012