Augustine's Mathematical Realism
Augustine's Mathematical Realism
Augustine's Mathematical Realism
Paul J. Zwier
Calvin College
a. p is true.
Put in English, the property f has the property “two” if and only if there are
exactly two objects which have the property. The charge that the definition seems to be
† circular is erred defused by pointing out that the definition can be phrased in purely
logical terms.
Bertrand Russell used set-theoretic terms to explicate the concept of number. He
described the number two, for example, as “the class of all sets which are pairs”; that is
the class of all sets which can be put in one-to one correspondence with some paradigm
set, say {a, b}. Thus, the number 2 gets identified with all the class of all two-element
sets.
Since the time of Frege and Russell, there has been much theoretical work in set
theory. In such theories, there is usually no attempt to identify any objects for
consideration except for sets themselves. Thus, the main concern in such theories is to
describe operations under which sets can be constructed from previously given sets.
Nevertheless, most set theories provide for the existence of an empty set which has no
members. This means that many sets can be constructed using say, the operations of
union and intersection, from this empty set. Furthermore, in many set theories certain
sets are specified which are taken to play the role of the numbers 0,1,2,3, in the given
theory. Thus, if 0 is the symbol for the empty set, then
Ø,{ Ø },{ Ø,{ Ø }},..
are playing the roles of
0,1,2, ...
within the theory.
So, the preceding statement refers to the fact that all modern explications of the
concept of number identify numbers as sets of certain kinds. Perhaps the reason that
Frege’s use of properties of properties gives ontological status to such a wide variety of
non-material objects like properties and properties of properties, and then properties of
properties of properties and that such ontologies may be subject to a snarl of logical
difficulties force modern philosophers to limit considerations to formal, first-order,
theories about sets.
11. But there are no particular sets to which the numerals refer.
It is a fact that many different set-theories have been proposed and that each has
its own paradigm series of specific sets which play the role of the number series 0,1,2,3,...
It also is clear that there are few good reasons for us humans to prefer one series of
paradigms over any other and thereafter declare that our favorite is, in fact, the actual,
one and only, list of entities to which the numerals refer. Again, it appears that there is
no good reason to prefer one list of sets which is purported to be “the list” over any other.
Some philosophers have taken the method used by Russell to declare that the
number “three”, for instance, is the class of all three-element sets. We are thus passing to
equivalence classes which presumably contain the paradigms for the number three. Yet,
others have said that the set-theoretic process of forming equivalence class using an
equivalence relation involves functions and relations. Furthermore, the concept of
function or relation involves the concept of ordered pair and, again, the definition of
ordered pair varies from one set-theory to another and again there is no particular
definition which is to be preferred over against another. Perhaps the most common way
to define an ordered pair in set-theory is to say that
(x,y) = {x,{x,y}}.
Yet, there is no good reason that we humans can propose that will select any one
way of defining an ordered pair over another.
12. Thus the numerals refer to abstract objects which are not sets.
The conclusion that we can draw is that the numerals that we humans have
concocted do not successfully refer to any sets that we are aware of or that we can
imagine will be of such a nature that we would prefer such over any other.
13. There are no abstract objects distinct from sets.
This statement is controversial. It says that there are two kinds of objects;
material objects, and the abstract, non-material objects each of which is a set of some
kind. Since the numerals of arithmetic do not refer to material objects and since the
numerals of arithmetic do refer to non-material objects which are not sets, we are faced
with contradiction. One cannot hold to all of the above statements 1-13 without being
logically inconsistent. The mathematical realist is supposedly in a dilemma.
What can be said about Kitcher’s analysis? One is tempted to begin an analysis
of these statements to show how to relieve the supposed tension. Certainly a theist will
deny Statement 13 which asserts that there are no non-material objects distinct from sets!
I have chosen not to refute the case against mathematical realism myself. Instead, I will
reach back many centuries to the great church father, Augustine of Hippo to present the
case for Mathematical Realism.
Before I describe Augustine’s views about mathematical knowledge, I would like
to give a short description of Augustine’s life and times. I do so because it will provide a
context for understanding his views.
Augustine received his early education in Thagaste and Madaurus. His early
education was classical in nature, almost entirely literary. Augustine learned the art of
words very thoroughly and he was trained to acquire the art of persuasion. His education
placed a great premium on memory, was exclusively in Latin and had little philosophy,
science, or history in it. Later on Augustine continued his education in the city of
Carthage. It is here that he took a concubine and it is here that he also had a son whom
he called “Adeodatus”. It is here that he came under the influence of the Manichaean
sect and, in fact, he joined it for a short time.
Augustine was deeply influenced with the literary works of those who preceded
him. Some of the books and pamphlets which influenced him most are these.
a. “Hortensius”: a lost book of Cicero. “This book, indeed changed all my way of
feeling. It changed my prayers to thee, O Lord; it gave me entirely different plans
and aspirations. Suddenly, all empty hope for my career lost its appeal; and I was
left with an unbelievable fire in my heart, desiring the deathless qualities of
WISDOM, and I made a start to rise up and return to Thee... I was on fire, my
God, on fire to fly away from earthly things to Thee.” The Hortensius carried an
exhortation to Wisdom for Augustine. (Confessions: Ill, iv, 7).
b. “Letter of Foundation”: Mani. When the hearers of this letter heard the
pronouncements of Mani, they were “filled with light”. This was the basic
religious experience of the Manichee; he was a man who had become acutely
aware of his own state. Blessed is the man that shall know his own soul. He
found that he could not identify himself only with a part of himself, his good soul.
There are two opposite, equally real forces in the world which are locked in
battle; namely good and evil and that each is represented in the life of a man.
These Two Principles have natures which are absolutely distinct. As a
Manichaean he could grasp for himself the essence of religion.
c. In the dialogues of Cicero, The Academici, the skeptics are portrayed.
According to the skeptics, the greatest virtue lays in suspended judgment. The
greatest peril is in unheeding adherence to a single opinion.
d. The sermons of Ambrose at Milan. He later describes his reaction: “I noticed
repeatedly in the sermons of our bishop (Ambrose) that when God is thought of,
our thoughts should dwell on no material reality whatsoever, nor in the case of the
soul, which is the one thing in the universe that is closest to God.”
e. The Enneads: a discourse by Plotinus, an Egyptian Greek who had died in
Rome close in 270. The Enneads were edited by a disciple of Plotinus, called
Porphyry. In Milan, where Augustine lived for several crucial years of his life,
much of articulate and fashionable Platonism was Christian. There was an
audacious attempt to combine Platonism and Christianity. Perhaps Augustine
read the short treatise by Plotinus called “On Beauty”. Augustine responded in
the Confessions: VII, xvii, and 23. “For I wondered how it was that I could
appreciate beauty in material things. . . and what it was that enabled me to make
correct judgments about things that are subject to change, and to rule that one
thing ought to be like this and another will like that. I wondered how it was that I
was able to judge them in this way, and I realized that, above my own mind,
which was liable to change, there was the never-changing true eternity of truth.”
According to Plotinus “the outward-going diffusion of the One coincides with a
continuous tension of every part to return to its source of consciousness. . .” The
Neoplatonic doctrine includes “procession” outward and a “turning” inwards.
The power of the good always maintains the initiative. The words of John in
Chapter 1 of his gospel were taking on new meaning. “In the beginning was The
Word and the Word was with God, and The Word was God.” Augustine was on
his way to authentic Christianity.
f. The pagan Platonists regarded the Christian myth of Redemption, and
Incarnation, a Crucifixion, and a Resurrection of the Body as a barbarous
innovation on the authentic teachings of their master, Plotinus. Augustine turned
to the sacred writings of Saint Paul. “Because even if a man takes pleasure in the
law of God in his inner self,” what about the other law which I see in my
members? What shall be done with “O wretched man that I am”? Who shall set
him free? God was no lonely aristocrat; the therapy of God was made available to
all men by an act of popwaris elementia. “Not in revelling and drunkenness, not
in lust and wantonness, not in quarrels and rivalries. Rather, arm yourself with
the Lord Jesus Christ and spend no more thought on nature and nature’s
appetites.” Augustine later reports “I had no wish to read more and no need to do
so. For in an instant, as I came to the end of the sentence, it was as though the
light of confidence flooded into my heart and all the darkness of doubt was
dispelled”. Augustine was baptized at Milan in the baptistery adjoining the
basilica.
Augustine would devote the rest of his life to theology. In preparation, he retired
to Cassiciacum to a country villa near Lake Como in the beautiful foothills of the Alps to
write. He began a period of Christianae vitae otium, Christian cultured retirement. He
proposed an appropriate training which would culminate in the contemplation of the
Trinity. In his view, education was to be disciplined and, in order to be complete, it
should be expanded to include the abstract sciences, geometry, and the mathematical
background of astronomy. Augustine’s God is the God of the philosophers. He is the
founder of the harmonies of the universe and his relation to men is as absolute and
necessary as the form of a geometrical theorem. Yet there is a sharp note of unrelieved
anxiety about himself and of his dependency upon God.
Thereafter, Augustine lived in Ostia, where his mother, Monica, who had brought
him up as a Christian, died. Later he lived in Rome and Carthage. Cultivating a few
close friends he then returned to Thagaste with his servi Dei. These men were baptized,
dedicated, laymen, determined to live in the company of bishops, priests and noble
patrons, the full life of a Christian. Augustine wanted thereafter to be more than
contemplative. Eventually he went to Hippo where he became a priest and then later the
Bishop of Hippo. “Whoever thinks that in this mortal life a man may so disperse the
mists of bodily and carnal imaginings as to possess the unclouded life of changeless truth,
and to cleave to it with the unswerving loyalty of a spirit wholly estranged from the
common ways of life - he understands neither what he seeks nor who seeks it.”
Augustine realizes that he will never reach the fulfillment that he had first thought was
promised him by Christian Platonism.
Augustine eventually came to appreciate the sheer difficulty in achieving the ideal
life. A looming fact is the permanence of evil in human actions. Again, it became
obvious that the human will does not enjoy complete freedom. As St. Paul says the
“flesh lusteth against the spirit and that which you wish not, that you do. . .Who shall
deliver me. . .” Man’s body is not only the tomb of his soul. In the final analysis, the
lives of his parishioners became a book for Augustine to read. This leads Augustine to a
new humility. Again, he turned to St. Paul. In June of 394, in giving lectures on the
book of Romans, he began to see with Paul that in this life there is always unresolved
tension between flesh and spirit. The true image of life is inter, a long highway. “To
solve the question, I had previously tried hard to uphold the freedom of choice of the
human will; but the grace of God had the upper hand. Paul said ‘Who has made you
different? What have you gotten that you did not receive? If you have received all of
this, why glory in it as if you had not been given it?’ ” The notion of “delight” and
feeling had taken its place as the ally of the intellect. Delight is discontinous and
startlingly erratic. All a man can do is to yearn for an absent perfection. Desiderium
sinus cordis. It is yearning that makes the heart deep.
Augustine, the contemplative philosopher, became a priest. In the long run his
intellectual interests became transformed by his new duties. Augustine deeply felt the
need to slowly adjust to a life of authority at Hippo. “Darkness has overwhelmed me...
Oh, that I had the wings of a dove, that I might flyaway and be at peace.” Augustine had
the attitude (in distinction from the Donatists) that the church had the power to absorb the
world without losing its identity. The church is hungry for souls: let it eat,
indiscriminately if it need be. The Donatist movement, on the other hand, was like the
Ark of Noah. It was well-tarred, inside and out. Augustine’s Neo-Platonism had
profoundly affected his conception of the church. The rites of the church take on an
objective and permanent validity, independent of the subjective qualities of those who
participate in them.
“Whoever does not want to fear, let him probe his inner self. Do not just touch
the surface; go down into yourself; reach into the farthest corner of your heart. Examine
it then with care: see there whether a poisoned vein of the wasting love of the world does
not pulse, whether you are not moved by some physical desires . . . then only can you
dare to announce that you are pure and crystal clear, when you have sifted everything in
the deepest recesses of your inner being.” Sermon 348, 2
Let me point out some of the important aspects of Augustine’s life which will
serve as a background for understanding his epistemological views.
1. Augustine was a key figure in the transition from Classical Antiquity to the
Middle Ages; from a time when Greek philosophy and culture were predominant
in the world to the time when Christianity had not only won the hearts of men but
had also gained political ascendance. Thus, Augustine was a man who stood tall
in two worlds; the classical Greek world and the Christian world. Though he felt
the tension and dissonance between them, he managed to combine them in very
creative ways in his thinking.
2. Augustine was trained in rhetoric and in literature and not in the sciences and
mathematics. His academic training placed a great deal of attention on the literary
works of Virgil, Cicero, Sallust, and Terence. There was little emphasis upon
science, philosophy and history. By training, therefore, Augustine was skilled in
writing and in the art of persuasion. As an academic, he held professorships in
rhetoric.
3. He was a prolific writer. By my count in our library, there were 26 volumes on
the shelf in one collection of the translations of his writings. He wrote on many
different topics from metaphysics, epistemology, and the philosophy of mind to
theology and expositions of the Sacred Scriptures. His writing was not systematic
and it is not hard to detect changes that he underwent in his thinking. He openly
acknowledged such changes. His writings which were philosophical in nature
were never cold and detached. His ideas were presented with great passion and
eloquence and were directed towards the goal of happiness and blessedness for his
readers.
4. Augustine was deeply influenced by the Scriptures in his writings. It is alleged
that he refers to the scriptures some 42,817 times in his writings.
5. Augustine was a man who had deep need for love and affection from others.
He was a man who was profoundly influenced by interpersonal relationships. I
cite his strong attachment to his mother Monica and also his constant contact with
male friends, especially Alypius and Nebridius. His writings are self-disclosing,
indeed. They reveal his deepest thoughts and even darker side of his life. How
otherwise would we know that he took a concubine for 15 years with whom he
had a son, Theodatus? Again, he often reveals the sinful tendencies within him as
a wielder of great power and influence in the latter stages of his life as Bishop of
Hippo.
Now that we have had a glimpse of the life of Augustine, we shall turn to a
general look at what I will call his “world and life view”. How did Augustine look at the
world? What is the general setting of his epistemological and ontological views? I shall
include a diagram which nicely illustrates Augustine’s cosmology. It is taken from the
excellent book by Ronald Nash entitled The Light of the Mind: St. Augustine's Theory of
Knowledge (The University Press of Kentucky: 1969, page 5). Notice the important
triads in Augustine’s thinking. As to his ontology he has discerns three levels of
becoming; the first and foremost being God, the source of all being; next souls, including
the souls of men and angels; and finally, bodies, the material things of the world. As to
his theory of knowledge, Augustine sees knowing as beginning in the senses and
progressing to knowledge of the imagination, and, finally, culminating in the knowledge
of the intellect or reason which knows the spiritual and the eternal. All of this is
manifested in a duality which mankind possesses. Man has a ratio inferior which
describes his knowledge of material things; his scientia. But, more importantly, mankind
has a superior knowledge, sapienta or wisdom, by which he discerns the spiritual.
Before considering Augustine’s views about mathematical knowledge, let us look
a little more carefully at his general epistemology.
Augustine on Knowledge
Augustine squarely faces the Academics who questioned whether we humans can
ever know anything for certain and who advocated a cultured tentativeness for
themselves and for others as our best stance towards knowledge claims. The first part of
his argument against the Academics is to identify one kind of knowledge which is
certain; namely the self-knowledge of one’s own existence. Augustine’s argument is
summarized in the epigram Si fallor, sum: If I doubt, then I am. Augustine hereby
claims that we have privileged access to our own self-existence since doubting such is a
proof of our existence.
Furthermore, Augustine continues, if Skepticism is true, then search for God is
ruled out from the start and thus skepticism also leads to immorality. The first step along
the path leading to the mind of God is to accept revelation by faith. The famous epigram
Crede ut intelligas summarizes Augustine’s views on the relation between faith and
reason.
REASON AND KNOWLEDGE
ONTOLOGY EPISTEMOLOGY
(levels of reality) (types of vision)
WISDOM
GOD (sapietina) INTELLECTION
(rationes acternae) (reason)
visio intellectus
BODIES CORPORAL
(rationes seminales) KNOWLEDGE (sences)
(scientia) Visio corpotis
Nash, Ronald, The Light of the Mind: St. Augustine’s Theory of Knowledge, The
University Press of Kentucky, 1969, page 5.
Augustine also comes to the defense of sense experience in his argument against
the skeptics. He asserts that Christians “believe also that the evidence of the senses
which the mind uses by aid of the body; for if one who trusts the senses is sometimes
deceived, he is more wretchedly deceived who fancies that he should never trust them.”
(Contra Academicos: 30, 111, 11, 25) In his defense of knowledge claims involving the
senses, Augustine relies heavily on notions about the memory (memoria) and the
accompanying capacity of the mind to construct images. To Augustine, an image in the
memory plays a role in all knowledge claims. Such memory is not accounted for by
“anamnesis”, which is a recollection from a past existence, as asserted by Plato. Rather
as Etienne Gilson says. “The Platonic recollection of the past gives way to the
Augustinian memory of the present.” To Augustine, knowledge claims about the past in
which we assert recollections from previous experiences which are images constructed by
the mind are essentially not different from the immediate assertions which we make
about our everyday experiences. Furthermore, the processes which account for such
knowledge claims are INNER. To remember is attend to an image which is immediate to
the INNER eye.
Gilson describes the view of Augustine as follows. “Once an image of the present
corporeal object is formed by the spiritual vision, the inner man judges that object by
appeal to the eternal truths that are provided by illumination.” Non-material, eternal,
extramental objects permit us to judge material, temporal extramental objects. Gilson
says, “So, contrary to all expectations, the analysis of sensation has brought us back from
the exterior of things to the interior of the soul.” From the material object we get the
image in bodily sight from which we get an image in the memory from which we get an
image in the gaze of thought.
As an example, in his essay De Musica in which Augustine analyzes how we
come to recognize the meter in the Strabose in the hymn Deus Creator Omnium, there are
described five stages in the process of recognition. There is the voiced stage (the
production of sound waves), the sounding change, the noise stage, the remembered stage,
the discriminating stage.
What is emerging in this description of Augustine’s views is the vital role played
by the “inner man,” even in the use of his senses to know about material things.
The part of Augustine’s theories that is of most interest to us as mathematicians is
his theory of a priori knowledge. Of course a prior question to ask is whether there is any
such knowledge as a priori knowledge; that is knowledge which is independent of
experience and which is certain. Another associated question is whether there are such
entities as objects of a priori knowledge. Augustine’s answer is a resounding “yes” in
both cases and God plays a vital role in Augustine’s account for each.
Interestingly, Augustine begins his argument by stating that the claims which we
make about numbers as excellent examples of a priori knowledge. Such knowledge is
universally the same for all men. It is certain, and is about “principal ideas” which exist
in the mind of God. It is God, therefore, who is the explanation of our knowledge about
numbers and other mathematical objects. In giving this account of our knowledge of
mathematical objects, Augustine rejects the Aristotelian view that “numbers make their
impression on our minds not in their own right, but as images of visual things which
spring from our contacts with corporeal object.” We do not merely abstract the concept
of number by experience with corporeal objects. Let me quote from the essay De libero
arbitrio where Augustine explains his view at length. The dialogue is between Evodius
and Augustine. (On Free Will: Book II,20)
Aug: Now consider carefully, and tell me whether anything can be found which
all reasoning beings can see in common, each with his own mind and reason; something
which is present for all to see but which is not transformed like food and drink for the use
of those for whom it is present; something which remains complete and unchanged;
whether they see it or do not see it. Do you perhaps think there is nothing of that kind?
Ev: Indeed, I see many such, but it will be sufficient to mention one. The science
of numbers is there for all reasoning persons, so that all calculators may try to learn it,
each with his own reason and intelligence. One can do it easily, another with difficulty,
another cannot do it at all. But the science itself remains the same for everybody who can
learn it, nor is it converted into something consumed like food by him who learns it. If
anyone makes a mistake in numbers, the science itself is not at fault. It remains true and
entire. The error of the poor arithmetician is all the greater, the less he knows of the
science.
Aug: Quite right. I see you are not untaught in these matters, and so have quickly
found a reply. But suppose someone said that numbers make their impression on our
mind not in their own right, but rather as images of visible things, springing from our
contacts by bodily sense with corporeal objects, what would you reply? Would you
agree?
Ev: I could never agree to that. Even if I did perceive numbers with the bodily
senses I could not in any way perceive their divisions and relations. By referring to these
mental operations I show anyone to be wrong in his counting who gives a wrong answer
when he adds or subtracts. Moreover, all that I contact with a bodily sense ... I do not
know how long it will last. But seven and three make ten not only now but always. In no
circumstances have seven and three made anything else other than ten, and they never
will. So, I maintain that the unchanging science of numbers is common to me and to
every reasoning being.
Augustine argues that numbers are not conveyed to us by the bodily senses. His
argument is that whatever we contact with a bodily sense is proved to be not one but
many. “But however I come to know unity, I have not learned it from bodily senses. . .”
In section 23, Augustine argues that we know the truth of the firm, unbroken rule
that the fourth number after 4 is its double, the fifth number after 5 is its double, . . . the
double of any number is found to be exactly as far from that number as that number is
from the beginning of the series. He then says: “How do we find this changeless, firm
and unbroken rule persisting throughout the numerical series? No bodily sense makes
contact with all numbers, for they are innumerable. How do we know that this rule holds
throughout? How can any phantasy or phantasm yield such certain truth about numbers
which are innumerable? We must know this by the inner light, of which bodily sense
knows nothing. By many such evidences all disputants to whom God has given ability
and who are not clouded by obstinacy, are driven to admit that the science of numbers
does not pertain to bodily sense, but stands sure and unchangeable, the common
possession of all reasoning beings... But I am glad that the science of numbers most
readily occurred to you when you had to answer my question. For it is not in vain that
the holy books conjoin number and wisdom, where it is written: ‘I turned and inclined
my heart to know and consider and seek wisdom and number.’” (Eccl 7:25).
In question 46 of De diversis Quaestionibus: LXXXIII, De Ideis Augustine says,
“...the principal ideas are certain images, or stable and unchangeable reasons of things,
which not being themselves formed are consequently eternal and always the same, and
are contained in the Divine intelligence.”
To see Augustine’s view of the role played by “principal ideas” in perception
consider the following quotation from Augustine. It is found in De Trinitate: XI,6,10.
“...the images of corporeal things ... which we draw in through the bodily sense
and which flow in some way into the memory, and from which things that have
not been seen are also presented to the mind under a fancied image, whether it
contradicts the reality or by chance agrees with it, are approved or disapproved
within ourselves by rules that are wholly different, which remain unchanged
above our mind when we rightly approve or disapprove of anything.”
In Augustine’s view, therefore, the eternal ideas that govern the universe must be
God’s Divine ideas. God uses these principal ideas as templates in his creation of
material objects. Mankind has access to these Divine ideas in his inner self.
Furthermore, in the gaining our knowledge through our senses, the principal ideas that we
possess in our inner selves play an integral part in the judgments which we make. Bruce
Bubacz has described the Augustine view as follows.
He says that “in the dual functioning of visio spiritualis we can see most clearly
Augustine’s notion of a human being as a unity of the immaterial spiritual realm and the
corporeal, temporal realm.” He describes the interaction of the inner man and the data
which it receives from the physical world as “vital attention.” How does this vital
attention operate, according to Augustine? Bubacz describes the process as follows.
Visio corporis presents unorganized raw sensations to the inner man. Using clues (in
particular those clues associated with the preservation of the life of the outer man) the
inner man constructs an image representing a likely coherent systematic picture of the
physical world. Since the physical world was constructed by God in accord with His
divine ideas, the physical world is formally harmonious - it makes sense. In order to
represent this world accurately, the inner man must construct a picture of the world that
itself is harmonious. In making this picture, the inner man is illuminated by the principal
ideas which were placed there by God. Among the principal ideas which men possess are
his ideas about numbers and other mathematical objects.
Of greater concern to Augustine than universals like mathematical objects are the
more important universals like truth, and justice, and wisdom, and the beautiful. He says,
“Concerning universals of which we have knowledge, we do not listen to anyone
speaking and making sounds outside themselves. We listen to truth which presides over
our minds within us . . . Our real Teacher is he who is so listened to, who is said to dwell
in the inner man, namely Christ, who is the unchangeable power and wisdom of
God.”(De Trinitate:Xl)
In order to explain how we humans gain knowledge of these essential universals
Augustine uses the analogy between physical and mental sight. He says, “But we ought
to believe that the intellectual mind is so formed in its nature as to see things, which by
the disposition of the Creator are subjoined to things intelligible in a natural order, by a
sort of incorporeal light of a unique kind; as the eye of the flesh sees things adjacent to
itself in this bodily light, of which it is made to be receptive and adapted to it.” We “see”
the principal ideas as objects in the same way that we see physical objects. To see a
physical object, we need not only an observer and something to be observed. We also
need light of illumination which falls upon the object to be observed and an observer
which is attentive to the situation. In like manner, in order to acquire knowledge about
numbers and, more importantly, about truth and beauty and justice we need illumination
which dwells in the inner man and whose presence is ultimately due to God Himself.
Let us now return to the first part of my talk which describes the tensions which
are supposedly present when one holds to mathematical realism. Augustine’s defense
would at least contain the following points. First, it is nonsense to say that the only
nonmaterial entities that exist are sets. The list of nonmaterial entities is much richer than
that! Secondly and more important, is the reality that God exists and that it is He who is
the ultimate reason behind the existence of all else. This God that we believe in is a
personal God with whom we have to do. It is He who has made each of us in His Image.
It is He who has equipped us for knowledge. It is He who provides the inner illumination
so that we can know justice and truth and beauty. It is He who illuminates our thoughts
about numbers and their properties even though we may not be aware of his presence.
I am sure that all of this sounds very strange to our twentieth century, Western
ears. Mathematical Realism is not a serious choice for many philosophers today. For
examples one has only to think of the almost gleeful conclusions which Morris Kline
draws at the end of his book entitled Mathematics: Loss of Certainty. His “truth” is
purely cultural, having been agreed to by “fiat” or by a social contract. Again, in the
impressive work of Philip Kitcher entitled The Nature of Mathematical Truth there is an
argument against the very notion that mathematics is a priori knowledge at all. Instead, it
proposes an account of mathematical knowledge which is empiricist at its foundations
and which accounts for present day mathematics knowledge in evolutionary terms.
Another example is the general agreement among the authors in the anthology New
Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics that, since the attempts to found
mathematics have failed, philosophers of mathematics should content themselves with a
study of the practice of mathematics and abandon, at least for the present time, any
metaphysical or foundational analysis of the discipline. The editor of this anthology calls
this “new direction” “quasi-empiricism.”
Yet, we are Christians as was Aurelius Augustus and I believe that the great
Church Father has some ideas which are worthy of our attention. What should we say by
way of analysis about Augustine’s views? Does the fact that Augustine’s philosophy of
mind was influenced by Platonic thought disqualify it from serious consideration by
Christians today?
First, I want to make a disclaimer or two about Greek philosophy in general.
There is no doubt at all that there is a great gulf between the God of the philosophers and
the Triune God of the Scriptures. There is also no doubt that there is a great gulf between
the Greek notion of the body as a prison house for the soul and the Biblical emphasis
upon the body in the Incarnation and in the resurrection body. Finally, there is a great
gulf between the Greek notion that the essence of man is to be found in his reason and
that the good life is an ascent to the wholly Other and the Biblical view that man is saved
from his sin by the grace of God who comes near to us through Jesus Christ and the good
life is a response to this salvation. Thus, any return to mathematical realism through
exclusively Greek ideas will be insufficient and unsatisfactory. But what about
Augustine’s views? Are they a good starting point for a satisfactory defense of
mathematical realism from a Christian perspective?
I shall list some aspects of Augustine’s position which are the source of the most
serious objections to his view.
1. Augustine is very optimistic about the possibility of certain knowledge.
Furthermore his view depends upon the notion that God can play an important role in an
account of man's knowledge. In this account Augustine refers to the Mind of God and
says that the principal ideas are found in the mind of God. But some Christians will say
that, as the result of man’s sin, they are very skeptical about any assertion that man can
find the truth through reason even if God is the alleged source of such capacity.
Furthermore, some Christians will say that it is improper for us to use God in an
explanatory way since, in essence, God is wholly incomprehensible, and so far above our
understanding that even our analogies about him have very little value as such
explanations. There is the good question of just what effect the coming of sin in the
world had upon man’s capacity to know the truth. What effect did the coming of sin have
upon the image of God in us?
2. Augustine has a rather high opinion of man and his relation to God's other
creatures. His views clearly differentiate mankind from the animals, for example, and
place mankind in a unique position in the creation order; a creature of God with a special
role to play and whose existence is immortal. Second, Augustine places strong emphasis
upon man’s reason as a most important characterization of the image of God in us. Some
Christians may demur at this point.
3. Of particular concern to many Christians is the dualism which Augustine
advocates in his view of man; man has an inner self and an outer self; a soul and a body
(in more common theological terms). Furthermore, Augustine gives a prominence to the
inner man over against the outer man in his explanation of human knowledge. It is
alleged, at least, that the Bible does not clearly describe man in such terms, but rather, has
a more holistic view of man and that the Biblical notion rooted in Hebraic terms is be,
more in terms of the ‘heart’ rather than the hierarchical view of Augustine.
It was of some interest to me to look into the writings of John Calvin to see if
there is any such dualism of body and soul in his writings. In Book I and Chapter XV
there is a lengthy discussion about the state of man at his creation: the faculties of the
soul, the Divine Image, free-will and the original purity of his nature. In fact, Calvin also
refers to the “pagan philosophers” and even grudgingly admits that the sentiment of Plato
is “more correct, because he considers the image of God as being in the soul.” I shall
quote from Chapter XV in section II.
“That man consists of soul and body, ought not to be controverted. By the ‘soul’ I
understand an immortal, yet created essence, which is the nobler part of him. Sometimes
it is called a ‘spirit’; for though, when these names are connected, they have a different
signification, yet when ‘spirit’ is used separately, it means the same as ‘soul’; as when
Solomon, speaking of death says that ‘the spirit shall return unto God, who gave it’.”
Later when referring to Stephen he asserts that the Bible intends “no other than
that, when the soul is liberated from the prison of the flesh, God is its perpetual keeper.
Those who imagine that the soul is called a spirit because it is a breath or faculty divinely
infused in the body but destitute of any essence are proved to be in gross error by the
thing itself and by the whole tenor of scripture. It is true, indeed, that while men are
immoderately attached to the earth they become alienated from the Father of lights, are
immersed in darkness so that they consider not that they shall survive after death, yet, in
the meantime, the light is not so entirely extinguished by the darkness but that they are
affected with some sense of their immortality.”
Later he goes on to say the following. “But the agility of the human mind,
looking through heaven and earth, and the secrets of nature and comprehending in its
intellect and memory all ages, digesting everything in proper order, and concluding future
events from those which are past, clearly demonstrates that there is concealed within man
something distinct from the body ... We apprehend what is right, just, and honest, which
is concealed from the corporeal senses.
Further on in the section he says that “it would be folly to seek for a definition of
the soul from the heathen philosophers, of whom Plato is almost the only one who has
plainly asserted it to be an immortal substance ... The sentiment of Plato, therefore is
more correct, because he considers the image of God as being in the soul.”
It is clear to me that there is within the Reformed tradition the view of some that
each person has a body and a soul (spirit) with an essence that is distinct from the body.
At least some in our tradition, including Calvin, assert that the Bible teaches that the
image of God has its locus in the soul and that this soul is immortal and it is what
continues to exist after our earthly death. Such a theological view of man can be the
foundation of a Christian epistemology which may include some aspects of mathematical
realism.
In conclusion, let me raise some questions for our consideration.
Is Augustine’s view so infused with Platonic notions so as to be unacceptable to
Christians today? Does it seem plausible that we Christians will need to develop a
philosophy of mathematics which will be totally unacceptable to the existing
mathematical community because it uses the Triune God of the Scriptures in an essential
way in its explanations? What should our attitude be to the current views about the
nature of mathematics which limit the categories of explanation to human culture and
social evolution. Will these views lead us into deep skepticism about human knowledge
and into profound relativity or are they more compatible with a Christian position than
Mathematical Realism?
Is the Christian Mathematical Realism as originated by the Bishop of Hippo a
viable option for a Christian philosophy of mathematics today?
Bibliography
1. Etienne Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine, Victor Gollanez LTD
(1961).
2. Bruce Bubacz, St. Augustine’s Theory of Knowledge: A Contemporary Analysis,
Edwin Mellon Press (1981).
3. Ronald Nash, The Light of the Mind: St. Augustine’s Theory of Knowledge, The
University Press of Kentucky (1969).
4. John Calvin, The Institutes of the Christian Religion, Volume 1, Presbyterian Board of
Christian Education.
5. John Burleigh, Augustine’s Earlier Writings, The Library of Christian Classics,
Volume VI, The Westminster Press.
6. Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo, Faber and Faber, London (1967).
7. Vernon Bourke, Augustine’s View of Reality, The Saint Augustine Lecture, 1963,
Villanova Press (1964)
8. Thomas Tymoczko, New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics: An Anthology,
Birkhauser (1985).