Jeffrey M. Jackson: Genealogy and Convalescence
Jeffrey M. Jackson: Genealogy and Convalescence
Jeffrey M. Jackson: Genealogy and Convalescence
JEF F REY M . J A CK S O N
Nietzsche and Suffered Social Histories
Jeffrey M. Jackson
Nietzsche and
Suffered Social
Histories
Genealogy and Convalescence
Jeffrey M. Jackson
University of Houston–Downtown
Houston
TX, USA
vii
viii Acknowledgements
1 Introduction 1
Bibliography
179
Index
183
ix
CHAPTER 1
Introduction
environment. For all three, the integration of subjectivity with its envi-
ronment is not a seamless unity, but rather an integration with the object
that constitutively eludes integration.
Nietzsche’s main concepts have relatives in Winnicott’s transitional
phenomena and Klein’s concept of the transition from the paranoid–
schizoid position to the depressive position. Nietzsche’s thinking is proto-
psychoanalytic, but not in the sense that he is a mere precursor who was
surpassed by psychoanalytic concepts. As in object relations psychology,
he insists on the suffered, embodied, relational origins of human sub-
jectivity—particularly its dominant forms which assume forms of ani-
mistic subjectivism. Moreover, reading Nietzsche in a certain way allows
an extension to adulthood and to culture of that relationally mediated
ordeal which Winnicott and Klein describe as typical of infantile develop-
ment and the facilitating environment. This also implies a way to read
the commonality between Nietzsche, Marx, and Freud. Their theories
interrogate the social histories of theorizing and moral subjectivity, which
is symptomatic of a troubled relationality within which that subjectivity
is not master. As this troubled relationality is mediated by concrete and
symbolic social arrangements, the critique of the subject implies a cri-
tique of those arrangements.
Social theory typically proceeds by the assertion of some sort of ontol-
ogy of human being and then describes social relations through this lens.
In this sense, Nietzsche might not be seen as having a social theory. For
Nietzsche, there is no social contract or foundational idea of reason or
spirit, human nature, morality, rights, duties, free will, etc. However, this
apparent lack of a traditional social theory is properly understood as a
more fundamental critique of the starting point of such theories in reflec-
tion. For Nietzsche, reflection cannot be an unbiased starting point for
theorizing sociality, because it is itself a symptom of sociality. At the same
time, there is no way around reflection, as if one could directly articu-
late the pure body, being, or existence in some sort of embodied meta-
phor, transgression, direct experience, revelation, clearing, event, etc.
Nietzsche’s social theory would then be implicit in his model of reflec-
tion: Biased reflection reflects on its own suffered, socio-historical condi-
tions. However, those conditions are not merely given, capable of being
described through a positivistic social science, nor are they simply the
causes of reflection. Rather, they are suffered or undergone in a way that
exceeds or ruptures reflection. Nietzschean reflection is symptomatic of
the situated vulnerability to that which exceeds reflection.
1 INTRODUCTION 5
Consequently, one might say that reflection takes one of two para-
digmatic forms—often subtly intermingled—that are symptomatic of
this encounter with this excess. On the one hand, reflection may take
the form of a reactive, defense mechanism—which Nietzsche designates
in a variety of ways as ressentiment, slave morality, or ascetic ideal—find-
ing truth in what is familiar, simplified, ahistorical, and socially shared.
On the other hand, genealogy or convalescence signifies a form of reflec-
tion that may be able to negotiate its suffered basis in an encounter with
what is strange, singular, and infused with the negative. For Nietzsche,
truth might be said to be a function of whether or not one can bear and
negotiate this negativity—either a magical system or a negative dialectic.
Furthermore, this affectivity of which truth is a symptom is socio-histor-
ically reproduced. On the one hand, truth is an expression of affective
social-histories, but on the other hand, truth reproduces those affective
social conditions.
Nietzsche can thereby be read as contributing to a critical social the-
ory. He does this not only by interrogating the imbrication between
reflection and embodiment, but by insisting on the primacy of suffered
vulnerability in the socio-historically mediated negotiation of that imbri-
cated complexity. This suffered element exceeds and overwhelms reflec-
tion which takes the form of a symptom. One might say that this socially
conditioned suffering undergirds, conditions, and ruptures reflection,
such that coherent reflection would seek its own conditions of possibil-
ity within vulnerability. Consequently, reflection’s interrogation of itself
leads back to a suffered need to transform the social conditions which
condition and rupture that reflection.
In this way, Nietzsche contributes to the sketching out of the condi-
tions of possibility of transforming the society which conditions reflec-
tion. His critique of idealism is an attempt to account for the process of
working ourselves out of our pasts and thereby create the conditions for
a better future. Reflection’s genealogical critique of itself shows that it is
conditioned by suffered, social histories and therefore implies the need
of transforming the conditions which reproduce those histories. In other
words, reason’s critique of itself does not merely imply a need to think
differently, but rather a need for new social conditions which would
facilitate convalescence. That critique reveals that reflection lies within a
pre-subjective, socio-historically conditioned crossroads between ressen-
timent and convalescence. These crossroads, however, cannot be navi-
gated merely subjectively, as the result of a choice or of virtue or ethical
6 1 INTRODUCTION
Genealogy could be said to refer to more than simply the text titled
“On the Genealogy of Morality.” Nietzsche’s thinking in general often
takes the form of genealogies of subjectivity via interrogations of moral-
ity, reflection, free will, truth, and experience. Such thinking does not
amount to merely naturalistic, causal accounts of subjectivity, but rather
provides accounts of the suffered social origins of subjectivity. As an ini-
tial account of Nietzsche’s varied genealogies of the subject, this section
considers several moments in Nietzsche’s texts, which gesture in differ-
ent ways toward the primacy of suffered social histories. Bringing these
three terms together—suffering, sociality, and history—implies their
imbrication, i.e., the way in which each is entangled with the other.
Nietzsche’s aphoristic style is often expressive of the impossibility of ade-
quately describing and knowing that imbrication; sometimes Nietzsche
addresses the histories or socialities of suffering, other times he empha-
sizes the suffered character of sociality and history.
Throughout his work, Nietzsche refers to the dominant form of sub-
jectivity and associated concepts—free will, intellect, morality, virtue,
etc.—as lies, errors, or fairytales. On the surface, such accounts seem to
maintain at least a trace of a cognitive subject which could be incorrect
or deceived and therefore could have access to truth. At the same time,
the truths disclosed within Nietzsche’s critiques not only unfailingly
exceed any notions of such a subject or truth as identity, but rather con-
dition and rupture such notions. They point to a suffered embodiedness
8 1 INTRODUCTION
There are two key points to focus on here. First, the list of qualifiers that
undergird the fairytale account of the subject implicitly suggest that sub-
jectivity is itself the effect of a complex imbrication of embodied, suf-
fered histories: an impure, suffered, temporal, affective, will-driven
imbrication. Will here, of course, is not a reference to a spontaneous
source of action, as in “freedom of the will,” but rather to something
closer to an unconscious drive that is socio-historically conditioned.
Elsewhere, Nietzsche describes the will as the expression of a more basic
relation between a plurality of embodied, physiological forces.4 The fact
that the will is imbricated with time and suffering suggests that this is
ERRORS, LIES, AND THE SUFFERED SOCIAL HISTORIES OF SUBJECTIVITY 9
Human beings do not so much flee from being tricked as from being
harmed by being tricked…they do not hate deception but rather the dam-
aging, inimical consequences of certain species of deception…They desire
the pleasant, life-preserving consequences of truth; they are indifferent
to pure knowledge if it has no consequences, but they are actually hostile
towards truths which may be harmful and destructive….9
…each word immediately becomes a concept, not by virtue of the fact that
it is intended to serve as a memory of a unique, utterly individualized, pri-
mary experience to which it owes its existence, but because at the same
time it must fit countless other, more or less similar cases, i.e., cases which,
strictly speaking, are never equivalent…Every concept comes into being by
making equivalent that which is non-equivalent.10
ERRORS, LIES, AND THE SUFFERED SOCIAL HISTORIES OF SUBJECTIVITY 13
predatory person would not have needed it. That our actions, thoughts,
feelings, and movements—at least some of them—even enter into con-
sciousness is the result of a terrible ‘must’ which has ruled over man for a
long time…he needed help and protection, he needed his equals…12
causality is a consolation for the unbearable fact that we are the prod-
ucts of an irreducible complexity of imbricated factors entailing exposure
to the strange and unfamiliar. As will be discussed in Chap. 3, in On the
Genealogy of Morality, this is described as a sensibility descending from
the dominated, obliterated life of slaves for whom the unfolding of exist-
ence in the negotiation and exploration of things was either impossible
or unbearable, giving rise to mass forms of dissociation. He writes:
Our hypothesis is that Nietzsche’s text, as a textual and bodily labour and
movement has the job of signifying the Ja-sagen (and not the Versagen)
that makes the body speak as grand reason: through the over determina-
tion of its central signs (genealogy, Übermensch, Will to Power, etc.), but its
metaphorical movement and rhetorical procedures, which are those used
by the play of drives: inverted commas, Sperrdruck, dots, dashes, anacolu-
thons, the world of aphorisms, alternating texts with blanks, the continual
emergence of the body. The body becomes a text: Nietzsche’s text is as
much a practice as thinking.21
This appeal to “life” and “body” abstracts from suffered sociality. The
body is not a thing, a plurality, or the Ur-form of non-identity. Rather,
ERRORS, LIES, AND THE SUFFERED SOCIAL HISTORIES OF SUBJECTIVITY 19
The body is thus that part of the world through which the world is revealed
to be something other than what it is. The body is living in so far as it is the
place in which different perspectives confront one another. Metaphor is the
mode in which a living passage from one perspective to another take place.
But the body itself: (1) can only be designated metaphorically; (2) acts as a
20 1 INTRODUCTION
metaphor for the metaphorical interpretation that the body is said to estab-
lish…The body is, as a location for perspectives that is always singular, the
place where the text is joined to its other outside of discourse and the place
where it is pluralized metaphorically. The body…is thus the principle of the
imaginary transcendence of the world.24
The body as a sexual cause then reveals itself to be the thing that produces
a being that, in questioning its own origins, questions its identity, evo-
lution and grouping habits. Moreover, the body, as an invisible anterior
origin is what produces us as beings who question things because we are
necessarily enigmatic to ourselves…Sexuality presents us as beings that are
unconscious of their origins and question themselves over the question of
origins…As a genealogical being, man merely manifests his position as a
being separated, by his corporeity, from his truth.26
ERRORS, LIES, AND THE SUFFERED SOCIAL HISTORIES OF SUBJECTIVITY 21
For Blondel, the goal is saying and unsaying, exceeding discourse, which
means affirming embodied life—not merely a “play of signifiers” but
again, a non-conceptual reality that exceeds all concepts in an infinite
pluralism infusing all singular perspectives. Nietzsche’s emphasis is not
on letting bodies speak—they always speak—rather, it is on the ordeal of
working-through fixated forms of suffered embodiment and the implied
social imperative of creating cultures to shelter and facilitate embodied
convalescence. Despite the admirable emphasis on textual labor, Blondel
occludes the broader suffered social history within which subjectivity and
writing take form. Letting the body speak through textual metaphor may
simply reproduce the status quo through countercultural ritual or a form
of maniacal release that would celebrate embodied need, in a Dionysian
affirmation of plurality, dance, and dissolution of identity. This would be
a reification of the body, which is abstracted from the messy socio-his-
torical imbrication discussed above; the body is primarily suffered and it
is socio-culturally mediated through this suffering which is inflected by
22 1 INTRODUCTION
loss, social arrangements, recognition, and the threat of losing that rec-
ognition.
division of labor. For each, this suffered sociality repeats itself; an amoral,
more or less traumatic meaninglessness repeats itself. On the other hand,
for each thinker, there is a social reproduction of a bad conscience in
relation to this imposition, such that the suffered, social history of this
imposition cannot be borne. In other words, there is a naturalization of
the status quo: in Marx, through ideology, commodity fetishism, and the
fixated social position of the working class; in Freud, through defense
against the traumatic character of the loss of infancy; in Nietzsche,
through slave morality, ascetic ideals, and consolation. Consequently,
each theory points toward the need to disrupt this naturalization—to
shelter and facilitate the working-through of this amoral meaninglessness
and create a convalescent culture where irredeemable suffering can be
negotiated, and integrated, insofar as integration is possible.
In the following chapters, Nietzsche’s thinking is read along with
aspects of Freudian theory and object relations psychoanalysis—spe-
cifically the theories of Melanie Klein and D.W. Winnicott, as well as
Freud’s theory of mourning, which is the part of his theory that is per-
haps most closely aligned with object relations theory. The latter is some-
times also called relational psychoanalysis, a concept that resonates with
the emphasis on the social character of the suffered histories of the sub-
ject. For the purposes of this introduction, one might borrow the term
“scene” from Freud’s appeal to the primal scene (Urszene), to character-
ize the thinking of Nietzsche, Marx, and Freud, who can be said to con-
tribute to sketching the scenes of history.
During Freud’s analysis of the so-called “Wolfman,” a variety of symp-
toms are traced back to an inferred primal scene, in which as an infant,
the analysand would have observed parental coitus.28 In his description
of the case, Freud is notoriously ambiguous as to whether the primal
scene actually occurred or is constructed retrospectively through the dia-
logical and associative process of analysis. Similarly, Freud describes the
dream as a “substitute for an infantile scene modified by being trans-
ferred on to a recent experience.”29 Dreams might be said to originate
in the suffered, relational scenes of infancy, imbricated with social his-
tory. Compatible with the ambivalent character of the scene as both
remembered and constructed, one might infer general characteristics of
the intersubjective dynamics of infancy which are excessive, and more
or less impossible to navigate. Love of parental figures generally takes
place within ambivalent scenes: aggressive and negligent caregivers, with
disruptions and loss of their consistent attentiveness, shifting of their
24 1 INTRODUCTION
criticize, but ‘Critics’ who beside that are unlucky enough to be human
beings as well. They therefore recognize only one real need, the need
for theoretical criticism … Consciousness, or self-consciousness, is per-
ceived as the only human quality. Even love is being denied, since in
it the beloved one is just ‘an object’. Down with the object!”31 As we
have seen in the passages above from Nietzsche, there is a similar cri-
tique of the idealism which posits a cause within subjectivity that could
direct itself toward morality or truth. Neither thinker sees that idealism
as being merely an “error” that is to be replaced by a true alternative;
rather, that idealism is itself seen as being reproduced by material his-
tory; Marx’s appeal to the division of labor has a parallel in Nietzsche’s
account of noble and slave. Moreover, as with Nietzsche, the ideal-
ist conception of subjectivity expresses an attempt to separate from that
which is inseparable.
To some extent, Marx sees the interrogation of this material history
as a positivistic endeavor.32 As has been suggested, for Nietzsche, such
an interrogation is thwarted by an excessive suffered element of that his-
tory of which that interrogation would be symptomatic. It seems to be
the case that for Marx, history is accessible through a relentless empiri-
cal social science, whereas for Nietzsche, history is a suffered relational
field. Nonetheless, one might see this as more of a difference of empha-
sis, such that Marx’s critique of the subject lays out essential dimensions
of the scene of suffered life. Whereas philosophy distinguishes humans
from animals by consciousness, for Marx, it is the social production of
the means of subsistence that distinguishes humans and produces con-
sciousness:
The production of life, both of one’s own in labour and of fresh life in pro-
creation, now appears as a double relationship: on the one hand as a natural,
on the other as a social relationship. By social we understand the co-opera-
tion of several individuals, no matter under what conditions, in what manner
30 1 INTRODUCTION
and to what end. It follows from this that a certain mode of production, or
industrial stage, is always combined with a certain mode of co-operation,
or social stage, and this mode of co-operation is itself a ‘productive force’.
Further, that the multitude of productive forces accessible to men determines
the nature of society, hence, that the ‘history of humanity’ must always be
studied and treated in relation to the history of industry and exchange.37
depiction of the suffered, social history within which “truth” and the
subject arise. They function to open up a conceptual space within which
concepts face their limits in the object’s negativity, which, as Adorno
says, is experienced by the subject as suffering. Historical critique evokes
the negativity of history along with its conceptualization of that history.
Its concepts are self-consciously tentative, put forward as proposed archi-
tectonics of socio-historical existence which undergirds, conditions, and
exceeds the concept. Any thinking which does not avow its own depend-
ence on suffered social life reproduces the social conditions from which it
would like to escape.
…it would serve no purpose to lift the veil in order to make reality
appear in its transparency…the darkness is primary and cannot be over-
come through theory, through a pure and simple unveiling…he declares
that only practical tranformations may—and then after a ‘long and pain-
ful development’—bring about transparent and rational relationships…
Clear meaning thus does not pre-exist ideological obscurity, and there is
no ‘truth’ without a labour of transformation. Clarity comes only in the
moment of the after-effect and is attained, not through a resolution of the-
oretical contradictions, but through a practical revolution.42
The point of view which sees relations as inverted is that neither of error
nor of illusion. It is that of a certain kind of mind—an anti-artistic one—
which wants to see reality without veils, naked, from the point of view of
indecency. Naked, in broad daylight, outside of the dark chamber of con-
sciousness. It is the perspective of those who are unaware that, behind the
veil, there is yet another veil. It is the symptomatic unawareness of the
instincts’ loss of virility. To seek the unveiling of truth is to reveal that one
no longer knows how to get it on with women…a perverse judgement,
by instincts neither strong enough nor fine enough to love appearance for
appearance’s sake…45
pure, interior search for truth … one can in reality traverse this descending
line only to restore the sparkling exteriority that has been covered up and
buried. The fact is that whereas the interpreter must go himself to the bot-
tom of things like an excavator, the movement of interpretation is, on the
contrary, one that projects out over the depth, raised more and more above
the depth, always leaving the depth below, exposed to ever greater visibility
… the eagle’s taking flight, the ascent of the mountain, all the verticality so
important in Zarathustra, is, in the strict sense, the reversal of depth, the
discovery that depth was only a game, and a crease [pli] in the surface.47
36 1 INTRODUCTION
Notes
1. Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics, Translated by Dennis Redmond,
151. All subsequent references will be cited in the text.
2. This thought is clearly expressed in The Gay Science: “In favour of criti-
cism. —Something you formerly loved as a truth or a probability now
strikes you as an error; you cast it off and believe your reason has made
a victory. But maybe that error was as necessary for you then, when you
were still another person—you are always another person—as are all your
present ‘truths’, like a skin that concealed and covered many things you
weren’t allowed to see yet. It is your new life, not your reason, that has
killed that opinion for you: you don’t need it any more …”. See Nietzsche,
The Gay Science, Translated by Nauckhoff, 174–175.
3. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, Edited by Keith Ansell-
Pearson. Translated by Carol Diethe. (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 1997), 87. All subsequent references will be cited in the
text.
4. For Nietzsche, willing is not a simple, self-evident result of a free action
of “I” as cause. For example, in Beyond Good and Evil, he writes: “… our
body is, after all, only a society constructed out of many souls—. L’effet
NOTES 39
Convalescence and Mourning
For Derrida, both Freud and Nietzsche see the subject as a function of
textuality, which is governed by non-phonetic writing. Writing—as archi-
writing, the writing of différance—would thus precede and enable the
subject as presence. Both thinkers would then essentially be critics of phi-
losophy as the ontology of presence and as such provide models for the
thinking of différance, in which “putting into question of the authority
of consciousness is first and always differential … All the differences in
the production of unconscious traces and in the processes of inscription
(Niederschrift) can also be interpreted as moments of différance…”.5
According to his strategy, Derrida will put the criticisms of Nietzsche and
Freud into play not only against the lingering metaphysics found in the
Nietzschean and Freudian texts themselves, but also when reading other
figures. For example, in problematizing the “nostalgia” of “a lost native
country of thought” implicit in the Heideggerian naming of “Being,”
Derrida appeals to Nietzsche, who “puts affirmation into play, in a cer-
tain laughter and a certain step of the dance.”6 But, does this valoriza-
tion of affirmation as play, laughter, and dance do justice to Nietzsche’s
convalescent thinking?
Other readings of the relationship between Nietzsche and Freud
(who, along with many in his circle, was very familiar with Nietzsche)
are possible.7 One might, for example, compare Freud’s notion of the
work of mourning with Nietzschean convalescence—a comparison not
made by Derrida or Deleuze—to help to clarify the suffered character
of thinking for Nietzsche. Both mourning and convalescence are con-
crete, salutary processes of undergoing a materiality that undergirds and
exceeds consciousness. The mourner undergoes a concrete disruption in
losing her object. She does not think or will her way out of her pain, but
slowly works through it, withdrawing and reinvesting libido. The conva-
lescent, in a similar fashion, suffers a wound that is beyond her control,
and she is obliged to allow the body to adjust, adapt, and retrain itself
on an incalculable timeline. In both cases, thinking and all that comes
with it (understanding, expectation, idealization, etc.) is worked on by a
concrete disruption of material life. Mourning and convalescence are not
simply “subjective” actions or internal experiences. They are modes of
suffering objectivity, of the subject’s embeddedness as an object within a
relational world of objects, of things, and of others. They are subjective
experiences of the suffered limit of subjectivity. That suffering works on
the situated subject, bit by bit, in a fragmentary way, such that thoughts,
expectations, goals, and values are suffered in their limit. To use the
46 2 CONVALESCENCE, MOURNING, AND SOCIALITY
is regularly the reaction to the loss of a loved person, or to the loss of some
abstraction which has taken the place of one, such as fatherland, liberty,
and ideal, and so on…The testing of reality, having shown that the loved
object no longer exists, requires forthwith that all the libido shall be with-
drawn from its attachments to this object. Against this demand a struggle
of course arises—it may be universally observed that man never willingly
abandons a libido-position, not even when a substitute is already beckon-
ing to him. This struggle can be so intense that a turning away from reality
ensues, the object being clung to through the medium of a hallucinatory
wish-psychosis. The normal outcome is that deference for reality gains the
day. Nevertheless its behest cannot be at once obeyed. The task is now car-
ried through bit by bit, under great expense of time and cathectic energy,
while all the time the existence of the lost object is continued in the mind.
Each single one of the memories and hopes which bound the libido to
the object is brought up and hyper-cathected, and the detachment of the
libido from it accomplished.8
There are several points to emphasize here. First, for Freud, conscious-
ness is embedded in affective sociality, i.e., the economy of libidinal
cathexis overly determines attention, expectation, and conscious life
generally speaking. Second, given this affective embeddedness, only
a concrete disruption—a new materiality—can lead to a shift in libido-
position. Since no one ever “willingly abandons a libido-position,” the
“bit-by-bit” recathexis of the work of mourning is the condition for the
possibility of a shift in thinking. Third, the loss at issue may concern his-
torically constituted abstractions and ideals which symbolically structure
society. Fourth, this loss, according to Freud, does not by any means
necessarily lead to mourning; in other words, the loss can be traumatic
and the object can by internalized, despite its material disappearance,
resulting in a delusional inability to bear the loss.
Nietzsche, of course, was one of the sources for Freud’s general view
on the material embeddedness of consciousness; one might think here,
for example, of Nietzsche’s characterization of the Pre-Socratic Greeks,
whose art is marked by their ability to bear their suffering, or the various
48 2 CONVALESCENCE, MOURNING, AND SOCIALITY
the sick person has only one great remedy: I call it Russian fatalism, that
fatalism without revolt which is exemplified by a Russian soldier who, find-
ing a campaign too strenuous, finally lies down in the snow. No longer
to accept anything at all, no longer to take anything, no longer to absorb
anything—to cease reacting altogether…because one would use oneself up
to quickly if one reacted in any way, one does not react at all any more…
Nothing burns up faster than the affects of ressentiment. Anger, patho-
logical vulnerability, impotent lust for revenge, thirst for revenge, poison-
mixing in any sense—no reaction could be more disadvantageous for the
exhausted: such affects involve a rapid consumption of nervous energy…
Ressentiment is what is forbidden par excellence for the sick—it is their spe-
cific evil—unfortunately also their most natural inclination.13
Out of necessity, the exhausted person ceases to react, accepts her vulner-
ability, and ceases to waste nervous energy. Material necessity thus serves
to slowly break the convalescent away from idealism, i.e., pathological
habitualities fixed by culturally enforced investment of nervous energy.
The convalescent’s placement within a concrete site of crisis allows her
to bear the struggle between the pathology of ressentiment and conva-
lescence. Only the convalescent is given the time and place to confront
and slowly work-through her ressentiment by gradually detaching from it;
only the convalescent has a chance to slowly throw off the weight of his-
tory and begin again.
Zarathustra’s Convalescence
In Ecce Homo, Nietzsche suggests that the entirety of Thus Spoke
Zarathustra is a dithyramb to convalescence; “I need solitude—which is
to say, convalescence, return to myself, the breath of a free, light, play-
ful air … My whole Zarathustra is a dithyramb on solitude…”.14 Recall
that for Freud, the work of mourning works on the multifarious libidinal
50 2 CONVALESCENCE, MOURNING, AND SOCIALITY
the things themselves: “Oh you pranksters and barrel organs!” he says,
“… have you simply made a hurdy-gurdy song of it all? But now I lie
here, still weary … sick from my own redemption … And you simply
watched all this! O my animals, are you, too, cruel?”24 Zarathustra thus
absurdly accuses the animals of taking pleasure in his loss, projecting his
own human ressentiment onto them. In misunderstanding his animals,
Zarathustra thus betrays a disgust for his own animality—which appears
to be petty, superfluous. Zarathustra’s own deafness to his animals tes-
tifies to the convalescent’s struggle with the Judeo-Christian idealism
which labels the animal as base in comparison with the grandness of
human morality and the culture of ressentiment.
But then, Nietzsche explains, Zarathustra’s animals would not let him
go on. They demanded that he stop speaking, leave his cave, and go out
into the world. His own animality then resists the resentful judgment
of itself, by demanding that he recathect with the world by learning to
sing from the songbirds. They tell him: “For your animals know well, O
Zarathustra, who you are and must become: behold, you are the teacher of
the eternal recurrence—that is now your fate! That you must be the first to
teach this teaching—how should this great fate not be your greatest dan-
ger and sickness too?”25 His animals thus remind him that to learn and
teach the eternal recurrence is to suffer it; it is not merely a concept, doc-
trine, imperative, but the suffered loss of one’s socialized attachment to
the herd, which demands a simultaneous reinvestment of love into “things
themselves.” What recurs eternally is the concretely undergone juncture
between convalescence and ressentiment. Zarathustra’s refusal to go out
into the world and the simultaneous disgust with his own animality are
symptomatic of the resentful. Yet, if the animals are a part of Zarathustra
himself—i.e., if the conversation between Zarathustra and his animals is an
allegory of de-idealizing convalescence—then their resistance to his own
resentful demands testifies to the work of convalescence, their voices call-
ing for and provoking the recathexis with the world.
Nietzsche locates the origin of the text within the precarious, concrete
struggle of convalescence. The latter is thus explicitly designated as the
condition of possibility of merrymaking, i.e., the dance, play, and laugh-
ter upon which Derrida—as well as Deleuze—ground their readings,
arises from conditions of possibility which those thinkers occlude from
their accounts of Nietzsche. For the latter, only the borne suffering of
the convalescent could enact the sought-after cultural renewal; without
such convalescence, one hears only the manic laughter of ressentiment.
For Deleuze, Nietzsche’s philosophy diagnoses the symptoms of forces:
“Phenomena, things, organisms, societies, consciousness and spirits
are signs, or rather symptoms, and themselves reflect states of forces.”39
These forces are further divided into types, primarily either reactive or
active. This then allows an account of the ethical, which asks not “what”
and “why,” but rather “who” and “what type” of person or community
is capable of saying or doing this.40 Deleuze explains that this typology of
persons and groups can be thus reduced to a topography of forces, expres-
sive of the will to power. He writes: “Genealogical means differential and
genetic. The will to power is the differential element of forces, that is to
say the element that produces the differences in quantity between two or
more…”.41 In contrast to the Hegelian dialectician—who sees only the
contradictions of thought—the Nietzschean genealogist attends to the sub-
terranean ground of forces which produce thought.
On this reading, metaphysics is the symptom of a nihilism produced
from the victory of reactive forces. Importantly, though, this victory
implies the forgottenness of the very forces which have given rise to the
symptom; the metaphysician is oblivious to the very nihilism which
produces metaphysics. In contrast, Nietzsche offers a “new image of
ABSTRACTION IN POPULAR READINGS … 59
thought” which not only grasps its own essence as the will to power, but
in so doing necessarily transmutates the reactive will to power into activ-
ity. Deleuze calls this transmutation, “affirmation.” He writes: “Nihilism
expresses the quality of the negative as ratio cognoscendi of the will to
power; but it cannot be brought to completion without transmuting
itself into the opposite quality, into affirmation as ratio essendi of that
same will.”42 Thus, according to Deleuze, nihilism completes itself by
inspiring “in man a new inclination: for destroying himself, but destroy-
ing himself actively.”43
Deleuze appeals to the “moment” of transmutation, or affirma-
tion, which ultimately arises from the differential character of the will
to power. However, with our discussion of convalescence continually
in mind, one cannot help but conclude that Deleuze—like Derrida—
occludes the essential element of suffering in Nietzsche in favor of
an appeal to a sort of abstract animism: Although the will to power is
non-atomistic, non-egoistic, pluralistic, and differential, to attribute
the overcoming of nihilism to a “moment” of affirmation is abstraction
nonetheless. One must contrast this with convalescent working-through:
The socio-historically embedded bearing of suffering cannot be fixed to
a “point” or “moment” of transmutation or conversion. The objective,
ambivalent, temporal character of this concrete struggle is essential; To
decathect, rehabituate, and retrain one’s inclinations and sensibilities
away from the weightiness imposed by nihilistic culture can only be con-
ceived as a work. Deleuze’s reading has the merit of showing the radical-
ity of Nietzsche’s genealogical model of thinking, which illuminates the
type and location of thought. Nonetheless, the fact that it interprets the
will to power as an, albeit differential, ontology of forces occludes reflec-
tion on the suffered dimensions of ressentiment and convalescence; this
threatens to reduce amelioration to a spontaneous moment of creation,
rather than as a suffered, gradual, detachment from the cultural norms
implicit in the subject.
Like Derrida, Deleuze explicitly appeals to Heidegger when trying to
clarify what he means by “affirmation.” He writes: “We are awaiting the
forces capable of making thought something active … thinking, like activ-
ity, is always … an extraordinary event in thought itself, for thought itself
… Violence must be done to it as thought, a power, the force of thinking,
must throw it into a becoming-active…”.44 Drawing upon Heidegger’s
appeal for a reticent openness for the event of Being, Deleuze portrays
Nietzschean affirmation as a rupture of historical forgottenness, which
60 2 CONVALESCENCE, MOURNING, AND SOCIALITY
We philosophers are not free to divide body from soul as the people do…
we have to give birth to our thoughts out of our pain…Only great pain,
the long, slow pain that takes its time—on which we are burned, as it were,
with green wood—compels us philosophers to descend into our ultimate
depths and to put aside all … things in which formerly we may have found
our humanity. I doubt that such pain makes us “better”; but I know that
it makes us more profound…out of such long and dangerous exercises of
self-mastery one emerges as a different person, with a few more question
marks—above all with the will henceforth to question further, more deeply,
severely, harshly, evilly and quietly than one had questioned heretofore…47
writes; “Politicized identity thus enunciates itself, makes claims for itself,
only by entrenching, restating, dramatizing, and inscribing its pain in
politics; it can hold out no future—for itself or others—that triumphs
over this pain.”49 Similarly, Berlant criticizes the “national sentimental-
ity” which she sees as the basis of identity politics in the United States.
Berlant writes: “In the sentimental national contract, antagonists mirror
each other in their conviction about the self-evidence and objectivity of
painful feeling, and about the nation’s duty to eradicate it.”50 Thus, poli-
tics becomes a seemingly endless screaming match between those who
seek redemption for the past suffering of their group. For both Brown
and Berlant, the imperative to overcome this culture of ressentiment
lies in the fact that it is an ineffective political strategy for marginalized
groups. As Berlant puts it, “… they so frequently make ethical a refusal
to counter the customary and structural violences of social life, which are
deemed somehow extraneous in the face of pain’s claims.”51
Largely because she reads Nietzsche solely through his notion of
will to power, Brown finds no resources in Nietzsche to help clarify the
overcoming of ressentiment. Instead, she suggests “reopening a desire
for futurity” by using political language in such a way as to deconstruct
identity: “the subject understood as an effect of an (ongoing) geneal-
ogy of desire, including the social processes constitutive of, fulfilling, or
frustrating desire, is in this way revealed as neither sovereign nor con-
clusive even as it is affirmed as a ‘I.’”52 Similarly, Berlant speaks of an
“imperative to place at risk the sense of belonging that national senti-
mentality promises,” and calls for “new vocabularies” and “new maps.”53
Certainly, using language in new ways to disrupt the institutionalization
of ressentiment within the symbolic order is essential, but Nietzsche helps
us understand how subjects who identify with the shared sentimentality
of their marginalized group could come to use language in new ways.
Both Brown and Berlant focus on the pernicious ideology of suffering at
the expense of a detailed analysis of the subject’s experience of the social
and of the way in which that experience is imbricated in the question
as to whether or not, and to what extent, that subject will be able to
bear the loss of its absorption into the group’s sentimentality. The con-
valescent subject slowly, painfully suffers her separation from the group’s
ressentiment and thus needs support in alternative forms of sociality
which could facilitate convalescence. As Nietzsche points out, there are
severe social consequences for rejecting the shared sentimentality of the
group; overcoming ressentiment often involves making those we love
ABSTRACTION IN POPULAR READINGS … 63
Notes
1. Webster’s Third New International Dictionary (Springfield, MA: Merriam-
Webster, 1986), 496.
2. See David Allison’s influential anthology, The New Nietzsche.
3. Jacques Derrida, “Différance,” 396–420.
4. Ibid., 409.
5. Ibid., 411.
6. Ibid., 419.
7. A related approach to Nietzsche is suggested by Robert Pippen, who
explicitly appeals to Freud in his analysis of Nietzsche as a thinker of
modern melancholy. However, Pippin does not consider Nietzsche’s dis-
cussion of convalescence and argues that Nietzsche fails to offer a cred-
ible account of the possibility of overcoming the melancholia he correctly
diagnoses. See Robert B. Pippin, “Nietzsche and the Melancholy of
Modernity,” 495–520.
8. Freud, Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud, 14, 244–245.
9. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality and Ecce Homo, 223.
NOTES 65
10. Ibid., 241.
11. Ibid., 229.
12. My account contrasts with that of Herman Siemens who argues that
Nietzsche can only overcome ressentiment—which continually threatens
to return—by using an “agonal discourse,” which “means what it says,
but also works as a code for the body in action … it becomes a metaphor
of the body in extreme, violent agitation, the transference of an affec-
tive engagement bound by an agonal economy of energy.” See Siemens,
“Nietzsche’s agon with ressentiment: towards a therapeutic reading of
critical transvaluation,” 83. According to Siemens, this agonal “model”
works by self-consciously exposing ressentiment to opposing forces, thus
contesting it. Nietzsche’s potentially resentful diatribe against resent-
ment, for example, is kept in check by opposing itself with other posi-
tions. The agonal relation to opposing forces transforms the force of
ressentiment into active contestation. However, this account, on my read-
ing, does not get at the materiality of Nietzsche’s text, reifying the work
of convalescence into the notion of an agonal “model.” What is missing is
the concrete moment of vulnerability which Nietzsche explicitly traces to
the heart of both ressentiment and convalescence.
13. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality and Ecce Homo, 230.
14. Ibid., 234. I have replaced Kaufmann’s translation of Genesung as “recov-
ery” with “convalescence.”
15. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, translated by Graham Parkes, 67.
16. Ibid., 131.
17. Ibid., 167.
18. Ibid., 194–195.
19. Ibid., 186.
20. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, Translated by Walter Kaufman, 273.
21. Nietzsche, Zarathustra, 189.
22. Ibid., 190.
23. Ibid.
24. Ibid.
25. Ibid., 192.
26. Derrida, “Différance,” 417.
27. Derrida, Spurs, 49.
28. Ibid.
29. Ibid.
30. This appeal to Heidegger is indicative of Derrida’s de-materialization of
Nietzsche. While Derrida acknowledges the positing of a certain unques-
tioned valuation of the proper in Heidegger’s notion of Eigentlichkeit,
for example, he also sees moments in Heidegger which seem to avow the
“abyssal structure” of propriation. The main example given is of Ereignis,
66 2 CONVALESCENCE, MOURNING, AND SOCIALITY
44. Ibid., 108.
45. Ibid., 176.
46. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, 34.
47. Ibid., 36.
48. See Wendy Brown, States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity,
and Lauren Berlant, “The subject of true feeling: Pain, privacy and poli-
tics”.
49. Brown, 74.
50. Berlant, 45.
51. Ibid.
52. Brown, 75.
53. Berlant, 45.
CHAPTER 3
Axel Honneth integrates this later psychoanalytic paradigm into his criti-
cal theory of liberation.2
In a very basic way, this psychoanalytic shift toward relationality can
be used for a reading of Nietzsche’s essay that offers a more coherent
account of the suffered histories at stake in the emergence of slave moral-
ity, the reproduction of bad conscience and its amelioration, and the
proliferation of the ascetic ideal. Like Freud, Nietzsche often uses meta-
physical language, and the proto-psychoanalytic character of the language
in Genealogy and other works is remarkable. For example, in the second
essay, Nietzsche suggests that the imposition of social constraints on our
prehistoric ancestors forced the inversion of their animal instincts which
produced the bad conscience. Given the way this corresponds with aspects
of Freud’s account of repression, neurosis, and the formation of the super-
ego, it is reasonable to infer that Freud was influenced by the essay. That
said, drawing on the relational model of psychoanalysis helps to clarify
the suffered situatedness implied by appeals to such psychical mecha-
nisms. Central to the thesis of this book is the idea that there are aspects
of Nietzsche’s own texts—in explorations of the lived social dimensions of
ressentiment, for example—that prefigure this relational model.
Psychoanalyst Stephen Mitchell describes relational psychoanalysis as a
theory in which humans
the power of the rulers: they say ‘this is so and so’, they set their seal on
everything and every occurrence with a sound and thereby take possession
of it, as it were). (12)
One can read this as an extension of the passages discussed earlier related
to the social history of language and consciousness into the themes of
class and morality (“good” vs. “bad”). The positing of existence and
value through naming extends and legitimates the concrete domination
of the ruling class through symbolic possession of things and existence.
Nietzsche implies that it does this primarily in the positing of moral val-
ues in the concepts of “good” and “bad.” In this essay, what is central
is not the positing of “reality,” of a web of simplifications used to refer
to and reflect on reality (albeit a web formed out of concrete socio-his-
torical contexts), but rather the positing of values which represent and
symbolically legitimate and fortify class distinctions in regard to ways of
living. “Good,” which implies a “should,” is an expression of the differ-
ent suffered social histories of the ruling class and fetishizes what they are
simply by virtue of the power to name. Nietzsche claims that there is ety-
mological evidence to support this view: “… the German word ‘schlecht’
(bad) … is identical with ‘schlicht’ (plain, simple)—compare ‘schlechtweg’
(plainly), ‘schlechterdings’ (simply)—and originally referred to the simple,
the common man with no derogatory implication, but simply in contrast
to the nobility” (13). He further links designations for the “good” with
being rich or propertied, with distinctions in skin and hair color, with
making war, and with being godlike (14–15).
Genealogy points out that the socio-historical source of the values—
the suffered, social history of domination—needs to be deciphered in the
form of the signifiers themselves. In subsequent forms of society, signi-
fiers persist in the structure of sociality and reflection in ways that may
immediately appear to be detached from social history—what is partial,
conditioned, and mediated appears to be impartial, unconditioned, and
immediate. It might initially be noted that this is not an illusion or mis-
perception of the “mind,” but rather a function of the distance in chron-
ological time. The symptomatic character of values is partly produced by
the distance from the situation or scene that they express; their fixated-
ness indicates their persistence despite the distance. On the other hand,
this symptomatic character is further complicated by an additional ele-
ment—the priestly spiritualization of values that finds its most enduring
adherents in traumatized slaves.
RELATIONALITY IN THE FIRST ESSAY OF ON THE GENEALOGY … 75
The priestly class grows and in its suffering at the hands of its rulers finds
a new ally—the mass of slaves.7 This new ally is receptive to a form of
spiritualization provided by the priests, which enables them to see their
own reflection in things, the glory of their own powerlessness, a vehicle
for their own resentment toward the rulers and toward themselves as
embodied, suffering, socio-historical beings.
Notably, he calls this “the slaves’ revolt in morality”—language
which emphasizes the concrete socio-historical conditions of those
whose morality became victorious, which then gave rise to the abstract
designation of “slave morality,” as if it were merely a type, a species
of morality, without a history. Moreover, he suggests that this victory
“needed two millennia to achieve” and therefore is difficult to perceive:
“all long things are difficult to see, to see round” (18). This designa-
tion of slave morality as a type is the expression of a suffered, social his-
tory and not simply expressive of the body, forces, difference, nihilism,
instincts, or some other abstraction. The revolt of slaves in the realm
of morality is a long, excessive history that is not primarily known, but
is rather the long, suffered, complexly social condition of possibility of
knowing. The symptomatic character of values is attributed to the tem-
poral and spatial distance between that abject history and contempo-
rary society, but also to the unbearable nature of that history. The long,
suffered, social, embodied history that constituted the slaves’ revolt in
morality is conceptualized by Nietzsche as the process by which res-
sentiment “turns creative and gives birth to values: the ressentiment of
those beings who, denied the proper response of action, compensate
for it only with imaginary revenge” (20). Ressentiment is not a simple
concept, mood, disposition, or emotion, but rather a signifier for the
most prominent psycho-social symptom of this excessive history. To say
that “it” creates values is to imply the excess of this history, not to posit
a cause in a type of physiology, personality type, or preponderance of
reactive forces, but rather to point toward the situated social position
of our enslaved ancestors, who were “denied the proper response of
action.”
In the diagnosis of what conditions the direction taken between
the slave’s positing of “Evil” and “Good,” and the noble’s positing of
“good” and “bad,” there is a conspicuous imbrication of physiology,
sociality, history, and suffering. Again, this distinction has both a con-
crete social history and a contemporary existence as a suffered struggle
between “types.” Nietzsche writes:
78 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
Whereas all noble morality grows out of triumphant saying ‘yes’ to itself,
slave morality says ‘no’ on principle to everything that is ‘outside’, ‘other’,
‘non-self’: and this ‘no’ is its creative deed…in order to come about, slave
morality first has to have an opposing, external world, it needs, physiologi-
cally speaking, external stimuli in order to act at all…The opposite is the
case with the noble method of valuation: this acts and grows spontane-
ously, seeking out its opposite only so that it can say ‘yes’ to itself even
more thankfully and exultantly… (20).
The figure of the slave implies a history of exposure to the other and
outside which was more or less traumatic—victimized by others,
deprived of motility and peaceful exploration. Such a history produces
symptomatic defenses against the outside and the other, which were pri-
marily experienced as sources of suffering. Slave morality is thereby based
on a socially shared dissociation from the other and the shared assertion
of a magical form of subjectivity.
On the one hand, slave morality emerges from a form of social life in
which slaves are dominated by another class which denies their action.
The slave is denied motility and therefore loses possibilities of explor-
ing, loving, resisting, hating, and negotiating objects (including oth-
ers). In some measure, one might say that for the slave, action is more
or less traumatic, entailing an exposure and vulnerability that circum-
scribes agency or inverts it into a magical form—magic as a symptom of
the internalization, incorporation of the concrete thwarting of the slave
class’s abilities to work-through the world of objects, to mediate their
needs. The material, social conditions give rise to a fixated psychological
form, which then seeks its oppressor, its barrier, and invents it, if it does
not exist. It becomes a floating narrative form founded on irresolvable,
fixated victimhood, reactivity, and vulnerability, but which nonetheless
facilitates the growth of mass societies. In contrast, the noble is mobile,
concretely free to explore and engage with others without trauma. The
noble seeks the other or the unknown to then find her or himself again,
anew. To be clear, this distinction is not unambiguous since Nietzsche
grants that this prehistoric noble was also ruthless and violent and that
the victory of slave morality created the necessary conditions for some-
thing like self-consciousness to emerge.8
Nietzsche writes: “The history of mankind would be far too stupid
a thing if it had not had the intellect [Geist] of the powerless injected
into it … ” (17). It is through the victory of slaves’ values that human
RELATIONALITY IN THE FIRST ESSAY OF ON THE GENEALOGY … 79
The assertion of free will helps to protect the narcissism of those who
cannot bear the other, cannot bear motile negotiation and contending
with objectivity. It acts as a node of power, which turns the tables on the
strong, who are then condemned for lacking the “moral strength” to be
like the herd, the group. It is imagined as a retroactive fantasy, an after-
thought, i.e., as a response, a defense mechanism to cope with power-
lessness, to delude themselves about their own unbearable entanglement
in the intolerable. Americans project fantasies of “the other,” for exam-
ple, to provide cover for an unspeakable history for which they and their
ancestors are partly responsible. If they did not believe in the prevalence
of evil people in Iraq, for example, they would have to face their com-
plicity in the unspeakable deaths, maiming, and displacement of count-
less Iraqis.
The inability to contend with objects, to bear the strangeness and
precarious suffering they bring, gives rise to the magical wish of their
overcoming. As a form of disguise of this wish, which is actually an
expression of futility, it is located in a non-location, outside of space and
time, in a “mind.” This is then made sacred: the foundation of dominant
forms of religion, capitalism, the philosophical subject, and the struc-
tures of morality that govern social relations (including the most con-
servative and the most liberal political positions). The structure of “free
will” is then co-implicit in a bipolar value system which posits Good vs.
Evil. The bipolarity expresses a partial, split sense of objectivity, which
infuses ourselves and the other. We end up on the “good” side, out of a
primitive need to maintain stability, both psychically and in terms of the
environment constituted by others—it provides consistent social bonds
and thereby an environment which protects me from regression to chaos.
The affiliation of ourselves with the slave’s “Good” is an expression of
narcissism, preserved socially both concretely and symbolically, which
protects us from disruption. The concept of free will is a symptom of this
narcissism, a crude remainder of an aborted attempt at object relations,
i.e., of negotiating suffered, social histories.
The concept of free will also implies the possibility of caricaturing the
other which preserves the herd, enabling the social preservation of narcis-
sism. To transcend the respective caricatures of the self or the other would
mean to suffer the loss of the protective herd which is built on this carica-
ture. Nietzsche’s analysis of “free-will” allows us to understand the blam-
ing of social chaos on other groups—Communists, terrorists, etc.—because
that blaming preserves the stability at the basis of slave morality and prevents
RELATIONALITY IN THE SECOND ESSAY … 81
Three dimensions of the second essay that are relevant to the theme of
relationality, are the ambiguous distinction between conscience and bad
conscience, Nietzsche’s linking of love with bad conscience, and the
ambiguous Sect. 7 of the essay. The latter includes a seemingly glaring
ambiguity that arises from the characterization of a claimed contempo-
rary inability to bear suffering in the midst of an argument which accounts
for the origins of modern subjectivity in self-torture. How is it that essen-
tially self-torturing creatures are said to be unable to experience pain? This
ambiguity is clarified if one sees conscience relationally, as a traumatic
symptom, rather than merely as the expression of a natural instinct to
inflict pain. Reading this with Sect. 338 of Gay Science supports the inter-
pretation that the symptom of conscience is socially and materially repro-
duced. Simultaneously, it suggests that the subject’s liberation from bad
conscience can be conceived as a social process of convalescence—bearing
our suffered singularity amidst the social pressure to obliterate it and creat-
ing new social conditions that would facilitate convalescence.
The essay begins with the question: “To breed an animal with the
prerogative to promise—is that not precisely the paradoxical task which
nature has set herself with regard to humankind?” (35) With this ques-
tion, Nietzsche begins his inquiry into the genealogy of conscience, which
is both the locus of promising and that which distinguishes the human
animal from other animals. In the first part of the essay, conscience is
more broadly characterized as constitutive of the human being as such;
however horrible its natural history, it is also what makes us what we are.
Nietzsche suggests that our ancestors were taught to promise within
sadomasochistic social economies, constituted by socially regulated tor-
ture and pain.10 He writes:
82 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
‘How do you give a memory to the animal, man? How do you impress
something upon this partly dull, partly idiotic, inattentive mind, this per-
sonification of forgetfulness, so that it will stick?’…This age-old question
was not resolved with gentle solutions and methods, as can be imagined;
perhaps there is nothing more terrible and strange in man’s prehistory
than his technique of mnemonics. ‘A thing much be burnt in so that it stays
in the memory: only something that continues to hurt stays in the mem-
ory’… (38)
There are at least two important aspects of this passage. First, essential to
living a social, human life is the fact that we owe others and others owe
us; because of our vulnerability and finitude, we always already find our-
selves in the position of both debtor and creditor. At the same time, this
indebtedness is suffered in complex ways as blame, as guilt, as desire for
revenge, as stimulus to overcome oneself and transform society—in other
words, as ressentiment. Human conscience is claimed to be a descendant
of our suffered indebtedness, which created a lasting memory in the con-
text of an all-pervasive prehistoric forgetfulness. By reminding ourselves
of our indebtedness and of the debts owed to us, the possibility of nor-
mative action emerges.
RELATIONALITY IN THE SECOND ESSAY … 83
Second, the claim that the idea that “everything has a price and can
be paid for” is the “most naïve” canon of morality is an insistence on the
negative moment of this social dialectic. There is something about our
suffered sociality that is excessive, that cannot be appropriated by com-
pensatory values, i.e., that defies meaning. This amounts to a critique of
a variety of religiously informed conceptions of history, including posi-
tive versions of Hegelian dialectics in which the cunning of world spirit
would ultimately redeem the abominable violence of human history by
bringing about a future of justice. For Nietzsche, relationality is consti-
tuted by moments of meaningless, irredeemable suffering, which rupture
our ideas. This positing of equivalencies implies a responsible, free-will-
ing subject—dissociated from its relational histories—discussed in the
first essay of the Genealogy. As discussed earlier, this is not merely the
result of a metaphysical belief, but rather is the symptom of suffered soci-
ality. The lambs invent the idea of free will to defend themselves against
the unbearable negativity of experience.
One of the main debates on the second essay of the Genealogy has to
do with the meaning of the difference between conscience and bad con-
science.11 If conscience as such is produced by the monstrous history of
the often violent imposition of the “social straightjacket” upon human
beings, then how are we to understand the socio-historical production
of bad conscience? On our reading, for Nietzsche, bad conscience oper-
ates like a symptom of trauma. In contrast, mere conscience—the ability
to promise—can to some extent be understood as a pragmatic adapta-
tion to naturalistically conceived events. Overall, this history might be
called “more or less traumatic.” Our suffered histories may not give rise
to bad conscience and do so when culture reproduces traumatic oblit-
eration of pragmatic subjectivity. For Freud, trauma designates the
rupture of experience that overwhelms us, exceeding our abilities to
practically respond; it is the constitutive excess of being outside of our-
selves, immersed in externality, and one of the vicissitudes of an external-
ity which is inevitably internalized.12 From this perspective, the human
being guided by a bad conscience could be seen as symptomatic, such
that his or her genealogy would, at a minimum, need to reflectively
uncover a history traumatic enough to produce such an absurd symp-
tom. However, to be clear, this traumatic element is of a different order
than reflection; it exceeds reflection and thereby needs to be negoti-
ated—only within such a negotiation can reflection do its work.
84 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
We have here a sort of madness of the will showing itself in mental cruelty
which is absolutely unparalleled: man’s will to find himself guilty and con-
demned without hope of reprieve…his will to infect and poison the fun-
damentals of things with the problem of punishment and guilt in order
to cut himself off, once and for all, from the way out of this labyrinth of
‘fixed ideas’…What ideas he has, what perversity, what hysterical nonsense,
what bestiality of thought immediately erupts, the moment he is prevented,
if only gently, from being a beast in deed!…Here is sickness, without a
doubt, the most terrible sickness ever to rage in man:–and whoever is still
able to hear (but people have no ear for it nowadays!–) how the shout of
love has rung out during the night of torture and absurdity, the shout of
92 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
the most yearning rapture, of salvation through love, turns away, gripped
by an unconquerable horror…There is so much in man that is horrify-
ing!…The world has been a madhouse for too long!… (64)
with the power to redeem from an intolerable social life. Guided by the
logic of equivalencies imposed by the “social straightjacket,” unsatisfied
with the available cultural rituals and the history of failure of human civi-
lization for resolving these debts, only the intervention of a magical god
could provide justice. The dialectic of credit and debt is reified into an
eternal indebtedness that can only be redeemed theologically, through a
revelatory event of forgiveness, a maniacal release from eternal guilt.
On the one hand, there are cultural rituals that establish codes of repay-
ment. On the other hand, there are cultural rituals that posit the constitu-
tive inability to repay the pain inflicted and suffered and hence the need
for a god to guarantee the logic of equivalence and redemption. Although
Nietzsche recognizes the latter as being the most pernicious cultural form,
there is no mere turning back to a pre-Judeo-Christian world without it.
Rather, the suggested salutary direction lies in a new, convalescent form of
exchange and culture governed by the non-equivalent, the non-identical.
One might also think of Nietzsche’s comments on the ability to “digest”
experiences, as expressions of this convalescence within which one comes
to have a good conscience about the excessive, suffered nature of suffered
life and is more able to work-through suffering inflicted by and on others.
In such a culture, suffering would not merely be an occasion for blame
and shame, but rather for the shared work of preempting the traumatic
and the facilitation of singular convalescences.
Nietzsche’s convalescent overcoming of this pathology would involve
breaking from these fixated sorts of attachments that obligate me to others
and others to me. This would mean neither a total break from all debts,
nor an unpayable infinite debt, but rather an ability to engage (to give and
get from others) and disengage (an ability to break, to transgress the limit
of that form of giving and getting), so that one might engage again in new
ways, with new forms of giving and new needs and desires. Such engaging
and disengaging need not take the form of a rejection of particular loved
ones, cultures, institutions (and a glorification of solitude or some sort of
idealized future), but rather the transformation of those relationships, cul-
tures, and institutions.
As an example of the humiliation at the heart of the imbrication
between the positing of responsible free-willing subject and this system of
equivalencies, one might consider Nietzsche’s remark in The Gay Science,
commenting on the dying Socrates. Nietzsche writes:
LOVE AND THE SOCIALITY OF UNPAYABLE DEBT 95
when suffering is always the first of the arguments marshalled against life,
as its most questionable feature, it is salutary to remember the times when
people made the opposite assessment, because they could not do without
making people suffer and saw first-rate magic in it, a veritable seductive
lure to life. Perhaps pain—I say this to comfort the squeamish—did not
hurt as much then as it does now… (43)
if you refuse to let your own suffering lie upon you even for an hour and
if you constantly try to prevent and forestall all possible distress way ahead
of time; if you experience suffering and displeasure as evil, hateful, worthy
of annihilation, and as a defect of existence, then it is clear that besides
your religion of pity you also harbor another religion in your heart that is
perhaps the mother of the religion of pity: the religion of comfortableness
[Behaglichkeit]…All such arousing of pity and calling for help is secretly
seductive, for our ‘own way’ is too hard and demanding and too remote
from the love and gratitude of others, and we do not really mind escaping
from it—and from our very own conscience—to flee into the conscience of
others and into the lovely temple of the ‘religion of pity’.35
Notes
1. See, for example, Stephen A. Mitchell. Relational Concepts in
Psychoanalysis: An Integration, and other works.
2. See Axel Honneth, The Struggle for Recognition. Also see J. Jackson,
Philosophy and Working-Through the Past, 73–99.
3. Mitchell, 3.
4. Sigmund Freud, Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Sigmund Freud, Volume 16, 257–285.
5. Ibid., 275.
6. See, for example, Freud’s Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego, The
Future of an Illusion, Civilization and Its Discontents, etc.
102 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
7. Nietzsche writes: “… the priestly caste and warrior caste confront one
another in jealousy and cannot agree on the prize of war … woe betide
it [the priestly-aristocratic method of valuation] when it comes to war!”
(Nietzsche 1997, 17).
8. Nietzsche writes: “We may be quite justified in retaining our fear of the
blond beast as the centre of every noble race and remain on our guard:
but who would not, a hundred times over, prefer to fear if he can admire
at the same time, rather than not fear, but thereby permanently retain the
disgusting spectacle of the failed, the stunted, the wasted away, and the
poisoned?” (Nietzsche 1997, 24).
9. He writes: “When ressentiment does occur in the noble man himself, it
is consumed and exhausted in an immediate reaction, and therefore it
does not poison … To be unable to take his enemies, his misfortunes and
even his misdeeds seriously for long—that is the sign of strong, rounded
natures with a superabundance of a power which is flexible, formative,
healing and can make one forget … A man like this shakes from him,
which one shrug, many worms which would have burrowed into another
man; actual ‘love of your enemies’ is also possible here and here alone—
assuming it is possible at all on earth. How much respect a noble man has
for his enemies! … he will tolerate as enemies none other than such as
have nothing to be despised and a great deal to be honoured! … imagine
‘the enemy’ as conceived by the man of ressentiment … as a basic idea to
which he now thinks up a copy and counterpart, the ‘good one’—him-
self! … ” (Nietzsche 1997, 22).
10. See Aaron Ridley’s insightful interpretation in which Nietzsche’s initial
sketching of the “internalization” of humans through the “social straight-
jacket” is “the neutral, ubiquitous form of conscience” required if man is
to live as a social animal; it provides the “calculability, regularity” that are
“fostered by the repression of his natural impulses” (18). Thus, accord-
ing to Ridley, at this basic level, conscience entails “the capacity for self-
reflection and the potential for self-transformation”(19). Ridley notes
however that Nietzsche’s discussion is ambiguous in so far as there are
moments where he calls this neutral, basic form of conscience “bad” and
suggests that it arises among the slaves, rather than the nobles—pure
artists who supposedly shape society without conscience. Ridley points
to other passages where Nietzsche makes clear that this basic form of
repression is the condition of possibility of all culture and beauty. Thus,
Ridley writes: “The pregnancy, the repression, which the ‘bad’ conscience
is in its beginnings, can go either way: it can become the bad bad con-
science of slavish ressentiment; or it can become the good bad conscience
of that affirmative, joyous, form-giving activity which Nietzsche, when
he’s straight with himself, calls nobility and mastery” (22). See Aaron
NOTES 103
Ridley, “Guilt Before God, or God Before Guilt? The Second Essay of
Nietzsche’s Genealogy”.
11. See, for example, the debate between Aaron Ridley and Mathias Risse
carried out in the following articles: Aaron Ridley, “Guilt Before God,
or God Before Guilt? The Second Essay of Nietzsche’s Genealogy,” and
Mathias Risse, “The Second Treatise in On the Genealogy of Morality:
Nietzsche on the Origin of Bad Conscience.”
12. To be clear, trauma, on Freud’s account, is notoriously indeterminate—
that which traumatizes me, does not necessarily traumatize you, and if
we are both traumatized, there is no simple causal trail that leads to a
particular symptom. There is a constitutive complexity to traumatic rup-
turing of experience and the way in which that rupturing manifests itself
in forms of dissociative defense. Nonetheless, there are shared traumatic
ordeals that are experienced collectively, and there are cultural processes
of giving meaning to these ordeals—in religion, for example.
13. See Hans Loewald, Papers on Psychoanalysis.
14. Loewald, 235.
15. See Daniel Conway, Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals: A Reader’s
Guide.
16. See Ridley, 22. He writes: “The inability to harness or discharge repressed
instinct leads to frustration and rancor—to the state Nietzsche calls res-
sentiment. And it is ressentiment that eventually gives birth to slave
morality, to the values of the bad bad conscience.” Although this is con-
sistent with the letter of Nietzsche’s own apparently causal explanation, it
abstracts from the suffered, social origins of ressentiment; on our reading
what is fundamental is not some sort of developed theory of the repres-
sion of instincts but the imbrication of suffered, embodied sociality that
conditions this “inability.”
17. Ibid.
18. Lawrence Hatab writes: “Nietzsche wants to explore new possibilities of
life-affirming values by drawing from historical sources that were deemed
‘immoral’ by traditional moral systems, but that can be redeemed as mor-
ally defensible life-values.” See Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality,
2.
19. See Christopher Janaway, Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche’s
Genealogy.
20. David Owen, Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morality, 144.
21. Ibid.
22. Michel Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 95.
23. Ibid., 78–79.
24. Ibid., 76–79.
25. Ibid., 80.
104 3 RELATIONALITY, TRAUMA, AND THE GENEALOGY OF THE SUBJECT
26. Ibid., 87.
27. In a manner similar to Deleuze’s appeal to affirmation as the ratio
essendi of the will to power, Foucault suggests that for Nietzsche, gene-
alogy implies the “unavoidable” sacrifice of the subject of knowledge.
However, despite this appeal to the destruction of the subject of knowl-
edge, Foucault’s analysis—like that of Deleuze and Derrida—makes fre-
quent use of subjective terminology. The question arises as to whether
Foucault is not begging the question as to how the historian of origins
becomes a genealogist and vice versa. In other words, how are the crude-
ness and tastelessness implicit in the historical search for origins overcome
and transformed into subversive genealogy? To these questions, Foucault
suggests two serious answers which both ignore the centrality of conva-
lescence in Nietzsche’s thinking. First, he suggests that because geneal-
ogy reveals history to be “the endlessly repeated play of dominations,” it
sets the stage for an active intervention into history. This abstract notion
of history as merely a play of power occludes convalescence. Domination
may be oppressive, and totalizing, but the fact that is can be suffered,
means that something exceeds it. Without this excess, we would not suf-
fer it, and therefore, we would not critique it. If all is domination and
the ceaseless parade of different regimes, then there would not be any
motivation for genealogy, i.e., rules must somehow be suffered if their
overthrow is desired; for Nietzsche, convalescence is the condition for the
possibility of overthrowing oppressive rules—thus, Zarathustra the con-
valescent longs for the flourishing of convalescence on the earth. Second,
Foucault attributes our inability to usurp power to the beliefs of our
fathers, giving voice to the provocative way in which Nietzsche character-
izes the weight of history inscribed within bodies. But, why then does
he designate as the cause of such suffering the “errors,” “mistakes,” or
“beliefs” of fathers? In so doing, he reduces the cause of suffered, domi-
nated bodies to thoughts. In the appeal to faulty thinking, Foucault fails
to account for the possibility of the healing of such bodies which suffer
the weight of history; on our reading, convalescence would be the condi-
tion of possibility of the ability to do genealogy as Foucault describes it.
In lieu of an account of convalescence, Foucault can only appeal to an
animism implicit in subjective traits or a type of thinking which somehow
would not succumb to the beliefs of the past.
28. Here, Conway appeals to the ascetic ideal, discussed in the third essay of
the Genealogy: “No longer content to hold himself responsible for the
finite debts he had (supposedly) incurred, the caged animal now wished
to hold himself responsible for debts that he would never repay. Having
persuaded himself of ‘his own absolute unworthiness,’ he gleefully
directed cruelty against himself, while also accepting it, penitently, as his
NOTES 105
of a dialectic between such values and the suffered, social life of which
they are symptomatic. Following Adorno, one might see Nietzsche’s
fragmentary style and critique of systems as expressions of a negative
dialectic.
A Nietzschean negative dialectics would not be an idealist, positive
dialectics in which the concept inevitably subsumes the negative, but
rather a dialectic in the sense that reflection is always accompanied by
moments of reflection’s own suffered rupture. This implies a form of
what Adorno calls the primacy of the object. The distinction between
subject and object does not mean “me” as opposed to the “object”; I am
both subject and object, and I suffer my objectivity. Thinking is condi-
tioned by suffered embodiedness, and without suffering, I would not be
in a world to form an idea of.
In philosophy “objectivity” is often taken epistemologically as a sub-
jective moment, and dominant critiques of identity tend to conceive of
the non-identical merely subjectively—as for example, plurality, uncon-
cealment, or difference. In Adorno’s view, such subjectivizing of the
non-identical would imply an inability to bear the object and the suffered
social histories which condition subjectivity. Some continental interpreta-
tions of Adorno’s philosophy mistakenly place him in this camp which
valorizes subjective negativity, but Adorno’s insistence on the negativ-
ity of the object implies that coherent reflection would avow that which
guides, situates, ruptures reflection within its suffered social histories.
Following Adorno, one might say that our relationship with objects is
not simply a perspectival situatedness, but rather a socially conditioned,
suffered vulnerability. We (as objects) need external objects, but are vul-
nerable to them—negotiating and defending ourselves against them, and
need is the manifestation of our own objectivity. That which transcends
the horizon of perspectival and reflective immediacy is not just darkness;
it marks a negativity which I cannot control, to which I am vulnerable,
yet which belongs inherently to my need and that which I need.
For some strains of philosophy, the idea that the concept can never be
adequate to reality points to the need for an interminable gesture on the
part of conceptualization to acknowledge its inadequacy. However, from
our perspective, the inadequacy of the concept is more fundamentally an
expression of its symptomaticity. The concept is not simply opposed to
a reality in relation to which it is inadequate, but it is a symptom of suf-
fered reality. Negative dialectics would be the form of thinking in which
the concept bears its own suffered social histories, in which the concept
4 NIETZSCHE’S NEGATIVE DIALECTIC: ASCETIC IDEAL … 109
The problem with this critique is that Heidegger never reduces thinking
to such simple gesturing. Behind the self-evidence with which we use the
word ‘Being’ in predication stands an enigma that can only be approached
through an interrogation of the entity for which Being is an issue, namely
Dasein in its everydayness. The ‘forgotten’ question of the meaning of
Being requires an anamnesis of the ordinary and the everyday.3
The mediation of essence and appearance, of concept and thing, does not
remain what it was either, the moment of subjectivity in the object. What
mediates the facts is not so much the subjective mechanism which pre-
forms and renders them, as the objectivity, heteronomous to the subject…
it would give the object what is its own, instead of being satisfied with the
false copy, only where it resisted the average value of such objectivity and
made itself free as a subject…the overwhelming power of what is objec-
tivated in subjects, which then prevents them from becoming subjects,
equally prevents the cognition of what is objective… (Adorno 1966, 170)
Since intellectual labor was separated from the manual kind in the sign of
the domination of Spirit, of the justification of privilege, the divided Spirit
was obliged, with the exaggeration due to a bad conscience, to vindicate
precisely that domination-claim, which it derived from the thesis that it
would be the first and originary, and that is why it takes pains to forget
from which its claim comes, if it is not to crumble. Deep down the Spirit
suspects that its stable rule is not at all that of the Spirit, but possesses
its ultima ratio in the physical violence at its disposal. It may not utter its
secret, at the price of its own downfall. (Adorno 1966, 177)
This quote could apply to Marx or Nietzsche. For the former, the
non-identical as the division of labor produces the subject guided by
the principle of identity to maintain and stabilize the system of power.
Identity thinking, or the domination of Spirit, is the expression of this
inability to bear the history of violence. For the latter, the domination
of Spirit would be reflected in the victory of the ascetic priest and ideal,
which reproduce a perverse need for the identical (and equivalencies)
as an expression of the inability to bear and negotiate the suffering for
which the priest offers consolation. Nietzsche thereby identifies the per-
verse sadomasochism which pervades dominant forms of spirituality and
morality.
This is not merely the assertion of a metaphysical view, or a positiv-
istically conceived history of human beings, rather it is positioned as an
114 4 NIETZSCHE’S NEGATIVE DIALECTIC: ASCETIC IDEAL …
It is easy for the polarity of subject and object to appear for its part as
an undialectical structure, in which all dialectics is supposed to take place.
But both concepts are originated (derived) categories of reflection (ent-
sprungene Reflexions-kategorien), formulations for something which is not
to be unified; not anything positive, nor any primary matter-at-hand, but
negative throughout, the expression solely of non-identity. In spite of this
the difference between subject and object is for its part not to be simply
negated. They are neither the ultimate duality, nor does the ultimate unity
hide behind them. (Adorno 1966, 174)
Adorno claims that the distinction between subject and object originated
in non-identity, i.e., it does not have a metaphysical origin that could be
identified. One can compare this to Nietzsche’s tracing of the geneal-
ogy of the subject back to suffered, social histories. In contrast to the
usual use of these terms to articulate the presupposed subject’s epistemol-
ogy, Adorno’s usage suggests an understanding of “objectivity” as our
suffered materiality, from which subjectivity inclusive of its epistemology
emerges. From this perspective, “objectivity” is not merely a cognitive
index but a suffered index, in so far as it expresses our ability to negotiate
our suffered social situatedness.
This parallels the reading of Nietzsche developed above insofar as
subjectivity is the expression of the non-identical as suffered, social
history. The dominant form of subjectivity and its supposed founda-
tion in free will and access to truth is not merely a metaphysical illusion
that can be overcome, but rather is symptomatic of the abjectness of
human sociality. There are many passages that suggest that Nietzsche
does not propose a rejection of this distinction between subject and
object—a distinction that is materially reproduced—and therefore can-
not be overcome with a philosophy. This is evident in the position of the
convalescent whose concepts fail within a suffered confrontation with
the non-identical. Beyond appeal to Nietzsche’s most-often repeated
concepts—Will to Power, Dionysus, Eternal Return, etc.—this work
of convalescence is expressed in his fragmentary, aphoristic grappling
with finite, limited, varied memories, feelings, thoughts. In “On Truth
and Lie in an Extramoral Sense,” Nietzsche says that “ … between
116 4 NIETZSCHE’S NEGATIVE DIALECTIC: ASCETIC IDEAL …
two absolutely different spheres, such as subject and object are, there
is no causality, no correctness, no expression, but at most an aesthetic
way of relating, by which I mean an allusive transference, a stammer-
ing translation into quite a different language.”11 Elsewhere, he sug-
gests that Schopenhauer’s philosophy demotes “physicality to the status
of illusion … similarly pain, plurality, the whole conceptual antith-
esis ‘subject’ and ‘object’—errors, nothing but errors! To renounce
faith in one’s own ego (Ich), to deny one’s own ‘reality’ to oneself—
what a triumph!—and not just over the senses, over appearance, a
much higher kind of triumph, an act of violation and cruelty inflicted
on reason … ascetic self-contempt decrees the self-ridicule of reason:
‘there is a realm of truth and being, but reason is firmly excluded from
it!’” (Nietzsche 1997, 86). This would suggest a reading whereby
Nietzsche’ critique of the subject—and the dominant epistemological
and moral frames within which that subject are understood—does not
reject the distinction between subject and object as does Schopenhauer.
Rather, Nietzsche could be read as maintaining the necessity of the
subjective moment, albeit as complexly mediated by the object.
On the one hand, it would be a mistake to read Nietzsche as
claiming that the distinction between subject and object is a contin-
gent social construction that can be cast away within an upsurge of
Dionysian affirmation—as if there were a magical mode of existence
which takes us outside of our concepts and the repressive world of the
cognitive subject. On the other hand, it is not simply that any given
conceptual structure is historically constituted, such that we are either
condemned to think within a particular frame or find ways to “think
outside the box.” This would imply that we could create new concepts
and think in other ways that allow us to escape a supposedly perni-
cious distinction between subject and object—e.g., in terms of forces,
intensities, temporalities, or difference. Both of these views presuppose
some sort of internal or external animating force which either “affirms”
or “thinks” differently. On our reading, his view of this distinction
between subject and object has a greater socio-historical complexity.
In Genealogy, as we have seen, the subject—and hence the distinction
between subject and object—is a symptom of a concrete socio-histori-
cal scenes.
Coherent reflection (reflection as taking account of the conditions
of possibility of reflection) is a reflection on the objective mediation
of that reflection. To repress this, and posit a realm of unmediated
READING NIETZSCHE IN LIGHT OF ADORNO’S PHILOSOPHICAL POSITION 117
Adorno writes:
…We know all too well how offensive it sounds when someone classi-
fies human beings as animals, without disguises and allegory; and we are
considered almost sinful for constantly using expressions like ‘herd,’ and
‘herd instinct’ with direct reference to people of ‘modern ideas’…People
in Europe clearly know what Socrates claimed not to know, and what that
famous old snake once promised to teach,–people these days ‘know’ what
is good and evil. Now it must sound harsh and strike the ear quite badly
when we keep insisting on the following point: what it is that claims to
know here, what glorifies itself with its praise and reproach and calls itself
good is the instinct of the herd animal man, which has come to fore, gain-
ing and continuing to gain predominance and supremacy over the other
instincts, in accordance with the growing physiological approach and
approximation whose symptom it is…it stubbornly and ruthlessly declares:
‘I am morality itself and nothing else is moral!’13
of the past which mass culture (understood through the culture industry
as well as the fascist tendencies of modern democracies) militates against.
To reflect on constellations would be to bear the non-identical, to devi-
ate from the fetishization of identity thinking and the fetishized system
of equivalences, which works as a culturally shared defense mechanism
against the non-identical.
The imbrication of embodied, suffered, sociality and history discussed
in the Introduction might be read as the expression of the primacy of
constellations—positions, situatedness, and scenes in which objects relate
to each other and from which subjectivity emerges. The constellation
might also be conceived as a suffered scene, not something that has been
forgotten—but rather something that is more or less unbearably abject.
Adorno writes: “… there is indeed a fallible, yet immediate experience
of the essential and inessential, which the scientific need for order can
talk the subjects out of only with violence. Where such an experience
does not occur, cognition remains immobile and fruitless. Its measure
is, what the subjects experience objectively as their suffering” (Adorno
1966, 169). The suffering of the object in its imbricated relationships
with others is not merely to be morally condemned, but is constitutive of
the socio-historically mediated subject. Suffering expresses the implicit-
ness of non-identical within the identical; the primacy of suffered social
histories gives rise to the concept, the positing of identity as a desire for
adequacy that always fails. Suffered excess motivates subjective conceptu-
alizations, which are constitutively haunted by the suffered histories that
motivate and rupture them; ideology as implied within identity think-
ing and the constitutive consciousness rests on the ability or inability to
work-through that suffering. Identity thinking arises from constellations
of object relations, marked by suffering. In this case, fear and inability
to bear and negotiate the other reproduce xenophobia.18 This can be
read with Nietzsche’s identification of xenophobia at the heart of slaves’
morality, which reproduces an inability to negotiate the other in myriad
forms of the ascetic ideal.
In effect, Adorno provides another frame from which to reflect on the
sociality of metaphysics and in so doing an alternative path to approach
Nietzsche’s critique of metaphysics. Standard readings of Nietzsche
often seem to posit a false choice: Either one believes in the illusion of
metaphysical stasis, or one explodes this illusion with a revelation of
eternal dynamism. But, to recruit Nietzsche for such a view would do
violence to his varied tracing of the suffered sociality which guides the
124 4 NIETZSCHE’S NEGATIVE DIALECTIC: ASCETIC IDEAL …
need for metaphysics. The popular claim that Nietzsche’s thinking can
be reduced to an exhortation to dance, play, and the exuberant or heroic
transgression of metaphysics may express more about problems with con-
temporary philosophy than it does about Nietzsche. As Adorno says of
idealism, such philosophy often converts real suffering into a philosophi-
cal critique of metaphysics—in so doing, they serve the cause of repro-
ducing the crisis they long to ameliorate, by expressing an inability to
bear their own histories. One might say that Nietzsche contributes to the
outlining of a coherent, negatively dialectical form of reflection—reflec-
tion which traces its own suffered conditions of possibility, which leave
their mark in the symptomatic character of thinking itself.
Adorno might be read as implicitly addressing a common interpreta-
tion of Nietzsche as positing a metaphysical dynamism—in the Will to
Power or Dionysus, for example. Adorno writes:
The woe lies in the relationships which damn human beings to power-
lessness and apathy and yet would have to be changed by them; not pri-
marily in human beings and the manner in which relationships appear to
them…Those who regard the thingly as what is radically evil; who would
like to dynamize everything, which is, into pure contemporaneity, tend to
be hostile towards the other, the alien, whose name does not resound in
alienation for nothing; to that non-identity, which would need to be eman-
cipated not solely in consciousness but in a reconciled humanity. Absolute
dynamics however would be that absolute handling of the facts, which
violently satisfies itself and misuses the non-identical as its mere occasion.
(Adorno 1966, 189)
along with the situated aphorisms of the published texts, such that the
ebb and flow of forces can be read as a representation of the subject’s
negotiation of its own socially mediated objectivity.
In many cases, one might read Nietzsche’s fragments as sketches of
constellations within which subjectivity is shaped. In thinking in constel-
lations, reflection grounded in the object’s primacy activates subjectivity,
which becomes coherent by tracing its own history. Fragmentary writing
would be an expression of the bit-by-bit process of working through that
which mediates the immediate, wherever one finds oneself thinking and
valuing. This would be a tracing of the way in which suffered history
conditions and ruptures the subjective.
As a point of contrast, one might consider Michel Haar’s characteri-
zation of Nietzschean genealogy as “… an art of deciphering symptoms
ad infinitum … the fragmented, aphoristic, and bursting character of the
text corresponds to Nietzsche’s own grasp of the world: a world scat-
tered in pieces, covered with explosions … a world freed from the ties
of gravity (i.e. from a relationship with a foundation); a world made of
moving and light surfaces where the incessant shifting of masks in named
laughter, dance, game.”19 In contrast, our Adornian reading the frag-
mented, aphoristic, and bursting character of the text corresponds with
the suffered ordeal of negotiating or working-through slave morality, as
the legacy of an ongoing suffered, embodied social history. If geneal-
ogy and Nietzsche’s thinking in general are the reflective grappling with
reflection’s own limit, it must take up this limit wherever it is encoun-
tered, in the working through of its own symptoms, its own ressentiment.
Although this takes place on the edges of identity wherever it is found,
concepts are not merely ideal objects that signify and reproduce a stable,
grounded, ethical world, which critiques can then “explode.” Although
Haar acknowledges that concepts are also guarantors of gregariousness,
his account occludes the suffered social context of the critique Nietzsche
supposedly valorizes. A world scattered in pieces must be borne.
Concepts are not symptomatic of abstractly conceived impulses or
forces, but of socio-historically conditioned need. To explode a cherished
concept would be to endure loss of love; to problematize the identity
upon which a concept is based entails an ordeal of disrupting the soci-
ality grounded in the shared concepts. This would not take place all at
once—as if the world would be free from the ties of gravity—and would
only be a moment in a more complexly suffered ordeal.
126 4 NIETZSCHE’S NEGATIVE DIALECTIC: ASCETIC IDEAL …
above all to burst open some traditionally accepted identity (e.g. Will,
Ego, Man)…the dominant words of Nietzsche’s discourse (especially Will
to Power and Eternal Return) are meant to subvert, fracture, and dismiss
concepts...his overall effort is one aiming to set the entire logical, seman-
tic and grammatical apparatus (in which the philosophical tradition has
naively taken up its abode) to move in a direction contrary to its constant
tendency: namely, the assignment of proper nouns, the reduction to iden-
tity and the passage to the universal. In other words, the specific nature
of Nietzsche’s discourse might well be defined in the first instance as an
attempt to encourage disbelief in the laws of logic, and the rules of gram-
mar (the final refuge of a defunct theology…20
We know what the three great catchwords of the ascetic ideal are: pov-
erty, humility, chastity: let us now look at the life of all great, productive,
inventive spirits close up, for once, –all three will be found in them, to a
certain degree, every time. Of course, it goes without saying that they will
definitely not be ‘virtues’—this type of person cannot be bothered with vir-
tues!—but as the most proper and natural prerequisites for their best exist-
ence and finest productivity… (Nietzsche 1997, 78)
problem is the form of this entanglement and the form of the ascetic
ideal—fixated or transitional.23
In The Gay Science, Nietzsche writes: “What is the seal of having
become free?—No longer to be ashamed before oneself.”24 This must
be read through Nietzsche’s socio-historical perspective; shame is not a
characteristic or feeling of an “individual,” but rather a social formation.
Nietzsche’s genealogies are the working-through of shame, as the con-
dition of possibility of singularity. Insofar as I am ashamed of myself, I
am kept in thrall by the status quo through affective bonds with others.
Convalescence is the working-through of these bonds, which puts the
need for those bonds into question, and integrates more of the suffered
socio-historical scene into that need, or more of the need into the scene.
To no longer be ashamed of oneself implies that one’s values would
be understood in their socio-cultural context, not merely in their natural
context. It would imply the overcoming of the socially reproduced fixa-
tion of values and that valuing is accompanied by a second moment of
failure implied by suffering. On this reading, one would not see shame-
lessness as an achievable, celebratory, transgressive final state, but rather
as a moment. Liberation would thereby be a moment that takes place
in a larger struggle with unfreedom; it occurs in the process of bearing
the fact that my subjectivity is symptomatic and hence out of my con-
trol, in other words, not in a moment of immediacy or empowerment
of the self, but within mediation. One becomes more whole when one
integrates one’s radical vulnerability and unfreedom with one’s values—
this is not liberation from all ressentiment, but only momentary freedom
from a particular instantiation of ressentiment. It would be wrong to sug-
gest that for Nietzsche “animality,” “embodiment” and “difference”
are things we can simply celebrate, as if these are simply facts that I can
or cannot affirm or deny. They are rather signs for excessive objectiv-
ity, and any process of coming to appreciate them, of integrating them
into ourselves, must be conceived as a more or less unbearable ordeal
of living from moment to moment. On this reading, if Nietzsche some-
times seems to advocate some sort of absolute transgression, it is only in
fragments or moments that only have meaning in connection with other
fragments or moments.
This genealogy of the philosopher is in effect Nietzsche’s version of
reflection’s accounting of itself. As discussed above, this is similar to
Marx’s claim that, like philosophy, materialist criticism is also only pos-
sible because of the division of labor. Philosophical idealism posits an
RELATIONALITY, ASCETIC IDEAL, AND STATUS QUO 131
origin of truth that is unmediated by the negative, unable to bear its own
history and conditions of possibility, and therefore allies itself with forces
that enable it to preserve itself and enable it to accept itself and feel as if
it is worthy of respect. In other words, it allies itself with the status quo
as a mode of defense in the form of the ascetic priest. Genealogical think-
ing—which is also only possible through the same separation of labor
and ascetic ideal—is historically associated with the priest and its symbol-
ically acceptable guise. To survive, philosophers needed to feel as if they
were worthy of fear and respect and needed to make others fear them; so
they created an ascetic meaning, with an unprecedented sublimity of cru-
elty toward themselves. Nietzsche writes:
…the philosophic spirit always had to disguise and cocoon itself among
previously established types of contemplative man, as a priest, magician,
soothsayer, religious man in general, in order for its existence to be possi-
ble at all: the ascetic ideal served the philosopher for a long time as out-
ward appearance…he had to play that part…had to believe in it in order
to be able to play it…The particularly withdrawn attitude of the philoso-
phers, denying the world, hating life, doubting the senses, desensualized…
is primarily the result of the desperate conditions under which philosophy
evolved and exists at all…the ascetic priest has until the most recent times
displayed the vile and dismal form of a caterpillar, which was the only one
philosophers were allowed to adopt and creep around in…Have things
really changed? Has the brightly coloured, dangerous winged-insect…
thrown off the monk’s habit and emerged into the light, thanks to a sun-
nier, warmer and more enlightened world? (Nietzsche 1997, 84)
feelings. The phrase, “man still prefers to will nothingness, than not will
… ” might simply refer to the magic of subjective omnipotence seem-
ingly dissociated from its objectivity. Nietzsche is not suggesting we dis-
solve ourselves into a meaningless, will-less sea of cause and effect, into a
cold obliteration of matter as if we are merely objects. Rather, in a man-
ner similar to Adorno, he wants to save the magic, integrating it with
our objectivity. Convalescence would be the work of this integration of
subjectivity into suffered social history. This would be a socio-historically,
psycho-somatically conditioned suffering of reflection on the suffered,
social histories of reflection and on the psychosomatic unconscious con-
stitution of our subjectivities. This will to nothingness must be worked
out of—a symptom reproduced by dominant culture from which we
must convalesce.
One might reread the quote mentioned in the Introduction, through
the lens of this analysis of the ascetic ideal:
Notes
1. A broader historical analysis of the relationship between Adorno and
Nietzsche can be found in Bauer, Adorno’s Nietzschean Narratives:
Critiques of Ideology, Readings of Wagner.
2. See, for example, Adorno’s texts, “The Meaning of Working-Through
the Past”, “Freudian Theory and Fascist Propaganda”, or Dialectic of
Enlightenment.
3. Espen Hammer, Adorno and the Political, 110.
4. For Adorno, the Heideggerian “mythology of language” is “an apothe-
osis of the objective Spirit, which from the very beginning ostracized the
reflection on the material process” (Adorno 1966, 180–181).
5. One might argue that Heidegger’s notion of unconcealment, for example,
contains a measure of respect for objectivity in that it reflects the way in
which objectivity shapes presence; objects come and go, hide, and appear
in their partiality, emerge and fade, they are not given as static wholes.
Nonetheless, the revelation of unconcealment does not indicate a coher-
ent reflection on the way in which objectivity—and its negativity—con-
ditions the possibility of that revelation. Unconcealment, as a subjective
manifestation of objective conditions, leaves the status quo undisturbed
in the valorization of revelation.
6. A similar critique of Heidegger can be made through psychoanalysis. See
Jackson, Philosophy and Working-through the Past, 129–150.
NOTES 139
12. In regard to the transcendental subject, Adorno writes: “The more auto-
cratically the I raises itself above the existent, the more it imperceptibly
turns into an object and ironically countermands its constitutive role …
Beyond the magic circle of identity philosophy, the transcendental subject
can be deciphered as the society which is unconscious of itself” (Adorno
1966, 178).
13. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, 89–90.
14. Ibid., 10.
15. Ibid., 97.
16. Ibid., 99.
17. Ibid., 99–100.
18. Adorno writes: “The circle of identification, which ultimately always iden-
tifies only itself, was drawn by the thinking that tolerates nothing outside;
its imprisonment is its own handiwork. Such totalitarian and for that rea-
son particular rationality was historically dictated by what was threatening
in nature … Identifying thought, the making of everything different into
the same, perpetuates the bondage of nature [Naturverfallenheit] in fear
… unreflective reason is deluded to the point of madness in view of each
and every one [anything] which eludes its domination” (Adorno 1966,
174).
19. Haar, “Nietzsche and Metaphysical Language,” 7.
20. Ibid., 6.
21. This is discussed in Chap. 2. See Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality
and Ecce Homo, 241.
22. Nietzsche suggests that asceticism would guide the philosopher’s salu-
tary avoidance of “noise, admiration, news, influence,” the seeking of
“a small position, daily routine,” tolerance of “a certain dependency and
darkening in the same way that he can stand the dark … not, as I have
to say again and again, out of virtue, out of a creditable will to modera-
tion and simplicity, but because their supreme master so demands, cleverly
and inexorably: preoccupied with just one thing, collecting and saving
up everything—time, strength, love, interest—with that end in view …
with regard to the chastity of philosophers, this type of spirit obviously
has different progeny than children … it is their dominating instinct, at
least during periods when they are pregnant with something great ...”
(Nietzsche 1997, 78–80). Again, this is not a moral antithesis of virtue
vs. vice, but the transfiguration of sensuality in the context of social rela-
tionships, and the harnessing of it in the creation of beauty for a better
social future.
23. Nietzsche writes: “… there is not, necessarily, an antithesis between chas-
tity and sensuality; every good marriage, every real affair of the heart
transcends this antithesis … This ought to be true for all healthy cheerful
NOTES 141
mortals who are far from seeing their precarious balancing act between
‘animal and angel’ as necessarily one of the arguments against life,–the
best and the brightest … actually found in it one more of life’s charms.
Such ‘contradictions’ are what makes life so enticing … On the other
hand, it is only too clear that if pigs who have fallen on hard times are
made to praise chastity … they will only see in it and praise the oppo-
site of themselves, the opposite of pigs who have fallen on hard times—
and oh! what a tragic grunting and excitement there will be!” (Nietzsche
1997, 69).
24. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, 153.
25. See Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical
Fragments, 94–136.
CHAPTER 5
What if some day or night a demon were to steal into your loneliest lone-
liness and say to you: ‘This life as you now live it and have lived it you
will have to live once again and innumerable times again; and there will
be nothing new in it, every pain and every joy and every thought and sigh
and everything unspeakably small or great in your life must return to you,
all in the same succession and sequence—even this spider and this moon-
light between the trees, and even this moment and I myself. The eternal
hourglass of existence is turned over again and again, and you with it,
SIGNS OF CONVALESCENCE: RECURRENCE AND INTEGRATING GOOD AND EVIL 147
speck of dust!’ Would you not throw yourself down and gnash your teeth
and curse the demon who spoke thus? Or have you once experienced a
tremendous moment when you would have answered him: ‘You are a god,
and never have I heard anything more divine.’ …2
On the one hand, this describes a sort of negative dialectics, in which any
given moment, or perspective, would avow its necessary loss and mediat-
edness and hence its necessary connection with other moments and per-
spectives. On the other hand, it describes the ability to accept the loss
and mediation of cherished moments and perspectives—their necessary
connections with unpleasant, overwhelming moments—as being largely
unbearable. Hence, the section is titled “The heaviest weight,” which on
this reading would refer to the unbearable entanglement of our pleas-
urable, joyous experiences with the negative, good with bad. Nietzsche
asks, “ … have you once experienced … ” in your “loneliest loneliness,”
the ability to bear such a thought?—implying the suffered ordeal of
overcoming recalcitrant partiality. The thought of eternal return is the
thought of eternal mediation, which is almost constitutively unbearable
for humans, given our genealogy. Nonetheless, the possibility of future
liberation is suggested in Nietzsche’s asking of this question: “how well
disposed would you have to become to yourself and to life to long for
nothing more fervently than for this ultimate eternal confirmation and
seal?”3 This implies a suffered social future in which we would be better
able to bear the partiality of our experiences, their inevitable loss, and
ineluctable mediation. One might say in such a future, we would be able
to bear ourselves and other objects as wholes, i.e., as objects infused with
a negativity that undergirds, conditions, and ruptures our partial perspec-
tives on ourselves and others.
The imbrication of this thought with the social, however, is often
missed, as if eternal recurrence were simply about time, and the indi-
vidual’s experience of time, such that some sort of revelation of repeti-
tion would transform an individual’s existence. However, it also poses
the essential contradiction between the subject’s socio-historically con-
ditioned normative categorization of experience and the suffered mate-
riality of that experience; the contradiction lies within the claim of
independence from that which conditions the claim. It thus represents
that same structure of reflection as that suggested by the concept of con-
valescence: perspectives and values as partialities of the same whole—
a whole that is suffered not known—in which partiality as a socially
148 5 WORKING-THROUGH PERSPECTIVES IN NIETZSCHE …
The question is how far the judgment promotes and preserves life, how
well it preserves, and perhaps even cultivates, the type. And we are funda-
mentally inclined to claim that the falsest judgments…are the most indis-
pensable to us, and that without accepting the fictions of logic, without
measuring reality against the wholly invented world of the unconditioned
and self-identical, without a constant falsification of the world through
numbers, people could not live—that a renunciation of false judgments
would be a renunciation of life, a negation of life. To acknowledge untruth
as a condition of life: this clearly means resisting the usual value feelings
in a dangerous manner; and a philosophy that risks such a thing would by
that gesture alone place itself beyond good and evil.5
Klein and Nietzsche
For Klein, the infant is faced with “reality” from the start, already in its
earliest experiences with the breast which, on the one hand, both satisfies
and frustrates it and, on the other hand, is the target of internal upsurges
of desire and aggression. In Adorno’s terms, the object has primacy in
at least two ways—in the objects the infant needs and in the infant’s
own internal nature, the impulses that drive it in uncontrollable ways.
One might say that the infant’s position is one of weakness in relation
to excessive and overwhelming objectivity. The vulnerable pre-subjective
infant lives in a split world—internally as the upsurge of love and hate
and externally as the valuing of the mother’s body as both a good object
and a bad object—an object that loves and hates. The infant projects its
own persecution by its own impulses onto the mother’s body and intro-
jects that body into itself. In this way, the objectivity or reality of the
mother’s body both satisfies and frustrates the infant’s drives and fanta-
sies insofar as it simply does not conform to them and does not always
satisfy them. This implies the simple fact of the primacy of the objectivity
of the mother’s body which transcends infantile impulses.
In “A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive
States,” Klein examines the difference between the paranoid introjection
of the young infant and the melancholic introjection of the older infant.
She writes:
This is the basis for psychotic or paranoid anxiety in infants. The infant
experiences internal and external nature as persecutors, to which he
or she is vulnerable. Outside of our control, the external object frus-
trates our desires, and we are overwhelmed by the upsurge of internal
nature, which only later enters into consciousness, confounding efforts
KLEIN AND NIETZSCHE 151
to control and guide it. The infant is not able to integrate this objectiv-
ity into a whole ego, or whole external object, but rather defends itself
through paranoiac, psychotic, schizophrenic mechanisms.
In normal development, there is a transition:
As the ego becomes more fully organized, the internalized imagos will
approximate more closely to reality and the ego will identify itself more
fully with ‘good’ objects. The dread of persecution, which was at first felt
on the ego’s account, now relates to the good object as well and from now
on preservation of the good object is regarded as synonymous with the
survival of the ego…Hand in hand with this development goes a change of
the highest importance, namely, from a partial object-relation to the rela-
tion to a complete object…Not until an object is loved as a whole can its
loss be felt as a whole.7
If things do not go well and the relationship with the caregiver is unsta-
ble, pathological defenses against the anxiety of disintegration and
the threat of loss, are developed: paranoia, mania, overidealization of the
internal good object, projection of all persecution onto external world,
and overidealization of the goodness of external objects to compensate
for anxiety arising internally and externally.
There are environmental conditions for an ongoing negative dialec-
tic in which relationships with loved and hated objects can be borne in
a progressive, less persecutory sense. But, Klein’s analysis invites further
questions about the conditions of possibility of overcoming the schizoid
position, since the caregiver himself or herself has a suffered relational
history that conditions the caregiving. What socio-historical conditions
are most conducive for facilitative caregiving—perhaps less traumatic,
more mournful, or convalescent forms of society? Moreover, it may be
the case that dominant forms of sociality, and consequently of subjec-
tivity, reproduce the potential for traumatic exposure and hence repro-
duce the loss of self that longs for an idealized, partial “good” object as
the occasion for the fixation of ego and culture. Threatened with ego
loss, the split, paranoid–schizoid world seems to find a social analog in
Nietzsche’s analysis of ascetic culture—a basic form of regressive group
stability.
It might be said that the position implied by Nietzsche’s bipolarity of
Good vs. Evil is at its worst indicative of regression to paranoid–schizoid
position, of floating partiality where the hold on a good stable object—or
environment—is so tenuous that threats and persecutors are seen every-
where. The world is then experienced as a chaotic struggle between ide-
alized good and idealized bad objects. However, instead of a full-blown
regression to paranoid schizophrenia, this may more often take the form
of manic defenses as symptoms of more or less normal inabilities to
work-through the depressive position. For Hannah Segal, manic defenses
If the mother is taken into the child’s inner world as a good and depend-
able object, an element of strength is added to the ego. For I assume that
the ego develops largely round this good object, and the identification
with the good characteristics of the mother becomes the basis for further
helpful identifications…makes it easier for the child to identify also with a
good father and later on with other friendly figures…All this contributes to
a stable personality and makes it possible to extend sympathy and friendly
feelings to other people.20
Winnicott and Nietzsche
In Klein’s paradigm, there is always that which exceeds the good object,
both within—as the upsurge of desire and aggression—and without—
in the objective finitude of the object, which inevitably turns “bad.”
Kleinian reparation implies the ability to negotiate this convoluted world,
based on a lack of equivalencies, with a good conscience. Winnicott’s
notion of play and the transitional space is similar—in playing, I am not a
separate “thing” among other “things,” within an independent value and
meaning that can be compared to that of other “things.” As with Klein,
my subjectivity is within the object (through projection) and it is within
me (introjection). Play happens within a protected environment which
allows the crossing of borders of self and other, of idea and reality—with-
out a bad conscience. Moreover, in that transitional space protected by
the caregiver, it is precisely the failures of the infant’s magic produced
by the imperfections of the caregiver’s response—i.e., the negativity of
experience that which ruptures, undergirds, and exceeds the infant’s sub-
jectivity—that drives the transition to having a shared world. This nega-
tivity—located in Klein’s analysis within the ordeal of internalizing the
whole object, characteristic of the depressive position—slowly teaches
the infant to bear the limit of its omnipotence, to incorporate that limit
into itself, as an initial but hopefully expanding the sense of objectivity.
Winnicott writes: “The change of the object from ‘subjective” to ‘objec-
tively perceived’ is jogged along less effectually by satisfactions than by
dissatisfactions … the frustrating aspect of object behavior has value in
educating the infant in respect of the existence of a not-me world … the
infant can hate the object, that is to say, can retain the idea of the object
as potentially satisfying while recognizing its failure to behave satisfacto-
rily.”30 It is the difference between subject and object—and the primacy
WINNICOTT AND NIETZSCHE 163
This suggests that future aggressiveness stems from the extent to which
motility was integrated in the attaining of desired objects, so that id satis-
factions are situated within a world within one must move and relate. In
less than optimal situations, the environment is not explored, but rather
experienced as impinging. This results in a defensive preservation of a
true self in withdrawal that merely reacts to, rather than integrates with,
the environment.
In bad environments, there are traumatic ruptures in the unfolding
of integrative motility, in which love and aggression would be mediated
by objectivity. Without sufficient covering, the infant cannot bear its
164 5 WORKING-THROUGH PERSPECTIVES IN NIETZSCHE …
the id, superego, and external reality, including social relations). For
Winnicott, the ego is that which, following Klein, would ideally come
to an ability to negotiate whole objects—objects that change, move, die,
cause us pain, affect us, etc. Whereas id relationships are those fueled by
bodily, affective attachments to partial objects, it is only in the context of
ego relations that the latter can be negotiated, integrated.
Winnicott implies that the use of metaphor—upon which so many
Nietzsche commentators place emphasis—is itself a legacy of the infant’s
environmentally conditioned play. As in Nietzsche, for Winnicott,
“health here is closely bound up with the capacity of the individual to
live in an area that is intermediate between the dream and reality, that
which is called cultural life.”50 Likewise, where there is a rigid split
between the True and False Self, Winnicott finds a notably hindered
ability to use symbols, i.e., to bear that ambivalent transitional status of
objects.51 The characteristic of the transitional object as both found and
created is also indicative of the ability of adults to use symbolic language.
He suggests that when the mother’s responses are good enough,
the infant begins to believe in external reality which appears and behaves
as by magic (because of the mother’s relatively successful adaptation to the
infant’s gestures and needs)…On this basis the infant can gradually abro-
gate omnipotence…can gradually come to recognize the illusory element,
the fact of playing and imagining. Here is the basis for the symbol which at
first is both the infant’s spontaneity or hallucination, and also the external
object created and ultimately cathected.52
This is then suggestive of the claim made earlier about the primacy of the
suffered environment which conditions the use of language. Nietzsche
does in fact use metaphorical language to subvert metaphysical concepts,
but more fundamentally argues that the ability or inability to think meta-
phorically is conditioned by suffered, social histories.
Winnicott identifies two sorts of groups. First, there are groups com-
prised of those who are relatively well integrated and who thereby do not
require a shared defense as a parental stand-in. Having been provided a
stable facilitating environment as infants, they did not develop rigidified
false selves as protection from objectivity, but were able to integrate—to a
certain degree—their subjective spontaneity with that objectivity: “ … the
organization that each individual brings in terms of personal integration
tends to maintain the group identity from within … the group benefits
172 5 WORKING-THROUGH PERSPECTIVES IN NIETZSCHE …
from the personal experience of individuals, each of whom has been seen
through the integration moment, and has been covered until able to pro-
vide self-cover.”53 This type of group is a collection of selves-in-process
who each provide self-cover, which is only possible because each had been
provided proper “cover” within a good facilitating environment, which
enabled them to work-through their exposure, vulnerability. The second
sort of group is “… a collection of relatively unintegrated persons can be
given covering … Here the group work does not come from the individu-
als but from the covering … ”.54 In other words, this a group that coheres
because of shared compliance. This implies that where the facilitating envi-
ronment has failed, integration (as the becoming able to cover oneself and
navigate objectivity) has failed, and the fixated false self is a symptom of
this failure. It identifies with bad social conditions in order to protect the
true self, which buried far away from the threatening otherness. In the
group, members have a shared identity, and shared defense, in the compli-
ance itself, which amounts to a shared, fixated partiality.
For Winnicott, there is no mind or spiritual core of will and under-
standing. Rather, at the beginning, “Here is a body, and the psyche and
the soma are not to be distinguished except according to the direction
from which one is looking … I suppose the word psyche here means the
imaginative elaboration of somatic parts, feelings and functions, that is, of
physical aliveness.”55 If the environment (i.e., caregiver) is good enough,
the infant becomes able to allow for her deficiencies by mental activity.
This applies to meeting not only instinctual impulses by also all the most
primitive types of ego need, even including the need for negative care or
an alive neglect…The mind, then, has as one of its roots a variable func-
tioning of the psyche-soma, one concerned with the threat to continuity of
being that follows any failure of (active) environmental adaptation…mind-
development is very much influenced by factors not specifically personal to
the individual, including chance events.56
Notes
1. As discussed in previous chapters, object relations psychoanalysis empha-
sizes relations over drive theory. Klein, for example, writes: “it seems
essential to regard the libido-disposition not merely as such, but also to
consider it in connection with the subject’s earliest relations to his inter-
nalized and external objects… ”. See Klein, “A Contribution to the
Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States,” 151.
2. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, Edited by Bernard Williams, Translated by
Josefine Nauckhoff, 194.
3. Ibid., 195.
4. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, 5–6.
5. Ibid., 7.
6. Klein, “A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States,”
145.
7. Ibid., 147.
8. Ibid., 149.
9. Ibid.
10. Ibid., 150.
11. See, for example, Edmund Husserl, Analyses Concerning Active and
Passive Synthesis.
12. Klein writes: “The persecutions and demands of bad internalized objects;
the attacks of such objects upon one another … the urgent necessity
to fulfill the very strict demands of the ‘good objects’ and to protect
and placate them within the ego … the constant uncertainty as to the
‘goodness’ of a good object, which causes it so readily to become trans-
formed into a bad one—all of these factors combine to produce in the
ego a sense of being a prey to contradictory and impossible claims from
within, a condition which is felt as a bad conscience… ”. See Klein, “A
Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States,” 151.
13. See Nietzsche, The Gay Science, 119.
14. Klein, “A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States,”
155.
15. Ibid., 159.
16. Ibid., 173.
17. Segal, Introduction to the Work of Melanie Klein, 82.
18. Ibid., 83.
19. Klein, “Our Adult World and its Roots in Infancy,” 294.
20. Ibid., 294–295.
21. Ibid., 297.
22. Nietzsche, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols and Other
Writings, 182.
NOTES 177
lengthiness, its frequent regressions and reversals—is due to the fact that
the herd instinct of obedience is inherited the best and at the cost of the
art of commanding … the herd man of today’s Europe gives himself the
appearance of being the only permissible type of man … ” See Beyond
Good and Evil, 86–87.
42. Winnicott, “Ego Distortion in Terms of True and False Self,” 143.
43. Ibid., 146.
44. Ibid., 147.
45. Ibid.
46. Ibid., 149.
47. Winnicott, “The Capacity to Be Alone,” 30.
48. Ibid., 34.
49. See Dorothy Dinnerstein, The Mermaid and the Minotaur.
50. Winnicott, “Ego Distortion in Terms of True and False Self,”150.
51. Ibid., 150.
52. Ibid., 146.
53. Winnicott, “Group Influences and the Maladjusted Child: The School
Aspect,” 149–150.
54. Ibid., 150.
55. Winnicott, “Mind and its Relation to the Psyche-Soma,” 244.
56. Ibid., 245–246.
57. Ibid., 246.
58. Ibid., 246–247.
59. Ibid., 247.
60. Winnicott, “Ego Distortion in Terms of True and False Self,” 145.
Bibliography
Brown, Wendy. 1995. States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Butler, Judith. 1997. The Psychic Life of Power. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Coe, Cynthia D., and Matthew C. Altman. The Paradoxes of a Convalescent
History: Nietzsche’s Genealogy as a Form of Working-through. In New
Nietzsche Studies, vol. 6 (Fall 2005) and 7 (Spring 2006), 116–228.
Conway, Daniel. 2008. Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals: A Reader’s Guide.
London: Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1983. Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1981. Spurs, trans. Barbara Harlow. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1986. Différance. In Deconstruction in Context, ed. Mark
Taylor, 396–420. Chicago: University of Chicago.
Dinnerstein, Dorothy. 1976. The Mermaid and the Minotaur. New York: Harper
Perennial.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1996. Being and Power: Heidegger and Foucault. In
International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 4 (1): 1–16.
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In Language, Counter-
Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, ed. D. F. Bouchard, 142.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Foucault, Michel. 1990. Nietzsche, Freud, Marx. In Transforming the
Hermeneutic Context: From Nietzsche to Nancy, ed. Ormiston and Shrift,
59–67. SUNY Press. Originally published in 1964 Nietzsche, Cahiérs du
Royaumont, 183–192. Paris: Les Editions du Minuit.
Freud, Sigmund. 2001. Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Sigmund Freud. ed. James Strachey. London: Vintage.
Hatab, Lawrence. 2008. Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality: An
Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger, Martin. 2000. Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Gregory Fried and
Richard Polt. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Honneth, Axel. 1996. The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Husserl, Edmund. 2001. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis:
Lectures on Transcendental Logic. trans. Anthony Steinbock. Dordrecht:
Kluwer.
Jackson, Jeffrey M. 2010. Persecution and Social Histories: Towards an Adornian
Critique of Levinas. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 36 (6), July.
Jackson, Jeffrey M. 2014. Philosophy and Working-through the Past: A
Psychoanalytic Approach to Social Pathologies. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Janaway, Christopher. 2012. Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche’s Genealogy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bibliography 181
G M
Genealogy, 2, 3, 5–10, 14, 17, 18, Marx, 3, 4, 22, 23, 25–38, 109, 113,
21, 24, 25, 33, 36, 62, 63, 69, 114, 122, 126, 130,
70, 72–74, 76, 81, 83, 86–90, 169
95, 96, 101, 107, 114–116, 119, Metaphor, 4, 13, 17–21, 32–35, 38,
121, 124–128, 130, 131, 143, 171
146–148, 152, 153, 156, 158,
164, 169, 173
N
Negative, 1, 3, 5, 16, 59, 60, 83, 89,
H 96, 98, 107–112, 114, 117, 119,
History, 1–3, 6, 7, 9, 11–16, 19–33, 121, 122, 124, 129, 131, 147,
35, 36, 38, 44, 46, 48, 49, 60, 149, 155, 159, 168, 172, 175
63, 69–74, 76–78, 80, 81, 83, Non-identity, 9, 18, 46, 54, 114, 115,
84, 86, 87, 89, 90, 92, 93, 95, 118, 124, 126
96, 99–101, 109, 110, 112–115,
117, 118, 121–123, 125–129,
131–134, 136, 137, 149, 155, O
156, 161, 164, 175 Object, 2–4, 6, 8–10, 15, 16, 18, 19,
23, 24, 26, 27, 29, 31, 33, 35,
38, 44–47, 50, 51, 54–56, 59,
I 62–64, 78, 80, 81, 86, 88, 90,
Identity, 1, 7, 10, 20, 21, 30, 54, 55, 95, 107–128, 130, 132, 133,
62, 63, 73, 89, 93, 108, 111– 136, 137, 143–165, 167–175
114, 117, 118, 121–126, 129, Object relations, 4, 23, 80, 123, 138,
144, 148, 149, 164, 169–172 143, 145, 153
K P
Klein, 3, 4, 10, 23, 69, 93, 122, 138, Play, 11, 18, 21, 45, 52, 55, 58, 60,
143–146, 150–160, 162, 168, 72, 124, 131, 152, 155, 159–
171, 174 163, 165, 168–171, 174, 175
L R
Language, 6, 11–14, 18–20, 26, 30, Ressentiment, 2, 5, 6, 9, 11, 15, 19,
43, 44, 46, 55, 60–63, 70, 73, 33, 43, 44, 48–53, 56, 58–64,
74, 77, 88, 92, 111, 113, 116, 70, 73, 77, 79, 82, 86, 88, 92,
126, 138, 146, 171, 172 93, 98–101, 113, 125, 128, 130,
Index 185