Holmstrom Milgrom 1991
Holmstrom Milgrom 1991
Holmstrom Milgrom 1991
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Law,
Economics, & Organization.
http://www.jstor.org
24 JLEO.V7 Sp
MultitaskPrincipal-Agent Analyses:Incentive
Contracts, Asset Ownership, and Job Design
Bengt Holmstrom
YaleUniversity
Paul Milgrom
StanfordUniversity
1. Introduction
In the standardeconomic treatmentof the principal-agentproblem, compen-
sation systems serve the dual function of allocatingrisks and rewardingpro-
ductive work. A tension between these two functionsarises when the agent is
risk averse, for providingthe agent with effective work incentives often forces
him to bear unwanted risk. Existing formal models that have analyzed this
tension, however, have producedonly limited results. It remainsa puzzle for
this theory that employmentcontractsso often specify fixed wages and more
generally that incentives within finns appearto be so muted, especially com-
paredto those of the market.Also, the models have remainedtoo intractable
to effectively address broaderorganizationalissues such as asset ownership,
job design, and allocation of authority.
In this article, we will analyze a principal-agentmodel that (i) can account
for paying fixed wages even when good, objective outputmeasuresare avail-
able and agents are highly responsive to incentive pay; (ii) can make recom-
mendationsand predictionsaboutownershippatternseven when contractscan
take full account of all observablevariablesand courtenforcementis perfect;
(iii) can explain why employmentis sometimes superiorto independentcon-
We are gratefulto the National Science Foundationfor financialsupportand to Gary Becker,
James Brickley, MurrayBrown, Joel Demski, Joseph Farrell, Oliver Hart, David Kreps, Kevin
Murphy,Eric Rasmussen, Steve Ross, Steve Stem, and especially AvnerGreif, JaneHannaway,
and Hal Varianfor their many insightful comments, examples, and suggestions. We also wish to
thank Froystein Gjesdal for pointing out two errorsin an earlier draft.
1. Some of the predictiveweaknesses of standardagency models are discussed in the surveys
by MacDonald, Hart and Holmstrom, and Baker, Jensen, and Murphy.
? 1991 by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. ISSN 8756-6222
Multitask Principal-Agent Analyses 25
for the control of incentives. In the standardmodel, when each agent can
engage in only one task, the grouping of tasks into jobs is not a relevant
issue.4
Our formal modeling of these issues utilizes our linear principal-agent
model (Holmstromand Milgrom, 1987), mainly specialized to the case where
the agent's costs depend only on the total effortor attentionthe agent devotes
to all of his tasks. This modeling assures that an increase in an agent's
compensationin any one task will cause some reallocationof attentionaway
from other tasks. First, we show that an optimal incentive contractcan be to
pay a fixed wage independentof measuredperformance,just as the opponents
of incentives based on educationaltesting have argued. More generally, the
desirability of providing incentives for any one activity decreases with the
difficultyof measuringperformancein any other activities that make compet-
ing demands on the agent's time and attention. This result may explain a
substantial part of the puzzle of why incentive clauses are so much less
common than one-dimensionaltheories would predict.
Second, we specialize our model to the case where the unmeasurableaspect
of performanceis how the value of a productiveasset changes over time. The
difficulties of valuing assets are well recognized, and the vast majority of
accountingsystems value assets using fixed depreciationschedules based on
historical costs, deviating from this procedureonly in exceptional circum-
stances. Under these conditions, when the principalowns the returnsfrom the
asset, the optimal incentive contract will provide only muted incentives for
the agent to produceoutput, in orderto mitigateany abuse of the asset or any
substitutionof effort away from asset maintenance.However, when the agent
owns the asset returns, the optimal incentive contract will provide more
intensive incentives to engage in production,in orderto alleviate the reverse
problem that the agent may use the asset too cautiously or devote too much
attention to its care and improvement. This analysis supportsWilliamson's
observation that "high-powered" incentives are more common in market
arrangementsthan within firms, without relying on any assumptionsabout
specific investments. Moreover, it provides a rudimentarytheory of owner-
ship, accordingto which the conditions thatfavorthe agent owning the assets
are (i) thatthe agent is not too risk averse, (ii) thatthe varianceof asset returns
is low, and (iii) thatthe varianceof measurementerrorin other aspects of the
agent's performance is low. Thus, it emphasizes measurementcost as an
importantdeterminantof integrationin contrastto the leading approaches,
which stress asset specificity.5
4. Riordan and Sappington also analyze an incentive model in which job assignment is
central, but for a very different reason. They ask when the principal should do one of two
sequentialproductionstages herself in orderto reduce the agent's informationadvantage.In our
model, job assignments do not affect the principal'sinformation.
5. Alchian and Demsetz argued that monitoring difficulties account for the formation of
firms, but their theorywas subsequentlyrejectedin favorof the view that asset specificity and ex
post bargainingproblemsdrive integration(Grossmanand Hart, Williamson). We are reintroduc-
ing measurementcost as a key factor, but in a way thatdiffersfrom the originalAlchian-Demsetz
theory. In particular, we do not argue that owners can better monitor the work force. Our
approachis more closely related to Barzel's work.
Multilask Prncipal-Agent Analyses 27
worker. This conclusion squares nicely with the intuition that it is the
differencesbetweenthe measurabilityof quantityandqualityin production,or
of the so-called "basicskills" and "higher-orderthinkingskills" in education,
that make those incentive problems difficult. The theory indicates that even
when the agents have identical ex ante characteristics,the principal should
still design theirjobs to have measurementcharacteristicsthatdifferas widely
as possible. The principalshould then provide more intensive incentives and
require more work effort from the jobholder whose performanceis more
easily measured.
Our results are variations on the general theme of second best, which
stresses that when prices cannotallocate inputsefficiently,then optimalincen-
tives will typically be provided by subsidizing or taxing all inputs. For in-
stance, Greenwaldand Stiglitz, in a vivid metaphor,point out the value of a
governmentsubsidy for home fire extinguishers,since homeownerswith fire
insurancehave too little incentive to invest in all forms of fire preventionand
to fight fires once they have started. This mechanismhas been most exten-
sively analyzed in the theory of optimal taxation and in welfare theory.
However, the study of interdependenciesamong incentives and the use of
instrumentsother than compensation to alleviate incentive problems have
enteredagency analyses more recently.Lazeararguesthat where cooperation
among workers is important,we should expect to see less wage differentia-
tion, that is, "lower-powered"incentives. Holmstromand Ricarti Costa have
observed how a firm's capital budgetingpolicy, including the hurdlerate and
the way the firmassesses idiosyncraticrisks, can affectthe willingness of risk-
averse managersto propose risky investmentprojects. Milgrom and Milgrom
andRobertshave studiedhow organizationaldecisionprocessesaffectthe allo-
cation of effort between politicking and directly productivework. Farrelland
Shapiroshow thata priceclause may be worse thanno contractat all, becauseit
reduces incentives to supply quality;this is similarto our resultthat it may be
optimal to provide no quantity incentives when quality is poorly measured.
Some articles containing related ideas have been developed contempo-
raneously.Itoh (1991), in an analysis complementaryto ours, studies condi-
tions under which an employer might induce workersto work separatelyon
their tasks, and those in which it is best for them to spend some efforthelping
one another.LaffontandTirole show thatconcernsfor qualityhelp explainthe
use of cost-plus contractingin procurement.Baker investigates a model in
which observable proxies of marginal product are imperfect in a way that
causes the agent to misallocateeffort across contingenciesand thereforeleads
to incentives that are not as powerful as standardtheory would suggest.
Minahanreportsa result on task separationthat suggests a job design similar
to ours but based on a differentargument,as we will later explain.
The remainderof this article is organized as follows. In Section 2, we
recapitulateourbasic principal-agenttheory,upon which the entireanalysis is
based. In Section 3, we specialize the analysis to the case where the agent's
costs depend only on the total attentionsuppliedand prove the various propo-
sitions aboutthe optimalityof fixed wages, the factorsdeterminingthe assign-
ment of ownership, and the optimal limits on outside business activities. In
Multitask Principal-Agent Analyses 29
x = i(t) + e,
subject to
6. Note that if an activity can be measuredwithout error, then a linear scheme allows the
principalto set this activityat any desiredlevel costlessly, assumingthatthecost functionis convex.
7. It is of interestto note that instead of a measurementerrorthe incentive problemcould be
Multitask
Principal-AgentAnalyses 31
a = (I + r[Cij]Z)-IB', (5)
x = t + E. (6)
We can apply (5) assuming that a2 is infinite and a12 is zero. Then, if the
optimal solution entails t > 0, it must satisfy
9. We are assuming that teachers are motivated to teach some higher-thinkingskills even
without explicit financialincentives to do so. In one-dimensionalagency models, it is typically
assumed that the agent will not work without incentive pay. The reason for this is not that the
agent dislikes even small amounts of work, but ratherthat the level of work the agent would
provide without explicit incentives does not affect the optimal solution. In multitask models,
however, the fact that agents supply inputseven withoutincentive pay can be quite consequential
as the teacherexample and the example in Section 3.2 show.
Multitask Principat-Agent Analyses 33
beyond that limit. Formally,we assume thatthere is some number > 0 such
that C'(t) 5 0 for t -i and C(t) = 0. This is important,because it means that
contractsthatprovidefor fixed wages may still elicit some effort, thoughmore
may be elicited by providingpositive incentives. It also means that there is a
range of effort allocationsamong which the agent is indifferentand willing to
follow the principal'spreference.
Proof. If a = 0, then the agent can be instructedto spend total time i where
C'(t) = 0 and to choose tf E [0,t] to maximize B(tl,f - i,), which is strictly
positive because f > 0. In this case, the cost of risk-bearingby the agent is
zero, so the total wealth will be B(l ,i - i ) - C( ). If a > 0, then t, will be
set to zero and the total wealth will be 0 - C( t) - ra2 2/2 ' -C( t) < B(ft ,
- f ) -- C( ) because i is cost minimizingfor the agent. If a < 0, then t2 = 0
and t, < t [because C'(t,) < 0 = C'(f)] so the total profits are
B(t,O0) - C(t,) - ra2a2 < B(,O) - C(t) < B(t,j - tl) - C(i).
Q.E.D.
taken is then the same as assuming that the principalcannot distinguish performancealong the
several dimensions of the vector strategy.The formal mappingfrom these "hiddeninformation"
models to our "hidden action" model is discussed in Holmstromand Milgrom (1987).
36 The Journalof Law,Economics,&Organization,V7 Sp
Proposition 2. Assume that r12 > Max('r1,r2). Then, the optimal em-
ployment contractalways entails paying a fixed wage (a = 0). Wheneverthe
independentcontractingrelationis optimal, it involves "high-poweredincen-
tives" (a > 0). Furthermore,thereexist values of the parametersr, o2, and a2
for which employmentcontractsare optimalandothersfor which independent
contractingis optimal. If employment contractingis optimal for some fixed
parameters(r,a2,a2), then it is also optimalfor higher values of these param-
eters. Similarly, if independentcontractingis optimal, then it is also optimal
for lower values of these parameters.2
Proof. First, consider the case of the employment contract, where the
returnsV(t2) accrue to the firm. If the principalsets a > 0, the agent will
respondby setting t, so that a = C'(t,) and setting t2 = 0. The total certainty
equivalent wealth is equal to B(t,) - C(tI) - rao2a2< 7r1 < 7r12. However, if
a = 0, the agent is willing to spend time f in any proportionsand so a total
certaintyequivalentwealth of r'2 is obtained.Therefore,it is optimal for the
principalto set a = 0 in an employmentcontract.
For the independent contractor,the maximum total certainty equivalent
wealth is computedas follows. Let (t1(a),f2(a)) maximize acu(tl) + V(t2) -
C(tI + t2) - ra2/2; this representsthe agent'soptimalresponseto a. The total
certaintyequivalent wealth for any fixed a is
12. One can derive a similar result with a general quadraticcost function C(tl,t2). The only
difference is that the commission rate would not necessarily be zero for an employed agent,
though it would always be smaller than for an independentcontractor.
Multitask
Principal-AgentAnalyses 37
= C(t + - (8)
c(ttl,...tN) 2Ktk) XKVk(tk).
Assume for the moment that this problem has an interiorsolution. Then the
first-orderconditions that characterizethe agent's optimum are
a = v,(tk)- (11)
We note from (11) that the amountof time the agent chooses to spend on task
k, denoted tk(a), only depends on a and not on A. Also, the total time spent
working, t + 2Atk, is independentof A. Consequently,if the agent is allowed
more personaltasks, without a change in a, all the time for those tasks will be
reallocatedaway from the principal'stask;this is the convenienceof assuming
(9) together with a cost function that only depends on total time. It makes it
very simple to determinewhich personal tasks the agent should be allowed
40 The Journalof Law,Economics,& Organization,
V7 Sp
for a given a. The benefit of allowing the agent to spend time on task k is
vk(tk(a)),while the (opportunity)cost is ptk(a). Therefore, the optimal set of
allowable personal tasks is
Proposition 3. Assume that a is such that t(a) > 0. Then the following
statementshold.
(i) It is optimal to let the agent pursue exactly those private business
opportunitiesthat belong to A(a) defined in (12); that is, those tasks k for
which the resulting average product v(t,(a))/tk(a) exceeds the marginal
product p in the principal'stask.
(ii) The higher is the agent's marginalrewardfor performancein the main
job, the greateris his freedom to pursuepersonalbusiness. Formally,if a
a', then A(a) D A(a').
(iii) If it is optimal to exclude task k, then it is also optimal to exclude all
tasks m, for which v,'(ti) > v(t4), where tf is defined by vj(t) = pi.
It is possible that for small enough a it will be optimal to set t(a) = 0 and
hence A(a) = K. In that case, there are no gains from tradeand the principal
will not employ the agent. Such a solution may be optimal if the cost of
bearingrisk becomes sufficentlylarge. One could exclude thatcase by assum-
ing that the agent's privatebusinesses are less productivethanworkingfor the
principal with zero incentive (as we saw earlier, zero incentive does not
preclude productive work), but there is no need to make such a restriction.
Obviously,if t(a) = 0, then t(a') = 0, for all a'<a. Therefore,job separation
will occur, if at all, below a critical cutoff value for a.
Part (ii) of Proposition 3 articulatesa familiarand fundamentalprinciple:
Multitask Prtncipal-Agent Analyses 41
Return
($)
t1(c0) t, t t ((0)
11 2 2
Effort
Figure1. Itis optimalto allowtask 1 but to exclude task 2, because tl(a) < fi but f2 <
t2(a). Notice that this is true even though the social returnsto task 2 are everywhere
higher than those to task 1.
a = pl[1 + ro21(dtlda)l,
Proof. The equationin (i) is a special case of (5); the expressionfor dtlda
follows from the agent's first-orderconditions. Revealed preference paired
with Proposition3 implies (ii). Part (i) implies that a c p and that a goes to
zero when ro2 goes to infinity;this proves (iii). Q.E.D.
If we assume that the agent's cost and benefit functions are quadratic,we
see from (i) that the agent's responsivenessto incentives, dtlda, increases as
the set of allowable tasks, A(a), expands. Consequently,viewing A(a) as
14. One can also show that by excluding privatetasks, the agent becomes less responsive to
increases in the commission a. A less flexible job design is associatedwith weaker incentives as
we mentioned earlier.
Multitask
Principal-AgentAnalyses 43
15. Nonlinearitiesin the principal'stask would not alterthe conclusion thata is reducedwhen
r or a2 is increased;this partis just a revealedpreferenceargument.However, the set A(a) would
be harderto characterizeas the exclusion of tasks would interactwith each other as a result of
integer problems. One could even find that a personal task is included when a is reduced.
44 V7 Sp
The Journalof Lav. Economics.&Organization,
ti = J t,(k)dk. (13)
Proof. Let k be a set of tasks for which thereis joint responsibility-that is,
a1(k)a2(k) > 0, for k E K-and suppose K has positive measure.Let ti(K)
fKti(k)dkand choose K' C K such that fK,t(k)dk= t (K). Define a new set of
attentionallocations and commission rates {It(k),ai(k)}so that these coincide
with the original specificationfor k ? K. For k E K', set ? (k) = t(k), da(k) =
a,(k), and t2(k)= d2(k) = 0; for k E K\K', set t1(k)(k)d(k) = 0, t(k) = t(k),
and a2(k) = a2(k).
The total attentiondevotedto each task as well as the total attentionof each
of the two agents is unalteredin the new scheme. By construction,therefore,
the first-orderconditions (15) hold and the new scheme is feasible. The new
scheme strictly improves the objective function as some of the commission
rates are lowered to zero for a set of tasks of nonzero measure. Q.E.D.
rI
Minimize C(t1) + C(t2) +
l
j [ l (k)a2(k) + I2(k)a(k)]a2K)dk (16)
(k),12(k)
46 The Journalof Law,Economics,& Organization,
V7 Sp
subject to
Constraint(17) merely defines a,(k), since t(k) and ti are fixed. If tf = f2,
then it is clear from (17) that al(k) = a2(k), and hence thatthe objective (16)
is independentof the task assignment:All feasible assignmentsthen yield the
same total certaintyequivalent wealth. As we will see below, the important
case is the asymmetricone, so let us assume that fi < t2.
To solve program(16)-(20), we first solve the relaxed programin which
(20) is replaced by the less restrictiveconstraint
In the relaxed problem, the objective and constraintsare all linear (hence,
convex) in the choice variables I,(k), so first-orderconditions fully charac-
terize the optimum. Let y, be the Lagrangemultiplierassociated with con-
straint (18). Then, optimizing in the usual way, we find that
and (22)
By (17), a, < a2 as F, < t2; therefore, (22) implies that y, > y2- Since li(k)
takes values 0 and 1 at the optimum of the relaxed programwith constraint
(21) in place of (20), Equations (22) also characterizethe solution to the
original problem and identify the marginal tasks. A marginal task is one
where the advantageof assigning the task to agent 1, in termsof the lower risk
premium required, is just offset by the higher marginal value of agent l's
time. The firstof these costs varies with the measurementerrorattachedto the
task and the second varies with the amountof time the task requires.These
observations suggest an alternativecharacterizationof the optimum assign-
ment policy.
Define the noise-to-signal ratio of task k by n(k) = a2(k)/tu'(t(k),k)2and the
informationcoefficient by o(k) = n(k)/t(k). Let
= (2/r)(y, - -
2)[C'(2)2 C'(il)21- (. (23)
Multitask Principal-Agent Analyses 47
16. Minahan derives a result that is related. In his model there are four tasks: two easy to
measure and two hard to measure. He shows that it is better not to mix the tasks. The main
differencebetween his model and ours is that in his model the principalcannotprovide incentives
on individualtasks, just on the sum of the tasks. This would greatlysimplify our analysis. On the
other hand, Minahan's analysis deals with nonlinear incentives and general utility functions,
which adds to the complexity.
17. One manifestationof the task allocation principle may be found in the organizationof
R&D activities in firms [see Holmstrom(1989)].
48 The Journalof Lav. Economics,&Organization,
V7 Sp
signal ratio n(k). If we let ii(k) denote the commission paid based on nor-
malized performance,it follows from (17) that
' i r o2(k)
2C"
2C"~ 22 f0''2tk)
(12(k) l1(k))
- 2(t( k),k)
k
Principal-AgentAnalyses 49
Multitask
L(k)s -<
The last step uses (18) and the facts thato(k) > g when i l(k)= 1 and
when I2(k) = 1 [and that g(k) is not constantso that the inequalityis strict].
The remainderof the propositionis verifiedin the paragraphsprecedingthe
proposition. Q.E.D.
5.2 Caveats
The model presentedin the previous subsectionrepresentsmerely a first pass
at studyingthe optimal groupingof tasks intojobs. Althoughit providessome
interesting insights, we have omitted so many key elements of the problem
and made so many special assumptionsto simplify an alreadycomplex analy-
sis thatit is well to make a preliminarylist of these featuresand omissions and
to speculate about how they may have affected our analysis.
First, we had assumed that all tasks are "small" and that the principalhas
perfect freedom to group them in any way to form a job. Neither of these
assumptionsis particularlyattractive.The assumptionthat all tasks are small
could be replacedby the assumptionthatthereare a finite numberof tasks that
all requiredthe same amountof time [t(k) constant];this, however, introduces
the possibility that i, = t2, in which case all task assignments are equally
good. When tasks require nonnegligible amounts of time and vary in size,
then the need to minimize costs borne by the agents by equalizing workloads
may reversesome of our conclusions. Moreover,tasks like maintainingquali-
ty and producing output cannot always be separated. In short, our model
exaggeratesthe principal'sability to group tasks into homogeneous measure-
ment classes and in so doing caricaturesthe problem of how jobs are con-
structed.The main virtue of our model is that it is structuredso that incentive
considerationsalone determinethe optimalsolution, so thatit lends some new
insights into the very limited question of how incentive concerns may affect
job design.
Second, we had assumed that the errors of measurementin the agent's
various tasks are all independent.We know from previous analyses, such as
Holmstrom(1982), that when errorsare positively correlated,separatingthe
tasks among the two agents allows the use of comparativeperformanceeval-
uation, which can help to reduce the risk premium incurredin providing
incentives. It is not hard to see that even without comparativeperformance
evaluation, separating tasks with positively correlated measurementerrors
creates a betterdiversifiedportfolioof tasks thatreducesthe risk thatthe agent
must bear. Similarly, grouping tasks in which performanceis negatively cor-
related reduces the agents' risk premium. So, even in the incentive domain,
our present model is highly incomplete.
50 The Journalof Law.Economics,&Organization,V7 Sp
6. Conclusion
The problem of providing incentives to agents and employees is far more
intricatethan is representedin standardprincipal-agent models. The perfor-
mance measures upon which rewardsare based may aggregatehighly dispa-
rate aspects of performanceinto a single numberand omit other aspects of
performancethat are essential if the firm is to achieve its goals. Commonly,
the principal-agent problemboils down to this: Given a highly incomplete
set of performancemeasuresand a highly complex set of potentialresponses
from the agent, how can the agent be motivatedto act in the social interest?
Our approach emphasizes that incentive problems must be analyzed in
totality;one cannotmake correctinferencesaboutthe properincentives for an
activity by studying the attributesof that activity alone. Moreover,the range
of instrumentsthat can be used to control an agent's performancein one
activity is much wider than just deciding how to pay for performance.One
can also shift ownershipof relatedassets, vary restrictionson the ways a job
can be done, vary limits and incentives for competingactivities, grouprelated
tasks into a single job, and so on.
In a related article (Holmstromand Milgrom, 1991), we study the simul-
taneous use of various instrumentsfor controllingagents to derive new, test-
able results from the theory of organization.Our emphasis there is on how
cross-sectionalvariationsin the parametersthat determinethe optimaldesign
of jobs, the optimal intensity of incentives, and the optimal allocation of
ownershiplead to covariationsamongendogenousvariablesthatare similarto
the patternswe find in actual firms.
Most past models of organizationfocus only on one instrumentat a time for
determiningincentives and a single activity to be motivated.Newer theories,
Multitask
Principal-AgentAnalyses 51
References
Alchian, Armen, and Harold Demsetz. 1972. "Production,InformationCosts and Economic
Organization,"62 American Economic Review 777-95.
Anderson, Erin. 1985. "The Salesperson as Outside Agent or Employee: A TransactionCost
Analysis," 4 ManagementScience 234-54.
--- , and David Schmittlein. 1984. "Integrationof the Sales Force: An EmpiricalExamina-
tion," 15 Rand Journal of Economics 385-95.
Baker, George. 1989. "Piece Rate Contractsand PerformanceMeasurementError,"manuscript,
GraduateSchool of Business, HarvardUniversity.
, Michael Jensen, and Kevin Murphy. 1988. "Competitionand Incentives: Practice vs
Theory," 43 Journal of Finance 593-616.
Barzel, Yoram. 1982. "MeasurementCosts and the Organizationof Markets,"25 Journalof Law
and Economics 27-48.
Brickley, James, and FrederickDark. 1987. "The Choice of OrganizationalForm:The Case of
Franchising," 18 Journal of Financial Economics 401-20.
Coase, Ronald. 1937. "The Natureof the Firm," 4 Economica 386-405.
Farrell,Joseph, and Carl Shapiro. 1989. "OptimalContractswith Lock-in," 79 AmericanEco-
nomic Review 51-68.
Greenwald, Bruce, and JosephStiglitz. 1986. "Exteralities in Economies with ImperfectInfor-
mation and Incomplete Markets," 101 QuarterlyJournal of Economics 229-64.
Grossman,Sanford, and Oliver Hart. 1986. "The Costs and Benefits of Ownership:A Theory of
Verticaland LateralIntegration,"94 Journal of Political Economy 691-719.
Hannaway,Jane. 1991. "Higher OrderThinking, Job Design and Incentives:An Analysis and
Proposal," American Education Research Journal (forthcoming).
Hart, Oliver, and Bengt Holmstrom. 1987. "The Theory of Contracts," in T. Bewley, ed.,
Advances in Economic Theory, Fifth World Congress. Cambridge:Cambridge University
Press.
Holmstrom, Bengt. 1982. "Moral Hazard in Teams," 13 Bell Journal of Economics 324-40.
- . 1989. "Agency Costs and Innovation,"12 Journalof EconomicBehaviorand Organiza-
tion 305-27.
, and Paul Milgrom. 1987. "Aggregationand Linearityin the Provisionof Intertemporal
Incentives," 55 Econometrica 303-28.
--- , and -- . 1990. "RegulatingTradeAmong Agents," 146 Journal of nstitutionaland
Theoretical Economics 85-105.
, and . 1991. "MeasurementCost and OrganizationTheory," working paper,
Stanford University.
---- , and Joan Ricart i Costa. 1986. "ManagerialIncentives and CapitalManagement,"101
QuarterlyJournal of Economics 835-60.
Itoh, Hideshi. 1989. "Coalitions, Incentives and Risk Sharing,"mimeograph,Kyoto University,
Japan.
. 1991. "Incentives to Help in Multi-AgentSituations," 59 Econometrica611-37.
Krueger, Alan. 1991. "Ownership,Agency and Wages: An Examinationof Franchisingin the
Fast Food Industry,"106 QuarterlyJournal of Economic Theory, forthcoming.
Laffont, Jean-Jacques,and Jean Tirole. 1989. "Provision of Quality and Power of Incentive
Schemes in Regulated Industries,"in W. Barnett, B. Coret, C. d'Aspremont,J. Gabsewicz,
and A. Mas-Colell, eds., EquilibriumTheory and Applications. Cambridge:CambridgeUni-
versity Press.
Lazear, Edward. 1989. "Pay Equalityand IndustrialPolitics," 97 Journal of Political Economy
561-80.
52 The Journalof Law,Economics,&Organization,V7 Sp
MacDonald, Glenn. 1984. "New Directions in the Economic Theory of Agency," 17 Canadian
Journal of Economics 415-40.
Milgrom, Paul. 1988. "EmploymentContracts,Influence Activities and EfficientOrganization
Design," 96 Journal of Political Economy 42-60.
, and JohnRoberts. 1988. "An Economic Approachto InfluenceActivities and Organiza-
tional Responses," 94 AmericanJournal of Sociology S154-79.
Minahan, John. 1988. "ManagerialIncentive Schemes and the Divisional Structureof Firms,"
mimeograph, University of Massachusetts.
Riordan, Michael, and David Sappington. 1987. "Information,Incentives and Organizational
Mode," 102 QuarterlyJournal of Economics 243-64.
Simon, Herbert. 1951. "A FormalTheory of the EmploymentRelationship,"19 Econometrica
293-305.
Tirole, Jean. 1986. "Hierarchiesand Bureaucracies:On the Role of Collusion in Organizations,2
Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 181-214.
Williamson, Oliver. 1985. The Economic Institutions of Capitalism. New York: Free Press.