Problems of Axiomatizing Religion

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

Studies in East European Thought (2022) 74:149–163

https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-021-09432-3

Problems of axiomatizing religion

Paul Weingartner1 

Accepted: 17 June 2021 / Published online: 31 August 2021


© The Author(s) 2021

Abstract
The paper discusses problems which arise in attempts to axiomatize parts of religion
or religious belief systems. Besides those problems already investigated by Bochen-
ski, like that of the propositional content or the meaning of religious discourse there
are several further ones. This paper deals with the question whether full Classical
Logic is suitable, whether one universe of discourse is sufficient, how to use defini-
tions and analogous concepts and whether justifications satisfy credibility criteria.

Keywords  Axiomatizing religion · Logical Structure of Religion · Credibility of


religion · Logical Structure of Religious Discourse

In this paper, I shall discuss some problems coming up if one applies logic to reli-
gion in such a way as to axiomatize a part of religion.
As is well known, Bocheński was the first to write a whole book in which he
describes in a detailed way the idea of a logic of religion.1 This book contains a
lot of interesting observations of how a formalization or axiomatization could be
done. In this sense, Bocheński has worked out several important preconditions for
an axiomatization. They are distributed among the three main topics of the book: (1)
Investigating the structure of religious language; (2) Investigating the semantics of
religious discourse; (3) Investigating the justification of religious statements.
This paper is divided into the following chapters:

1. Certain facts concerning the structure of religious language established already


by Bocheński
2. Difficulties when applying the usual classical logic to religion
3. Problems of the Universe of Discourse
4. How to use definitions?
1
  Cf. (Bocheński 1965).

* Paul Weingartner
[email protected]
1
Salzburg University, Franziskanergasse 1, 5020 Salzburg, Austria

13
Vol.:(0123456789)
150
P. Weingartner

5. Analogous concepts and operations


6. The justification of religious statements

Facts established in Bocheński’s logic of religion

Fact 1: Religious believers use a certain language called by Bocheński: Religious


Discourse (RD).
Fact 2: In order to apply logic to RD, at least a part of RD has to be propositional,
i.e., the statements in this part are true or false and are called propositions.
Fact 3: It can easily be proved that a part of the RD of the Judaic—Christian
Religion is propositional: this RD contains profane statements which are historical
or geographical and genuine religious statements which are about God the creator,
Christ’s incarnation, passion and resurrection etc.
Since a part of religion has to be propositional in order to apply logic to it, the
religions referred to in this article are based on a written text. This is most definite
in Judaism (Torah or Pentateuch), Christianity (Old and New Testament) and Islam
(Koran). It is satisfied in a weaker sense for Buddhism (Sutta Pitaka), Hinduism
(Veda) and Confucianism (Lunyü).

Objections to fact 3

In modern Christian theology it is sometimes claimed that genuine religious state-


ments like the following ones and similar ones have to be interpreted symbolically:
“In the beginning God created the heavens and the earth “(Genesis 1,1) or “Jesus
took bread and said: Take and eat, it is my body (…) drink from it (…) it is my
blood’ (…) for the forgiveness of sins” (Mathew 26, 26–28).
And by “symbolically” they mean that the respective sentences are not proposi-
tions that are true or false, but expressions that are neither true nor false. The reason
for such a claim may be twofold: (1) to save or defend religion from attacks of non-
believers, (2) error. As to the first, such a “defense” has the opposite effect since the
claim will be unmasked as swindle or dishonest excuse. God is the creator of the
world or he is not; and a religious believer believes that he is, i.e. that this is true.
Similarly, for the other passages. Of course, critical exegesis is included, but also
critical exegesis cannot turn such propositions into non-committal sentences without
truth-value. As to the second, the claim cannot be correct since it leads to absurd
consequences. Some are as follows:

(a) Religious believer and disbeliever lose its meaning and cannot be distinguished
anymore. There cannot be belief or disbelief in something that is neither true
nor false.
(b) There is no demarcation possible for being or not-being a member of a certain
religion if there is no Creed consisting of propositions.

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 151

(c) If the claim would be correct for genuine religious statements in the Bible, then
logic is not applicable to genuine religious texts. But the latter can be refuted
by showing that important passages of the Bible have a formal valid logical
structure. Two examples are as follows. The first one is a true conditional where
antecedent and consequent are both false. The second one is a derivation by
contraposition.
(i) Thomas Aquinas comments this as follows: “But could Christ say these things
[“I do not know him” and “I would be a liar”]? He could indeed have spoken
the words materially, but not so as to intend expressing a falsehood, because
this could be done only by Christ’s will inclining to falsehood, which was
impossible, just as it was impossible for him to sin. However, the conditional
statement is true, although both antecedent and consequent are impossible.”2
(ii) “Then he [Jesus] turned toward the woman and said to Simon: ‘Do you see this
woman? I came into your house. You did not give me any water for my feet,
but she wet my feet with tears and wiped them with her hair (…) Therefore,
I tell you, her many sins have been forgiven because of her great love. But
whoever has been forgiven little, loves little.’” (Luke 7, 44, 47)

The logical inference by contraposition is this:

Great love ⇒ many sins forgiven.


Therefore: not many (little) sins forgiven ⇒ not great (little) love.

Fact 4: RD contains norms

At the conference “La Nature de la Verite Scientifique” of the Academie Internation-


ale de Philosophie des Sciences (April 27–29, 1981) in Brussels I told Bocheński
that an essential part of RD consists of norms, i.e. of prescriptive statements in addi-
tion to propositions. An important example are the Ten Commandments (Exodus
20,3–17; Deuteronomy 5,7–21). Bocheński agreed that this is an essential part of
RD although he did not consider it in his The Logic of Religion.
Norms can be translated into propositions by using that-clauses or some deontic
operator: That you shall not steal is true. Lying is forbidden. To honour your father
and your mother is obligatory.
The decisive point for our considerations here is that logic and moreover axio-
matic thinking can be applied to such norms of God’s Commandments as systems
of deontic logic show. However, there is the following difference. Deontic Logic is
applied logic and is concerned with the logical relations between norms. Examples
for principles of deontic logic are: If it is obligatory that p (Op) then it is not forbid-
den that p ( ¬ Fp). If it is obligatory that if p then q (O(p → q)) then if it is obligatory
that p (Op) then it is also obligatory that q (Oq): O (p → q) → (Op → Oq). These

2
  Cf. CGJ Section 1285.

13
152
P. Weingartner

principles are formal in the sense that no specific content is mentioned, i.e. it is not
said what is obligatory or what is forbidden.
God’s Commands, however, are contentful informative norms, rules or advices
which say what is obligatory or what is forbidden. Examples for such norms are:
“Honour your father and your mother, so that you may live long in the land the Lord
your God is giving you”; “Love your neighbour as yourself” (Leviticus 19,18; Mat-
thew 22,39; Mark 12,31; Luke 10,27; Galatians 5,14). “Carry each other’s burdens”,
(and in this way you will fulfil the laws of Christ) (Galatians 6,2).
There is however, a most general principle of Natural Law underlying all com-
mands and commandments. It connects values with norms and is also formal: “The
good should be done, the bad should be avoided.”3 This principle is value-scale
invariant and invariant w.r.t. legal orders, i.e. it holds in all legal orders and is inde-
pendent of different hiecharchies of values.

Difficulties when applying classical logic (CL)

Some of the difficulties are very general and not specific concerning the application
to religion; some others are specific. We shall deal with some general ones in this
section and with some specific ones in Sects.  3 and 4. In Sect.  2 we use only the
classical two-valued propositional calculus (CPC).

Principles of CPC which cause difficulties

One example of such a principle is the principle of addition: p ⇒ (p ∨ q). It looks


as a harmless weakening but it is the culprit of the following paradoxes when CL is
applied to empirical science and ethics: Hesse’s confirmation paradox, Goodman’s
paradox, Ross paradox.4 Another example is p ⇒ (q → p). Take p = First Order
Predicate Logic is complete and q = Syllogistics is decidable. Then from First Order
Predicate Logic is complete it follows that both are logically dependent, i.e. if the
second is true, so is the first. Take p = God is allgood, and q = God is not created.
Then from God is allgood it follows that if God is not created then he is allgood.
A further important example which leads to difficulties is that by CL from every
conjunction an equivalence and the respective implications follow logically: (p ∧ q)
⇒ (q ↔ p); (p ∧ q) ⇒ (q → p). Moreover, CL allows that from any two true proposi-
tions p, q the true conjunction p ∧ q can be built.
From such considerations it is plain that this understanding of derivation and
proof is not in accordance with its understanding in mathematics and in science.
No mathematician or scientist would dream to derive from two true theorems or
from two true results (or their respective conjunctions) that they imply each other, or
that one is derivable from the other. Because the two true theorems or the two true

3
  Cf. Thomas (1948), I–II, 94, 2.
4
  For details and proofs see Weingartner (2001).

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 153

results are usually not logically dependent of each other. Take FT to be Fermat’s
Last Theorem (proved by Wiles in 1995) and PT to be the Poincaré Conjecture
(proved by Perelman in 2002) then it would be crazy to claim that FT → PT, because
both are true and can be put into a true conjunction.
Assume that an axiom says that: God is omniscient and God is omnipotent and
God is allgood and God is creator of the universe. Then from this true conjunction
it follows by CPC that all the four parts (conjuncts) imply each other. This is com-
pletely untenable for an attempt to axiomatize religion.

Solution for the difficulties

To avoid this difficulty for axiomatizing religion in ASG (Weingartner 2021a), the
derivations of CL (CPC) are restricted by Intuitionistic Logic and by the relevance
restriction RC (replacement criterion).
RC forbids valid inferences of CPC in which parts of the consequence class can
be replaced by any arbitrary parts (including by their negations) salva validitate of
the inference. Such parts cannot be relevant consequences even if they are the result
of a CPC-valid derivation. RC is defined as follows:
RC α is a relevant (non-redundant) consequence of A if A ├ α or A ⇒ α (accord-
ing to CPC) and it is not the case that a propositional variable is replaceable in α on
some of its occurences by any other propositional variable salva validitate of A ├ α
or A ⇒ α.5
Examples: The following principles are CPC-valid but do not satisfy RC (i.e.,
have irrelevant consequences): p ⇒ (p ∨ q); p ⇒ (q → p); (p ∧ q) ⇒ (q → p); (p ∧ r)
⇒ ((p ∧ q) ∨ (r ∧ ¬q)).
In the first two, q can be replaced by any arbitrary propositional variable (includ-
ing its own negation) salva valididate (of CPC); in the third, the second occurrence
of q and in the fourth both occurrences of q can be replaced by any arbitrary propo-
sitional variable (including its own negation) salva validitate of CPC.6
The third example shows that RC forbids to derive an implication (or equiva-
lence) from a conjunction. Such a derivation is also ruled out by Intuitionistic Logic
which is also satisfied in ASG (with only few exceptions). This understanding of
derivation and proof is in accordance with its understanding in mathematics and in
science.
An axiomatization of religion obeying these logical restrictions has been realized
in ASG in the following sense: A considerable part of Natural (or Philosophical)
Christian Theology (chs. 1–5) and even a part of Christian Theology (ch. 6) has been
described by axioms, definitions and derived theorems. It concerns God’s essence,
omniscience, omnipotence, benevolence, creation (including evil in the world) and

5
  This criterion originates in Schurz and Weingartner (1987), where it serves to rehabilitate Popper’s
theory of verisimilitude. Cf. Weingartner (2000b), Weingartner (2009), and Schurz and Weingartner
(2010) for further development.
6
  The fourth example plays a role in modern physics since it is one form of Bell’s inequalities. Cf. Wein-
gartner (2009, §4).

13
154
P. Weingartner

Incarnation. Ch. 7 contains a consistency proof of a considerable part of ASG with


the help of a model which is a 10-valued decidable logic. A part of this axiomatiza-
tion is also used in THEO (Weingartner 2021c).

Problems of the universe of discourse (UD)

The assumption of First Order Predicate Logic as a part of CL that its UD is non-
empty is very well justified if the individual variables run over things of the universe
or creatures. Since we know that human beings, living things and non-living things
of our universe exist in space and time, the UD for the variables referring to crea-
tures cannot be empty. However, this assumption is too strong if the individual vari-
ables run over persons like God or angels. The reason is that in the non-empty UD
of CL the proposition (∃x) (x = a) is a truth of logic. From this it follows that (∃x)
(x = g) (‘g’ for God), i.e. that God exists. Thus, God’s existence would be a matter of
Classical Logic and this is of course untenable. Therefore, such existence assump-
tions have to be explicitly made by special axioms as it is done in ch. 1 of ASG.
In consequence of that the UD for creatures cannot be the same as the UD for
supernatural beings. Whereas the first must be non-empty the second must be
allowed to be empty. This means that the logic to be applied to religion has to be at
least two-sorted. If trinity is included, as in Christian Religion, we have to assume a
third UD; since the individual variables referring to the three divine persons have to
be different from those, or from the respective individual constant, referring to the
triune God. Therefore, in this case, the underlying logic has to be three-sorted as in
ASG. It also holds of the third UD that it is allowed to be empty. In other words, the
existence of the three divine persons have to explicitly stated by an axiom (axiom
A2 in ASG).
Many articles concerning proofs of the existence of God with the help of formal
logic use only one UD. This means that these articles or their respective authors
do not care to put God together with contingent individuals (his creatures) into one
UD.7 Because of the enormous difference between an infinite, necessary, omnis-
cient, omnipotent (…) etc. being and finite, contingent, fallible, limited (…) etc.
beings such an equalization is completely unacceptable. What has to be done at least
is to restrict variables to creatures or contingent things with the help of restricted
quantifiers: ∀x ∈ W, ∃x ∈ W (for all, some x belonging to the world). Certainly this
means that in cosmological arguments the “bridge” between the world or things of
the world and God has to be explicitly stated in at least one of the premises.
In the discussion to my talk Jan Woleński gave the advice to use “God” as a pred-
icate in order to avoid that his existence follows from the logic of identity. This,
however, is only a preliminary and not a real solution to the problem. It seems first
a solution on the lowest type-level, but the problem comes back with the question to
which entity this predicate belongs. Does this entity belong to the individuals of the
single UD or who is the bearer of this predicate? On the first type level the question

7
  Several examples of this kind can be found in Szatkowski (2012).

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 155

is whether this predicate “G” is just one among the other predicates attributed to the
contingent things etc. Because of such difficulties a two-sorted logic with two differ-
ent universes of discourse seems to be more suitable.

How to use definitions?

Two views of definitions

There are two main-views concerning definitions in the more recent tradition of
logic. The one is due to Russell, described in a short and concentrated way on page
11 of Principia Mathematica (2nd ed. 1927):
“Definitions are (…) strictly speaking, mere typographical conveniences.” “For a
definition is concerned wholly with the symbols, not with what at they symbolize.
Moreover, it is not true or false.” Moreover, the sign “ = Df” is not any functor of
Principia Mathematica, but a sign in the metalanguage combining two expressions
on the level of the object language.8
The other view is that of the Lvov-Warsaw School. In this case definitions are true
equivalences and the sign “⇔” is a functor of the object language of the system. Its
main points—the criteria of eliminability and non-creativity—are due to Lesniewski
and Tarski.9 Already according to Aristotle definitions are true equivalences. And if
the essence concerning a species is defined then the equivalence is necessary. More-
over, Aristotle had a restricted criterion of non-creativity: From a definition no exis-
tential statement can be derived; most importantly it cannot be derived that the refer-
ent of the definiendum or that of the definiens or that of a part of definiens exists.10
The important definitions in mathematics and in science satisfy the view of the
Lvov-Warsaw School, they are true or false. This can be proved by the fact that the
question of their truth or validity is investigated and that they can be revised and
improved by new knowledge. As Kreisel puts it, “the motto ‘Definitions are just
stipulations and therefore neither true (valid) nor false, but a matter of expediency’
is grotesque: since for more than 2000  years some central questions of the form
‘What is (object) X’ are answered by—of course valid—definitions”.11

Definitions in axiomatizations of religion

It is plain that such definitions have to be viewed according to the Lvov-Warsaw


School as true (or approximately true) equivalences. Even if it is a problem to pro-
pose a definition of God at all, it would be ridiculous to call such a definition a

8
  Cf. Weingartner (1989) and (2000a, ch. 5). Merely abbreviations which are sometimes called defini-
tions like ‘U.L.’ for ‘university library’ or DNA do not create problems and do not need a theory of
definitions at all.
9
  Cf. Tarski (1956, ch. X) and Suppes (1957, ch. 8).
10
  Cf. Weingartner (1991).
11
  See (Kreisel et al. 1981, p. 186).

13
156
P. Weingartner

typographical convenience. This also holds in less problematic cases where it is


defined what is meant by saying that God has certain attributes, for example that
God is perfect or that God is eternal.
In such cases a certain peculiarity comes up. Usually, the definiendum contains
a variable that can be universally quantified. Thus, we could try to define x is per-
fect or x is eternal. Then the universe of discourse of these variables would include
either God and creatures or only God. Because of the essential difference(s) between
God and creatures it cannot be accepted to put them both into one universe of dis-
course. Moreover, it would not be a way out to have two separate universes (UD)
and to use superposing variables for the universe of both. Therefore, it can only be
accepted that the respective UD only contains God as a reference since it is clear
from the very beginning that only God can be perfect and eternal. But then it makes
no sense to use variables. In consequence of that such definitions using constant ‘g’
(God), in the definiendum can be viewed like an instance of a virtual universal defi-
nition which in this case does not exist. The situation is similar when we make an
instance of the definition of man:

Definition of man: x ∈ Man ⇔ x ∈ Animal ∧ x ∈ Rational


Definition of: Socrates is a man: s ∈ Man ⇔ s ∈ Animal ∧ s ∈ Rational

This is a particular instance of the above definition of man where ‘s’ is a constant
standing for Socrates. There is an important point to notice here: the first is a defini-
tion of a general concept man and therefore we must have a variable in the definien-
dum. The second definition which is an instance of the first is not a definition of man
but of Socrates is a man. Analogously we do not define perfection and eternity, but
God is perfect and God is eternal. This also holds for the definitions of the other
properties of God like being logically omniscient, logically infallible, or for saying
what it means that God permits or causes some states of affairs.

Analogous operations

Operations

It is evident that knowledge, will and causation must have an analogous meaning,
but cannot have the same meaning in the following two groups of propositions: x
knows that p, x wills that p, x causes that p (where ‘x’ refers to human beings) and g
knows that p, g wills that p, g causes that p (where ‘g’ refers to God).
The strength of the analogy relation depends on stronger or weaker similarity.
Thus if we assume a strong concept of knowledge for human beings then the simi-
larity between x knows and g knows is greater than that between x wills and g wills.
The reason is that it holds: If God knows that p then p is true and if x knows that
p then p is true. For God this also holds for his will and causation: Whatever God
wills obtains and whatever God causes is the case. This does not hold for humans.
Observe that statements as “God wills that men obey his commandments” (which
is not always the case) are no objections, since they are ill formulated. In respect to

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 157

free will actions of men the correct formulation is: God wills that men should obey
his commandments, since God does not destroy men’s free will.
A further difference is that God can direct his will to both to himself and to his
creation, but he can direct his causation only to his creation: God can will his own
goodness but he cannot cause it. For humans it holds that they can direct both will
and causation to themselves and to things different from them. Thus they can will
and cause the improvement in their skills and in their virtues.
Despite a great literature about analogy, there are only few studies which could be
helpful for an axiomatization of religion. One is the seminal article “On Analogy”
by Bocheński which has some preparatory work in Salamucha and Drewnowski as
Bocheński says there in a note. In a further development the concept of analogy is
extended from a relation between two names to a relation among things in general
(including linguistic things).12 I do not know of some work in which analogy rela-
tions among operations or actions are investigated with precise logical means. This
seems to be still a wide and interesting field of research which can serve for axioma-
tizing religion.

Epistemic principles

At the end of this section I shall pick out one question concerning epistemic princi-
ples which are concerned with the analogy of the operations contained in them: The
following two distribution principles for the operation knows are understood as basic
and valid in Epistemic Logic:

(∀p,q)(∀x ∈ H) [xK (p ∧ q) → (x Kp ∧ x Kq)]


(∀p,q) (∀x ∈ H) [xK (p → q) → (x Kp → x Kq)]

Can we assume that these two principles also hold for God? The reason to ask
this question is that in an axiomatization of God’s knowledge and omniscience such
principles could be used as axioms. In ASG the second principle (distribution of
K over → ) is used to prove that God is logically infallible. This could be proved in
another way too, since it is a theorem there that God knows all logical truths. How-
ever, such considerations lead to an important point: Every axiomatization of reli-
gion is an axiomatization of our understanding of God and of religious statements
concerned in a more direct or indirect way with God. This does not mean that such
an approach is only subjective, since it may be supported by the revealed text of
the Bible. However, any such axiomatization, even if best supported by biblical and
Church Documents is not an axiomatization of God’s thoughts, since:
“For my thoughts are not your thoughts neither are your ways my ways” (Isaiah
55,8).

12
  Bochenski (1948), Cf. Weingartner (1976, ch. 6.4; 1979; 1998/1999).

13
158
P. Weingartner

Nevertheless, investigations whether God’s thoughts as revealed in the Bible


(according to critical exegesis) obey the law of non-contradiction are valuable13
since they help us to have a consistent interpretation and understanding of the
texts and of God. Moreover, they help to refute wrong attacks and logical fallacies
brought forward against religion.

The justification of religious statements

In chapter V of his The Logic of Religion Bocheński discusses the justification of


religious discourse. Besides of other strategies he describes a very important kind
of justification of religious statements by epistemic authority. Both concepts, that of
epistemic authority and that of deontic authority are inventions of Bocheński him-
self and have been defined and described by him.14 I shall discuss the problem of the
justification of religious statements from another point of view: From the credibility
of belief systems; more specifically from a comparison of the credibility between
scientific belief systems (SBS) and religious belief systems (RBS).
Observe that it is justified to talk of scientific belief-systems: Most of what sci-
entists “know” they believe their colleagues. What they genuinely know is relatively
small in proportion to that what they believe. Of course, they believe their col-
leagues in a rationally justified way, since they trust their results which are based on
an accepted scientific methodology. Subsequently I shall formulate two criteria and
two norms for the credibility (CRD) of a belief system (BS) which are applicable to
the CRD of religion.15

Criterion 1 for the credibility of religion

Upper bound for the credibility of a belief‑system

Thesis 1: For every particular belief system concerning some domain, there is an
upper bound for the credibility of it. This upper bound is a threshold beyond which a
rational justification of that belief system is impossible.
Example: Assume the belief system to be Physics. Then the requirement that the
degree of credibility is verfication is beyond the upper bound. As is well-known,
verification of universal physical laws is impossible. We cannot investigate all met-
als in the universe in order to verify: all metals, when heated, expand. We cannot
verify E = mc2; not only because most of the masses of the universe are not acces-
sible to us but also because of the technical difficulties to convert mass into energy.
On the other hand corroboration by testing consequences of the laws is below the
upper bound and is therefore a candidate for credibility.

13
  Cf. Heller (2019) and ASG Section 1.5.1.
14
  Bocheński (1965 Appendix 51.1) and Bocheński (1988 ch.1).
15
  A detailed study “On the Credibility of Religion” will appear in the journal Theologie und Philoso-
phie 2021 (Weingartner 2021b).

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 159

Requirement for religious belief systems

Norm 1: It should not be required that the degree dr of credibility (CRD) for
a particular religious belief system (RBS) must be higher than the degree ds of
CRD for any scientific belief system (SBS).
Since it cannot be required that the degree ds of SBS is higher than its upper
bound (which would make a rational justification of SBS impossible) this cannot
be required either of the degree dr of CRD for any RBS.

Internal consistency

Is it rationally justifiable to require internal consistency for the CRD of a BS?

The answer to this question depends very much on whether the whole of a huge
BS is concerned or only certain parts of it. We consider first the whole of certain
BS.

(1) Take SBS to be the whole of mathematics; or take ZF-Set Theory of NBG-Set
Theory from which a great part of whole mathematics can be deduced. Then to
require a proof of internal consistency for the CRD of SBS is beyond the upper
bound; this follows from Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem.
(2) Take SBS to be the whole of physics. Then to require internal consistency of
the CRD of SBS goes beyond the upper bound (we may say, at least so far). In
CM (Classical Mechanics) an object has a continuous trajectory and has identity
over time. In QM (Quantum Mechanics) a QM-object does not have a continuous
trajectory and is (as an individual object) not identifiable over time; Identity over
time holds only for the kind of objects (electrons, neutrons, photons, protons,…
etc.) because of permutation invariance. There are further well-known incom-
patibilities.
(3) Take RBS to be the whole Christian Revelation documented in the canonical
scriptures. This is defined by the Synode of Rome (382) and the councils of
Florence (1442) and Trent (1546). Cf. Denzinger (2005) D179, 180, 1335, 1502,
1503. These are scriptures of the Old and New Testament.

Should we require a proof for the internal consistency of the whole Christian
Revelation documented in the canonical scriptures of the Old and New Testa-
ment? It follows from (1) and (2) above together with Norm 1 that this should
not be required. Since the requirement for showing the internal consistency of
the most strongest scientific domains, mathematics and physics, goes beyond the
upper bound of credibility it should not be required for a religious BS either.

13
160
P. Weingartner

Is it rationally justifiable to require internal consistency for the CRD of an essential


part of a huge BS?

We think that such a requirement is rationally justifiable and does not go beyond
the upper bound for CRD of a huge BS. This can be substantiated as follows:
Gentzen proved the consistency of First Order Peano Arithmetic; the theory of
real closed fields is consistent and decidable. Classical Mechanics (CM) is appar-
ently internal consistent, although some hidden assumptions like universal time
and simultaneity are external inconsistent with SR (Special Theory of Relativity).
SR seems to be internal and external consistent.
The internal consistency for the CRD of an essential part, seems also to be ration-
ally justified for a religious belief system (RBS). An example for an essential part of
a RBS is the “Creed”. As Bocheński (1965, 3.4) says the Creed of a religion is of
such an importance that a person can be called a member of a certain religion if s/he
believes all the statements of the respective Creed. As is clear from 1.2 we have to
add the belief in the validity of norms for example the Ten Commandements. Since
the Creed is of such an importance for a religion—this holds especially for Judaism,
Christianity and Islam, because their Creed is based on written texts—it is rationally
justified to require internal consistency of the respective Creed. This is the more the
case because it holds for the respective religion or RBS that the Creed should be
believed (or is obligatory to be believed) by every member of the respective religion.

Criterion 2 for the credibility of religion

Lower bound for the credibility of a belief‑system

Thesis 2: For every particular BS concerning some domain there is a lower bound
for the credibility of it. This lower bound is a threshold below which a rational justi-
fication of that BS is impossible or hardly possible.
Examples:

(1) Take the BS to be the cosmological theory of the Big Bang. This theory has
three strong supports: The expansion of the universe, the singularity theorems
of Hawking and Penrose and the discovery of the cosmic background radiation
by Penzias and Wilson. Assume now that none of these supports were true or
available: The universe would be static and not expanding (Einstein’s original
conjecture), no singularity theorem could be proved and the cosmic background
radiation has not been discovered or did not exist. Then the credibility of the
Big Bang theory would be below its lower bound; a rational justification would
hardly be possible.
(2) Take the BS to be the Torah (the first five books of the Old Testament). The
second book of the Torah the book “Exodus” describes the exodus of the people
of Israel from Egypt (see Ex 12,17;31. 13,8;14.23,15). It happened during the
government of Ramses II (1304-1237). This description has further support
in other books of the Bible. First in book Leviticus (23,43) and Deuteronomy

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 161

(6,20-23; 16,1; 26, 5-10) which both belong to the Torah. Second in the Psalms
(Ps 78; 12,43,51), in Joshua (4,23) and in Judges (8,23) all belonging to the Old
Testament. Third there are supports in the New Testament, for example Acts
7,6;36. Heb 3,16; 8,9, Jude 5. It is presupposed that these supports are the result
of critical exegesis. Suppose now that except the description of the exodus in
the book “Exodus” there is no mentioning of this important historical fact in
any other part of the Bible (Old and New Testament). Then the credibility of
the exodus would be on the boarder of the lower bound or below it. A rational
justification for such a disconnectedness to other parts of the Bible would hardly
be possible.
(3) Similar justifications or reasons for the credibility being higher than the lower
bound can be given for Christ’s incarnation, for his passion and for his resurrec-
tion.

Requirement for religious belief systems

Norm 2: If it is required that the degree ds of CRD for any SBS is higher than or
equal to the lower bound d (ds ≥ d) then it should also be required that the degree dr
of CRD for any RBS is higher than or equal to d (dr ≥ d).
Since it cannot be permitted that the degree ds of SBS is lower than its lower
bound (which would make a rational justification of SBS impossible) this cannot be
permitted either of the degree dr of CRD for any RBS. Therefore: If the permission
that the degree ds of CRD of any SBS is lower than d (ds < d) leads to the impos-
sibility of a rational justification of SBS then it is not permitted that the degree dr of
CRD for any RBS is lower than d (dr < d).

The question of circularity

There is some difficulty from which all RBS seem to suffer

One important reason in order to keep the degree of CRD for RBS above the lower
bound is that the text is revealed by God. However that this text is revealed by God
is said only by this very text itself and is not guaranteed by some source outside.
Thus there is no ultimate external resource that can provide an absolute justification
for the RBS as based on a text as revealed. When it is said that Moses or the apostles
have been witnesses and made proof by observation (hearing the voice of God or
seeing and hearing Christ) then the problem is that we know this only from that very
text which should be made credible by Moses or by the Apostles. It seems that this
kind of circularity cannot be escaped.

It is an interesting fact, however, that this kind of circularity has a striking analogy


in science

An example is the experimental tests for corroborating or confirming the Special


Theory of Relativity (SR). The underlying methodological assumptions are these:

13
162
P. Weingartner

(i) Physical measurement instruments (rods and clocks) are real physical objects,
not ideal entities. (ii) Because of (i) they have to obey physical laws. But which
ones? According to the Copenhagen-Interpretation, quantum–mechanical phenom-
ena have to be measured by a measurement instrument “outside” the QM-System
which obeys the laws of Classical Mechanics. Einstein refused this view for both,
his Theory of Relativity and for Quantum Mechanics. Therefore, he required (iii).
(iii) The measurement instruments (rods and clocks) applied to test the Special The-
ory of Relativity (SR) have to obey the laws of SR:
It is plain that assumption (iii) leads to a kind of circularity: The measurement
instruments which are used to test SR presuppose and obey the laws of SR since
they are real physical objects and not ideal independent measures.
Does this mean that such a test is not reliable? As the facts show, this is not the
case and moreover reveals that this is the only way to test predictions of SR, i.e.,
time-dilatation (tested by Hafele and Keating16) and mass-increase (tested by parti-
cle accelerators).

The situation in both cases of circularity is this

The test for the confirmation of SR or RBS is made either by instruments ruled by
SR or by events described in RBS, in neither case independent of SR or RBS. In
general, such a situation reveals a fact which we have learned from the Theory of
Relativity: We cannot have an ultimate external measurement apparatus outside and
separated from the physical system to be measured by it.
Similarly, there is no external absolute last resort, available to us now, and inde-
pendent of RBS, which could be used to confirm RBS. Every test of SBS or of RBS
is relative in this sense without being unreliable.

Funding  Open access funding provided by Paris Lodron University of Salzburg.

Conflict of interest  The author declares that there is no conflict of interests.

Open Access  This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Com-
mons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article
are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the
material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is
not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission
directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creat​iveco​mmons.​org/​licen​
ses/​by/4.​0/.

16
  Hafele and Keating (1972).

13
Problems of axiomatizing religion 163

References
Bocheński, J. M. (1948). On analogy. The Thomist, 11, 474–497.
Bocheński, J. M. (1965). The logic of religion. New York: New York University Press.
Bocheński, J. M. (1988). Autorität, Freiheit, Glaube. Sozialphilosophische Studien. München: Philoso-
phia Verlag.
Denzinger, H. (2005). Enchiridion symbolorum definitionum et declarationum de rebus fidei et morum.
Kompedium der Glaubensbekenntnisse und kirchlichen Lehrentscheidungen. Ed. P.Hünermann.
40th. Edition, Freiburg: Herder.
Hafele, J. C., & Keating, R. E. (1972). Around the world atomic clocks. Science, 177, 166–170.
Heller, M. (2019). The logic of god. Edukacja Filozoficzna, 68, 227–244.
Kreisel, G., et al. (1981). Zur Bewertung mathematischer Definitionen. In E. Morscher (Ed.), Philosophie
als Wissenschaft/Essays in scientific philosophy (pp. 185–207). Bad Reichenhall: Comes Verlag.
Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (1987). Verisimilitude defined by relevant consequence-elements. A new
reconstruction of Popper’s original idea. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth: A parade
of approaches to truthlikeness (pp. 47–77). Amsterdam: Rodopi.
Schurz, G., and Weingartner, P. (2010). Zwart and Franssen’s impossibility theorem holds for possible-
world-accounts to verisimilitude. Synthese, 172(3), 415–436.
Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Szatkowski, M. (2012). Ontological proofs today. Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos.
Tarski, A. (1956). Logic, semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thomas, A. (1948). Summa Theologica vol. 5. Transl. by Fathers of the English Dominican Province.
Christian Classics. Maryland: Westminster. Reprinted: 1981. Abbreviated as STh.
Thomas, A. (2010). Commentary on the Gospel of St. John. Part II. Ed. J.A. Weisheipl and F. Larcher.
Petersham, Mass.: St. Bede’s Publications. Abbreviated as CGJ.
Weingartner, P. (1976). Wissenschaftstheorie II, 1. Grundlagenprobleme der Logik und Mathematik.
Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.
Weingartner, P. (1979). Analogy among systems. Dialectica, 33, 355–378.
Weingartner, P. (1989). Definitions in Russell, in the Vienna-Circle and in the Lvov-Warsaw School. In
K. Szaniawski (Ed.), The Vienna Circle and the Lvov-Warsaw School (pp. 225–247). Dordrecht:
Kluwer.
Weingartner, P. (1991). A note on Aristotle’s theory of definition and scientific explanation. In W. Spohn
(Ed.), Existence and Explanation (pp. 207–217). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Weingartner, P. (1998/99) Bocheński: Attempts to apply logic to problems of religion. Philosophia Scien-
tia, 3(4), 175–198.
Weingartner, P., et al. (2000). Reasons for filtering classical logic. In D. Batens (Ed.), Frontiers of para-
consistent logic (pp. 315–327). Baldock: Research Studies Press.
Weingartner, P. (2000a). Basic questions of truth. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Weingartner, P. (2001). Applications of logic outside logic and mathematics: Do such applications force
us to deviate from classical logic? In W. Stelzner (Ed.), Zwischen traditioneller und moderner Logik
(pp. 53–64). Paderborn: Mentis.
Weingartner, P. (2009). Matrix based logic for application in physics. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 2,
132–163.
Weingartner, P. (2021a). An axiomatic study of god. A defence of the rationality of religion. Berlin, De
Gruyter. Abbreviated as ASG.
Weingartner, P. (2021b). On the credibility of religion. Theologie und Philosophie.
Weingartner, P. (2021c). Theodicy—From a logical point of view. Berlin: Peter Lang. Abbreviated as
THEO.

Publisher’s Note  Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published
maps and institutional affiliations.

13
Studies in East European Thought is a copyright of Springer, 2022. All Rights Reserved.

You might also like