Antigone and Identity
Antigone and Identity
Antigone and Identity
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Blackwell Publishing and Law and Society Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Law & Society Review.
http://www.jstor.org
12
Comnary
CarolJ. Greenhouse
ready among the dead, she does not appear at the end of the
play with the other charactersto mourn the death of Antigone.
The action of the playsharpensthe focus on particulardiffer-
ences in the relationshipbetween Ismene's and Antigone's rela-
tionship to the state as women. Ismene is a sympatheticcharac-
ter, but Antigone is heroic. Ismene's choice is an ordinaryone.
She prefers to live.Antigone, in refusingchoice, places herself in
a literally impossible unlivable position. Importantly (and
this is essential to what follows here), we need bothcharactersto
understandthe course that eqwt)r takes. In other words,we need
bothcharactersand their respective tragedies to comprehend the
force of circumstancesupon their spirits, and to take the mea-
sure of their loss in our own lives.
Ismene and Antigone live in the world Creon made: choices
frame events, events shape experience, experiences add up to
(or cancel) a lifetime, and so on but the world is still Creon's.
In such a world, Creon will alwaysinsist that Antigone's act was a
choice; this is how he legitimates his punishing authority. But
Antigone has notchosen; she has acted. Her act is the extension
of her birth. Her act is not an event;it is her meaning as a self, a
"meaning-event"(Foucault 1977:174). Antigone insists on her
own sel£referentiality;she enters the play alreadyjustifed.5
By a fatal confusion, Creon himself is blocked from seeing
the connections in which Antigone constitutesher claims to per-
sonhood. Creon cannot see the justice in Antigone's act because
he views her act as her choice;he cannot imaglne otherwise be-
cause he also mistakesher beingfor her gender.Twice,he saysthat
he will not be ruled by a woman (11.526, 678-80), in the context
of sealing his case againsther. Creon'snotion of a woman'sgen-
der is the one that Ismene embodies in the play constituted in
obedience to laws,or, to be even more specific, in events in time
(e.g. acts of law or lawmaking,acts of obedience). Antigone re-
fuses to acknowledgethis specific concept of "woman"because it
would subdivideher personhood (pitting subject against sister),
makingit impossiblefor her to act in accordwith timeless princi-
ples of justice.
These inflections of gender, agency, power and temporality
develop aroundAntigone's character.Antigone alone in the play
5 In Sophocles' version of the play, Antigone's self-sufficiency is underscored by her
exalted liminality: she is between girlhood and womanhood (see, e.g., 11.578-79), and
between betrothal and marriage; the action of the play is staged outdoors, outside palace
doors and city gates, and, ultimately, at the mouth of a cave. At the same time, though she
might be self-sufficient, Antigone's self is not autonomous. Her self encompasses the
"children of [her] mother's womb", and all the citizens who are too "cowed" by Creon to
speak (1. 509; see also Haemon's speech, 11. 683-723). While her self-referentiality
removes her from the realm of choice, her inclusion of others within her personal mean-
ing hints at other (rival) canvases of self-realization. Similarly, she explains her "defiant"
act as an acknowledgment of the compass of divine agency, especially in her sense of the
burial rite as a sacred personal duty. Her act is her own, but her agency is not individual,
as Creon would have it.
Greenhouse 1237
never refers to her gender, nor even to the man she was to have
married (withthe exception of her lament en route to her death,
11.813-14). She does not "have"a gender. Shets.And Antigone is
the first to point to the temponalflaw in Creon's reasoning, in
her distinction between his order and the "unfailinglaws"of the
gods (1.455). The Chotus reiteratesher temporal distinctionbe-
tween laws in time and timeless laws (11.602-13).6 Again, Creon
sees a distinctionbetween Antigone's logic and his own, but, see-
ing Antigone as a woman, he initiallyunderstandsher insurrec-
tion only in relation to her disobedience. Only later does he see
that her insurrectionwas lodged against more than his rule it
was also against his injustice.
Until the end of the play, the disobedient act is all-important
for Creon, since his own centralityas the ordering principle of
the kingdom prerequiresa worldof events,constitutedin choices.
It is only by this means that he can interpellate himself in the
autobiographies of his subjects, short of sentencing them to
death. For Antigone, too, meaning is constituted in acts; how-
ever, the origin of her actions is not in her choices, but her per-
sonhood. Ismene's agency is of the other kind. Their doubled
figure puts the disjunctionbetween being and choosing squarely
at stage center. This disjuncturereturnsus to the essaysby Espe-
land and Gooding.
Real-World
Choicesand ie Myi of Freedom
Thinking in terms of"cultural constructions"is the begin-
ning of a challenge to the pervasivenotion that social life consists
of a succession of individual decisions occasioned by the need
and opportunityto maximize self-interest.There might seem to
be little room around this notion-and less need for it given its
centrality as an organizing principle of many institutions and
practices associated with dominant formulations of modernity.
Yet room must be found, if people's "choices"are to be under-
stood for what they are, animatedby powerfulneeds and hedged
by powerfillconstraints. At issue in the problem of the law'srole
in the culturalconstructionof identities is a series of distinctions:
between being and choosing, power and politics, meanings and
events, names and things, agency and organization,demands for
justice and practicesof recognition.
Espeland and Gooding, in different ways,address this proW
lem by making questions of identity secondary to a prior ques-
6 The full passage (11.452-57) reads:uNordid I thinkyour orderswere so strong/
thatyou, a mortalman, could over-run/ the gods' unwrittenand unfailinglaws./ Not
now, nor yesterday's,they alwayslive, / and no one knows their origin in time."The
Chonssechoes this temporal distinctionlater (11.602-13): uWhatmadness of man, O
Zeus,can bind your power?/ . . . Unaged in time / monarch you rule of Olympus'
gleaminglight. / Near time, far future,and the past, / one law controlsthem all: / any
greatnessin human life bringsdoom."
1238 ConstlucJdve
Approachesto Law, Culture,and Idelltit,r
References
Agnew,Jean-Chnstophe (1986) Worlds Apart:TheMatet and theTheater in Anglo
Arrcan Thought,1550-1750. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Clifford, James (1988) "Identity in Mashpee," in J. Clifford, ThePredicarnwnt of
Culture.Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.
Comaroff,Jean &John (1991) 1 OfRevelation and Revolution. Chicago: Univ. of
Chicago Press.
Cooper, Frederick, & Ann Stoler (1989) "Tensions of Empire: Colonial Control
and Visions of Rule," 16 Ameracan Ethnologist609.
Foucault, Michel (1977) Language,Counter-manery, Practice:SelectedEssaysandIn-
toviews,trans. D. F. Bouchard & S. Simon. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press.
Grene, David, & Richmond Lattimore (1954) Sophocles I. Chicago: Univ. of Chi-
cago Press.
Lazarus-Black,Mindie (1994) Legitimate ActsandIllegalEncounters: Lawand Soci-
etyin AntiguaandBarbuda.Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press.
Lazarus-Black,Mindie, & Susan Hirsch, eds. (1994) Contested States:Law,Hegem-
ony,and Resistance. New York: Routledge.
Mertz, Elizabeth (1988) "The Uses of History: Language, Ideology and Law in
the United States and South Africa," 22 Law e Society Rev.661.
Steiner, George (1984) Antigones.Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.