Austin, S. - Parmenides Being, Bounds, and Logic
Austin, S. - Parmenides Being, Bounds, and Logic
Austin, S. - Parmenides Being, Bounds, and Logic
sie)
ieee ueeae
aes
raisers pert
oe
iyaaleesoaae Ss
aan
at
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2020 with funding from.
Kahle/Austin Foundation
https://archive.org/details/parmenidesbeingbOOO0aust
.
Parmenides
scorrausnn Parmen ides
Being, Bounds, and Logic
{
! | Megan Memorial Libr
Cumberland Coll
ary”
aze
, Williamsburg,
KY 40769
xa we BEd
TOOPOWV
vmedéEato
tewveeere: ames tabs
neil
(a 9 widiate ex ©wale 2. wl 7
penne: 2 One ay tas0 Eee, onih
ae wie: Speei yeep abet Pl
panier ee “+ i 8)
* A ; ae
Ven Sores pil cltomier & yenderccelt Ge pa a oe » 1 s
1 . es ® ae . os 7 ‘ fae, 7 'aa
pret kon
a A "Fab
9
inane =
. "7 at,
z9
» ne
= oe
ie Bh F 7 oa¥.
Bt ate 4 vx. pedi - \ < 7
C as
ees
&e
‘> s
on i
f; 1Ne
‘ -¥ i
e
a 3
‘
ai a i
, r . a
ay i i
AYics ch atea
nae wen yy
Yr. 7
v i
Contents
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
INTRODUCTION
vii
(hae
Pi .
| ve
i eu
p=; Piedie Pp ae
ee ’ ¥
af
v
4 / -
‘4 ;
! ae ;
»
» ¥ Ti
ol a
7 i»
=,
re)
Ao ok aah; :f vite
cesar Oh ie, Oe
i Swat ae «aU I
a@et
toa®
- x
as xf -
™~ ao
cm : ~ Ki 7
: oo ihe 5
ig’ ; yj f B 1 :
1 ; !
i Whalen Aa - oy
rt , t, 5
} ie Paton 7 2 hae
: Air ent ae 2 -
: ’ 7 Ps i ‘ ii wy A
iG ae eNO ten *
¢ , 5 i. 5
r ee ta Ala
1:Te abey
eid ; haa
a
f he
re :
Soe ]
a
7
D
Pa iy 7 |
Pi Zs
ey,
. i i Ny
Acknowledgments
ix
x ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
and flexibility. Thanks to Bruno Scherz for keeping Apollo and Dionysos
in balance with a laugh. Thanks to Kenneth Edelman for his aqua-
fraternal faith, and to him and Denise Hemmerly, Christian Sees, James
Sabat, Steven Plotnick, and Jeff Goodman for warm fellowship. Thanks
to my family for years of love and support and kind enlightenment in
the text of the world. And to Susan Zaleski-Austin, for her gracious
wisdom and love and editorship and all else that is hers, this book is
dedicated.
:)
aa tt 6 :
—
’
_ ; - ‘ ’ ¥ 7.
nycy Te ie cha #
“Aeshty ar Goh Ps
hie Aaa’ sagan eens
ne «peeeiis APE k We thw
‘ Bae a (tights pie eee
an i
Us 1ib.S agra aaa
+5 oie ie beset ee
-
rc oe oyone
7 Sire
Introduction
The epigraph is from Thomas Traherne, Centuries of Meditation, Third Century, sec. 21,
lines 7-8, in H. M. Margoliouth, ed., Thomas Traherne: Centuries, Poems, and Thanksgivings,
vol. I, p. 122. “Becaus” (sic) is what Margoliouth prints in the former quotation.
Z INTRODUCTION
man, one who (we are told) knows, far from the beaten track of humanity,
in a chariot drawn by cunning mares. Traveling at tremendous speed,
escorted by the maiden daughters of the sun, he arrives at Hesiod’s’
huge, lintel-surmounted gates, where the paths of night and day con-
verge at the edge of the world—the gates are guarded and locked by the
figure of avenging Justice. This is a place beyond, and also at the source
of, the contrariety and opposition characteristic of ordinary human life.
It takes the maidens to persuade Justice to let him through with his
train—the gates strain open—but, once admitted, he is given the gra-
cious welcome appropriate to a Homeric hero. The goddess who greets
him reassures the charioteer that, though his route has been an unusual
one, he is not doomed but, in fact, has been conducted along by Rightness
and Justice. And she promises him an account, not only of the unshaking
heart of truth, but also of the opinions of mortals, in which there is not
true trust. The epic quest for victory and homecoming has now been
transformed by Parmenides into the search for truth, and the youth, like
Odysseus and Telemachus, is about to receive further positive and neg-
ative directions along the road to ultimate reality.®
This is a fascinating prologue, and commentators since ancient times
have attempted to find meaning in it: it is a shaman’s journey, an Orphic
allegory, a secularization of the Phaethon myth, a conceptualized version
of the journey of the Homeric hero to his home and goal, a journey to
a place where normal distinctions between opposites break down.° The
last two are certainly part of the poetic apparatus, which works by in-
corporating themes from other literary works, especially Homer and
Hesiod, but the general purpose of the chariot ride is clear and can be
apprehended by the imagination alone. A young man journeys toafar-
away place with tremendous urgency under the protection and guidance
of maidens; the topography of his journey is one in which the normal
directions of up and down are muddled; after penetrating through a
gate guarded by an initially severe female figure, he receives a warm
welcome from another female, his superior, who proceeds to initiate him
into the right path and course of inquiry to follow. This (I believe) non-
controversial description of the journey, if seen as the product of some-
one’s imagination, should allow us to sidestep controversies about timing,
topography, underlying metaphors, religious overtones, and direction.
Initiation, illumination, katabasis (descent), homecoming, the reception
of adulthood—all are ways of describing the journey and its meaning;
and metaphors from mystery, epic quests, and cosmic archetypes of all
sorts will lie beneath the surface simply because of the nature of the
subject matter, regardless of whether the author intended to evoke them
specifically. We need not try to excavate them all as distinct from each
a Na Ae See me
other. And surely there is an element in the initial story which, though
the Parmenidean voyager is male, could be generalized into a universal
human content for all philosophical imaginations.
The rest of the poem (fragments 2—19) is taken up with the goddess’s
speech. It is usually divided into the two parts she promises to deliver:
the account of truth (fragments 2—8.51) and the account of mortal opin-
ion (fragments 8.51—19). Fragments 2—7 Of the “Truth” section prepare
the way for the extended deduction of the transcendental attributes of
reality that takes place in fragment 8.
The “Truth” section, then, begins in fragment 2 with the enunciation
of two “routes” or “ways” of inquiry. Both routes are described rather
elliptically: the first, the “path of persuasion,” as the route “that it is and
that it is not possible for it not to be”; the second as the route “that it is
not and that it is right that it should not be”’—“And this,” says the god-
dess, “I point out to you as a completely uninformative route: for neither
could you get to know what is not (for it cannot be completed) nor could
you point it out.”!° As the poem continues, these brief route-descriptions
are expanded; everything incompatible with saying how it is is rejected
as inappropriate in a description of being, of what-is, and an attempt is
made to separate the two routes clearly from each other, so that the
positive one can then be chosen. There is much disagreement among
scholars about the meaning of these compressed requirements and pro-
hibitions and the nature and number of the routes they generate.!! (For
a summary of some current hypotheses, see chapter 1.)
The goddess continues her discussion of the routes in fragment 6:
being, the object of the route that it is, must have some connection with
language and thought, for it can be, whereas nothing cannot. The god-
dess bars the youth from the route of nonbeing, but also bars him from
the mixed route taken by mortals, those two-headed creatures whose
straying minds are steered by Helplessness, who are tossed about like a
senseless swarm of the deaf and blind, who consider being and nonbeing
to be the same and not the same.
Thus far, then, we have three routes: one of what-is, the route of
persuasion and truth; one of what-is-not, which is completely uninfor-
mative, and one taken by mortals, who attempt to mix the two routes.
After this point in the fragments we have, the route of what-is-not is
discussed only as rejected, and the route of mortals is given full exem-
plification in the “Opinion” section. It remains, then, for the deductions
of fragment 8 to present to us the route of what-is, the route of truth.
Along the route of what-is, the goddess says, are many signposts as to
how being is ungenerable, unperishing, a whole of a single kind, un-
moving, and perfect. These are the transcendental predicates of being,
or what-is. What-is is the subject of the route how it is, the subject about
INTRODUCTION sic aca tien
be the truth, the implicit and single object of all language. Parmenides
is thus the first metaphysician (or, if you prefer, theologian) to argue for
those eternal attributes also shared by Plato’s Forms, by Aristotle’s pri-
mary movers, and by their descendants in the history of philosophy. This
picture of the truth as a single, abiding whole is next contrasted with the
picture the mortals subscribe to. The “Opinion” section of the poem is,
in fact, a plausible cosmology of the pre-Socratic type, a description of
the world we think we live in, done in great detail and with tremendous
richness of scope.
The mortals begin by separating two cosmic opposites—fire and
night—in familiar pre-Socratic style, and filling the cosmos with them in
such a way as to leave no gaps, at least at the beginning of the cosmic
process (fragment 8, lines 51-61, fragment 9). Descriptions are then
given of ether, sun, and moon (fragment 10), the encircling heaven, the
earth, and the stars (fragment 11), a system of cosmic rings of fire and
night containing a Damon (a divine or semidivine being) who is respon-
sible for the blending of the sexes in copulation (fragment 12), the cre-
ation of Love (fragment 13), the statement (apparently for the first time
in the West) that the moon receives her light from the sun (fragments
14-15), a discussion of the relative placements of the sexes on different
sides of the womb during embryological development (fragment 17), a
theory of the generation of gay men (fragment 18), and a concluding
statement seeming once again to suggest that the entire scheme is the
work of mortal nomenclature and classification (fragment 19). With this
the goddess completes the sketch of the misleading opinions of others
that she had promised to the youth, “so that no mortal judgment will
ever outstrip you.” And yet it is a little surprising to find such a wealth
of detail in the descriptions of unstable and changing objects from the
philosopher of an immutable cosmic Entity.
It seems that, though the propositions of “Opinion” about the sensible
world are not ones that the goddess will herself assent to, there is still
something that we, as mortals, are supposed to learn from her descrip-
tion of our world. Scholars have disagreed widely about what that some-
thing is, all the way from seeing the “Opinion” section as a serious
exposition of Parmenidean doctrine to discarding it as Parmenides’ re-
jection of the sensible world as a mere error.'* What are we supposed to
learn? First, “Opinion” contains many descriptions that recall, and yet
are ironically distanced from, the descriptions of being given in
“Truth.”!® Fire, one of the two elements separated off by mortals at the
beginning of “Opinion,” is “in every way the same with itself and not the
same with the other” (i.e., with Night). The assertion about sameness is
also made about being, as if Fire were trying to imitate the solidity and
substantiality of being; but the assertion about difference would not be
INTRODUCTION 7
said of being, and it represents the respect in which the entities of opin-
ion reveal themselves as copies and caricatures. Second, the two sexes,
which are distinguished as opposites by the mortals, just as Fire and
Night were, immediately try to overcome this distinction and (as Par-
menides sees it) revert to some kind of more primal unity in the phe-
nomena of copulation and homosexuality, thus undercutting the sharp
boundaries which the mortals in vain try to set up between their oppo-
sites. These opposites, which try to mimic the isolation and distinctive-
ness of being, end up (as he sees it) mixed together in a parody of
themselves in different forms of human sexuality. The irony here is sup-
posed to make us see the ontological values of “Truth” as imperfectly
mirrored, or only temporarily attained, in the entities of “Opinion.”
But “Opinion” is more than a piece of profound irony; it is also (or,
perhaps, consequently) a serious attempt to describe things, in consid-
erable detail, as we do in fact perceive them. This aspect of “Opinion”
has often raised suspicions that Parmenides had a serious motive in writ-
ing it. And yet there is no incongruity in supposing that an author,
convinced of the derivativeness or unreality of the sensible world, could
nevertheless try to describe that world as exactly as possible. In fact, the
better the description, the more effective the irony would be, as if Par-
menides had said to his cosmological contemporaries: “I can give as good
a descriptive account of the cosmos as you can, starting from a pair of
contraries. But, since I have already shown in “Truth” that the logic of
contraries only mirrors and distorts the logic of being, it follows that,
since the sensible cosmos has been shown to derive from contraries, such
a cosmos is only a reflection in a moving pool of waters of an unchanging
sun above.” In this way a serious sensible cosmology is at the same time
an ironic reductio ad absurdum of the sensible world. (See chapters 1
and 4 for more discussion of “Opinion.”)
With the end of “Opinion,” then, the goddess has delivered on the
promise she made to the youth at the beginning, to show forth and show
through not only the truth but also the untrustworthy opinions of mor-
tals. It remains for us to explore in more detail just what she thought
was right about “Truth” and wrong with the route of what-is-not and
the mixed route of opinion. In chapter 1, I attempt to describe what
exactly the goddess requires and prohibits. One scholarly issue arises
from the puzzling fact that, though the goddess prohibits discourse about
what-is-not, her own discourse is full of negative words and expressions,
thus seeming inconsistent. I try to arrive at an interpretation of her
prohibition which does not make her rule out the language that she
herself uses, which clears her of some inconsistencies by allowing her to
mean what she says, negatively as well as positively. In the process I
attempt to determine what Parmenides thought were the ultimate rela-
BE EEE CRON
tionships among ontology, sentence structure, and logic. I also claim that
Parmenides’ attitude towards contextual relativity determines what is
right about “Truth” and wrong about “Opinign.” This claim, if correct,
allows us to make connections between Parmenides, the Sophists, Plato,
and Aristotle, connections which are taken up again and historically am-
plified in chapter 5. This first chapter is the most controversial in its
claims. Chapter 2, taking as its premise the goddess’s use of different
sorts of positive and negative language, tries to determine just how many
sorts of language there are, how comprehensive the coverage of them is,
and why certain sorts occur in specific places in the poem. In this chapter,
I claim that Parmenides deliberately set out to use, in a systematic and
comprehensive way, almost all the possibilities for positive and negative
expression. If such was his intention, then the ultimate reasons for his
methodology were in part logical ones; the proof for the attributes of
being is at the same time a catalogue of the different uses of predicates
in positive and negative judgments. The method of exhaustion of pos-
sibilities will also be read as a way of insuring determinacy, both because
of its rigor and because it assigns determinate attributes to the object
(being) of its discourse. Chapters 3 and 4 make the same claim about
comprehensiveness and determinacy for Parmenides’ treatment of con-
traries, for his proof that there is nothing besides being, and for his use
of metaphorical modal language. Here the method of elimination of
alternatives has the same ontological outcome: a single, noncontrary,
necessary being is rendered determinate and, to use Parmenides’ own
metaphor, is bounded by being the object of a discourse which operates
by systematically examining the spectrum of possibilities. In chapters 2—
4, then, logic and a comprehensive method of enumeration and variation
appear intimately intertwined with ontology in a combination originated
by Parmenides and (as chapters 5 and 6 try to show) decisive in subse-
quent philosophy and in its own right. Chapter 5 attempts to trace the
history, from Thales through Parmenides to Aristotle, of the Parmeni-
dean logic of contextual variability, of the method of variation, and of
the theory of negative language attributed to Parmenides in the first four
chapters, thus to situate his thought in its immediate historical context
while showing that later developments can be predicated retroactively in
his terms. The concluding chapter meditates on the philosophical and
theological significance of the views attributed here to Parmenides, es-
pecially in light of his identification of the transcendent with the deter-
minate or bounded rather than with the unbounded, and in connection
with the methodology and theory associated with that identification in
earlier chapters. Christianity, Buddhism, Heraclitus, Hegel, and Nietz-
sche appear as alternatives in the spectrum of possibilities, and I discuss
the connection between different views of being and different views of
INTRODUCTION 9
Though Parmenides is famous for saying that one ought not say or think
what is not (whatever that is), he went on to compose a poem that seems
to do almost nothing else. Since Plato’s Sophist, perhaps, Parmenides has
been almost as famous for apparent inconsistencies! as for the rigid dicta
that seemed to land him in them. Here I try to extricate him from some
if not all his inconsistencies and to suggest a new role for him in the
history of mysticism and logic. I suggest that previous interpretations
have not dealt adequately with the problem of Parmenides’ negative lan-
guage, note that there is one negative expression (ouk esti, “isn’t”) which
he does not use except innocuously,? suggest that his abhorrence of neg-
ative language was not an abhorrence of negative facts and extended
only so far as a directly and assertorically negated copula, and try to
generate a philosophical rationale which will explain both this limited
abhorrence and the rest of the poem. I discuss previous interpretations
of Parmenides’ negative language in section 2.
Like all interpretations of Parmenides, mine is controversial. Without
downplaying my commitment to it, I will say that much of the rest of the
book is independent of it. At the end of the chapter I describe which
parts of the remaining chapters do not depend on what is said here.
Though we are told that the route of “is not” is completely uninformative
and the route of what-is trustworthy, the goddess’s language in
fragment 8 abounds in denials, negative words and phrases, and contra-
positive methods of proof. This fact has long been noted, but it has not,
I think, been sufficiently appreciated. Being “is not lacking” (B8.33),
“nor is it divisible” (B8.22), is not such as to be here bigger and there
smaller than being (B8.47—48), is “ungenerable” (B8.3), “unmoving”
(B8.4), “immovable . . .without beginning, without end” (B8.26—27), and
11
12 WHY NOT “IS NOT’?
sweet grapes of the vine. Surely the burden of proof is on a view in which
all her words are disqualified right off the bat.
The resort here is to read fragment 8 as an example of a familiar sort
of philosophical self-referential inconsistency: the ladder is rendered un-
necessary by its very trustworthiness. Owen recommends transcendental
argument; Furth suggests that, given a student of intelligence, the same
effect could have been achieved by repeated beatings, Zen-fashion, every
time the student used negative language. A supple youth like Zeno
would, presumably, respond well to this sort of “negative reinforce-
ment.”!° But then why bother to compose a poem at all? Why not just
say “Being is’—if one can even say that? Practical charity or vanity are
plausible motives, but Furth does not give a philosophical reason why
Parmenides should have designed his argument to show how being is by
denying how it is not. And this is what Parmenides did do, as was indi-
cated above. And if Parmenides had a genuine antipathy towards neg-
ative language, would he not at least have reduced his use of it to the
bare minimum, even if the constraints of communication forced him
into negative statement? This reduction he certainly does not make—if
anything, he flaunts his Mephistophelian side. Or, one who thought self-
referential inconsistency was unavoidable might embrace it and become
promiscuously inconsistent. In that case, why aren’t there even more
negations, clearly indicating that the goal is silence?
It might be replied that many philosophers have been in the predic-
ament of saying what they know they ought not to say in order to explain
why they ought not to say it. Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is an example,
if Fichte was right about it; Wittgenstein’s Tractatus has already been
mentioned; the Platonic likely stories are perhaps another example. Here
the philosopher is depicted as both master and victim of a proper ob-
session, walking about with cast and crutches in order to demonstrate
the impossibility of doing so. Or, perhaps, out of a real charity and
concern for truth, Parmenides is willing to bend a principle in order to
make it accessible. But Wittgenstein and Plato at least say that this is
what they are doing and give good reasons for why they need to do it.
Why not Parmenides? If he is indeed as scrupulous about negative lan-
guage as he is represented to be, then the repeated negations in fragment
8 might be thought daring, as if he were flaunting his violation of the
principle, inviting the reader to pounce. This might be good pedagogy
in certain situations, but it invites misunderstanding if used as a general
method.
What is needed is an explanation of how self-referentially inconsistent
or paradoxical (Mackenzie) discourse!! could be regarded as “trustwor-
thy” in the sense demanded by the goddess. Her language of trust has
to do with the fixity of being within its bounds (B8.13—15, 26-33), with
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 17
But there are problems with the exhaustiveness of the existential read-
ing even in the “Truth” section, with Parmenides’ discussion of local
inhomogeneity in fragment 8. We hear, in two similar but distinguishable
passages, that what-is is not bigger or smaller anywhere. There is some
discussion in recent literature about just what the inhomogeneity in-
volves, whether it is one of density, or.spatial distribution, or even
(wrongly, I think) temporal distribution (see chapter 3). But surely a
thing can be (though it does not have to be) more dense in one place
and less dense in another without thereby containing a zone of nonbe-
ing.!? It is true that if a stuff is less in one place and more in another,
then, even if it contains no gaps, it “is not more” in the place in which
it is less, and “is not less” in the place in which it is more. But this is not
the “is not” of denial of existence. We still have to explain what Parmen-
ides thinks is wrong with certain statements involving negative predica-
tions, not just negative existential statements. Moreover, there are
negative existential statements within the body of fragment 8 (“For there
neither is nor will be an other besides what-is,’ B8.36—38). For the ex-
istential reading, these are allowable because (like fragment 2) they are
to be read as ways of telling us how not to talk. Thus they are not taken
to be direct discourse but instead part ofa self-referentially inconsistent
metalanguage. However, I would like to bring these statements, too, di-
rectly within the ambit of allowable Parmenidean expression.
I do not rule out the possibility that a combination of the existential
criterion with some other criterion against contradiction (of the sort I
present later) might be workable at least as a deduction of the predicates
of being.'* But if a purely existential reading of the “is” is not wide enough
to rule out “Opinion” and preserve “Truth,” one might want to look for
some other construal of “is.” Here the view to deal with is that of Moure-
latos. In what follows I argue against his claim that Parmenides’ world
could have been composed of many monads, each with its own proper
or constitutive name. A potentially pluralistic claim is shared by Moure-
latos and Barnes.
Basic to a view of the world as a paratactically ordered plurality of
monads, without negation-inviting relations among them, is the view that
each thing is what it is and not another thing. If there is only one thing
in the world, then one doesn’t have to worry, since there aren’t any other
things, though one may need to show that there aren’t any others. But
if the world has many monads in it, then whenIsay, “This is Odysseus,”
I also say or imply, “This is not anything which is not Odysseus.” Par-
menides seems to say not only how what-is is, but also how it is not
possible for it not to be (B2.3). On Mourelatos’ reading, in which the
statements made in “Truth” are more or less guidelines for what ought
to be said, one ought to avoid characterizing Odysseus in terms which
\
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 21
device, not only just because it is language, but also because of the kind
of language it is. (2) It is worth viewing the negative language seriously
as a kind of language to which Parmenides apparently felt himself en-
titled. Previous interpretations have too often attributed to him a pro-
hibition against the very language that he uses in fragment 8, and this
tells me that it is no longer fruitful to try to figure out what is prescribed
and prohibited without examining that language more closely. (3) Par-
menides knew (at least on the level of right opinion) that one could make
a negative predication without making a negative existence-assertion.
Thus he could not have fused or confused the two. (4) On the assump-
tion that, for example, “it is not lacking” (B8.33) and “nor is there what-
is-not” (B8.46) are acceptable forms of expression for Parmenides, he
cannot have objected to sentences which express negative predications
or negative existential statements. (5) Nor could the Parmenidean uni-
verse have included a plurality of totally real beings.
how a sentence like esti gar ouk epidees, “for it is not lacking,” could be
taken as a sentence which says “hds esti,” “that it is,’ one in which the
goddess speaks of being as it is and not as it is not; and to explain, in
the same breath if possible, why the locution ouk esti, “isn’t,” is not used
as such to make adirect predication or assertoric negative existential
statement.
I assume, first, that metrical considerations alone would not have pre-
vented Parmenides from using the locution ouk esti, or a contraction
thereof, in assertoric negative predications and negative existentials.'”
The locution already finds its place in the Parmenidean hexameter, and
its omission in an otherwise highly negative poem where the prohibited
route is described as the route hdés ouk esti, “how it isn’t,’ could not have
been decisively affected by such considerations.
My proposal is very simple. Parmenides thinks that esti gar ouk epidees,
“for it is not lacking,” says hés esti, “that it is,” precisely because it says
esti, “is.” It literally says esti (“it is”) owk epidees (“not lacking”) and does
not say ouk esti (“it isn’t”) epidees (“lacking”). He thinks that an assertoric
sentence which can be read as saying esti, “is,” is a sentence which belongs
to the route hopés esti, “that it is,” and that an assertoric sentence which
had to be read as saying ouk esti, “isn’t,” would be one which belonged to
the route hés ouk esti, “that it isn’t.” The fact is that sentences which say
esti in this way are found in fragment 8, no matter how negative they
seem; but sentences which say ouk esti in making an assertoric negative
predication, or a negative assertoric existential statement, are not found,
though they are found in modal discourse. And a systematically self-
referentially inconsistent poem, it could be argued, would have included
them. Thus, fragment 8 accords with fragment 2, and Parmenides obeys
his own prescriptions and prohibitions in every word. It is a simple recipe
for correct speech, one whose nature and rationale any intelligent
speaker could understand.
Behind the apparent simplicity of such prohibitions and prescriptions,
however, might lie a philosophical rationale of some depth. The point
can be made either in ordinary language or in theoretical language.
Ordinarily I might suppose that there is a difference between “he isn’t
in debt” and “he is not-in-debt,” and think that the first tells me what he
isn’t (thus telling me nothing) while the second tells me what he is,
namely, not-in-debt, even though it looks like it might be telling me
nothing. And I want to know something, namely what he is. I might have
thought this difference up for myself, become enchanted with it, and
made a theory out of it.
Theoretically, the origin of such a view might lie in an intuition (think
of this as only a matter of intuition, of philosophical insight, on Par-
menides’ part, since there is no evidence for its being part of a formal,
24 WHY NOT “IS NOT’?
oute gar ouk eon esti, to ken “For neither is there what-is- 46
pauoi min hikneisthai eis not, which might prevent
homon it from attaining same-
ness”
out’eon estin hopos eié ken “Nor is it in any way possi- 47-48
eontos téi mallon téi d’hés- _ ble for what-is to be here
son _ more and there less than
what-is”
pan estin asulon “All of it is inviolable” 48
It is striking to notice the number of times esti, “is,” is repeated and
how consistently it is not associated with an immediately preceding neg-
ative. I would suggest that we read these sentences as follows: the cases
where no negation could possibly attach to the copula pose no difficulty
even if the predicate is alpha-privative. Lines B8.3—4, the second half of
5-6, the second half of 22, 24, 25, 26-27, 42, and 48 fall into this
category. They are all unambiguous sentences of the esti-type. As I said
above, I believe that the frequent use of alpha-privatives testifies to a
desire to move negations away from the copula.
On the present interpretation, 22 (first half) and 33 are syntactically
ambiguous sentences which, because they do not contain the locution ouk
esti as such, are intended by Parmenides to be taken as sentences of the
esti-type with negated predicates, or negations of the sentence as a whole
(see below).'8 Lines 8—9 and 47-48 are essentially modals, and as such
need not be thought of as on the negative route. They could belong to
a modal side of the positive route wherein we are supposed to say neg-
ative things, to say not only “that it is,” hds esten, but also “how it is not
possible for it not to be,” hés ouk esti mé einai (B2.3); I discuss the dis-
tinction between assertoric and modal language in this poem in more
detail later. Still, even though the context in 8—9 and 47—48 is not asser-
toric, Parmenides does not use the locution ouk esti as he did in the modal
negation of B2.3. Lines 8—9 and 47—48 can be thought of as doing the
same job as méden d’ouk estin (“nothing cannot be”) or mé eon d’an pantos
edeito (“nonbeing would lack everything”), that is, they say that and why
something is prohibited. Méden d’ouk estin (“nothing cannot be,” B6.2),
of course, like B2.3, does negate the modal estin, and part of what I am
suggesting is that such negative modal language, as opposed to an as-
sertoric ouk esti, is legitimate. But I also suggest that Parmenides is so
careful to avoid the appearance of error that he does not even use the
locution ouk esti as such modaily in fragment 8.
In 36-37 and in 46, Parmenides is denying the existence of some-
thing—in the first case, of an “other besides what-is” and, in the second,
of a “what-is-not” which “might stop it [what-is] from attaining same-
ness.” In neither case, however, is the locution ouk esti used. Moreover,
36-37 is also essentially modal, since something which neither is nor will
be is something which is impossible, as the following imagery with the
figure of Doom suggests. Or one could take the negation as part of the
subject (ouden allo, “nothing other’) rather than the verb, so that the
underlying positive structure is “there is something which is nothing
other than being.” And 46—which is the:most difficult case—could be
taken as negating the subject, thus leaving the esti free, which would
make the sentence say underneath that there is something which is not
an ouk eon, a not-being, with the to, “which,” then picking up ouk eon. Or
46 could be seen as a version of “nothing cannot be,” given the modal
context in “which might prevent it from reaching sameness,” even though
the esti in 46 1s itself assertoric. The sentence will then be part of a general
explanation of why certain sorts of inhomogeneity are impossible owing
to the impossibility of what-is-not. Or the negation could be taken as
negating the estz-sentence as a whole (see below). In both 36—37 and 46,
then, I would suggest that the sentence is either modal or has as its depth-
structure the negation of the sentence or the subject or predicate rather
than the copula, or both. If Parmenides thought that an alpha-privative
or directly negated predicate can function within a canonically good
sentence, it is also possible that he would allow himself to negate a subject
provided that the copula was unnegated and the ultimate subject re-
ferred to was being. Such subject-terms are not necessarily too indefinite
in a monistic ontology. But this would depend on the scope of the ne-
gations.
If these explanations are adopted, then all the sentences about being
in fragment 8 will be negations of the predicate, the subject, or the whole
sentence, or will be modal negations, and so all will be on the positive
route. The pattern of absence of assertoric ouk esti is, I think, supposed
to clue us in to the possibility that something else is going on underneath
the surface of these sentences, that is, that they may not necessarily be
negating the copula assertorically. So long as such a negation is or can
be avoided, modal negations and also subject- or predicate-negations can
clear the bar. And these are not the only modals in the poem; some of
the personified female figures who guarantee the boundedness of being
are also ways of saying how it is not possible for being to be as it is not.
(I discuss these figures further in chapter 4.) That there must be a clear
distinction between modal and other uses of ouk esti is guaranteed by its
double occurrence first in the description (B2.3) of the positive route as
containing hés ouk esti mé einai, “how it is not possible for it not to be,”
and, second, two lines below in B2.5, where the negative route is de-
scribed as the route hos ouk esti, “how it isn’t.” Thus Parmenides must be
aware of a permissible use of the locution as well as of an impermissible
\
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 27
one, and of the distinction between them: the permissible use is clearly
in a modal context. “Nothing cannot be” in B6 seems to be such a use,
as would be the possible implicit modal negations of the copula in B8.36—
37 and 46, if these are not taken as subject-negations. All can be grouped
together as language which is tolerated by Parmenides under circum-
stances where direct statement would not be tolerated. My claim is thus
that to say that Parmenides does not make this distinction is to say that
the second half of B2.3—the statement of the positive route—is already
on the negative route from the very beginning, since ouk esti occurs there
too. A distinction between the two routes can be sustained only by mak-
ing a distinction between modal and assertoric language. These assimi-
lations of the language in fragment 8 to innocuous kinds of discourse
are rendered plausible by what may be a deliberate avoidance. Otherwise
the absence in assertoric discourse of the very expression named in the
negative route from a discourse containing many other negations has no
philosophical point. But, if it is avoided for a reason, we can seek the
reason in an attempt to defuse the sentences, to assimilate them to in-
nocuous kinds of negation already permitted in the statement of the two
routes or in different ways of construing sentences. The objection of
Gallop is that “any determinate affirmative predication entails a host of
negative ones”;!® I reply by representing Parmenides as merely disqual-
ifying the negative rephrasings of sentences without being concerned
about their possible equivalences to positive ones, as being preoccupied
with a canonical form in which the copula is or is not negated.
Two philological objections can be made to this case. One is that the
difference between negated copula and negated predicate in, e.g., oude
diaireton estin, “nor is it divisible,” is very slight. How can one assert
Parmenides to have made a distinction which is not consciously formu-
lated until Aristotle’s logic? It might be said that one has enough trouble
trying to construe sentences in hexameters without attributing such so-
phisticated distinctions to the fluid language of verse.”° The other objec-
tion is similar: the interpretation presented here seems to take for
granted that Parmenides could have distinguished the roles of copula
and predicate in theory as well as distinguishing between modal and as-
sertoric discourse. What historical evidence is there that he could have
made such distinctions? :
The first objection suggests a possible difficulty in localizing the focus
of negations in verse. A. C. Moorhouse, in Studies in the Greek Negatives,
summarizes a survey of some evidence as follows.
In Hom. JI. 1-12, there is no case, out of thirteen sentences, of ow followed
by eimi. Instead the adjective predicate comes next ... or else another
word. ... This means that the adjective, as predicate, is treated in the same
28 WHY NOT “IS NOT’’?
way as a verb predicate where a “full” verb is used; and that the presence
of the verb “to be” is disregarded. This is in contrast with later usage. It
seems likely that this Homeric treatment wasvnfluenced by the usage in the
pure nominal type (from which the verb “to be” was absent). . .. The free-
dom of position of the adjective, when ov is initial, is a striking feature, and
this too is paralleled by the freedom of placing of the verb generally in
Homer after initial ow.?! io
Moorhouse adds that the separation between negative and copula is later
reversed and that in the New Testament both regularly occur together.??
Thus a general Homeric avoidance of this negative followed by forms of
“to be” in impure nominal sentences means that the adjective is there
most directly negated. Parmenides, in following this practice with his
adjectival negations (also in his alpha-privatives, which encapsulate such
negations), might thus be supposed to have been doing so for purely
linguistic rather than philosophical reasons. But, as I said above, when
we add to this the fact that ouk esti is what is prohibited, putting the
weight of the negation on the adjective can also acquire a philosophical
significance. Parmenides will then have performed a metaphysical re-
flection on this epic practice, which now becomes one way of producing
canonically good sentences. This point about word order, then, means
that it is possible to localize the ouk, “not,” in esta gar ouk epidees, “for it
is not lacking,” more decisively away from the copula.
Moorhouse also makes a relevant point about sentence (‘“nexal”) ne-
gations.
Now we shall see that nexal ow was most often either initial, or else in
second place (less frequently). Other positions were comparatively rare. The
verb was by no means always associated with it: in Iliad, Books 1-12 the
verb follows the negative immediately in only 50 per cent. of all cases. Yet
it is the verbal idea which we would expect to find negatived in a sentence
with a nexal negative, if any single element 1s to be so selected.”
specifically, just as the earlier adjectival negations can be taken with the
adjective. Though Moorhouse also mentions the verb, the proposition
expressed by the sentence is really the focus of attack. If this were the
case, then the negations would not be taken as part of the proposition,
but rather as floating outside it, outside the brackets as in the sentence
Moorhouse analyzes. The copula, then, which is inside the brackets, is
not negated except as a part of the sentence as a whole just because the
negations are nexal. Such a practice could acquire philosophical signif-
icance for Parmenides, who was a theoretician of negation and affir-
mation; the significance that it might naturally acquire in his case would
be that the proposition in a negative sentence must be itself internally
free of a directly negated copula even though there are negative words
floating outside. If such were his trend of mind, Parmenides would have
reflected deeply on his language and encoded that reflection in his poem
by prohibiting ouk esti and keeping negations away from copulas as a
signal to readers that all his judgments about being were canonical and
genuine. This reflection would have been signalled by an interpretation
of the -owk in ouk esti as (in effect) a negation bearing directly on the
copula.
These canonical judgments, then, would naturally fall into various
classes, some of whose members are actually found in the poem: (1) esti-
sentences with no negations except, perhaps, within alpha-privative
predicates; (2) esti-sentences with word-negations attaching to predicates
or subjects; (3) sentence-negations where the negation is in effect outside
brackets; (4) modal affirmations or rejections of the first three classes or
rejections of ouk esti-sentences. The idea is that an assertoric esti-sentence
is a basic carrier of meaning in the direct object-language about reality,
which must be accepted or rejected as a whole, or piece by piece, without
violating the copula. Modal ouk esta can occur (4), as can negations equiv-
alent to “it is not the case that” (3); the former can be used in rejecting
the negative route (ouk esti in lines 8—9), but the latter seem to bear only
on sentences which are canonically good inside the brackets. If all this
language is taken as being on the positive route, it will be because of the
unnegated copula, or the rejected negative copula, at the core of each
sentence. This guarantees its meaning and reference, its capacity to carry
a judgment. Such, then, would have been Parmenides’ philosophical re-
flection on syntax. Now it is possible to call the negations outside the
brackets “metalinguistic” and to group them, together with the modals,
the personified figures, and the chariot ride, in the category of permis-
sible language which is not itself an esti-sentence; but I prefer the looser
formulation adopted above, in which the close connection between these
negations, which are not themselves expanded into sentences, and the
full sentences on which they bear is expressed inaclassification of can-
onical judgments. In this way one can speak of classes 1—4 as acceptable
and distinguish them from myth on the basis of their having a non-self-
referentially inconsistent core. Thus oude diaireton estin, “nor is it divisi-
ble,” would be read as “not [it is divisible],” while cute gar ouk eon esti,
“nor is there what-is-not,” could become “not [what-is-not is],” with free
copulas inside the brackets, unless one adopts one of the other expla-
nations given above. Negative existentials, if there are any nonmodal
examples of such in the poem, and all other types of discourse, will be
translated directly into estz-sentences or into (negative, modal, etc.) op-
erations on such sentences. These operations are thus performed on
sentences which do not themselves violate any laws. Canonical judgments
can thus include the denial of existence and of fact as well as modal
denials. I take up the question which of such judgments are true and
which are false below.
To sum up from a different angle: however rare predicative ouk est
might be in Homer as compared to existential or modal ouk estz,?° the use
of modal ouk esti in Parmenides where ouk esti is prohibited means that
at least one ouk esti—the modal—must be allowed. The question then
arises of which ouk estz is in fact prohibited. The absence of the locution
in assertoric negative existentials and negative predications in fragment 8
suggests that these uses are barred. One rephrases the sentences, as the
text does already to some extent, pushing the negations to the outside,
and the result is canonical discourse in which the locution or its unam-
biguous equivalents do not appear inside brackets. To the question,
“Aren’t you just ruling out what may not be likely to occur anyway?” I
reply that the infrequency of some uses of ouk esti in the language com-
pared to others could perhaps have been a fact of great importance to
Parmenides. Assertoric existential owk esti or equivalents do not occur as
such either in fragment 8, and since modal ouk esti does occur in B2.3,
we should, I think, suppose that the total absence even of an improbable
predicative ouk esti could have had a philosophical rationale. In this way
one can interpret the Homeric practice of using certain negations to bear
only on predicates or on the sentence as a whole as crucial for Parmenides
in a more theoretical way, and so see him as reflecting on what he in-
herited in terms, not necessarily of statistics, but of what types of sen-
tences there can be and what they mean. The result will be the use of
Homeric ambiguity to provoke thought, disambiguation, and an unam-
biguous and ontologically proper prose version; the freedom of verse is
thus indispensable without making it impossible to tell where the nega-
tions go. This is a complicated hermeneutic to follow, but it seems pref-
erable to the (genuinely important) alternative in which the poem self-
destructs as soon as its meaning is even partly understood. If poets are
freer in their language than other writers, then a philosopher preoccu-
xX
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 31
pied above all with negation could use Homeric fluidity in order to make
sure that certain things were conspicuously absent.”” And if, as Moor-
house says, Aristophanes, perhaps reflecting colloquial speech, has a
“more frequent use of initial ow than in either Herodotus or Thucydides,
though not rising as high as in Homer,’?* then perhaps Parmenides’
hearers could recognize negative words freely positioned away from the
copula as preserving an essential positivity within the sentence itself. This
hypothesis avoids difficulties in other interpretations of the poem’s pro-
hibitions.
But how self-conscious were Parmenides’ notions? Doesn’t this hy-
pothesis require Parmenides to have aset of theoretical distinctions among
sentence, subject, copula, and predicate, as well as modal and assertoric
discourse? What evidence is there for his use of material usually thought
to be found only in later philosophy and grammar?
My reply to all such objections is that it is not necessary to suppose
that Parmenides had a body of articulated theoretical statements in which
such distinctions were drawn. Clearly, he was not a grammarian or a
systematic formal logician like Aristotle. Equally clearly, however, he was
not a mere speaker of the ordinary language, but rather someone for
whom negation and negative discourse, to give only two examples, posed
deep theoretical problems. What I want to attribute to him is a state
appropriate to a discoverer. (I attempt such an attribution again in
chapter 2 with reference to his logic of terms.) This would beastate in
which, for whatever reasons, he wished to avoid the locution ouk este or
its equivalents in assertoric discourse, and therefore produced only sen-
tences where no negation could attach to the copula, or verse sentences
where (without an explicit body of grammatical theory) he felt the weight
of the negation as pressing elsewhere than on the copula, or modals.
This is perfectly possible given the poem’s evidence, even without his-
torical antecedents or a theoretical superstructure. A response for the
distinction between assertoric and modal ouk esti has already been of-
fered: the wealth of modal expression is used to say negative things which
seem to flout the laws. And poetic flexibility is used ingeniously. Thus
distinctions possible in language, though not explicitly formulated until
later, can be invoked in order to explain Parmenides’ behavior so long
as they are (as I would claim) required in order to understand the text
but are not (as I would not wish to do) claimed to have been held in full
theoretical self-consciousness by an author. All Parmenides needed was
a philosophically heightened sensitivity, a desire to display the laws of his
logic as laws of his words without writing a science of logic.
Another apparent difficulty is posed by lines 5—6, “nor was it, not will
it be, since it is now altogether one, cohesive.” Here we have forms of
“to be” negated without anything in between or anything else for the
32 WHY NOT “IS NOT’?
negation to attach to. Of course, part of the point of the passage is that
these are not (in Parmenides’ mind) fully genuine forms of the verb;
moreover, the locution ouk esti is not present; but this does not remove
the difficulty; I still must explain what is supposed to be special about
these other tenses, which can (one supposes) clearly introduce predicates
on their own, just like the present tense. Also, the announcement of the
two routes in fragment 2, since it uses the-infinitive in the second half
of line 3, might be thought to include any tense in the range of expres-
sion of the positive route. Moreover, in B8.36—37, “nor is there nor will
there be any other besides what-is,” “will be” seems included in the same
scope as “is” in a way which seems to give the future a sanction of its
own in legitimate predications. In response, I would say that there is no
indication that the “to be” and “not to be” in B2.3 and B2.5 are anything
more than required infinitizations of the “is” and “is not” which imme-
diately precede them in the same lines. This is made clear by B8.5—6,
which show that the “is” is the only legitimate tense. Moreover, the “will
be” in lines 36-37, which seems coupled with an “is,” is not functioning
assertorically, but modally, as the following imagery with the figure of
Doom suggests. “It is not, nor will it be” means “never.” Thus it might
be permissible to deny “will be” modally but not to affirm it assertorically
about being, because of the unsavory ontological implications of past or
future temporal existence on the part of an eternal being. This criterion
is more complicated than the one I used before, because it already seems
to presuppose a doctrine about the relationship of being to time, but this
presupposition does not seem to be virulent. (See chapter 3.)
But before attempting to assess further whether my hypothesis allows
Parmenides to know too much, let me furnish its reading of the rest of
the poem’s theory. Two questions must be answered: first, what deter-
mines the truth or falsity of est7-sentences? Second, what is wrong with
the world-view of mortals?
I suggest that a modified principle of noncontradiction, combined with
an archaic logic whose outlines are still visible in Plato’s Phaedo and Eu-
thydemus, allowed Parmenides to generate the predicates true of being.?°
(I say more about this logic in chapter 5.) Some of those predicates which
Parmenides denies in fragment 8 would, if true, imply sentences of the
following form:
It is P and it is not P
where P stands for the same predicate in both of its occurrences. I sug-
gest either that Parmenides saw such forms as instances of contradiction
or “doubletalk” regardless of additional qualifying terms which, to an
Aristotelian mind at least, would remove the contradiction; or that he
felt the contextual relativity that such sentences embody—and which is
\
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 33
within brackets on a subject which cannot carry it. In these cases as well
the sentences are canonical but false.
This may also have been what Parmenides thought wrong with the
sentence which introduces the cosmologies of mortals. Fire is declared
by them to be “with itself in every way the same, with the other (Night)
not the same” (B8.57—58). This would have been babble to Parmenides
if all he allowed himself to hear was “the same and not the same.” What
is Fire is the same with itself and not the same with what is not Fire, and
Night (which is not Fire) is the same with itself and not the same with
what is not Night. Or so we mortals would believe. This sentence from
“Opinion” seems almost designed as the antagonist for Plato’s statement
in Sophist 256A—B that motion, for example, can be the same and not
the same in different senses, though the sense of “the same” in the
passage from the Sophist is not the same. (This point has also been made
by A. A. Long; see chapter 6, n. 34). It is here in this Parmenidean line,
I think, that the goddess for the first and decisive time explicitly signals
to us just what is wrong with “Opinion” and right with “Truth.”
The logic that would have allowed Parmenides to think this way is not
only not anachronistic, but also of a piece with what I am attributing to
him in his use of the copula in fragment 8. It is an interesting logic. First
the qualifying phrases on the predicates are dropped (in an effort to
discover any underlying “contradictions” or contextual relativities which
might prevent the predicates from being true), and then the predicates
themselves are dropped in a process of simplification aimed at getting
out the underlying assertion(s) and/or denial(s). “What-is is here bigger”
becomes “what-is is here bigger, and there not bigger” becomes “what-is
is bigger and not bigger”; while “what is isn’t (ouk esti)lacking” becomes
“what is isn’t.” (But to eon esti owk epidees, “what-is is not-lacking,” is ac-
ceptable because it reduces to esti, “is,’ and moreover Says something
true—something which does not require what-is to be “in this respect
lacking, in that respect not lacking.”) I claim in chapter 3 that the proofs
of most signposts in the poem proceed by a denial of incomplete pred-
icates; thus the ruling out of “contradiction” of the sort I am concerned
with here is a central feature of the poem’s argument as well as of its
logic. Such a world-view is certainly possible for the likes of Euthydemus
and Dionysodorus; whether it is worthy of Parmenides is another ques-
tion, to be dealt with later. But it is worth noting that such a view of
contradiction is the natural expression of the (still viable) Heraclitean-
Parmenidean variety of monism, from which it follows and which follows
from it. It may be, therefore, not a fallacy at all.
There is additional textual evidence also. The “it is not possible for it
not to be” of B2.3 can be given a sense which bears both on the logic of
“Opinion” and on the rejection of false predicates in “Truth.” This sec-
‘\
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 35
as the mutual chase of the opposites (in sex and reproduction, for ex-
ample—B 12, 17, 18) shows that neither one of a pair of “Opinion”-type
opposites is sufficient in itself; each is sufficient only with reference to
the other, just as the moon only borrows the sun’s light (B14)—only
undivided being, without ouk esti and contextual relativity, is a true object
of knowledge. The initial postulate of nonidentity creates a network of
distinctions which are undercut in the very.act of making the distinctions,
as the indiscriminate mixing of opposites reveals the core of ambiguity
underlying their separation. The result, as I claimed in the Introduction,
is surely a reductio ad absurdum of our everyday cosmos, which is in-
tended to illustrate the result of breaking the goddess’s laws by showing,
first, that the result is identical with the cosmos as we usually accept it
and, second, that that cosmos is therefore illegitimate even though pos-
sessed of a weird internal logic of its own—illegitimate, because it tries
to engrave on sand. Fire and Night, sharply distinguished in the begin-
ning, soon generate a world in which mortals can lead their ambiguous
lives on both sides of a dichotomy of nonidentities. The law of noncon-
tradiction, or the prohibition against contextual relativity, can be satisi-
fied only in a world where predicates apply without distinctions of
respect; for any such distinctions soon bring about a coincidence of op-
posites, the very opposite of what they hoped to achieve. The language
throughout “Opinion” is, of course, as well-scrubbed and positive as
possible, as though the mortals were trying to conceal from themselves
the negation that lies at the bottom of their souls; but the attempt fails.
It is possible to bring the criteria for canonical judgments together
with the anti-contradiction rule if one supposes that Parmenides thought
assertoric ouk esti was contradictory when used of being either existen-
tially or in a predication. If one supposes this, then there is a single
criterion; but it is also possible to suppose that meaningfulness for him
was a matter separate from truth or falsity. I discuss below how such a
separation would affect the history of philosophy and the independence
of this chapter from my other conclusions.
When, at the beginning of fragment 8, Parmenides announces that
what follows will be the account of the route “that it is,” and when this
is immediately expanded to “that being is ungenerable and unperishing,”
I take it we are supposed to understand “how it is” in B2 and B8 as
shorthand for telling it like it is (est?) and not like it isn’t (ouk esti). A
sentence which says “that it is P” is a sentence which says “that it is,” so
long as it does so in so many words. If I told you that Socrates was ugly,
you would say that someone who says that legei ta onta hés estin, “states
the facts (or reality, what-is, or the truth) like they are.” A similar position
underlies the views of Calogero, Mourelatos, Kahn, and Furth,?° but my
Parmenidean est has to remain unnegated, except innocuously, because
\
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 37
it is the only kind of sentence-copula which makes contact with the truth
assertorically, and it can be followed by a de re negation in an assertoric
sentence about being—for reasons which reflect a profound ontology of
syntax.
Thus I suggest that for Parmenides a canonical sentence makes a judg-
ment that can be true or false, while a noncanonical sentence does not
really make a judgment. The canonical sentences that are true do not
contain or imply both the assertion and denial of the same predicate-
term or statement in the same or in different contexts. Those that are
false do contain both. Parmenides rejects all the false terms in canonical
judgments; in the words of B2.3, he shows that it is and that it is not
possible for it to be in any sense otherwise.
The following rules can be adopted as ways to explain and generate,
more accurately and economically than before, both what Parmenides
did say and what he did not say. They are his rules for the construction
of.an adequate logos which expresses being.
(1) When you wish to tell the truth about being the way it really is,
always say esti or use one of the other forms of canonical judgment. It
doesn’t matter how many negations there are in the sentence, grammat-
ical subject, or predicate, so long as the negative words in the judgment
do not have to be taken with the assertoric copula alone. For only these
judgments can say what is, that is, put reality into language, and so be
affirmed or denied meaningfully.
(2) Though you may say that the locution ouk esti as such is prohibited,
use it as a nickname for the uninformative negative route, say that noth-
ing is not, use it modally, or mention it as a consequence to be avoided,
you cannot use it to say something true about what is real in the assertoric
mode.
(3) Never contradict yourself, either explicitly or implicitly, either by
asserting or by implying anything which, if true, would state or require
that two contradictory predicates or statements be admissible in the same
or in different senses. (Alternative formulation: never allow the saying and
unsaying of the same thing to enmesh you in contextual relativity.) These
two formulations, I suggest in chapter 5, could have been distinguished
only by Protagoras or Plato.*!
(4) However, when applying rule 3, remember that the predicate or
statement proper does not include qualifying terms, such as “in this re-
spect ... in that respect,” “with itself ... with the other,” “at this ime
o> 6
belong to his time and yet be worthy of the respect accorded to him by
Plato. For, on the one hand, an ontological abhorrence of a negated
copula leaves something for Plato to discover, since Parmenides has only
a relatively simple mapping of the present tense onto the participle; the
supposition that the mapping of language onto reality is so direct that
a negated copula robs the sentence of ontological import belongs to a
period before the Sophist; Parmenidean monism as a significant perennial
position is imaginable without that particular doctrine. On the other
hand, a Parmenides who (in some sense) understood double-negation
and the logical role of the alpha-privative and who saw a difference
between “is not-P” and “isn’t B” even if he rejected the latter, might well
have been the teacher of Zeno, the “father of dialectic.” The inclusion
of negations as part of the predicate in est7-sentences is even reminiscent
of Plato’s redemption of negation in the Sophist, as I conjectured above,
and I discuss Parmenides’ relationship with negative theology in
chapter 6. That these things were the common coin of sophistry in the
hands of Euthydemus and Dionysodorus does not mean that they were
debased by their inventor. And it is surely no accident that Plato repre-
sents Parmenides as the father of ontology and of logic, even as he dis-
agrees with him. I wondered earlier whether even Plato understood that
Parmenides’ negations could have been deliberate, meaningful, and care-
ful.
-Parmenides very cleverly navigated between the Scylla of giving voice
only to the tautology “what is, is” and the Charybdis of saying ouk esti
while trying to describe what-is assertorically. He bravely tried to derive
everything from the law of noncontradiction plus an injunction to say
esti. He was deaf to the siren song of sensible cosmology, which promised
him a complete science at the price of a violation of justice. It was left
for Plato and Aristotle to carry on the enterprise by breaking their mas-
ter’s prohibition.
This way of drawing the connection between Parmenides’ “is” and
Greek “being” as a name for truth or reality is, of course, related to
what many critics have been saying since Owen’s article. But it is high
time that we used these critical points to develop a criterion which relates
the surface of Parmenides’ sentences to their underlying ontology, a cri-
terion which applies literally to what Parmenides actually said. I try to
supply the criterion, the ontology, and some of the subsequent history
here. Once these have been laid out, the insights of earlier interpretations
can be incorporated. In my terms, Parmenides believed that what he
actually said met the goddess’s criteria for adequate discourse, because
he thought that a canonical sentence (rules 1 and 2 above) which is,
moreover, true because not “contradictory” in the peculiar Parmenidean
sense (rules 3 and 4 above), (a) makes contact with an ultimately positive
40 WHY NOT “IS NOT’’?
fact (Furth considers positive facts as one of three possible things ex-
pressed by positive predications), (b) describes the ultimate existing log-
ical subject (Owen), (c) really characterizes an entity which is the object
of speculative inquiry (Mourelatos). I think that the criterion presented
here can incorporate all three of these. Nor is there anynecessary conflict
among them. The entity of an absolute monist must be each of them, if
discourse is to be possible at all. But theseother views were not adequate
by themselves to generate fragment 8 as we have it. My agreement with
them is thus limited to their explanations of what is wrong with negative
language and does not constitute an endorsement of their accounts of
what counts as negative language in the first place.
What becomes of the other self-referential inconsistencies in the poem?
What about goddess, chariots, daughters of the sun, multivariant lan-
guage, and the three routes among which nonidentity statements obtain?
Here I am prepared to allow a more complicated hermeneutic, which
involves obtaining the violation of precepts that hold in the canonical
discourse (much of the language of fragment 8), so long as this violation
is not extended to that discourse itself. That is, so long as discourse about
being is securely bound by the fetters of esti and noncontradiction in such
a way that even statements like those of the two routes are bound by
laws, I can allow the other language, which incorporates the pathway
from our everyday opinions up to the house of truth, to be exempt from
the rules, for we are not told that it has to fall under them. (I discuss
below what counts as part of this “other language” and why.) But even
within the canonical discourse as I describe it, there also has to be a
complicated hermeneutic: we have to see, first, that the negations appear
to break the law; second, that the negations do not break the law; and,
third, that they are essential for the full statement of truth. So I am not
robbing the poem of any of its heuristic profundity, a profundity in
which the role of the opposite side, of negation, is as large as it is in
Heraclitus, the Sophist, Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, or Moses Mai-
monides. (See chapter 6 for more on this point.)
One can thus, if one wishes, distinguish three sorts of language in the
poem. “Truth” purports to be true and trustworthy and succeeds because
it does not break the laws; “Opinion” tries to be true but winds up as a
reductio of breaking the laws. Both of these purport to describe what
really and truly is, but “Opinion” misunderstands the nature of its de-
sired object. The portraits of the chariot ride and goddess, however, as
well as some of what the goddess herself says about distinguishing the
three routes (B1.24—32, B2—B7, except for the “that it is” and “that it is
not possible for it not to be” in B2.3, and the other things spoken about
being, e.g., B1.29, B3, B4, B6.1—2, or along the other two routes, B2.5,
B6.8—9, B7.1), as well as about other metalinguistic issues (B8.15-18,
me
WHY NOT “IS NOT’? 41
myth and then does away with the need for both myth and explicit,
discursive thought; and in this sense the rules, if followed to the limit,
make themselves not false but no longer necessary except for others, as
guides to future generations of mortals.** At any rate, I have tried to
narrow the scope of that discourse which must be regarded as violating
(for whatever purpose) the precepts of truth, in order to preserve the
distinction between reason, on the one hand, where the goddess clearly
means literally what she says about being, and myth and opinion, on the
other hand. Many interpretations of Parmenides up to now have not
allowed enough of “Truth” to be literally meant, and I hope the way is
now open for a compromise which will preserve legitimate hermeneutical
profundity while allowing the goddess, on some level at least, to mean
what she says about being in a trustworthy way.
44
ee,
I aen aeee
dinate terms fall under a single, more general term, which, if it supports
them, cannot exist without one or both of them, but which, if it opposes
them, rules them both out. Some of these have already been mentioned.
Here we have the subsumption of one of our original dyads under a
more general term. This happens first with “later” and “earlier” in line
10, which are modes of coming-to-be “out of what-is-not” (7); such a
coming-to-be cannot occur except earliet or later or both, and Parmen-
ides first rules out the general term “out of what-is-not” before ruling
out the logically subordinate contraries. A parallel case occurs in lines
22-24 with “divisible,” “more,” and “less.” The best reading of “divisible”
comes when we see it opposed by “similar” in the same line; it must mean
that there are inhomogeneities or gaps in what-is; “more” and “less” are
thus kinds of inhomogeneity—the only kinds, so that whatever is the
latter is also the former. This triad is also opposed by another triad of
positive terms: “divisible” by “similar,” “more” by “to cohere,” and “less”
by “all full.” “To cohere” opposes “more” if the latter represents a pro-
tuberance which would hold together and be equal with the rest of the
mass under the pressure of the coherence. “To cohere” and “full” are
also different from each other, though both are modes of “similar,” since
“holding together” and “being full” examine, respectively, what might
be called the centripetal and the centrifugal dimensions of a cohesive
whole. (I discuss lines 22-24 more fully in chapter 3.)
A solid can be full everywhere and still have a place sticking out, and
a solid can cohere and still be small in one place. (At least until one
realizes that all the other places are less and more, respectively, than the
places which are sticking out or being smaller). Thus we have two coin-
ciding triads, and can represent the relationships thus:
divisible
more peas
to cohere full
eae
(Iwo contradictcries and two pairs of opposed contraries). The next
triads are not as complete and in some of them the logical structure just
examined begins to vary. With “immovable-without beginning-without
end” there is a subordination of two opposed terms under a general
term, all alpha-privatives just as the first two triads were all positive. This
third triad is said to be true “since to come to be and to perish have been
driven far off” by True Trust (27-28). “To come to be” and “to perish”
occur in the same line as “without beginning” and “without end” and
TERMS 51
seem paired in meaning with the latter pair; it would seem that to be
without beginning is to be immune from a kind of birth, and that to be
without end is to be immune from a kind of destruction. So we have two
triads again, but the second is lacking a more comprehensive term, and
this time the positive terms are paired with alpha-privatives instead of
with other positives.
immovable
“Pushing out equally” (44) and “inviolable” (48), one positive and one
privative, are on the good side. Thus this passage sums up the earlier
passages, in which one of each kind of predicate was a hero. Each op-
poses two mutually opposed contrary terms which would fall under its
(unmentioned) contradictory if the contradictory were mentioned. This
pattern differs from the preceding ones in that the only general term
we have is opposed to the only contraries we have and is not on their
side.
Thus Parmenides’ dyads and triads give us a fair sampling of logical
relationships—including agreement, incompatibility, being individually
necessary but jointly sufficient, contradictoriness, contrariety—in a uni-
verse which has a fair degree of complexity and which goes through
most of the permutations of positive and privative predicates. Let us
proceed for the moment under the assumption that all this is deliberate—
an assumption explicitly examined later. The following questions may
then be asked of a poem this rich and this careful: Why do four triads
appear in succession in lines 22—33? Why are the dyads concentrated in
lines 6—21? Why are single terms really not treated until 32? Why does
52 TERMS
the general term switch gears and oppose the two contraries only in 42—
49? If we can find answers to these questions, then we may also be able
to say that the facts the questions point to are deliberate.
Let me attempt to answer these questions by noting another feature
of the divisions of the poem and their characteristics. It may be useful
to divide fragment 8into sections (this division will be illustrated further
and justified in the next chapter): ‘
being, but of the routes; still, the words themselves are being accepted
or rejected, so these lines can find their place in the spectrum of Par-
menidean language (see n. 1 to this chapter). PartI thus contains all
possible sorts of pairs. In the following list, + or — outside the paren-
theses stands for affirmation or denial, respectively, and + or — inside
the parentheses represents positive or privative.
St ate, ungenerable, unperishing
— (— =) unthinkable, nameless
+ (4:4) to be, to be true
esi oho) coming-to-be, perishing
The section also includes two parallel triads which are denied; they are
parallel because in both cases nonbeing is the general term and two
contraries are the subordinate terms.
és out of what-is-not
is not
fsCss)
c(t wee)
He Gels?
+ (+ +)
—(+ +)
oe
Each triplet occupies the middle of one half of the structure and is
bracketed by a pair. The structure is symmetrical and circular. I am
speaking here only of the plus and minus signs, not of the number of
lines allotted to each portion.
Section IIJ.A features triads just as I featured pairs. Two positive triads
and one privative triad are affirmed, and one positive triad is denied.
Here, unlike in section I, all the members of each triad have the same
sign, either positive or privative. The first two triads, as explained earlier,
oppose each other, one denied positive and one affirmed (“divisible-
more-less” versus “similar-to cohere-all full”), and are devoted to the
signpost(s) “whole, of a single kind”; the third (“immovable-without be-
ginning-without end”) is an affirmed privative devoted to “unmoving,”
the next signpost, and the fourth, “the same—in the same place—by
itself,” sums up the section by combining elements of both signposts.
These are all the possibilities for triads all of whose members are of the
same sign—affirmation and denial of positives and affirmation of pri-
vatives—except the denial of privatives. And, in fact, the denial of a
single privative (“incomplete,” 32) immediately follows, inaugurating the
treatment of single predicates in section II.B, after the treatment of
doublets and triplets in the first two sections. “Incomplete” (which, of
course, looks forward to section III) and “lacking” are denied in close
connection in 32 and 33, and then “whole” and “immovable” (which, of
course, recapitulate the signposts of II.A) are affirmed because of Doom
(36-38); the sequence is thus
— (—) incomplete
— (+) lacking
+ (+) whole
+ (—) immovable
and covers all of the possibilities for singles. I call these single terms,
even though each is closely associated with another, because “whole” and
“immovable,” for example, do not seem as close together as “ungenera-
ble” and “unperishing,” since they are not proved or denied in the same
breath and are not opposed in meaning. Similarly, “unthinkable” and
“nameless” belong with each other in a way that “lacking” and “incom-
plete” do not, even though the denials of the two latter terms are con-
.
TERMS 55
I do not claim that every iota in the text falls into a scheme. But I think
the regularities, symmetries, and comprehensiveness are there. In par-
ticular, there seems to be clear evidence of an intention to cover all of
the possibilities for affirmation and denial on the monadic and dyadic
levels and a great many of the possibilities on the triadic level. (Levels
beyond these, it could be argued, are reducible to the first three.) More-
over, the levels appear to be separated from each other into argumen-
tatively distinct areas of the text. Finally, the third section of the poem
appears to be recapitulatory on the level of affirmation and negation
56 TERMS
just as it is on the level of meaning. One may conclude that, for Par-
menides, a full description of being was also a catalogue of the forms of
affirmation and denial, plus examples of every type of predication. The
connection between being and the logic of language appears to be tight.
Why do the doubles occur in the first section and the most prominent
triples in the second? The first section is concerned with time, the second
(literally or metaphorically) with space, of with the relation of masses to
places (see chapter 3 for partial justification of my argument here). Now
time has only one dimension of variation, whereas in the mass-place
section there are two dimensions. In time, to be other is to be earlier or
later; every point is saturated with contraries, and every point is both
later and earlier than other points simply in virtue of the nature of time.
So a mean between contraries is not possible in time; points can be
equidistant and that is all. If we consider the relationship between place
and mass, however, we see that the amount of mass per place does not
necessarily vary with place, and so a mean can exist—a set of places
which, in relation to other places, are free from contrariety as regards
their mass. Thus, a general term expressing the mean can be given in
opposition to the two contraries. In addition, an opposite to such a gen-
eral term can be denied in tandem with the two contraries, in opposition
to the mean and to two different terms allied with it, as in lines 22—25.
Neither of these situations is possible with respect to time. Thus it is
possible to affirm and deny certain sorts of contradictory triples about
space, but not about time. And dyads flourish where there is no mean.
There are kinds of triples that can be affirmed in connection with
time, but they are not like the spatial triples. The triples that have to do
with time either express something which is not directly concerned with
the contrariety characteristic of time (like “immovable-without begin-
ning-without end” in 26-27; since time itself does not require starts and
stops, a startless and stopless mean can be affirmed just as a mean
amount of mass was affirmed in the case of place). Or, a triple connected
with the denial of contraries will deny them, but with an unrestrictedly
negative term as the general term, like “out of what-is-not—later—ear-
lier” in 7-10. The use of such a term is necessary, I would suggest,
because no particular or determinately negative term can be used in
opposition to a nonexistent mean. The only term that can cover both
contraries is itself not the opposite of any particular mean and so is
entirely negative.
Thus the denial of dyads and the affirmation of contradictory dyads
are characteristic of time, while triads with finite or determinate general
terms will be characteristic of the mass-place section; only triads with an
unrestrictedly negative term, or those which do not intrinsically oppose
time’s saturated contrariety, will be used of time. This is, I think, a
\
TERMS 57
These reasons, of course, unlike the previous set, are thematic, not
formal or logical. Yet there is a natural relationship between the two. A
logical tool-kit whose purpose is to display all sorts of structural and
argumentative relationships among terms will not necessarily begin with
the simplest building block, but it may begin with the most fruitful one.
And the marriage of singles and dyads to produce triplets may begin
more fruitfully with the internal dialectic of two than with the abstract
independence of one. Moreover, three and one (assuming that one is
combining and separating terms) can be reached more easily from two
than from each other. Two is at the midpoint; it represents a type of
contrariety that this poem, among all others, cannot leave alone; it must
either expel it or tame it or both. The sequence as a whole is one in
which dyadic contrariety is first expelled, then incorporated into triads,
and then reconciled into a harmonious unity; dyads are thus both a
natural starting point for the theme and a logical underpinning for the
formal structures of affirmation and denial.
Thus I suggest that the near-completion of table 2.2 captures a delib-
erate feature of the poem’s presentation. The numbers of terms (single,
double, and triple) make them fit into specific sections of the poem, and
the range of discourse (covering affirmation and denial, positivity and
privativeness) shows the scope of rational speech. The connections in
meaning and proof between terms of different types show that the same
‘point can be expressed in many different ways. The types of inference
and logical/argumentative connection treated earlier are part of the same
sort of composition, one which fructifies into an impressively varied ar-
ray. I claim later that the logical laws are visible in generating the un-
derlying calculus in which terms and judgments are varied in sign and
TABLE 2.2
Affirmed (+) or Positive Privative
denied (—) term (+) term (—)
Singles Be whole immovable
(sec. II.B) — lacking incomplete
Doubles Ae to be and ungenerable
(sec. I) to be true unperishing
= coming-to-be unthinkable
perishing nameless
Triples - the same immovable
(sec. II.A) in the same without beginning
by itself without end
- divisible
more oe
less
60 TERMS
then related to each other in meaning and proof in most of the possible
combinations—a good way of jogging readers into an understanding of
the laws. :
Let me make a few more suggestions. First, to expand on what was
said earlier, the triples may be combinations of the singles and the dou-
bles not only in number but also in mode. Some of the doubles exhibit
the contrariety characteristic of the subordinate terms in almost all the
triples, and the single terms (e.g., “immovable,” which is both a single
and a constituent of a triple in 38 and 26) can become the topmost
general terms of the triples when the doubles are joined to them. Thus
the triples could be said to incorporate the structure as well as the num-
ber of elements of one single and one double. This is mirrored by their
placement in the poem between doubles and singles. Second, I men-
tioned earlier that the singles and doublets contain specimens of every
type of assertion while the triplets lack the denial of a privative, and that
the triplets come at the end of the argument proper, just before the
recapitulatory section. Consider again the sequence in section II.A,
which has many more triplets than any other section. If there were a full
spectrum of positives and negatives, we would expect the denial of pri-
vatives to occur at the very end, after their affirmation with “immovable-
without being-without end.” But there is no denied privative triple in the
poem. Instead there is, once more, the affirmation of a positive triad.
Dare I suggest that this positive triad is standing in for the expected
denied negatives as their double-negation? “The same—in the same
place—by itself,” after all, encapsulates section II.A, as was explained
earlier. And, if this is the end of the argument, isn’t it possible that a
form of closure could be attained by rounding off the poem’s construc-
tive sections with an unequivocally positive assertion? I suggest that we
are to interpret Parmenides as producing a deliberately incomplete cat-
alogue. The reader’s attention is certainly supposed to be drawn, first by
the negations, then by the many kinds of statements contained in the
poem. When one sees that these fall into groups, and that the poem is
very carefully put together, one is tempted to attribute to the author the
intention of showing how one thing can be written in many different
ways, plus the desire to show the ways themselves as examples of rules
of transformation which relate positives to negatives. One then may con-
clude that the rules according to which the catalogue was generated can
be invoked in order to explain why certain of the most complicated ele-
ments (the denied alpha-privative triplets) are missing from the cata-
logue—one may suppose that the denied privatives are replaced by
affirmed positives in order to show that two negatives make a positive.
The catalogue is deliberately left incomplete in order to test the reader’s
understanding of the reasons for its construction. Without the deliberate
\
TERMS 61
think a desire for poetic variation alone could have produced the array
of predications that I describe. This author was not one for whom neg-
atives and positives had merely rhetorical significance.
The goddess’s speech is a deliberate survey of the forms of logic and
inference in discourse about being. An opposition between ontology (and
Parmenides’ is of the most transcendent sort) and logic (his is of the most
formal sort) does not occur in Parmenides as, for example, it presents
itself historically as splits between positions in twentieth-century philos-
ophy. His insight is that, while logic merely expresses being, being is
nothing to us unless it is spoken according to trustworthy rules; this
insight transcends both sides of the contemporary split and incorporates
both. If abstracted from the goddess’s speech, the laws are merely con-
ventions; but if spoken without the laws, being becomes merely illusion
or falsehood. I show in chapter 6 how this two-way connection between
speech and being is rendered possible for Parmenides because both are,
in a deep sense, bounded.
CHAPTER 3
Contraries
65
66 CONTRARIES
diaireton (“divisible,” line 22), ouk eon (“what-is-not,” line 46). Then there
is the third alternative, a partial one involving contrariety, which must
be ruled out in order to distinguish clearly the univocally positive alter-
native from the negative one, so that the positive one can then be chosen:
husteron-prosthen (“later-earlier,’ in 10), mallon-cheiroteron (“more-less”
in 23-24), meizon-baioteron (“bigger-smaller” in 44-45), mallon-hésson
(“more-less” in 48). The terms having tosdo with coming-to-be and per-
ishing in 13—14, 21, and 27, though they are opposed, are, I think, part
of the picture involving terms generally rather than contraries specifi-
cally, because they are not adjectives or adverbs envisioned as applying
to what-is. The contraries, moreover, are all elements of triples discussed
in the preceding chapter.
This sequence of the three alternatives occurs three times in the
poem—in lines 6-11, 22-25, and 42—49. Since the world view of the
“Opinion” section involves contrarieties (Fire and Night) which, unlike
those in the “Truth” section, are reified rather than being relational
predicates, it is worth examining the “Truth” section in order to deter-
mine why and how the contraries are rejected there, and in particular
whether there is any reason why the contrarieties are rejected three
times, and whether there are any differences in the sorts of contrariety
being rejected.
There is another reason why the selection of contraries as foci of the
argument is not arbitrary. As mentioned in chapter 2, each of the sign-
posts introduced in lines 3—4 is proved, more or less, separately in the
poem. The signposts “ungenerable” and “unperishing” are argued for
in 6—21; “whole of a single kind” in 22-25; “unmoving” is first asserted
in 26—28; and whatever the last signpost was is first mentioned in 32
and then given a more extensive treatment in 42—49. That is, the core
treatment of each signpost (except “unmoving,” which is proved on the
basis of the two preceding signposts) corresponds to one of the passages
where contraries occur. The affirmation of most of these signposts in-
volves the negation of contraries in such a way that, if the contraries
were to hold of what-is, the signpost would have to be denied; conse-
quently, to affirm the signpost is to deny the contraries. “Ungenerable”
and “unperishing” have “later-earlier’; “whole” has mallon-cheiroteron
(“more-less”); and the signpost whose meaning is “perfect” or “complete”
has two pairs, both parallel to mallon-cheiroteron: meizon-baioteron (“bigger-
smaller”) and mallon-hésson (“more-less”). I claim that the different pairs
of contraries correspond to real differences in the poem’s treatment of
what-is. The contraries are not just rejected all at once. Rather, each pair
corresponds to a definite situation or phase in a method of one-many
variation. The conclusion is that being is here said to be one in three
different ways, corresponding to the three groups of signposts, except
x
CONTRARIES 67
“unmoving,” and that the four pairs of contraries betoken three ways of
not-being-one which are rejected. I analyze the passages in which the
contraries occur in the “Truth” section and then draw the conclusions
just summarized.
There are intriguing differences in the wording of these three pas-
sages. The first is phrased as the question why what-is should be occupied
by either contrary (lines 9-11). The second deals with one contrary ap-
plying to some degree somewhere (¢é), and then with the other, in an
almost leisurely way, as if the contraries could be treated independently,
though the tone of “neither ... nor ... nor” is stronger than that of a
question, stronger than that of lines 9-11. And in the third passage,
lines 42—49, it is clear not only that neither contrary is acceptable to any
degree, wherever either might apply (té é té, “here or there”), but also
that both are unacceptable, that one cannot apply here and the other
there (té mallon téi d’hésson, “here more and there less”). Why the differ-
ences? And why the alternations, in the statement of the contrarieties
rejected, between an “or” formulation (“later or earlier” or “later rather
than earlier,” line 10), a “neither-nor-nor” formulation (lines 22—25 and
44-45), and a “not-and” formulation (lines 47-48)? Are these simply
literary variations, or are they also logical? And, if they are also logical,
what is the logical point? What might be the underlying machinery that
generates the pattern according to which they are arrayed?
Even if they are literary variations, they are variations with logical
overtones. An alternation between “or,” “neither-nor,” and “not-and” for-
mulations of similar points, given the results of chapters 1—2, leads one
to suspect not only that Parmenides was aware of these differences and
connections among conjunctive and disjunctive formulations of similar
points—which he must have been, even if his purpose were merely lit-
erary—but also that he set them in that order for a reason, even if only
to display all the different variations on similar points. The differences
in the ways contraries are pinned down naturally lead one to suspect
that the contraries are seen as applying in different ways in each of the
different passages. Of course, it is first necessary to show that the pas-
sages in question do contain alist of all the variations in the application
of contraries that are possible in a Parmenidean discourse on Truth.
The following, then, are questions that stand in need of an answer.
They are not answered fully by the single hypothesis that contyaries are
being rejected; I propose to explain them. (1) Why are there alternations
between conjunctive and disjunctive formulations in the rejections, of
contraries? (2) Why are the contraries rejected singly, with an intervening
explanation for each in the second part of the line, in lines 23 and 24,
and together, without intervention, in lines 44—45 and 48? (3) Why does
Parmenides use a single ¢é, “here,” in lines 22—25 and two occurrences
68 CONTRARIES
of té: in 44—45 and 47-48? And why is there no similar specifying device
in lines 9-11? Do these differences in formulation carry any import for
the interpretation of the manner in which the contraries apply?
Of the three passages in which contraries occur, the most difficult
(according to Hermann Diels!) is found in 22-25:
oude diaireton estin, epei pan estin homoion.
oude ti téi mallon, to ken eirgoi min sunechesthai,
oude ti cheiroteron, pan d’empleon estin eontos.
toi xuneches pan estin. eon gar eonti pelazei.
[Nor is it divisible, since it is all alike. Nor is it here somewhat more, which
might prevent it from cohering, nor somewhat less, but all of it is full of
what-is. And all of it is cohesive, for what-is draws near to what-is.]
I take these lines to represent Parmenides’ proof for, or offering of
considerations in support of, the attribute “whole” he announced earlier
in the list of signposts, also “of a single kind.” The lines, as stated earlier,
both deny what would be inappropriate for what-is and assert what is
appropriate. Each of the clauses introduced by “nor” is opposed and
counterbalanced by a clause affirming the contradictory of what the
“nor”-clause denies. Very generally, these lines seem to be saying that
what-is is not divisible because it is all homogeneous; that it is not more
anywhere, because then it would fail to cohere; and that it is not less,
because all of it is equally full of what-is. In what follows I skirt the
question whether the spatial language is meant metaphorically or liter-
ally.
The first problem of interpretation in these lines is the following: what
is Parmenides talking about when he denies “divisible,” “more,” and
“less” of what-is? The basic language seems to be that of mass and place;
is he asserting that what-is is or is like a finitely large, spatially homo-
geneous mass? ‘Taran sees the lines as saying that, since what-is is every-
where self-identical, no distinction in it is possible. Mourelatos? suggests
the lines imply that “it is all of the same stock. It is not thicker, or bigger,
or stronger here, and thinner, or smaller, or weaker there. Rather, all of
it is evenly and tightly packed or distributed, and the constituents agree
out of mutual affinity . . . [or] it cannot be separated or segregated into
two classes: good or noble, on the one side, and bad or common, on the
other.”* These are only part of a forest of problems of interpretation. In
section II of this chapter, I address these problems on a more detailed
textual level. In section III, the thread of the overall interpretation re-
sumes.
The problems posed by lines 22—25 may be grouped around the follow-
ing topics. (1) Which signpost is being proved here, how is it to be rep-
\
CONTRARIES 69
resented in a critical text of B8.4, and what does it mean in those lines?
(2) Is Parmenides here talking about spatial or temporal homogeneity?
In what follows I engage in dialogue with Mourelatos, Stokes, Taran, and
Owen.
As for B8.4, most people today read oulon mounogenes te, which might
be rendered as “whole and single”* or “whole and of a single kind”® or
“whole and only-begotten,”® rather than a variant reading, est gar oulo-
meles (“for it is whole in limb”), found in Plutarch (Pros Koloteén 1114C11).
The question of whether the Parmenidean what-is can tolerate a nu-
merical plurality, such as that apparently envisaged by “whole in limb,”
immediately arises. The picture is further complicated by the interpre-
tation of Untersteiner, who argues for the existence of such a plurality,
partly on the basis of his adoption of “whole in limb.” The reading risks
being associated with the thesis that what-is consists in such a plurality,
and the reading “whole and of a single kind” risks association with the
thesis that what-is is absolutely one in the sense that no parts or elements
can be distinguished in it. I accept the reading “whole and of a single
kind,” because the objections offered to it need not hold,’ but neither
reading is decisive on the question whether what-is, while remaining one,
might not have some kind of interior plurality. “Whole in limb” has no
more connotation of a unity formed out of a diversity than does “cohe-
sive” or “what-is draws close to what-is” in 25. Conversely, if, as Moure-
latos claims, “whole and of a single kind” can mean an absence of inner
contrariness and strife,® there is nothing to prevent sucha whole from
being like a handful of taffy or a block of ice, a glob composed entirely
of a single sort of stuff, without being inhomogeneous or interrupted by
gaps. Thus far one may agree with Untersteiner, who remarks, “Ma
questa sunecheia non esclude la pluralita di homoia che stanno uniti in un
oulon”—(to paraphrase) the coherence which “cohesive” attributes to
what-is is not incompatible with a plurality of similar things which stand
together united in a whole.® (I discuss the question of divisibility later.)
But whether “whole and of a single kind” is to be read, with Stokes, as
implying an entire absence of interior multiplicity depends on how one
reads 22~25. Mourelatos is right in claiming that “of a single kind” need
not describe only a single thing; but I have argued against the view of
fragment 8 as applying de dicto to namings oi many things. The reading
“whole and of a single kind,” then, is acceptable and need not by itself
commit one either to absolute unity or to numerical plurality on the part
of what-is or of the things that truly are. Solmsen says that the “whole
in limb” reading might make more sense of lines 4—21 of the fragment:
“It would be defensible to prefer ... the minority reading esti gar oulo-
meles, especially if we understand séma (v.2) as a poetic equivalent of
sémeion ( = “proof” ...) in Melissus B8.1.... On this view, 8.4—21 (note
70 CONTRARIES
the last verse) would indeed be a full and coherent presentation of the
proofs (or sémata) for agenéton and andlethron.”!° Solmsen himself favors
“of a single kind” as emphasizing the singleness or solitariness of what-
is; it is “the Hesiodic (or epic? see esp. Theog. 426) word for an only
child.”' Here the connotation of “the only one in its family” would apply
literally to what-is, while the connotation of “begetting” (rightly objected
to, if taken in the sense of having a beginning in time, by Burnet!2) would
be ironically ruled out here. But it is hard to see what Solmsen means
in his statement of the case for the minority opinion. Jf whatever occurs
in the first part of line 4 is in some way connected with 22—25—as seems
likely, even given only that the last signpost in the line, whose meaning
is “complete,” is shown in 32-33 and 42—49—and if 22-25 are not pri-
marily temporal in meaning (as I claim later), then lines 4-21 are not
all commentary on “ungenerable” and “imperishable.” It has been sug-
gested to me that the est? gar, “for it is,” before “whole in limb” may be
part of Plutarch’s text and not Parmenides’;!’ if so, then “whole in limb”
may be a misquotation from memory, and there is no reason to take
line 4 as part of the argumentative support for line 3.
The words “whole and of a single kind” announce what is to be proved
in 22-25. There seems to be no clear separation in proof between
“whole” and “of a single kind,” though there is a separation between
“whole” and “unmoving,” which is discussed in 26-28, even though a
later statement of the lack of motion of what-is (“to be whole and im-
movable,” line 38) treats that lack as being just as closely connected with
“whole” (however close that is) as “of a single kind” is in line 4. Somehow,
what-is is a whole which is of a single kind, or the only one of its kind,
and unmoving; somehow “whole” comes first.
Next, however, one runs up against the fact that there is an assertion
in B8.5—6, starting in the next line after “whole and of a single kind,”
which has some vocabulary in common with 22-25, but whose relations
with the list of signposts and with the argument beginning in line 6,
immediately after the assertion, are controversial, as is its translation.
The assertion is “nor was it nor will it be, since it is now all together one,
cohesive.”'* The variant given by Ammonius cannot be fitted in with 22—
25, since, though it asserts mounon, “single,” it denies that what-is is homou
pan, “all together,” and we hear pan homoion, “all similar,” in 22.15
The following are elements of common vocabulary between lines 5—6
and lines 22—25: Pan (“all”) and related words occur in a cluster in 22—
25 (pan homovon, “all similar,” pan empleon . . . eontos, “all full of what-is,”
both in 24, and xuneches pan, “all cohesive,” in 25), as do suneches-words
(sunechesthaz, “to cohere,” in 23, xuneches pan in 25). Given this clustering,
it is reasonable to suppose that lines 5—6 also have something to do with
what is announced, with “whole and of a single kind” in 4, as to be proved
*
CONTRARIES 71
sive” have to do with the homogeneity of the single what-is; “one” here
functions as one element in a wider context.!” This said, one has disso-
ciated oneself from any a priori claims about Plato’s comprehension of
Parmenides and about the adequacy of Neoplatonic readings of the his-
torical or dialogical Parmenides. But it is still Sees that “one” is
not explicitly mentioned again, even though, asI suggest below, lines 5—
6 are not part of the signpost-list proper. I shall say below that Stokes is
essentially right in claiming that 5—6 present a prospective picture of the
entire argument as well as an index to the signposts. Since this is so, the
application of “one” is not necessarily restricted to the context of 22-25,
the question about the oneness of being in Parmenides ought not to be
settled either by taking Platonic and/or Neoplatonic testimony for
granted or by thinking that assigning “one” an important role in Par-
menides is improbable because of the fact (which I agree with) that Plato
makes the Parmenides of the dialogue focus on oneness rather than on
the eon, “what-is,” of the historical Parmenides. “One” and “being” in
Melissus may in places be functioning as practically interchangeable
names, which they would need to do if there is only one thing.’
Given that 5-6 have some relation to 22-25, and so, presumably, to
the “whole and of a single kind” of line 4, it remains to be determined
what that relation is. The textual problem is set by the following facts.
Line 5 begins with a “nor,” which may be continuative; it contains a
“since,” which introduces something that argumentatively supports what
is said just before the “since”; and line 6, “for which birth would you
seek for it,” has a “for” near the beginning, which may indicate that the
72 CONTRARIES
depends on “one” in the proof. Line 5 and the first part of line 6, then,
summarize the signposts and encapsulate the proof, but are not part of
the proof proper, which begins in the second part of line 6 with “for
what birth... ?” The “for” indicates that the question “for what birth
would you seek for it?” is at least related to what has just been said (“nor
was it nor will it be, for it is now...” in line 5, also probably to “ungen-
erable unperishing” in line 3); it may also mark the transition to the
proof proper. The “for” indicates that what is being considered in the
question “what birth?” is going to serve as support for something that
goes before, and this is what happens, since the question cannot be an-
swered for the Parmenidean what-is, as the succeeding lines (7—15) show.
But the “for” does not, I think, have to mean that what begins in line 6
supports only what immediately precedes the “for” (say, lines 5—6); these
lines do not have to be construed as containing signposts not already
listed in lines 3—4 or as saying something not anticipated in those lines.
This is so even though (since 6-15 support‘ ‘now” in 5 and‘ ‘ungenerable”
in 3) the “for” is not only continuative and explicative but also logical in
meaning. (Further commentary on lines 6—15 is provided in chapter 4.)
Given that the list of signposts proper ends with the end of line 4, that
there is heavy stress on the unity of what-is, and that the signposts proved
in lines 22—25 are “whole and of a single kind,” it remains to be deter-
mined what Parmenides is talking about in lines 22-25. Owen has
claimed that the lines refer to the temporal indivisibility and continuity of
what-is. The argument is too complicated to summarize in detail here.
To the objections already raised by Stokes, I have only this to add.”» Owen
argues that lines 22-25 have as a premise the successful conclusion of
the temporality-argument in 6—21; even if this is so, it does not by itself
show that lines 22-25 are temporal, since they would presuppose the
temporality-conclusion even if they were spatial. Spatial cohesiveness can-
not be proved if part, or all, of the spatial whole is exposed to the risk
of coming-into-being or going-out-of-being.
Moreover, Owen feels that, in two of the three occurrences where epez,
“because, since,” in fragment 8 is found at the beginning of major ar-
gument-sections of the poem (namely 27 and 42), it introduces some-
thing previously proved. Indeed, in these two occurrences epei does
introduce something previously proved. The feeling is then that, since
the eper in 22 also occurs at or near the beginning of a major argument-
section, it, too, ought to introduce something previously proved: It would
be nice if it did, but one cannot argue that it must, first, because it is
very difficult to say that 27 is the beginning of a major argument-section
(it introduces the demonstration of “unmoving,” but 22-23 constitute a
single section in which, as 29—31 indicate, “unmoving” is seen together
with “whole and of a single kind”), and, second, because, of the three
74 CONTRARIES
an antecedent for “similar” just because of the epe: which introduces it—
we would also then need one for “inviolate” in 48—and spatial homo-
geneity is not proved as such in lines 6-15. Mourelatos cites line 11 as
containing a general principle that might apply to spatial or to qualitative
“altogetherness” as well as to temporal; I discuss this in chapter 4. Many
points in the structure of fragment 8 remain obscure, and some, I think,
become less obscure if one resists the urge to find a sequence of proof
in which each assertion has a clearly specifiable antecedent. My proposal,
though it is highly structured, does not attempt this, and what generates
the assertions is not so much a formal pattern of proof in the strict sense
(where is the assumed “to cohere” in 23 proved, rather than asserted?) as
a method of exhausting alternatives which are generated by an under-
lying pattern of one-many variations. Owen’s desire to read homoion
(“alike”) as adverbial in line 22 came from the feeling that an adjectival
homoion (on his reading of 6-21, in which adverbial totality is shown
there) would have represented the introduction of a previously unproved
premise. But this is perhaps not such a dangerous alternative to fall into.
Our calling a given assertion unproved does not mean that we would
have to fill the gap with a view of Parmenides in terms taken from
previous cosmologists, which is what Owen was trying to avoid. Given
the nontemporality of 22-25, I see no alternative to saying that 22—
though logically different from what precedes and follows it in a method
which (I claim below) adds up in its totality to proof—is not the strict
argumentative consequence of anything before it. This, if my conclusions
are accepted, will be harmless.
Finally, as Mourelatos and Stokes have pointed out, the language of
22-25 is compatible with a ruling out of variations in qualitative intensity
as well as with a(literal or metaphorical) ruling out of variations in the
amount of mass in different places, variations in density.?° “More” and
“less” are shorthand for these variations.
I proceed by taking the point of lines 22—25 to be that what-is is, in some
fundamental—perhaps physical—sense, a unity in the sense that in-
equalities and divisions are not found in it. Indeed, the underlying im-
agery (“divisible,” “to cohere,” “full,” “draws near to”) is that of the
distribution of a mass in space or in place. I take this as being perhaps
metaphorical—or at least capable of covering qualitative homogeneity
and variation, and equal or varied intensity—and I take it that Parmen-
ides, while not committed by these lines to the assertion that what-is is a
mass in space, still found in the consideration of masses in space a con-
venient embodiment for the sorts of relations he was concerned with. As
76 CONTRARIES
when he compares what-is with a ball in lines 42-49, the language here
is not necessarily literally meant; the boundaries between the ball and
what-is are very hard to draw. I suggest, then, that we are being asked
to imagine a field of places—“place” in the sense of a container for
mass—together with a mass which is to be distributed across the field of
places in an equal or cohesive manner, as if we set a block of ice on a
piece of graph paper or poured water into the many divisions of an ice-
tray. I imagine what-is as being like a single, cohesive, homogeneous
stuff, like taffy, a concretized mass-term all gathered together. That there
is a field of places which coheres does not mean that there are boundaries
or junctures within the field. In making this imaginative experiment, I
am responding to language which—whether metaphorical or not—is
within the text. The denial of “divisible,” then, means either that there
is no place within the field of places which is completely without mass,
or that all the places have the same amount of mass; the denials of “more”
and “less” mean, respectively, that no place has less mass. “More” and
“less” than what? I attempt to explain this below.
Herein, however, lies the second problem of interpretation. If “divis-
ible” simply means that there is a difference, within what-is, between the
amount of mass in one place and the amount of mass in some other
place, then to rule out “divisible” (as Parmenides does when he says “all
of it is alike”) is also to rule out “more” and “less.” Why, then, would he
repeat himself, amplifying his point at the sacrifice of argumentative
economy? The other possibility is that Parmenides means by “divisible”
the existence of a fracture in what-is, or (to use the language of masses
in places) the existence of a place which has none of the mass of what-
is in it. But here, too, there are difficulties: first, such a place would
certainly be “less” than the other places which did have mass in them,
and they would certainly be “more” than it, so that Parmenides would
again be repeating himself; second, if “divisible” meant that there would
be an empty place dividing what-is from itself, then “all of it is similar”
would have to mean not “having an equal mass at every place” but simply
“having mass.” (Barnes has a similar difficulty with both bigger and
smaller.*°) On either interpretation of “divisible,” then, Parmenides ends
up repeating himself. I offer no explanation for the fact that he does,
unless he is independently and for reasons of his own interested in triads
where the two contrary terms are subsumed under the general term (as
suggested in chapter 2) and in the different ways in which contraries can
apply, as is discussed below. .
Similar problems occur in lines 23 and 24. These problems go back
to Diels,*! whose difficulty was that it seemed in line 23 that “which would
prevent it from cohering” could not be the answer to “nor is it here
somewhat bigger,” because (to paraphrase) what spoils the cohesiveness
CONTRARIES 77
of a whole is not the existence in it of parts which have more mass than
others, but rather the existence of parts which have less mass than others.
That is, one would have expected “less,” not “more,” to oppose “which
would prevent it from cohering.” And yet, in the next line, “all of it is
full of what-is” seems to be a perfect answer to “nor somewhat less,” since
to deny that one place in what-is has less mass is to affirm that no place
is defective in mass, that is, that all the places are equally full of mass.
Because of these difficulties, Gomperz was even led to postulate a radical
reorganization of the order of lines in the passage, a reorganization
objected to adequately by Diels on philological grounds.*? So line 22,
where “all similar” seemed to cause difficulties with the “fracture” inter-
pretation of “divisible,” would not be the only line which seems to lack
an adequate positive answer to a predicate denied in the “nor”-clause.
At this point there are several alternatives, short of junking the lines
or ignoring them. We could take both “all of it is full of what-is” and
“which would prevent it from cohering” as being directed against “less”—
but that would leave “more” without an answer, which would be unac-
ceptable. We could propose that all of the positive statements—“all sim-
ilar,” “cohesive,” and “all of it is full of what-is’—are different ways of
saying the same thing, in such a way that each of these positive statements
opposes all of the negative statements. Or, we could argue that “which
would prevent it from cohering” is an adequate answer to the denial in
“nor is it here somewhat more.” Let me treat this third argument briefly.
Sunechesthai (“to cohere”) and suneches (“cohesive”) seem to be words
with a fairly wide resonance; they seem not only to have the meanings
just given, but also those involved in “to draw together” (in the sense of
retreating from an attack), “joining,” and “holding together.”* If the
word is taken this way, then it seems reasonable that “more” should be
opposed by “to cohere.” For—to form a mental picture that might not
have occurred to Diels—the existence of a lump in a mass of dough, that
is, the existence within what-is of a place that has more mass, does prevent
the mass (what-is) from cohering, in the sense that the unit of greater
mass not only fails to cohere with the other units of mass in the sense of
being equal to them, but actually prevents (eirgoi, “would prevent”) the
mass as a whole from drawing together (sunechesthat) in a uniform way,
because it obtrudes and is not homogeneous. Whereas, if part of the
mass is smaller, nothing prevents the mass as a whole from drawing
together and expelling the empty space. So the present conjecture is that
“to cohere” is an appropriate answer to “here somewhat more”—just as
appropriate, in its way, as “all full” is to “less.”
I return for a moment to the predicate “divisible.” We saw that “sim-
ilar” did not seem to be an adequate answer to taking a “division” as a
fracture, and that “similar” did seem to be adequate if the division is
78 CONTRARIES
Just a difference in mass between one place and another. I do not attempt
to resolve this question here, except to point out a consequence that
seems to follow on either interpretation. Either way, as mentioned in
chapter 2, “divisible” is the more extreme case of which “more” and
“less” are less extreme cases: if “divisible” just means that not all the
parts are the same in mass, then “more” and “less” detail, respectively,
the two possible ways in which the parts might not be the same; whereas,
if “divisible” means that some place has no mass, then that place is ab-
solutely smaller than the other places which are absolutely bigger than
it, so here too “divisible,” while being broader and more inclusive than
either “more” or “less” taken by itself, also represents the limiting case
for the application of these two subordinate relative terms. Why then
does Parmenides duplicate his argument? I leave this question unan-
swered for the moment, except to note that similar things happen in
lines 6-15, where coming-to-be later or earlier is considered after com-
ing-to-be out of what-is-not; and in lines 42—49, where being here bigger
and there smaller is taken up after consideration of the possibility that
what-is-not might interrupt what-is (which would make what-is less).
Before proceeding, I would like to address a possible objection to my
use of the terms “mass” and “place.” I have already proposed that the
language of lines 22-25 is possibly metaphorical. But Taran might object
that it is illegitimate to use “mass” and “place” as terms of analysis, since
Parmenides is clearly denying, not only an inequality or lack of cohe-
siveness in the body of what-is, but also the very applicability of the
notion of place—in particular, of the notion that there are many different
places in what-is. The logical simplicity of what-is asserted in these lines,
one might say, rules out even the bare and abstract sort of plurality
involved in the notion of many places.
This objection goes too far beyond the text. The text does not rule out
that there be many places; it rules out only that the places be different
from one another with respect to the amount of mass they contain. More-
over, even if we assume that Parmenides would not have wanted what-is
to be subject to the sorts of contrarieties and asymmetries involved in
the occupations of real places by real masses, still there is nothing to
suggest that he would have ruled out the abstract sort of plurality-in-
unity that is called to mind by terms like “cohesive” and “all full.” Or, as
I shall claim later, it is possible that an abstract plurality is called into
play only to remove the differences and contrarieties that would make
its members different from each other, so that—with contraries re-
moved—the members can again collapse into a unity.
I take it, then, that Parmenides is concerned in lines 22—25 to rule out
certain defective kinds of unification in what-is. In “nor is it divisible”
he rules out that some place might have a different amount of mass than
CONTRARIES 79
the others or have no mass; in “all of it is similar” he states that all the
places have equal amounts of mass. With “nor is it here somewhat more”
he denies that some place might have a greater amount of mass; with
“which might prevent it from cohering” he asserts that the existence of
more mass in a place would mean that what-is would fail to be cohesive.
Finally, with “nor somewhat less” he denies the alternative involving a
smaller amount of mass; with “all of it is full of what-is” he states that
every place has an amount of mass which is not less than the amount of
mass in any other place. Each denial is followed by its corresponding
contrapositive assertion.
The third problem of interpretation in lines 22-25 is posed by the
word ¢é (“here” or “this way”) in line 23. This problem is set forth by
Diels.** He said that a single té is somewhat incongruous in this context.
The problem is caused by the fact that té is not repeated in line 24, “nor
is it somewhat less,” after it appears in line 23, oude ti tér mallon, “nor is
it here somewhat more.” But in this context it might be thought natural
to expect a téi... téi, “here ... there,” construction such as the one that
Parmenides uses in line 48, té mallon téi d’hésson, “here more and there
less.” Or, in line 23, the first té could have been dropped, giving the
sense “nor is it more ... nor is it less.”
What motivates the feeling that there is an incongruity here is the fact
that, if something is more somewhere, it must be less somewhere else, as
Parmenides himself seems to realize in line 48. Why not indicate the
second point with ¢é as well as the first? Or, if one is not going to indicate
the second, why bother to indicate the first? It is, | think, worth trying
to explain the lines without Stein’s emendation of pé for téi, “nor is it in
some way more.” The feeling recently has been that this is not so much
the anomaly that it was for Diels*> as a context in which we are to under-
stand what Owen calls an “implicit answering ¢é”*° in line 23.
In fact it is not the case that a single t@, meaning “here” or “there,”
needs an answering #é in Parmenides. The argument that there has to
be an implicit answer comes from the contraries but not from the té&
itself. In Bl, line 4, t@22 means “there”—on the route—in both of its oc-
currences. The second occurrence echoes the first, and since té2 can mean
“that way,” the two occurrences denote the same place (the road), or
path, or direction, echoing rather than contrasting with each other.
Line 20 of fragment 1 is formulaic, but the té: adds dramatic effect—
“right through those doors there!” and clearly has a component of spatial
location in its meaning. “There (té) the bright flame of Fire” (B8.56) is
in contrast to “but off by itself is the other, dark Night” (B8.58—59), and
the contrast, whether or not it has specifically spatial purpose, helps to
locate the two contrary forms as apart from each other in whatever sense;
the mortals attempt to make a daring and dramatic distinction which, as
80 CONTRARIES
Fobod 4
The pictures lend themselves naturally to what seems to be imagined in
lines 22—24. A coherence, a joining, would be interrupted if what-is were
here somewhat more; the contraries “more” and “less” are trying to
breach the defenses in the ordered and coherent array of what-is and
are driven off. There is no distinguishable focal or nodal point, of stress
or of weakness, which is in danger of being penetrated or being made
into a highway for opposing forces. Being is secure.
Téi é téi, “here or there” (Parmenides B8.45), is not a Homeric expres-
sion; Hesiod uses téi kai téi, “to and fro,” with reference to the swimming
of dolphins, darting about this way and that, Aspis 210. Ta. . . té, téi men
... tei de (Empedocles B61.3—4), “here ... there,” and ¢té haz téi, “here
and there,” are familiarly used, in later philosophical contexts, either in
opposition to pantéi, “everywhere” (as in Parmenides B8.45), or in con-
texts where the local variability characteristic of the sense-world is being
stressed as against the changelessness and lack of variability of eternal
things, for example, absolute Beauty, which is not beautiful in one way
(téi men) and ugly in another (¢é d’) (Plato, Symposium 210E6—211A2), or
Parmenides B8.49, té mallon té d’hésson, “here more and there less.”
Thus, first, it is reasonable to take the single ¢é in lines 22-25 as
referring to a single point among many at which a coherence is inter-
rupted, and there is no need for an explicit antecedent or subsequent
specifying word in order for the té to have this meaning. Second, in
general, a single #é stands for a single point or way, so two occurrences
of té stand for two different points or ways.*?
But let us suppose for a moment that the case is not decided by the
considerations that have just been introduced, and examine interpreta-
tions in the abstract for a moment. Parmenides says “nor is it here some-
what more ... nor somewhat less.” The following interpretations are
possible: Parmenides means us to understand a second (é in line 23; the
lines bear the sense “nor is it here somewhat more ... nor is it there
somewhat less” (and so on for every pair of places); or Parmenides means
us to understand that a single ¢é suffices for both line 23 and line 24;
the lines bear the sense “nor is it more at some place. . . nor is it less at
82 CONTRARIES
that place” (and so on for every single place). I say “and so on,” and this
is clearly what is meant. He writes “nor is it here somewhat more,” and
one asks, “where?” Clearly the answer is “anywhere.” The first possibility
says that it is not the case that some place is more than some other place
which is less; the second says that it is not the case-that some place is
more or less. The choice between these two possibilities is a choice be-
tween two methods of treatment of contraries. The first takes all the
places two by two and denies that any pairs of places, one of which is
more than the other which is less, can exist within what-is; the second
takes each place, one by one, and asks of it, first whether it is more, and
then whether it is less. In the first, the contrast is between one place and
one other place, with the first place more than the other which is less
(and, by extension, to a similar situation in the case of any pair of places);
in the second, the contrast is between more and less, as first one, and
then the other, predicate applies to some single place (and, by extension,
to each place within the compass of what-is). I suggest a decision between
these two possibilities in a moment.
First, however, a further question arises: more or less than what? Here
again there are two possible answers, given that, in line 48, Parmenides
wrote “here more and there less” with the implication clearly that there
are two points within what-is, one of which is greater than the other which
is less. First, lines 22—25 could deal with exactly the same situation as
that dealt with in line 48: some one point is more, and some other point
is less. This would be required on the interpretation that there is an
implicit answering ¢é in line 23, for then 22—23 say, implicitly, “here more
and there less.” But this interpretation is also possible, though much less
probable, if a single téi is held to suffice for both 22 and 23; in that case
“here somewhat more ... or somewhat less” would mean, implicitly,
“here somewhat more or somewhat less than somewhere else.”
As was stated above, it is obvious that nothing can be more without
being more than something else, but a second possible reading would
interpret the situation involving a single téi as saying “here somewhat
more or somewhat less than everywhere else.” That is, the single téi would
here be read—as in the Homeric examples—as singling out one distinc-
tive place among many, a place at which a coherence is interruptible. I
read the lines this way because, on this reading, lines 22—25 have some-
thing different to say than lines 42-49. This gives the single té the special
function that it seems to call for in the text. On this reading, the single
té in 23 does just what each of the two occurrences of téi does in 45 and
in 48: a single ¢é picks out a single point. But ¢é by itself does a different
job than that done by both occurrences of té together; it picks out a
single point which is different from every other, while they together pick
out two points which are different from each other. This gives the single
‘
CONTRARIES 83
tei something to do, and makes the point of lines 22—25 different from
that of lines 42—49, not only in subject matter, but also in logic. All of
these considerations seem to me to make it plausible that the single té
in 23 is to be read in this manner. Moreover, even if there had been an
explicit answering /é in the next line, it would not have to be read as
“more here and less there.” It could, because the contraries are separated
into two different lines, be read as “more somewhere (with respect to
everywhere else) or less somewhere (with respect to everywhere else)”;
it would be left open whether the two somewheres were the same or
different, so long as the referent of each ¢é was a single point. The two
contraries, considered separately in lines 99-95, are considered together
in lines 42—49.
The suggestion is, then, that Parmenides writes out only one ¢é be-
cause he wishes us to understand that only one place is being examined,
first with regard to its being more and second with regard to its being
less. There is no need for an emendation. More or less than what? More
or less, I suggest, than every other place within the compass of what-is.
Only one place? Not exactly; the point is surely that the #é is general,
that it stands for any single place, taken in its relations (of equality or
inequality with respect to mass) with every place other than it. That is,
in lines 23 and 24, Parmenides is considering the possibility that some
one place might not be the same (with respect to mass or qualitative
intensity) as any other place.
I suggest, then, the adoption of the following points of interpretation
in lines 22—25: (a) each item in the “nor ... nor ... nor” construction
receives an appropriate answer in the second half of its line; (b) whatever
“divisible” means in line 22, it is not unconnected with the issues raised
by “more” and “less”; (c) the use of the single ¢é in line 23, without an
explicit echo in line 24, is intended to signify that only one (unspecified)
place in what-is is being analyzed with respect to its occupation, first by
one contrary, and then by the other; (d) this place is being compared,
not only with one other place, but with all the places which are other
than it; (e) the place in question is perfectly general, that is, it stands for
any place in what-is (or, if you like, each place in what-is is being ex-
amined singly); (f) there may therefore be crucial differences between
the treatment of contraries in 22-25 and their treatment in the sphere-
section, lines 42—49. ;
Lines 22-25 systematically exhaust the possibility that contrary relative
terms might apply within what-is at some single point in relation to every
other point. This may be why the language of place and mass can be
taken metaphorically, referring to the intensity of the quality “being,”
without making too much of a difference in the sense. If the purpose is
to compare the members of an (essentially abstract) plurality with one
84 CONTRARIES
The fact that Parmenides seems to have in mind, when he rejects the
notion that what-is might come into being at some particular time, is a
fact about time itself. It is a fact that, for any point in time, there is some
other point in time which is later and a third which is earlier. And, given
two distinct points, one is always later and the other is always earlier.
This is, I suggest, why Parmenides writes husteron é prosthen (“later or
earlier”) instead of tote men ... tote de (“then ... then again”); I submit
that he could have written the latter, just as he later writes ta é te, “here
or there,” if he were not interested in underlining this elementary fact
about the time-series, that to be other in time is already to be either
earlier or later, that temporal difference is necessarily either temporal
priority or temporal subsequence. This is a fact about time (and about
other asymmetrically ordered series, like the sequence of integers,
whether or not the series is continuous, as is time, or discrete, as are the
integers), but it is not a fact about places and masses; for two places to
be different, it is not necessary that their masses be qualified by one or
the other of a pair of contraries. But two points in time can only differ
if each one is already qualified either by the one contrary or by the other.
Moreover, if we consider not just two points in time but the entire tem-
poral series, we see that each different time is in fact already qualified
by both contraries, though in different respects. The comprehensiveness
\
CONTRARIES 87
of the argument here is also underlined in the logic and rhetoric with
which it is expressed: husteron é prosthen, “later or earlier,’ with its dis-
junctive “or,” reminds us that it is a matter of indifference which point
we pick, since all are both earlier and later. The “nor here somewhat
more ... nor somewhat less” of 23 and 24 consider their contraries
separately, as if one could be considered apart from the other, and it is
not until 42—49 that the contraries are again considered together, first
disjunctively and then conjunctively, in their interrelationship. The
method is one of variations in expression which get across an underlying
logical or dialectical point: first the disjunction of two contraries which
are in fact always conjoined, then a mixed conjunctive and disjunctive
“neither-nor” formulation, then the disjunctive and conjunctive separate
formulations of the freedom of what-is from contrariety.
Thus the application of contraries in a temporal situation, lines 9-11,
is different from the applications of contraries in a mass-place situation
and in the sphere-section. In a temporal situation, every plurality is rid-
dled with contraries; there is no escape, no average density, no homo-
geneous whole, no group of equal radii; instead, every group of time-
points is such that no point is the same as any other; in order for what-
is to be freed from temporal contrarieties, it must be freed from time
itself, or at least from temporally conditioned variations. This, I submit,
is why Parmenides goes on to say that what-is ought either to be alto-
gether or not at all (line 11); the choice has to be very radical. The
prohibition on time, then, must be taken literally, regardless of whether
or not the space-sections are taken metaphorically.
Let me now make a brief remark on the three passages before sum-
marizing my interpretation of them. If Parmenides simply wanted to
reject contraries in time, space, and the ball, he need not have combined
them with ¢é, which represents the contraries as applying to what-is in
some particular way. Lines 6-11 felicitously exploit the fact that “later”
and “earlier” apply at every point in time. And the single ¢é in 23, which
has seemed incongruous to several people, is read naturally as denoting
a single point in its relation to all other points, and, if so read, completes
the picture in the manner explained below. The point made in chapter 1
against a world of monads—that such a world must involve the mutual
nonidentities of individuals—can, however, be extracted from 6—11 and
42-49 without 22-25, for the first does rule out a situation in which no
point is the same as any other, while the second rules out a situation in
which some one is not the same as some other, though the case for
reading them that way is strengthened by 22-25: to reject both of these
is to reject “not any other than this” along with “not that other than this”
and so, even if one does not go so far as to claim (which one can if one
includes 22—25) that Parmenides made the connection between “not any”
88 CONTRARIES
and “not this,” it is still the case that “not any” is rejected in 6-11, and
that “not any” includes “not this, or that, or that...”
The present interpretation of the passages involving contrariety may,
then, be summarized as follows: Parmenides is interested in rejecting all
forms of contrariety as they might apply to what-is; the rejection of
contrariety is as important a part of his task as are the proofs of most
of the signposts; in fact, it is the same task, since the contraries are set
up in such a way that to reject each pair is to affirm one signpost-group.
The forms of contrariety that are rejected are the following:
A. lines 9-11 No point is the same as any other. (Each point is
either earlier or later than every other.)
B. lines 22—25 Some place is not the same as (i.e., has more or less
mass than) any (every) other place.
C. lines 42-49 Some radius is not the same as (i.e., is bigger or
smaller than) some other radius. Or: Some two radii
are different.
The “is the same” and “is not the same” in these formulations are
expressions of numerical nonidentity, but, more importantly, they are
expressions of qualitative difference: “X is not the same as Y” means
“with respect to the characteristic being measured (temporal position,
amount of mass, and length of radius or push), X differs contrariwise
from Y.” Now, of course, such a qualitative difference would carry nu-
merical nonidentity with it; but by “not the same” here, I mean some-
thing like “having its numerical nonidentity secured by means of
qualitative difference.”
Another way of expressing these differences is to say that, in A and C,
both contraries are thought of as applying at the same time, except that
A makes them true of the same point in time while C makes them true
of two different points in space. And, in B, one contrary is taken at a
time, applying to one point, and is then connected disjunctively with the
other contrary, which is also seen as applying at one point. These are
real differences in treatment.
Now these are in fact complete catalogues of the ways in which con-
trarieties might apply as within a plurality, though the principle of in-
ventory isa little unusual—to start with, logic tells us that two contraries
cannot apply at the same point in the same respect (in ruling this out,
Parmenides is one with modern logic). But a single point can be bigger
and smaller at the same time if it is bigger in one respect and smaller in
another. Let P and Q stand for the contraries. Our three situations are
these: (1) each point is both P and Q (time); (2) one point is P and all
the others are Q (mass-place); (3) one point is P and one other is Q
(sphere). Now situation 3, as has been observed, includes both 1 and 2.
\
CONTRARIES 89
Parmenides puts 3 last because he wants to show that | and 2 boil down
to 3—and 3 is similar enough to the introductory statement of the world-
views of mortals commented on in chapter 1 to have been thought a
rudimentary error by Parmenides. The principle of inventory in virtue
of which this is a complete catalogue is the principle of “collation,” dis-
cussed below.
The sequence of denials in this passage is interesting, because the items
have internal connections with one another. In particular, the successive
items are nested, in the following sense. Imagine A, B, and C as utterly
abstract assertions, apart from the contexts in which they occur; that is,
read A as “no one is the same as any other,” B as “some one is not the
same as any other,” and C as “some one is not the same as some other.”
Now: to reject A is not necessarily to reject B, since A can be denied via
the assertion that some point is the same as some other point (even
though Parmenides, on the present interpretation, is making the far
stronger assertion that no point is earlier or later than any other point);
but the former assertion is not enough to rule out B. Similarly, to reject
B is not necessarily to reject C, since B can be rejected via the assertion
that no place is different from every other place (though in the text
Parmenides makes the far stronger assertion that all the places are the
same); but this does not rule out C. However, to deny C is to deny both
A and B, since the only denial available for C is that all the radii are the
same. Whatever the principle underlying it, this is an extremely inter-
esting formal progression. ;
Why does Parmenides end with “here more and there less,” which on
my reading denies “some one is not the same as some other,” when he
could have shortened his whole task by pointing out this alternative at
the very beginning?—-since to rule it out is also to rule out the others,
and since on my account the temporal, spatial, and metaphorical contexts
alone are not sufficient to explain why the contrarieties are rejected three
times. I suggested an answer above: Parmenides wanted to show that the
first two alternatives boil down to the last, which is itself both one of the
alternatives and the expression, in capsule form, of what is wrong with
all of them. What is wrong is that all the points, places, and/or radii
which one is endeavoring to distinguish are within what-is, and so, if
there were such a distinction, what-is would not be one. Parmenides could
have dealt with the last alternative first and shortened his argument
considerably; but then he would not have presented all the different ways
in which contrarieties might apply within a thing. He might also have
contented himself with saying that what-is is. That he says more may
mean that he was concerned with method, with the maximum possible
amplitude in the expression of a given point. The three rejections of
contraries do not have the function of an ordinary argument. If they
90 CONTRARIES
did, the last would have sufficed. Rather, the point must have been to
compare what-is with itself in all the ways in which this can be done. It
is as if he had said to his imaginary interlocutor: You can’t have con-
traries applying everywhere—that’s obviously wrong. Now you want to
try having one of the contraries at only one place, and the other contrary
everywhere else? That’s wrong, too. In fact, even if you try having the
one contrary applying at only one place ahd the other at only one place,
it won’t do. They’ve got to be expelled altogether. The net effect is rhe-
torically and elenctically powerful precisely because the last alternative
includes the other two. But he gives all three because he is interested
also in the ways in which a thing might be compared with itself.
In making these points I temporarily put aside considerations of the
contexts within which the assertions and denials occur. Let me now reex-
amine these contexts. As I read them, they are these:
Signpost-group Contrary Context Situation rejected
ungenerable, later-earlier time Both contraries are
imperishable true of every time.
whole and of — more-less density or Either contrary is
a single kind intensity true at some place.
complete, bigger-smaller radius or Either contrary true
perfect resistance to _—_at any place. (Or,
push both contraries true
at some pair of
places.)
Each of these contexts presupposes its predecessor, just as the abstract
formulations did. It is not worth worrying about the density or qualitative
intensity of what-is if it is continually, or even occasionally, coming into
or going out of existence; nor is it worth worrying about the symmetry,
or equal resistance to push, ofa ball if it is not already homogeneous, of
the same density.
Moreover, the contexts themselves have interesting relations of simi-
larity and difference with one another, relations that run in parallel with
the ways in which the contraries are varied. In lines 6—15, the context is
that of a time line; there is only one dimension of difference between
and among points; to be other is to be earlier or later. As we saw, this
necessitated the rejection of later and earlier together, since both were
true of every point in time. In 22-25, on the other hand, there are two
dimensions of difference. For this reason the contraries could be denied
without at the same time denying an implicit or explicit plurality of
places, since neither contrary had to be true of any place in order for
that place to be numerically different from some other place, though
‘
CONTRARIES 91
there was also good reason for thinking that a plurality of places itself
would have interfered with the unanimity of what-is. What, then, is ac-
tually being compared, if the contraries are envisaged as applying to
what-is? That is, what is the meaning of the contrary terms?
If no point in time is the same as any other, then each point is being
compared with every other point, all at once, and every point is different;
all the points are being compared with all the others at the same time,
and so there is a collation or comparison of many onto many. The case
in lines 22—25 is this. Suppose that one place has more mass than every
other place. Here one does not compare each point with every other
right away; instead, one compares one place with all the other places
with respect to the amount of mass that each contains, and then does
the same for every other place. This, then, is a one-many collation, re-
peated for each point. And, if we take all of what-is into consideration,
we see that there are in fact many of these one-many collations (since
the ¢é in 23 is perfectly general). Then, in the sphere-section, one point
is being compared with some other point; so the collation here is between
one and one, and there are many of these collations, since the two #é-
points are perfectly general.
So we have three passages containing contraries, which correspond to
three ways in which the members of a plurality might be collated with
each other. First, the members of a plurality might be collated with each
other one-on-one, in which case the plurality would be being counted up
in many one-on-one collations, in which each point was compared with
every other one at a time. If contraries were to saturate any one of these
collations, some one point would possess the one contrary, and some
other point would possess the other; this is what happens in the sphere-
section with “here more and there less.” The second kind of collation is
that in which the plurality is counted up in many one-on-many map-
pings; each point is taken singly in its relations to all the other points at
once. If contraries were to saturate any one of these collations, some one
point would possess the one contrary, and all the other points would
possess the other contrary. This is what happens in 22-25, with first
“bigger” and then “smaller” being imagined to apply at the same point.
(A one-many collation is also a many-one collation. I use “collation” here
in such a way that if A is collated with B, then B is collated with A. But
if, for example, one point is greater and the other is less in a one-one
collation, then two asymmetrical relations will apply as within a single
collation.) Third, a plurality could be counted up by making a single
many-on-many coliation in which all points were compared with all.
When contraries saturate this collation, however, both contraries apply
at every point; the result is like the situation in time.
The basic plan of the method I attribute to Parmenides is this: a man-
92 CONTRARIES
In the above diagram, “many” means “more than one,” so “two” counts
as “many.” But, if it is thought that Parmenides would have objected to
duality but not to plurality, a similar diagram can be made using four
points in the shape of a square. The straight lines in the above diagram
refer to single comparisons between points to see whether and how con-
traries apply. A collation in this sense can consist of several comparisons,
if it is a One-many or many-many collation. A collation in this sense is
like a state of affairs in which two or more elements stand in relationships
(of contrariety or the lack thereof) to each other or to one another.
In conclusion, one of the purposes of the proof-portion of fragment
8 is to show that what-is is ungenerable, imperishable, and so on. But
most of these “signposts” envisage different situations, involving the re-
jection of contraries. The situations are described and in each case some-
thing (namely, the contradictory of the signposts at issue which, if it
applied, would involve the application of contraries to what-is) is rejected.
In the process, the meaning and import of the bare “it is” of fragment 2
are amplified through metaphorical concrete embodiments (i.e., density,
the sphere; the rejection of time, however, seems literally meant). The
*
CONTRARIES 93
conclusion is that to say what-is is means also to say how what-is is not,
and this in turn means that one must not only affirm what what-is is but
also deny what what-is is not. The antagonist is within fragment 8. One
must, in the words of fragment 2, say not only how it is, but also how it
is not possible not to be. The denial takes place according to a sequence
dictated, on my interpretation, by a previously thought-out scheme in-
volving one-many counting or collation. The scheme details all of the
different ways it is necessary to reject disunity in order to assert unity.
Thus, the signposts can all have different proofs and still be expressions
of a single meaning—the unity of what-is, the entity they all signify. This
is part of the reason why apparently negative language is tolerated, and
why such language has more than merely heuristic significance. It does
not involve leaving the positive route, nor is it just a ladder to be thrown
away; it is, rather, a vehicle, not only permissible but also necessary, for
saying what what-is is. And, since the situations rejected are modes of
disunity, it would seem to follow that the most important of the assertions
in lines 5—6 of fragment 8 is the one that does not receive explicit further
mention of its own, namely, “one,” which includes ungenerability, un-
perishingness, wholeness, homogeneity, and perfection, or, in the words
of 5—6 themselves, what-is is “now altogether one, cohesive.” The ques-
tions asked earlier about the conjunctive and disjunctive formulations
and the use of ¢é find their answers in this picture. Thus there is no
underlying self-referentially inconsistent plurality of meanings or objec-
tive referents corresponding to the many signposts; they all have the
same object. As I claimed at the end of chapter 1, whatever the ultimate
dissolutions of language may be, this is not one of them, at least until
language itself disappears. And, as I also claimed earlier, time, qualitative
intensity across space, and a metaphorical sphere are appropriate expres-
sions of these various kinds of collation, though, of course, they are not
the only possible ones. Every point in time has both contraries, while
masses in place can differ in number without being contrary. The sphere-
section presupposes the equal density or homogeneity of the mass-place
passage, the equal occupation of what-is by itself, or relation of itself (as
“spatially” distributed plurality) to itself (as the quality “being”). It then
goes on to inquire whether what-is, as a homogeneous distribution
through space, is equal to itself in yet another way, not as a quality evenly
distributed, but as a mass with boundaries at distances from, a central
focus. The points on the surface of the sphere well-rounded from every
side are all at equal distances from this focus: what-is is again compared
with itself, this time not as mass onto place, but as one relation between
surface-point and center onto the relation between another surface-point
and the center. And all these relations of relations are equal, that is,
what-is is, in its expanse, in every relation of relations to the center, the
94 CONTRARIES
same. But then the mortals spoil everything by calling what-is “Fire” in
such a way as to introduce another with which it is not the same, and
the contrarieties creep back in the manner described in the next chapter.
What-is in “Truth” is thus folded onto itself like a paper carnation, the
same in all the relations and relations of relations in which a thoroughly
unified plurality might be collated with itself. There is no diazresis, “di-
vision,” only sunagégé, “leading together. And what-is appears here as
the name for a thing, “being,” as the quality (being) which is evenly
distributed throughout that thing which it is, and as the Truth, utterly
equal with itself from every one of these points of view. Whence, per-
haps, on a quite different level, the referential-existential (“what is there
to be spoken and thought about must exist,” as in Owen), veridical (“one
must say how things stand and how they do not”) and informational (one
must not give characterizations of a thing which do not touch it in ways
on which one can cognitively rely) aspects of the Parmenidean “is.”
Is being in time? No. Is it in space? Perhaps not, or perhaps equally
at every point in space, and perhaps thought of, like the ether of Mich-
elson and Morley, as a stuff rather than as the omnipresence of God. At
any rate being is not distributed unevenly through space or through
places.
Thus, with contraries as well as with the other terms, Parmenides uses
a method of exhausting possibilities. The goals are, of course, different,
for contraries themselves are rejected while negative language is, I be-
lieve, embraced. But the means are the same, and they involve covering
the ground as widely as possible in a way remarkable for the consistency
of its application and for the sophistication of its method. The stages of
the method of contraries are correlated with the ways in which different
kinds of terms (single, double and triple) apply at different points in the
poem, in the way explained in chapter 2; just as the spatial or temporal
situations vary the logic of contraries, so they vary the numbers of terms
in order to display the many different alternatives that are available from
a single logical or inferentially relevant rule of construction.
Now that a technique of varying and exhausting alternatives has (I
hope) been demonstrated and shown to be philosophically relevant in
two such different domains, a preliminary inference to the existence of
a general Parmenidean procedure seems warranted. In this procedure,
one demonstrates or illustrates something by displaying all the alterna-
tives that fall under it (if it is a law) or oppose it (if it is a proposition
like “Being is One”). The purpose of such a procedure will be to guar-
antee exhaustiveness and precision in the statement and proof of the law
or proposition. A consciously used method of this sort is appropriate in
a philosopher to whom is usually attributed the discovery of the canons
of reason. I explore this question further in chapter 5, along with the
CONTRARIES 95
96 ?
MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD 97
Without the emendation, lines 12-13 read “Nor will the strength of
Trust ever permit anything besides it to come to be out of what-is-not.”
With the emendation, the lines end “. . . to come to be out of what-2s.”®
One important element of support for the emendation comes from the
feeling that, without it, Parmenides’ argument is not complete; let me
turn, then, to the immediately preceding lines, in order to examine
whether this is so.
In lines 7—9, it is clear that Parmenides’ argument is directed against
a coming-to-be of what-is from what-is-not. Lines 9-11 are ambiguous,
and, I submit, deliberately so. One might paraphrase: what Need urged
it (i.e., what-is) on to come to be later or earlier, starting (as it would in
this case) from nothing? And line 11 says something to the effect that
one has to choose between being altogether or not at all. Now there are
at least three components of meaning in 9-10. As distinguished by
Stokes,‘ they are the following. Husteron é prosthen might mean (1) “later
rather than sooner” (following Burnet), or (2) “at one particular moment,
either later or sooner” (following Diels and Kranz), or (3) “What necessity
might ever have caused it to grow, starting from nothing?” (following
Stokes). What-is cannot need to come to be at some particular time,
because, given the nature of the time-series, there are always many other
particular times. Now interpretation 2, if I read it right, presupposes 1,
and 3 presupposes 2. The first asks why it should come to be at this time
rather than at that time, later rather than sooner, or, for that matter,
sooner rather than later. The second asks why it should come to be at
some particular moment, either later or sooner. (The question “later or
sooner than what?” arises in this context, but the fact that it has no
particular answer is part of the reason why there is need for what-is to
come to be at all.) If reading 2 does not mean the same thing as 1, then
it says, “Given that there is no principle of choice between moments, as
is shown by 1, why should some particular moment be chosen? And,
98 MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD
But if pampan pelenai chreon estin é ouchi does not rule out a tertium quid—
something existing but not identical with what-is—then this reason for
the emendation does not hold. For then there will still be room in lines
12-13 for the discussion of the coming-to-be ofa tertium quid out of what-
is-not, and such a coming-to-be is discussed in the unemended text. What
do the words of line 11 mean, and what do they rule out? The line
contains the word houtos, “thus,” and so might (as Mourelatos has noted®)
comment globally on the facts about what-is, that is, not only on the
immediately preceding lines 9-10, but also on the denial of a coming-
to-be of what-is from what-is-not in lines 7~9. So one cannot assume that
the line functions only in the temporal context of the surrounding ar-
gument; line 11 might also be saying that what-is must be fully or com-
pletely to begin with, if it exists at all (i.e., spatially as well as temporally)
and so cannot come to be (i.e., temporally).”
Note, however, that the line is embedded in a temporal context, and
\
MODALS,
Ree eee eee ee AND
THE OTHER, eeeMETHOD 99
Another version (Simp. Phys. 146.9-11) has oud’ei chronos before estin é
estai, a text objected to since Diels on the grounds that the phrase in-
volving chronos, as Taran says, “does not make sense in the context.”!4 As
far as I am concerned, the reading quoted above is acceptable for the
whole of 36, and might be rendered “For there neither is nor ever will
be any other besides what-is, since it was this which Doom bound to be
whole and immovable.” On either reading, the point of lines 36-38 is
that there will never be any other besides what-is on account of what-is’s
MODALS, THE OTHER
OTHER, , AND METHOD
AND METH OD COT
MODA LS, THE
bility that such an other might be in the future but not in the present.
But then it would have had to come to be, presumably either from what-
is or from what-is-not. F
Can “immovable” have this meaning at this point in the poem? The
earlier “immovable” in 26 looks back to the signpost “unmoving” of 4
and could refer either to qualitative change, or to change of place, or to
both in line 26. That it means at least change of place is guaranteed by
“to change place” in 40—41.!° That “immovable” rules out change of
place in 26 is also shown by “the same and remaining in the same place,
it stays by itself” in 29. Here I agree with Stokes that, in this line, “The
themes [of qualitative and locomotive change] are inextricably mixed.”!’
But I do not see why Stokes says that “immovable” in 37 would be ruling
out primarily qualitative change,'* especially in view of the remark just
quoted. He argues that a qualitative “immovable” in 37 is required if the
term is there to exclude “the future existence of anything other than
Being.” I don’t understand why what both Stokes and I find in these
lines—the coming-to-be of a new entity, a new logical subject—is_pri-
marily a qualitative change; nor do I understand why “immovable” would
have to be qualitative here in order to rule out such a coming-to-be, nor
how it could be qualitative here but locomotive in 26, especially since (as
I try to show below) the terms tend to widen in meaning, not narrow, as
the poem goes along. Line 29, which immediately precedes a description
of what-is as “bonded” in line 30, is, on Stokes’s own reading, a combi-
nation of spatial and qualitative language.
As line 29 helps to show, change in place—in Parmenides as in Zeno—
is thought of as egress from one’s own place.!® We learn from 22-30 at
least that what-is does not move out from its own place as a whole. I
suggest that in 36-38 we hear something new, namely, that another
whole does not move out from what-is—or, equivalently, that part of it
does not move off and start living on its own as a whole in its own right.
“Whole” and “immovable” would, then, each separately work against the
existence of another; being would not be whole because there would be
two things, separate from one another. And if such an other were ever
to come out of what-is, then being (“being” now names only one of the
pair, which is just what Parmenides thinks is wrong) would not be “im-
movable.”
It will be objected that “immovable” is now being represented as mean-
ing, in 38, more than it meant in 26. But it occurs in 26 in the context
of two other alpha-privative predicates, “not starting up” and “not stop-
ping.” The context is at least that of motion as a whole across space.
What-is cannot move like a ball along the sidewalk—in particular, it can-
not start moving or stop moving. Thus the meaning of “immovable” in
26 is narrowed by the context, and there is no reason why in the context
\
MODALS,
Bh
THE OTHER, AND METHOD 103
eed
surely complete at least by the end of 21, which begins with a triumphant
tos, as if announcing alogical conclusion, and after which is begun a new
subject, the treatment of inhomogeneity in lines 22-26. One might ask,
given this apparent ring of finality in line 21, is it really reasonable to
suppose that 36-38 do anything more than repeat (though perhaps from
a more inclusive perspective) what has been shown by the end of 21?
After all, passages of reiteration and conclusion (15-18, 34-36, 38-41)
are scattered throughout the elenchus. And, it will be suggested, if this
is so, then perhaps we do need the emendation in line 12, in spite of all
the foregoing considerations.
My reply is that Parmenides seems to use genesis, “coming-to-be” and
(what we might call) kznésis somewhat differently. Genesis, before line 21
in the unemended text, seems solely to mean what we might call absolute
coming-to-be, the coming-to-be (either of what-is or of something else)
from bare nothing. Later, in 26-30, a connection between genesis and
kinésis, “motion,” is drawn with “it is in the bounds of mighty bonds
immovable, without beginning, without end,” since coming-to-be and
perishing have been driven far off by True Trust. In order to support
the denial of the possibility of motion in these lines, genesis must be wide
enough to cover that sort of coming-to-be involved in change of place,
the coming-to-be in a different place of something that used to be some-
where else. And yet this wider meaning of genesis is not found in lines
6—21 as they stand. Thus we are not really under the gun—either the
ring of finality (tds) in 21 is meant to announce the demise only of ab-
solute coming-to-be and not yet change of place, or we do not have to
do all our refuting of genesis before the end of 21, in spite of the ring of
finality. So we need not be in haste to emend in order to finish by then.
Finally, what I earlier called the coming-to-be of something besides
what-is out of what-is, 2s found in 36—38, but there it is not called coming-
to-be (genesis); it is called kenésis, or would be if Parmenides used the
word, since the reason why no other ever comes to be is that what-is is
“whole and immovable (akinéton).” Thus there is no evidence that Par-
menides liked to call such a coming-to-be a genesis. All the less reason to
emend line 12 in order to find there denied the coming (perhaps not
genesis, but kinésis in the sense of the egress of a part from a whole, or
of a second whole from the original place of the first whole) which is
comfortably denied so much later, in 36—38. Moreover, the parex tou eontos
of 37 might be more suited to carry this meaning than the par’auto of
13, since the latter can mean mere juxtaposition (“besides,” “alongside”)
and the former could perhaps mean something like “from out of what-
is,” as well as “alongside what-is.”?” A being besides what-is which sprang
from (ek) nothing (as in the unemended line 12) would naturally be
described as “besides” or “alongside” (para) what-is; but one which leaped
106 MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD
out from what-is would more naturally be described as “from out of”
(parek) what-is. Thus the unemended text is more natural. And it would
be much more appropriate to find the assertion that being does not give
rise to another made in 36-38, after its wholeness and immovability have
been asserted by the time line 32 rolls around. Otherwise there is no
sense in saying that, because what-is is immovable, there can be no other.
Once its bounds have been drawn, it is much easier to say that it cannot
transgress them. Such boundaries would not be affected if an other were
to pop into existence from nothing besides it, but they would be affected
if a new being budded off. Thus, it is also more natural to have the
unemended text, and the assertion found in 36-38 after 22-33. Par-
menides did not seem to feel himself under any compulsion to speak of
a coming-to-be parex tou eontos as a genesis. The fact that children come
from parents is apparently of little importance here. So we should not
feel under any compulsion to find this possibility discussed or refuted
before line 21. Lines 36-38 belong to the proof of “unmoving” (line 4),
not to that of “ungenerable” (line 3). Of course they recapitulate and
include what went before; but they also add something new.
The final reason for making the emendation is that it is supposed to
explain how lines 6—21 can be read as containing a refutation of olethros
(perishing) on the part of what-is. For this seems to be one respect in
which the poem is entirely lacking in logical rigor. “Unperishing” is an-
nounced in line 3 as one of the signposts to be proved; but the proof
seems to be lacking in lines 6—13, which, on the surface at least, are
entirely devoted to proving “ungenerable”; and yet, in lines 13-15, Par-
menides says that Justice did not permit what-is to perish, as if this were
a conclusion that had been established in the intervening lines. Again,
lines 19-21 do seem to be devoted in part to perishing, but one seems
to look there in vain for the sort of detailed refutation of destruction
that one finds for birth, and the lines are, in any case, partly recapitu-
latory, as can be seen from the fact that some sort of conclusion is drawn
in lines 12-15.
It is claimed that the emended version of line 12 supplies such a re-
futation. I have already explained why I think that Stokes’s version of
this claim does not make sense for Parmenides. Barnes’s proposal is very
close to Stokes’s. He begins by paraphrasing the relevant lines:
“Nor from a state of existence can o [Barnes’s object of discourse and
thought, i.e., being] become something other than what is”; i.e., o cannot
change from existing to not existing, o cannot be destroyed. That offers a
statement, not an argument. Yet it is obvious what argument we are to
supply: if o is destroyed at t, then o exists before ¢ and o does not exist after
t. But “it is not sayable or thinkable that it is not.”28
MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD
OD —C—C“‘(‘CNCCOC‘(!C"C«CNO:
MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METH
This, I think, actually militates against the spirit of Barnes’s own inter-
pretation, for one would have expected him to read the emended lines
as saying that the object of knowledge and discourse cannot turn into
any existing thing besides itself. Otherwise it is not really worthwhile for
Barnes’s Parmenides to spend time discussing the possibility raised in
the emended line; for a Parmenides who takes it as nearly undeniable
that what is available for discourse or for thought must exist would hardly
spend time discussing the possibility that such a thing might suddenly
cease to be. It would be much more worthwhile for such a Parmenides
to show that there is only one such thing.
Finally—and this applies against both Barnes and Stokes—if it were
already so obvious in lines 12—13 that anything (é) besides being would
have to be nothing, so obvious that the turning of what-is into such a
thing would be no less than the complete destruction of what-is, then
why is Parmenides still bravely denying, some twenty-four lines later in
36~38, that there ever could be anything other than what-is? Surely, if
this needs to be said so forcefully so late, it cannot be obvious in the
earlier passage, even if the later passage is to some extent recapitulatory.
And yet it must be taken to be no less than obvious in 12-13, if the
emendation is in fact to furnish us with a refutation of perishing. The
equation (on all accounts still unproven before 12-13) “what is other
than being equals what does not exist”—an equation which both Barnes
and Stokes must attribute to Parmenides in those lines—is one which
Parmenides himself never took for granted, as lines 36-38 show.
I conclude that the emendation does not provide us with a refutation
of perishing before line 19. In fact, there is no such refutation there,
and there does not need to be. For, if being undergoes perishing, then
there is a time when “being is not” is true, and this would have crisped
Parmenides’ hair with horror. That this is impossible for Parmenides is,
as Barnes implies, obvious and (I would add) therefore not in need of a
separate argument. As Barnes and others have pointed out, there is some
connection in Parmenides’ mind between perishing and future being, as
5-6 and 19-21 reveal; but a comprehensive study of the temporal lan-
guage in Parmenides’s poem, one to which Barnes, Owen, Kneale, Mou-
relatos, and Schofield have made contributions, is outside the scope of
the present investigation. In any case, no matter what is really happening
in 19-21, perishing is really announced as disproved in 13—h5, and if
the emendation does not help Barnes and Stokes before then, it does not
help them at all, since they want to find a refutation of perishing before
19:
I suggest, then, the adoption of the following points. (1) Lines 36-38
are to be read as denying, in part, that something besides what-is (i.e.,
something existing but not identical with what-is) might come to be out
108 MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD
possible that there be another, that is, it is not possible for it not to be
whole and immovable, since Doom bound it to be whole and immovable.
Here, with both a positive and a privative term tied to the same person-
ified figure, we have another modal recognition of the fact that the truth
can take either positive or negative guise.
Again, in using terms like “necessary,” I do not mean to call into play
their precise modern meanings but only their metaphorical flavor; “nec-
essary not,” for example, calls up active exclusion, and this is a much
stronger metaphor than “not possible,” which, in spite of the logical
equivalence, merely expresses failure to allow. Similarly, what is necessary
is what is bound to be; the metaphor is as deep in English as it is in
Greek. If one thinks of the pictures rather than of possibly anachronistic
logical notions, the point I would like to convey is that all of the pictures
which are possible in a Parmenidean ontology are in fact presented:
refusal to admit something wrong (Justice), active exclusion of what is
wrong (True Trust), requiring what is right (Necessity), requiring that
what is right not fail to be what it is (Doom). The boundary is not crossed
from the outside in (the first two) or from the inside out (the second
two). In each case, moreover, there is a connection between the meaning
of the action performed and the nature of the predicates brought into
play. Thus, Justice supports “ungenerable” and “imperishable” by not
allowing coming-to-be and perishing, while True Trust supports “im-
movable,” etc., again by ruling out coming-to-be and perishing; in both
cases privatives are (implicitly or explicitly) supported by the denials of
positives; while the action in the first is merely refusal to do something
passive (allow), the action in the second is that of active driving. But
when Necessity supports both “the same,” etc., and the denial of “incom-
plete” and changes the object of the modal action from the contraries
outside the bound to what-is inside the bound, we learn that the lines of
demarcation can be crossed in the other direction to favor positives and
rule out privatives; and finally Doom, with catholic impartiality, prevents
both positives and privatives from failing to appear as it does not allow
being to escape the bound. Moreover, the assertions and denials are
related. The two positive terms, “to come to be” and “to perish,” ruled
out by Justice are almost the same as the coming-to-be and perishing
whose ruling-out by True Trust establishes the three privatives “immov-
able,” etc., the first of which is also required by Doom. These in turn
are roughly the contrapositives of the three positive terms required by
Necessity. All are different possible modal expressions of the same com-
plex point. The list of kinds of modal assertions and kinds of predicates
is complete. It contains: (1) the ruling out of a positive term (Justice);
(2) the ruling out of a privative with “it is not right” in 32; (3) support
for a positive (Necessity); (4) support for a privative by ruling out a
MODALS, , THE OTHER, riAND METHOD 113
positive (True Trust); and (5) support for both privative and positive
(Doom).
Both in the complete range of their metaphorical pictures and in the
many sorts of predicates they affirm and deny, these modal figures are
one with the rest of the poem and show how being is necessary in every
way. But here the urge to elaborate seems even more like mere decora-
tion unless we suppose it to have some philosophical rationale. Why
bother to build up the metaphors of ball and boundary in all possible
ways unless obsessed with architectonic, unless desirous of a complete-
ness and expansiveness in what is to be said? The variation seems par-
ticularly superfluous in this case—where there are two pairs each of
whose members is equivalent to the other because concerned with the
same signpost (“the same,” etc., is a prefiguration of what is summarized
in “whole and immovable,” and there are two treatments of coming-to-
be and perishing)—unless it is deliberate, an exploration of different
forms of discourse toward a goal of completeness. These modal figures
are central in the proof, and I now claim that what is true of the rest of
the poem is true of them as well. They traverse the various kinds of
discourse in an exploration of the four ways of being modally necessary,
of being bounded. I explore the significance of this metaphor further in
chapter 6.
It is time for some conclusions about the first four chapters. In
chapter 1 I suggested that Parmenides’ way of truth gave full rights of
citizenship to negative as well as positive statements by leaving the copula
free from direct negation (except innocuous negation) in even negative
cases. The resulting positive discourse has a very wide range. As I showed
in chapter 2, all of the possible affirmations and denials of single, double,
and triple positive and privative terms—except one—are present, and
the particular kinds of terms are, more or less, segregated into those
areas of the poem whose underlying concerns make them both possible
and necessary. The contraries of chapter 3, too, are denied in all the
ways they might apply to a plurality within a single whole, and these
denials generate and unify the proofs of most signposts as well as the
variations of terms in chapter 2. The modals as metaphors for bound-
edness in chapter 4 cover all the noncontingent possibilities for modal
discourse and themselves affirm and deny both positive and privative
terms, while the sections of the poem which rule out an other do so by
ruling out all the possible sources for such an other. Finally, the treat-
ments of contraries and the other dovetail in the “Opinion” section,
which presents the final possibility for both treatments that was not ex-
plicitly discussed in the “Truth” section.
Assuming that the details of these schemes have been accurately pre-
sented here, what significance should one attach to all of this? I argued
114 MODALS, THE OTHER, AND METHOD
telling it like it is while ruling out what it isn’t, of displaying the unity of
all the signposts in a hall of mirrors. But the final explanation has to do
with what-is as the truth: as claimed above, the truth of Parmenides, like
the truth of Heraclitus, requires both positive and negative statement,
though in a different way. Truth must be expressed in a finished—that
is, perfect, bounded, guaranteed, complete—speech, so that there may
be an exact fit between the speech and the thing spoken of. Complete
speech includes both the light of affirmation and the darkness of ne-
gation, and blends them both into one as it circles the bound. It also
includes the displaying of all the required things and of those forbidden.
It is therefore trustworthy only when it includes both in a catalogue of
logical and thematic possibilities. If Parmenides’ ontological motives, and
his philosophy of truth, were something like this, then one may perhaps
attribute to him such a goal—deeper than that of mere efficient argu-
ment, though certainly including it—for the method of variation that I
attempt to see in his poem. Even if much of the discourse is on the
negative route, the point about affirmation and negation in relation to
method still holds.
Thus the poem—in attempting to derive everything from the “is” plus
the law of noncontradiction, but also in the way things are said in many
contexts and ways—is a circle.*! It covers all the ground and loops back
on itself in a systematic way after having enumerated all the possibilities.
One way of taking the goddess’s remark about her own method (“it’s all
the same to me where I start from; for I’ll come back there again,” B5)
is thus to connect it with the method I have attributed to her. She loops
through the many ways of putting predications, unity, and necessity. This
method is argumentatively, rhetorically, and philosophically practical,
and it seems to be Parmenides’ method in four rather different contexts
of argument governed by the goal of a complete, discursive speech. In
the next chapters I shall consider first the ancestors and descendants in
Greek philosophy of Parmenidean logic and argument as I have char-
acterized them, second the way his logic and method hang together with
his characterization of a bounded being so as to occupy a viable and
important alternative in the history of philosophy and theology.
CHAPTER 5
Context x
and
Contradiction
116
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 117
predicate ‘...is good for ———,’”* I claim that the relativist allows us
to drop the “for ———” in order to get to the conclusion that the same
thing is both good and bad. It is, I would claim, Protagoras who specifies
the context of the incomplete predicates, as Barnes has also suggested;
for the thesis that one has access only to appearance is the thesis that
nothing appears to anyone in a manner which is not qualified by the
relation of that appearance to the person to whom it appears. That is,
Protagoras claims that what is hot is also what is cold, but this, he will
say, is so because what is hot to me is the same as what is cold to you.
This is the disambiguation of an incomplete predicate into a contextually
variable situation; the Protagorean claim is ultimately that the incomplete
predicate is nothing but incomplete outside of such a situation. Or, as
Barnes puts it, “to say that contradiction is impossible is not to assert
that a proposition and its contradictory may both be true at the same
time; it is to assert the perfectly distinct thesis that you cannot contradict
me,”? because (I would say) the predicates cannot be emancipated from
the variable contexts in which they occur. Protagoras thus manifests a
provisional reliance upon the argument-pattern of dropping the quali-
fiers attributed to the relativists in the Dissoi Logot above; he uses this
pattern as a corrosive; but he is equally concerned to stress that the
conclusion should not be interpreted as a logical contradiction, because
of the disambiguation into contexts. Here Zeno’s patterns of inference
come home to roost. Zeno had found statements of the form “S is P and
not P” to be characteristic of the sensible world, the inference being that,
as with Parmenides, there was some other world in which such statements
did not apply. But, for Protagoras, the option of another world is not
available, so all he has are contextually relative contexts; the inference is
not allowed to proceed so far as to eliminate the sensible world as well
(as it could have); so all Protagoras can do is lay stress on the fact that
the apparent contradictions among incomplete predicates can and must
be disambiguated in the sensible world, and that they are not real con-
tradictions. But his interest in variability, in potential conflicts and in
avoiding them, locates him squarely in the tradition of Parmenides and
Zeno, with this difference: that it is now clearly understood that not every
case of contextual relativity is also a case of contradiction. That is, adopt-
ing Barnes’s interpretation of Protagoras’s attitude toward contradiction,
Protagoras is reported as saying that it is not possible to contradict;!° but
what this means is, since each person is the measure of all things, it is
not possible for my report that X is F to contradict (antilegein) your report
that X is not F since the affirmation and the denial do not occur in the
same sense, since one is relative to me and the other to you. Barnes
writes, “Thus the denial of antilegein, far from opening Protagoras to a
peculiarly damning charge of inconsistency, is actually designed to pro-
\
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 121
tect him from that charge: the clouds of contradiction . . . are evaporated
by the thesis that ‘it is not possible to contradict.’”!! If so, then Protag-
oras’s view is more sophisticated than that of Parmenides and the Dissoz
Logoi, and it advances toward the sort of understanding of the law of
noncontradiction that was later to come to birth in middle-late Plato and
Aristotle. For, on the Eleatic view, dropping the qualifiers results in a
logically suspicious situation in which the contextual relativity (not yet
clearly distinguished from contradictoriness) relegates the subject and
predicate alike to the realm of Opinion (in Parmenides) or generates
impossible conclusions (in the case of the Dissoz Logoz). But, if Barnes is
right, Protagoras sees that the contradictory or contrary terms are not
true in the same sense, and he sees that the fact that each is true to a
different observer means that the two opposed views of the world do not
contradict each other in an argumentatively fruitful way. If he could do
this, Protagoras must have had a working knowledge of (or at least right
opinion about) the law of noncontradiction in its precise (Platonic and
Aristotelian) sense (in which it prohibits as contradiction only the appli-
cation of contradictories in one and the same sense), even though he put
that knowledge in the service of a non-Platonic relativism by using it to
permit any and every term, provided that opposite terms apply in dif-
ferent senses. Thus Protagoras’s non-Parmenidean attitude toward the
senses: Parmenides, thinking that even opposites true in different senses
disqualify a sentence (as they do indeed in a monistic ontology), proceeds
to disqualify the senses; Protagoras, after freeing the senses from this
(to his mind) overly rigid interpretation of the law, denies just the op-
posite—any world free from contextual relativity. He is now free to en-
dorse the relative world, because, even in this world, as opposed to what
Parmenides thought, it is not possible to contradict in the strict sense.
Plato struggles all his life with the task of showing that nonsensible en-
tities are still needed even on this new understanding of the law as pro-
hibiting contradiction only in one and the same sense—a need whose
ultimate justification, I argue, took even Plato a while to clarify. He could
have remained a happy monist had Protagoras not seen that not every
case of contextual relativity is a case of logical contradiction and had he
not understood, as Barnes points out, that it is precisely an improved
understanding of contradiction that can be used to deny its very possi-
bility. .
Let me now attempt to sketch the course of this development in Pla-
tonic thought. Again, the reader will see my indebtedness to many au-
thors, particularly Owen, Ranulf, Szabé, Lloyd, Prauss, Nehamas, Wood-
ruff, and Jordan, as mentioned in notes; see also Acknowledgments.
The Euthydemus represents sophists as using the logic of dropping qual-
ifiers to arrive at apparent contradictions whose conclusions—whatever
122 CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION
their deeper connections with genuinely Platonic theses such as the the-
ory of recollection!?—are resisted by Socrates not only as morally bad
but also as bad arguments. Whatever may be divine about the dual vis-
itors to Athens does not include their understanding of the role of logic
in philosophical protreptic. Here I am _ particularly indebted to
Rosamond K. Sprague’s treatment.
It is part of Euthydemus’s and Dionysedorus’s logic not only to drop
the terms to get at the copula but also to drop the qualifiers to get at the
terms, as when they get Socrates to admit that if he knows something,
he knows everything, and if he does not know something, he knows
nothing (293B7—294A8).
Euthydemus You do know something then? . . .
Socrates I do.
Euth Then you are knowing, since you know?
Soc Certainly, in that same something.
Euth That makes no difference. ... Isn’t it necessary that you know every-
thing since you are knowing? ,
Soc Why, no indeed. ... There are many other things I do not know.
Euth Then if you do not know something, you are not knowing.
Soc Not knowing that, my friend... .
Euth Are you any the less not knowing? But just now you said you were
knowing, and so you are really this very same you, and again not the
same, in relation to the same things at the same time.
..- Surely ... they cannot know some things and not others, or they
would be at once knowing and not knowing.'*
The phrasing of what Socrates is supposedly guilty of is an explicit ac-
cusation of contradiction. The Parmenidean case was that the world of
the senses is the object of mere opinion because it contains such “con-
tradictions.” Thus this passage gives us, once again, the dropping of
contextual qualifiers and the relegation of the resulting conjunction of
opposites to a violation of the law. A similar trope occurs when Socrates
is forced to subtract the qualifier “which I know” in 296C6—7, and in the
paradoxes about fathers and dogs in 297D3-299A5 (your father is not
my father, so your father is other than a father and is not a father; and
your dog is a father and is yours, which makes you the child of your
father the dog). Here the qualifiers are amputated and reassembled as
if they were entirely separate in function from the terms they qualify—
as, I believe, they are indeed, on a Parmenidean understanding. Without
in any way attempting to date the arguments in the dialogue (though
one set of arguments not examined here is attributed to Protagoras in
286C), I think we may fairly claim that Plato has, at least, put into the
mouths of fifth-century sophists a logic which is that of Parmenides as
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 123
the present hypothesis interprets him, and which has affinities with the
logic of Protagoras, Zeno, and the Dissoi Logoi, though Euthydemus and
Dionysodorus apparently do not believe that it is not possible to contra-
dict, and their metaphysical views (if any) are a deep mystery. I am not
necessarily claiming that Parmenides was guilty of a mere fallacy even
though he did not believe in Protagoras’s distinction between contextual
relativity and logical contradiction. It is just that his conceptions of cop-
ula, predicate, and qualifiers meant that the sensible world had to be
viewed as no place for determinacy. It is a place of paradox and irony
where everything turns out both to be and not to be everything else, but
that is not logic’s fault; it is the world’s fault. The entities about which
his logic can be used to lead to fallacious conclusions (in our terms) are
the very entities which cannot be other than fallacious in his terms. More-
over, of course, Parmenides does not use his logic for sophistical effect;
it serves only to undercut the world of the senses in general, and it is
not a fallacy as such to say, as he does, that things which are in one
respect what they are not in another are not ultimately real, though it
might be thought a mistake to go on to say that such things are contra-
dictory. Instead, Parmenides draws an ontological conclusion from a cer-
tain logic, or vice versa. That this logic can be easily misused to morally
debasing or epistemologically corrupting ends does not mean that its
original use was also suspect. And that, perhaps, is the point of the
Euthydemus as well, the divinity and seriousness behind the eristic joust.
Once again, evidence from the dialogue is hard to situate within the
context of Plato’s philosophical development. Some believe that the di-
alogue’s tricks cannot be resolved without the heavy artillery of the late
dialogue, the Sophist, and therefore, since Plato would not have written
Euthydemus unless he had a solution and the artillery, it must be later
than (e.g.) the Phaedo or the Republic, where Plato still appears to be
struggling with such issues. Others feel that Plato would not have had to
struggle so hard with Eleatic patterns of argument if he had already had
a solution tailor-made.'* Be this as it may, however, we can conclude at
least that the issues are there in a context relevant to Eleaticism before
going on to examine the middle and later dialogues.
The Phaedo is the first place in Plato where the theory of Forms re-
ceives a canonical statement, and there is much controversy about the
motivations for the theory, the sorts of things to which Forms are as-
signed, the nature of particulars and characters, and so on.!° I do not
enter into these controversies here, though it will be obvious that I am
indebted to earlier critics. I merely point out what I take to be the nature
of a certain inference apparently recommended in the Phaedo and ap-
parently (in some way) involved in the genesis of the theory of Forms.
124 CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION
Soc Where did we get our knowledge? Was it not from the particular ex-
amples that we mentioned just now? ... Look at it in this way. Is it not
true that equal stones and sticks sometimes, without changing in them-
selves, appear equal to one person and unequal to another?
Simmias Certainly.
Soc Well, now, have you ever thought that things which were absolutely
equal (auta ta isa) were unequal, or that equality (isotés) was inequality
(anisotés)?
Simm No, never, Socrates.
Soc Then these equal things (tauta . . . ta isa) are not the same as absolute
equality (auto to ison)'®
(Phaedo 74A9-—C5)
The difference between the things which are equal (particulars) and the
equal itself (what is absolutely equal) is that the former appear equal or
unequal depending on the observer, while the latter is never thought to
be unequal.
As I have just stated it, however, there is a missing link in the inference.
We hear, first, that equal sticks and stones appear equal or unequal
depending on the observer; second, that the equal itself is never unequal.
The missing inference is from “appears equal to observer P and unequal
to observer Q” to “is equal and unequal in a way which makes it impos-
sible for it to be what is absolutely equal.” I am not talking here about
the inference from “appears” (phainetai) to “is” (auto to ho estin, 74D6),
but about the inference from “is equal to one person and unequal to
another” to “is both equal and unequal.” The predicates are considered
without their qualifiers, which are dropped, and then juxtaposed to the
absolute entity which possesses only one of the predicates, and that in
an unqualified sense. The move, once again, is from “X is F in context
p’ to “X is F” (not “X is F” simpliciter, which would make the particular
into either the form or something logically self-contradictory—Plato does
not, unlike some of the sophists, commit the fallacy of secundum quid ad
simpliciter here) but “X is F” in the ordinary sense that whatever has F in
sense P thus has F in some sense or other (not necessarily in all senses).
And this is the dropping of the qualifiers that originates with Parmen-
ides. Now, since our first clear understanding that contextual relativity
does not necessarily mean logical contradictoriness seems to come from
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 125
the Forms, since they are not identical with each other, are the same with
themselves and not with each other, just like Parmenidean “Opinion”;
but a retreat into monism is by this time also impossible for Plato, for
whom the possibility of a discourse which would do good to the soul was
bound up with there being a plurality of different reified meanings for
such a discourse to be about. Aristotle, whose Plato is the artificer of the
architectonic middle period, apparently believes that the system never
recovers from the crisis, as I will attempt to explain below; but Plato’s
own attempt to find his way out is contained in the Sophist.
One can say without controversy that Plato shows in the Sophist that
even the Forms are and are not, that he then says that the “are” and
“are not” occur in different senses, and that these two claims are sup-
posed to rescue discourse from the Eleatic view that an avoidance of
contradiction leads inevitably to monism.!? This short and uncontrover-
sial statement is enough to situate the Sophist in the context of the de-
velopments I have been tracing: (1) the Forms, too, both are and are
not, just like the particulars of the middle period and unlike both Par-
menidean being and the Forms of the middle period; (2) but the law of
noncontradiction as formulated in the Republic is now applied to these
Forms in such a way that the “are” and “are not” are said in different
senses; (3) in this way the Forms of the middle period, though they lose
their pristine Eleatic transcendence of all relativity, retain their immut-
ability, universality, and their status as ultimate objects of knowledge and
sources of meaning. Being is and is not in the Sophist, but it always is
and is not. Critics have disagreed voluminously about just which senses
of the verb “to be” (or which senses of being) are marked off from each
other in this dialogue,” but it suffices for my purposes merely to indicate
that some distinction is drawn, without specifying the terms distin-
guished.
Consider the passage where this happens most obviously:
Stranger First about motion, let us say that motion is altogether different
from rest. Or is that not so?
Theaetetus It is so.
Str So motion is not rest (ow stasis ar’estin).
Theae Not in any sense.
Str But motion is (esti) by virtue of partaking of existence (tou ontos).
Theae. Yes.
Str And once more motion is different from the same.
Theae No doubt.
Str So motion is not the same (ou tauton ara estin).
Theae No.
Str But on the other hand, motion, we said, is the same as itself, because
everything partakes of the same.
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 127
Theae Certainly.
Str Motion, then, is both the same and not the same (tauton ... kat mé
auton); we must admit this without boggling at it. For when we say it is
“the same” and “not the same” we are not using the expression in the
same sense (ou .. . homoids eirékamen). We call it “the same” on account of
its participation in the same with reference to itself, but we call it “not
the same” because of its combination with difference. .. .
(Sophist 255E11—256B2)”!
Motion is not rest but also is by partaking of being; it is the same with
itself but is not (the Form of) the same; these, however, are not logical
contradictions because the opposites are not being asserted in the same
sense. The entire world of Forms can be described by the dialectician as
a congeries of opposed terms which do not contradict one another, and
the possibility of discourse about the Forms—and thus about reality—
depends both on the fact that all the opposed terms apply and on their
not applying in the same sense.
Parmenides, of course, would have reacted with horror. So Plato’s dis-
ambiguation of all the apparent contradictions among Forms into state-
ments true in different respects is intended to show, ironically, that the
rights of reason can be preserved—not only in spite of Protagoras—but
also only through an abandonment of Parmenides. Here the revised
version of the law is shown to have an anti-relativistic outcome: the old
tie between Parmenides’ version and the existence of a transcendent
realm is now snapped in the attempt to show that only by abandoning
that version can we save the ontology and discourse that Parmenides had
irivented—shorn, of course, of what Plato regards as its monistically pro-
found unintelligibility.
It is interesting to speculate about the role of the Parmenides in this
picture of Plato’s development. It is not necessary to state that interpre-
tations of the dialogue vary; even to sketch the extent of the variation
would take too much space.” But an observation on the structure of the
dialogue may give us some index of directions to follow.
The younger Socrates is not impressed by Zeno’s antinomies, because,
he says, they are easily obtained from any sensible object. This is the
doctrine of Phaedo and of Protagoras as I and others have sketched it.
But what would surprise him would be if the same antinomies were true
of Forms. (That is what happens in the Sophist’s revision of middle-period
doctrine.) Parmenides then deduces antinomies from the Forms in an
impressive response to Socrates’ dare. It is tempting to conclude from
this that we are to take each Parmenidean antinomy, say P and not F
and disambiguate the purported contradiction, finding out the different
senses in which P and not P are true, just as the Sophist recommends.
The Parmenides will thus seem to call explicitly for the Sophist as part
128 CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION
(though of course not all) of its message and work. Unfortunately this
program of disambiguation is difficult to carry out in detail, because
there appear to be true sides to the antinomies, as well as errors of
reasoning not corrected in the Sophist, and a good—though not deci-
sive—general critique of this way of reading the Parmenides’ relation to
the Sophist has been offered by Robinson.”* Still, one can say this in
general: the Parmenides purports to demonstrate that compresence of
Opposites (in respects not explicitly specified) among the Forms which is
denied in the Phaedo and the Republic as well as by the younger Socrates
in the later dialogue itself. The Sophist shows that such a compresence is
possible—indeed necessary for discourse—so long as the opposites are
not true in the same sense. However the details are worked out, it will
appear that late Plato no longer absolves the Forms from relativity.
A word about method in the Philebus in relation to the Sophist. The
Sophist tells us to take note of the precise senses and respects in which
“contradictory” statements are true.*4 Similarly, the Philebus tells us that,
in addition to concluding that the same thing is at once one and an
indefinite plurality, we must discover precisely how many it is (i.e., how
many subdivisions a given classification has).2° Here the oneness of the
genus corresponds to the singling out of the subject matter in the Sophist;
the indefinitely many correspond to the application of opposite terms;
and the just how many correspond to the specification of respects. The
method in both cases has as its most difficult feature the specification of
a precise middle ground between distinctiveness and haziness, between
boundedness and unboundedness.
If this story makes sense, Plato’s development can be viewed as a grad-
ual clarification of the import of Eleaticism and its logic for a theory of
Forms, that is, a pluralistic theory involving supersensibles related to
each other by nonidentity in order to preserve distinctions of meaning.
Parmenides had distinguished sensible from supersensible on the basis
of a looser formulation of the law; Protagoras had tried to use the tighter
formulation to dispense with the supersensible and condemn everything
sensible to an ethically loose variability; Plato applies the tighter for-
mulation first to sensibles and then to Forms as he moves from the
Phaedo’s denial of Form-relativity to the Sophist’s specification of precisely
that relativity in total tightness of respect.
It has already been observed that Aristotle behaves as if Plato’s late
revision of his ontology was not a success; he takes the Third Man ar-
gument as working against the theory of Forms, and his interpretation
of the separation between Forms and particulars does not allow for the
possibility that his own theory of ambiguity might apply within that
separation.” In particular, one might suppose him to have reasoned like
this: “The big reason for holding Forms was that they were independent
\
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 129
of relativity. Now Plato has allowed this into the Forms, too, so the ar-
gument for their existence based on incomplete predicates collapses.
Nothing therefore is left but to find the universality of Forms in the
immanent formal characteristics of particulars, since Forms and partic-
ulars are now indistinguishable from each other on narrowly logical
grounds. We must be modern and swallow the anti-transcendent impli-
cations of the new law of noncontradiction.” This is one possible corre-
lation between Aristotle and a certain attitude toward the transition from
middle to late Plato. For Aristotle, a distinction between immaterial and
material substances is no longer a distinction between universals and
particulars.
There is another way of putting these same points. As R. E.Allen has
pointed out, an expression like to ison, “the equal” (or to eon, “being”),
is, as Plato remarks in Phaedo 103A4—C2, ambiguous in Greek; it can
refer both to the thing which has the characteristic and to the charac-
teristic that the thing has.?”? In Parmenides such an expression would
refer to both in the world of truth, for being is both; it is never qualified
by its opposite, and so it 2s what it has. Plato’s middle-period distinction
between Forms and particulars, with their different sorts of accessibility
to relativity, is supposed to cut through the ambiguity: a particular zson
is both equal and unequal, while the Form (to ison) is only equal. Thus
the sophistic paradox “the equal is unequal” is found only in particulars
and is not surprising in them; they have different predicates true in
different respects. Later, however, the Forms also appear to be qualified
by their opposites, though in different respects (just like particulars). It
is at this point that an Aristotelian qgua-locution can come to the aid of a
Platonic ontology (the Forms are P qua x and not P qua y)—or of an
Aristotelian one, for it might be argued that, since both Forms and par-
ticulars are contextually variable, there no longer is a clear distinction
between them, and so their ontological separation must be dropped.
Both are P qua x and not P qua y, and therefore the middle-period
distinction between Forms and particulars can reappear on the level of
immanent concrete particulars alone as it becomes the distinction be-
tween substance—which must have a given essential property P—and
accidents, which are and are not indifferently.
Thus this second part of Parmenides’ logic, involving the dropping of
qualifiers, may have been historically fruitful in sophistry, in Plato’s de-
velopment, and in Aristotle as it provided raw material for subsequent
adoption and revision, for ontology and for clarifications of the laws. It
remains to be seen whether philosophers earlier than or contemporary
with Parmenides were concerned with similar issues in their own fashion,
with the relationships between opposites applying to an underlying sub-
stratum and with the permissibility, necessity, or impermissibility of those
130 CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION
but he probably believed that they broke his own version of the law, in
which there is a contradiction even in different senses, and that, in so
doing, they demonstrated that opposites were in some sense one as parts
of a cosmic harmony which could survive being ripped apart. But secun-
dum quid would have been there only if Heraclitusshad demonstrably
concluded that day and night are true of God in the same sense, or that,
given that God was day in some sense, God could not have been night
in any sense. Similarly for Parmenides: the inference is not from “Fire
is not the same with Night” to “Fire is never the same,” but rather from
“Fire is the same with itself and not the same with Night” to “Fire is the
same and not the same”—this, though unspecified, being rejected as
relativistic, contradictory, or vague according to the earlier version of the
law. The sophists are guilty of secundum quid, but the real philosophers
are not—they are working with an “archaic” theory of sentence structure
in which relativity and contradiction are not yet clearly distinguished,
or—to put it differently—they feel that the tensions evoked by dropping
the qualifiers are metaphysically decisive, for good or for ill, in ways
which the more commonsensical later version of the law would conceal
(see n. 33, below). In this theory, the core of the sentence is a subject-
predicate-copula complex which is directly mappable onto reality (in
Parmenides, the mapping is so exact that the copula of an adequate logos
must even remain unnegated in order to express being). Within the
complex, there are levels of importance (thus qualifiers are dropped to
see if terms contradict each other or are contextually relative, and terms
are dropped to see if the copula is negated). The sophists think that this
dropping can occur without damage to truth, but Parmenides and Her-
aclitus use it to produce sentences with no blanks filled in.%3
So much, at any rate, for the claim that Parmenides’ logic of qualifiers
could historically have been what I have attributed to him. The dropping
of qualifiers as well as the dropping of terms are two parts of the same
logic in Greek philosophy, that attributed to him in chapter 1.
Chapters 2-4 made my third claim—that Parmenides used a method
of enumeration and variation in order to demonstrate and illustrate
things. Insofar as such a claim simply means that he used a rational
proof-procedure, there is no historical difficulty with it.24 But there is
more to Parmenides’ method than enumeration and variation: there is
reductio ad absurdum argument (B8.6—15), transcendental argument
(B2), modal argument (see chapter 4), and proof by ironic reversal
(“Opinion”). If I want to single out one tree from this forest of rational
procedures, I must show that it can be found outside Parmenides as well,
even if it be antecedently granted that the whole apparatus of rational
argument is Eleatic.
There would appear to be some reason in Zeno and in Plato for at-
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 133
\
CONTEXT AND CONTRADICTION 135
accordance with its version of the law. Zeno, adhering to the same logic,
uses the method asa scaffold for the finding only of opposites in the
sensible world. Plato, still committed to the method as part of a search
for truth, uses it to call for disambiguation in the light of a new under-
standing of the law. It is Parmenides who is at issue throughout, as the
dialogue’s title indicates.
Thus, I think, it is historically possible for Parmenides to have held
the views on syntax and ontology and their relationship to logic, in par-
ticular the treatment of contradiction, that I have attributed to him, and
it is likely (in view of his successors) that he was a methodological orig-
inator who hada lot of influence. Again, it is not new to claim that
Parmenides was influential and related to his historical context in various
ways, but I think that the particular logic attributed to him in preceding
chapters—the relation of contradictions, terms, and the copula toa single
method—is new, as a whole, with him. In the next chapter I consider
how the being which is reached by this method is related to some other
entities in the history of philosophy.
CHAPTER 6
The
Bounded
and the ‘
Unbounded
136
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 137
itself that his canons for positivity are looser than Maimonides’ and can
allow negative states of affairs to be positive; this enables him to cheat,
as it were, and not have negatives import, the infinite. The classical
(Pseudo-Dionysian) form of negative theology, as distinct from Maimon-
ides’, requires both positive and negative statements;!* with this, Par-
menides in a sense has no quarrel, since he too requires both, so long as
both are along the positive route; but the.determinacy which is required
by canonical speech never vanishes, and so, once again, it is not as if he
required infinity by corralling the negative route into “Truth.” Paradox,
contradiction, and self-referential inconsistency would tend to dilute the
very finiteness which is required by his prescriptions and prohibitions,
while a preference for the infinite in language and reality would undercut
what he sees as his intrinsic positivity. Thus an answer to the question
“why would Parmenides have chosen the method I have attributed to
him?” can be given, not only in terms of his early versions of later rules
of rationality, but also in terms of a general transcendental argument to
the effect that reality is only approachable as bounded. The origin of
many rules which were to be dominant in Western thinking thus lies in
an intuition of the real as finite.
Let us now look at some of the less bounded alternatives. Heraclitus
is one. Parmenides is, of course, noted for turning an ironic eye on our
dualistic cosmologies, our copulation and sexual disjunctions, our fetuses
and our astronomy.'* But his work also shines with the confidence be-
gotten by a realized, rational access to the transcendent, to which all
names spoken by mortals ultimately refer in spite of themselves.!® To
know a being which lies at the heart of language and to know that this
being is undivided from itself even in the worst of life’s vicissitudes—
perhaps also to know that one’s thought is one with this which it contem-
plates—is, perhaps, Parmenides’ formula for happiness, if this is not too
far from the text. One can even imagine a gospel: “Nothing isn’t real,
so it’s impossible for anything to alter, to be other than it is. Everything
is already full, complete, perfect. You are also fully real, in fact you are
reality itself, and your mutable becoming is only a dream. Simply be
what you cannot keep from being—namely, the being that you are.” This
doctrine could carry with it reassurance and tranquility, even bliss. And
in a way its underlying message, if not its mood, is not too different from
that of Heraclitus, for whom the tensile strength of the divine Fire is
never interrupted and indeed shows itself forth most strongly when it
springs forth in a new form after being quenched,!° thus overcoming
death in the moment of death’s triumph. Heraclitus’s God proves to be
the same in and through all the changes to which the world is subject,!’
and Parmenides’ being turns out to be the real, though ironically implicit,
object even of mortal language. But there are two different attitudes
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 141
\
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 145
in order to contain the transcendent; they are as they are. This, too, is
a coincidence of transcendence and finitude, but with a different meta-
physical twist.
Similar considerations can perhaps be discovered through the figures
of Apollo and Dionysos on a somewhat Nietzschean interpretation of
them. Apollo is the spirit of measure, restraint, clarity, and order. His
kind of immortality involves resistance to death and its corroding action.
Dionysos is the wisdom involved in allowing periodic spillovers of the
irrational; his is the ability to be reborn through death, to be torn apart
and thus made whole. For Apollo, the transcendent is a pure finite form
against which the waves of time lap in vain, as they do against Parmen-
ides’ being. But with Dionysos, the transcendent rips and bites in fury
into the corpus of finite form, destroying it and guaranteeing its im-
mortality at the same time. Yet the two are brothers, just as Parmenides
and Heraclitus are; immortality is guaranteed by both, since the form
which is born again out of its own destruction, which is knit together by
being dismembered, is the form which survives death by being aloof from
it. Parmenidean form accomplishes in its stasis the same timelessness and
immortality which are given through the death and resurrection of the
Heraclitean elements. Eternity in some sense resides both in the timeless
of an abiding “now” and in the cycles of temporal recurrence. Perhaps,
then, the three perspectives thus far discussed might again be said to
come to the same thing: the transcendent finite form of Parmenides
accomplishes the same thing as the infinite does when it murders and
resurrects finite form, and both express the message that finite form,
just as it is, has the infinite behind it. Yet the ethical outcomes are very
different. The first gets expressed as an ironic Parmenidean detachment
from flux and transiency, the second as a willing Christian submission
to insult and humiliation or (paradoxically) as the Heraclitean prosecu-
tion of war, and the third as a tranquil Buddhistic acceptance of the
scene as it passes. The Parmenidean position is in between the two others.
Like the Buddhist position, it does not mar finite form, but, unlike that
position, it also views transcendence as initially characterized by form;
in this emphasis on form it differs from the Christian position on the
formless infinite which, however, it resembles in not leaving sensibles as
ultimately real. The three positions represent possibilities which are
there, ground which can be staked out. .
I have alluded to Nietzsche’s conception of the Apollinian and Diony-
sian without mentioning his own conception of the eternal recurrence
of the self-same, which is explicitly presented in Thus Spake Zarathustra
as part ofa vision of eternity.?” This conception adds another member
to the spectrum of possibilities. The eternal recurrence is of course dif-
ferent from the return of a resurrected body, for, not only does it occur
146 THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED
form and proportion which animates the sculptors of this and later times,
the same emphasis on self-sufficiency and an internal principle of bal-
ance. The contrast with individual Gothic forms, which acquire meaning
only by being part of a hierarchy which transcends them, is evident.
Independence from variation is purchased at the cost’of leaving our lived
world behind, and transcendence by leaving out the infinite. This com-
promise acquires stability at a cost, that of having no rapprochement
between the transcendent and the immanent. And yet, if we take the
immanent not necessarily as the sensible but as what participates in the
transcendent, then, if being is the only thing there is and it is like a
sphere, the cost is small, since the transcendent and the immanent are
both the same, enclosed within the same boundary: being is the only
thing that participates in being. If one wants to escape a certain concep-
tual divorce between the transcendent and the finite which is inevitable
(at least initially) for Buddhism and Christianity, then the transcendent,
finite sphere is a plausible alternative. If, on the other hand, one wants
to transcend this sphere without falling once again into the sensible, one
must conceive of the infinite-finite distinction as strictly parallel to the
transcendent-immanent distinction, as the two religions seem to do. The
next question is how the essential unity of the two domains is to be
indicated: is it a matter of converting the one into the other through the
overcoming of immanence by transcendence, or simply a matter of ac-
cepting the finitude of the finite, knowing that this finitude itself reveals
the infinite in the very act of accepting its limits? Here Christianity and
Buddhism, paradoxically, are able to draw sensible things into closer
relationships with the transcendent than Parmenides is—even though,
for him, the finite sphere is transcendent, it is the only finite thing that
is transcendent, since he thinks of sensibles as at least partly indetermi-
nate. For the two other views, on the contrary, everything is either di-
vinisable or already divine.
One name should perhaps have been mentioned before now—that of
Hegel. For it is in Hegel, above all, that one finds a mutual coimplication
and relation of the finite and the infinite; the entire system is incarna-
tionalist. There is, however, this difference between Hegel and the reli-
gions: in Hegel the coincidence of bounded and unbounded is thought
of rationally and is something which can be communicated in a kind of
fusion of intuitive and discursive reason, while in the religions it is some-
thing already accomplished, not needing further penetration by the hu-
man intellect. One may note in this connection that the system of Hegel
in a sense covers the same ground as that of Parmenides, though in a
diametrically opposite way. For whereas in both the coincidence of the
transcendent and the finite is accessible to reason, in Parmenides it is a
reason subject to—indeed, generated by—the law of noncontradiction
\
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 149
(though not taken in its later sense), while in Hegel the conquest of spirit
is precipitated precisely by the overcoming of this law.** One might say
that all other traditional Western philosophy hangs between these two
extremes of tautology and contradiction. Parmenides, indeed, might
(from a Hegelian perspective) be seen as the arbiter of an unstable com-
promise, in that definiteness of form can be purchased without un-Par-
menidean contradictions only in a monistic ontology; a pluralistic world,
as Plato sees in the Sophist, cannot be had without a revision of Parmen-
ides’ version of the laws.34 And, as Aristotle sees, this latter admission of
negation and contextual relativity prepares the way for the finding of
conceptual determinacy in the sensible world. If one does not accept the
Parmenidean solution and does not find the transcendent in something
finite, one must find it in the infinite, and there then arises the task of
reconciliation between the infinite and the finite, a task which perhaps
cannot ultimately be accomplished, on the intellectual as opposed to the
religious or practical level, without Hegel’s overcoming of the logical laws,
for a logic designed to encapsulate certain sorts of infinite cannot do so
unless it is no longer restricted to the merely determinate. I shall say
more later about the role of the laws in relation to these issues.
The identity and the difference between Hegel and a branch of Chris-
tianity close to him in spirit can be seen if we compare him with Pseudo-
Dionysius the Areopagite, whose negative theology has already been
mentioned. For Pseudo-Dionysius, true discourse about God consists in
affirming of God all positive perfections (on the grounds that created
perfection comes from God and must preexist in God) and at the same
time in denying them of God (on the grounds that God is infinite and
no finite property can univocally be possessed by God), thus striking a
balance between strict proportionality and lack of proportionality be-
tween the finite and the infinite.*> Here the affirmation and the denial
occur in different senses and do not violate the law because Pseudo-
Dionysius does not equate creatures with God; the one sense traces crea-
tures back to God and the other measures the distance. And yet there
is supposed to be a flavor of paradox, as if the affirmation and the denial
concealed the answer to a riddle. One can predict that if God and crea-
tures are wholly identified in a coincidence of transcendent and finite,
the end result will be the coincidence of opposites in one and the same
sense, the Hegelian logic. From the rational point of view as expressed
by Hegel, the Christian dichotomy between God and creatures is one
that has yet to be overcome; it collapses only in the Incarnation itself,
which is not a logical process. A rational overcoming of the same di-
chotomy would express the coincidence between bounded and un-
bounded not as a historical scandal but as the coincidence of opposites,
not merely in God and in different senses, but also in creatures and in
150 THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED
the same sense. Hegel thus accomplishes the Parmenidean and Christian
goal, but at the cost of violating the logical canons that are tied to these
systems’ different treatments of finite and infinite, transcendent and im-
manent. Yet it was these canons that set up the goal in the first place,
for only the boundedness of reality initially led to its approachability in
a discourse governed by the law. Hegel achieves the goal at the price of
abandoning what made the goal desirable.
In these various ways, I think, Parmenides’ vision of the truth can take
its place in the history of philosophy, can be seen to accomplish the same
goal as other conceptual and mythic structures, while differing in method
from them. This vision possesses a conceptual clarity and isolation, but
it also possesses a sterility and remoteness from the temporal that is all
its own: as noted earlier, it embodies the frozen rigidity, but also the
antique charm, of a Greek sculpture in the archaic style. The philo-
sophical originality (over and above the methodological and logical orig-
inality) of Parmenides consists in his bounded vision of the coincidence
of the transcendent and the finite. Many relationships with other systems
are, of course, possible: those with Heraclitus, the Sophists, Plato, and
Aristotle were touched on in the preceding chapter, while connections
between Parmenides and Leibniz, logical atomism, and the like are also
available.*° But Christianity, Hegel, and Nietzsche represent nodal points
in the Western tradition, while Buddhism (even as imperfectly under-
stood here) represents a cross-cultural alternative. From these, others
can be deduced besides those I have mentioned.
There is thus another possibility besides Parmenides—not to find an
abiding transcendent form beyond this world, but to find in the world
itself, with its forms which do not abide, the abode of the transcendent.
This can be done either in the Heraclitean/Christian way or in the
Buddhist way, either by finding an immortality of forms in their per-
petual dissolution and recreation or by finding in the forms themselves
the infinite hiding behind the finite and also being revealed by it. It is
precisely in its limitation and weakness, or at the moment of its death,
that the finite is thought to be closest to the infinite in these ways of
thinking—a powerful contrast to the perduring, transcendent finite of
Parmenides. It may be that one is never reborn except by being slain,
that there is no rose without an antecedent cross; on such an account
the Parmenidean attempt to give language a solid basis by fixing and
making stable a piece of finite reality would look like madness, since the
real purchase of the intellect on things will be revealed in its picture of
their diversity and changeability, not in an empty snapshot of logical
form. Parmenides’ goddess was supposed to be giving criteria for rational
Judgment, and yet she ended up restricting that judgment to one object
about which very little could be said—a solution which is un-Dionysian
\
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 151
in the extreme. Even an Apollinian work of art, one might say, is not
supposed to be the triumph of boundedness as such and over every-
thing—that would be Pentheus, not Apollo—but is rather one which
declares its own incompleteness by the very perfection of its bounded-
ness. Parmenides might be thought to go too far. The smooth surface of
his sphere, though unblemished, perhaps ought to have had the same
effect as the deliberate flaws introduced by Japanese artists into their
work. The flaw connects the work with its unbounded creative source by
commenting on its own status as finished, and therefore limited and
incomplete. This is, perhaps, again the same phenomenon as that in-
volved in the wisdom of Socrates. It might be said that Parmenides should
have recognized that the bounded and the unbounded need each other
here just as in Heraclitus, Christianity, and Buddhism. One could thus
suppose that Parmenides’ flawless sphere is just this Pentheus-like ten-
dency to boundedness writ large and made perfect—a far cry from let-
ting the transitory be transitory or flawing it so as to make it dissolve
into the infinite.
But which is he really, Pentheus or Apollo? He is the former if we take
him as merely stamping boundedness on reality, merely demanding that
it be conceptually graspable. He speaks from Apollo if we take his def-
initeness and limitedness to express the sort of stable position that I have
been attributing to him in this chapter. If the transcendent finite occupies
the same position as the infinite which becomes immanent, then it is not
the expression of limitedness for its own sake so much as an articulation
of a complicated moment of balance between other metaphysical vari-
ables. Parmenides’ encounter with the limits of language is not a flat
insistence on conceptual graspability; instead, it displays the limits of
what is attainable within the scope of a prohibition, the agile twisting of
language within the limits of the speakable, a sort of antinomianism
within the law. That he has all that wealth of negation within the limits
of an archaic rigidity means that Pentheus is only part of the story; there
is also an effect in which the Dionysian, though completely subdued in
one sense, is still visible as a set of negations within an Apollinian calm.
Thus, pace Heidegger, the Western impulse toward rational speech,
which begins with Parmenides and proceeds in accordance with later
revisions of his logic and with the inclusion of the infinite in the tran-
scendent, far from being a covering-up of being, might be thoyght to be
the ultimate expression for the zeal, so to speak, of the unbounded to
behold a stable finite image of itself in a delimited mirror. What for
Parmenides would bea flaw is for others the opening into the infinite;
but all preserve the same balance in an ethic far more ample than that
of Pentheus; for all, the finite is transcendent simply as finite.
In the end it all comes back to the circle or sphere. This lovely figure
152 THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED
has seemed to many to contain all perfection within it—Goethe said that
the sun was the most beautiful object that could be seen with the eyes,
not only because of its golden color, but also because of its shape. In
putting Parmenides on a par with other traditions in the examination of
what is perfect, one can be said in the end only to be exploring a met-
aphor for what is discrete, definite, and determinate, and to be treating
that metaphor as one not only for being but also for at least one kind of
reason. If that reason contains within itself one way of solving the prob-
lem of finite and infinite, rational and irrational, then Parmenides’
sphere can stand asa metaphor for that way in Western thought. It is
one extreme in a dialectic of the bounded and the unbounded.
Before concluding, I would like to make one further remark on the
history of logic in relation to this specimen of dialectic. Up to now I have
been treating Christianity as if its coincidence of the bounded and the
unbounded took place only in the redemptive events like the incarnation
and not in the divine nature by itself. But perhaps Christianity can be
seen to occupy an intermediate position between Parmenides and other
views when we reflect on the fact that its deity (though this fact is sup-
posed to be revealed, not rationally ascertained) is not one infinite, one
purely unbounded, but a Trinity consisting of three infinite persons
bounded off from each other. In this way Father, Son, and Holy Spirit
would be a coincidence of bounded and unbounded halfway between the
bounded transcendent of Parmenides and the transcendent infinite of
Buddhism. The fact that there can be relationships of nonidentity among
the three persons, of imaging, precession, and spiration, makes it easier
for the Trinity to be imitated by and become embodied in creatures in
creation and incarnation, and so makes the Christian finite have a ten-
dency to become associated with the Trinity, to be swept up and trans-
formed in a way that, as we have indicated, does not happen with
Parmenidean and Buddhist finite form. There is also a difference in the
attitude toward contradiction, in the logic of respects. Parmenidean
bounded being is what it is by casting out all distinctions in the same or
in different respects; the trinity allows distinctions of respect to exist
(God is not three and one in the same respect), but only in a transcendent
which is not only bounded but also unbounded; it is only in Hegel that
we get a coincidence of opposites in the same respect which, not sur-
prisingly, is tied to the total infinitization of the finite. What Parmenides
cast out is redeemed in a system with different parameters, and Chris-
tianity once again appears as a midpoint along the way. The three stages
involve an allowance of the infinite into the finite which is at the same
time a gradual allowance of opposition and contradiction. Like the stages
in the revision of the law in the Greek context discussed in the preceding
chapter, the wider dialectic discussed in this chapter thus permits us to
THE BOUNDED AND THE UNBOUNDED 153
Much of the present study consists of textual analysis, and in this Ap-
pendix I have attempted to add Parmenides’ words and a translation—
only, however, for the reader’s convenience. This is not a critical text,
and I make no claim to signal all important issues in either Greek or
translation. Instead, I imagine readers who may wish to see Greek and/
or English versions of the whole in order conveniently to have a sense of
the poem’s range or to determine the context in which certain quotations
and arguments are nested, but who may not initially wish to have, for
those purposes at least, a critical apparatus, an exhaustive commentary,
or a list of alternative translations. Following are some comments on the
construction of and limits on this Appendix.
1. A version of Parmenides, together with commentary, an account of
differences from the preceding critical edition of Taran, and many re-
productions of alternative translations, has recently been published by
David Gallop. While no interpretation of Parmenides is uncontroversial,
Gallop’s fine work on the fragments will surely figure in discussions
among readers, including those who are approaching the text for the
first time. (For my disagreements with Gallop, see chapter 1 and below.)
Thus it seems advisable simply to start from this work and to indicate
the places where I would represent the Greek differently, also supplying
other notes about matters of text and translation. The following are the
places where differences from Gallop’s renderings occur: the accentua-
tion of esti (see below), the capitalization of certain personifications, and
matters of text and/or punctuation in B1.3, 8.4, 8.5, S12 orb. o. 22,
8.31, 8.33, 8.48, 8.53, 8.60-61, the omitted heading for fragment 9 (see
note to B8.51), 16.1, 17, Cornford’s fragment, and the ends ‘of certain
fragments. All important differences are explained below or in the notes.
Readers who wish to dig further are advised to go, first to Gallop, then
to recent studies by Mourelatos and Barnes for interpretation and bib-
liography, and to Taran fora critical edition and an account of earlier
interpretations. See also my Bibliography.
155
156 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 1
position, otherwise enclitic (see Charles Kahn’s The Verb ‘Be’ and W. S.
Barrett’s edition of Euripides’ Hzppolytus).
4. The translation is in many places indebted to versions by Moure-
latos, Taran, Gallop, and Barnes. Large borrowings (e.g., sentences) are
indicated if they occur in places where the translation borrowed is not
one of the clear possibilities.
5. Ellipsis dots in parentheses (...) in Greek or translation indicate
something which I am either omitting or not translating; in these places
there are explanatory footnotes.
PARMENIDES’ ON NATURE
FRAGMENT 1
The mares that carry me as far as my heart desires were taking me along,
when once they brought me to and put me on the very significant route
of the goddess, which guides the man who knows through every (.. .).
That way I was carried, for that was the way the attentive mares were
carrying me, stressing the chariot, and maidens were leading the way.
The axle, glowing with heat in the naves, sent forth a sharp whistle (for
it was being made to revolve by the two round wheels on either side)
when the daughters of the Sun, leaving the house of Night behind for
the light, were hurrying to conduct me, having brushed the veils off
from their heads. There are the gates of the paths of Night and Day; a
lintel and a stone threshold go around them. The shining gates are filled
with huge doors, whose keys of retribution are held by much-avenging
Justice. The maidens, appeasing her with soft words, cleverly persuaded
158 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 2
5. Here one should read eupeitheos instead of eukukleos, in spite of the inviting comparison
with lines 42—49, because the context involves reliability versus lack of trust (for rea-
sons see Gallop’s text and Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 154ff).
6. Or per onta. These lines are apparently about an extension of the goddess’s teaching
on the opinions of mortals, one in which she clarifies their significance further for the
young man’s benefit. It is not really safe to say much more than this, nor to attempt
to substantiate an interpretation of Parmenides by using these lines. See Gallop for
the differences among interpreters and translators.
7. Agreeing with Barnes (Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1, p. 158n6) that this and related
words must be wide enough to cover both successful and unsuccessful thought; as one
reads from fragment 2 through the end of fragment 8, it becomes clear that the god-
dess’s intention is to start with a word expressive of thought generally, then to show
that real insight is only possible on her own ontology. Thus “thinking” rather than
“knowing” at first and afterwards.
APPENDIX 159
her to push the bolted bar quickly back off the gates. As the gates flew
open, they made a gaping gap out of the doors, having set the bronze
jambs, fitted with bolts and pins, revolving by turns in their sockets. Then
the maidens brought the chariot and the mares straight through them
on the broad way. And the goddess gladly received me, taking my right
hand, and spoke to me, addressing me in these words:
“Young man, coming to our abode the companion of immortal char-
ioteers, with the mares which carry you, Welcome! For it is no bad Fate
which sent you along this route (though it is far off the beaten track of
men) but rather Rightness and Justice. Now you must learn everything,
both the unshaking temper of persuasive Truth and the opinions of
mortals, in which there is no true trust. Still, though, you will learn this
as well: how the things of opinion should have been in order to be ac-
ceptable (.. .)
FRAGMENT 2
Come now, and I shall tell you, and you take charge of the story once
you have heard it, which are the only routes of inquiry for thinking: the
one, that it is and that it is not possible for it not to be, is the route of
Persuasion (for she accompanies Truth); the other, that it is not and that
it is right for it not to be, this I point out to you as a completely unin-
formative track. For neither could you get to know what-is-not (for it
cannot be accomplished) nor could you point it out. ;
160 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 3
FRAGMENT 4 ;
FRAGMENT 5
FRAGMENT 6
8. To say this is to say what is said in fragment 8, namely that all genuine thought is
about what-is. But this is certainly not to rule out the ultimate identity, necessary for
an absolute monist, between invariable thought and being which some translators find
in this line. It is only to defer the explicit announcement of that identity until the
monism has been clinched in B8.38—41 (see chapter 4).
9. Or (with Taran) taking ho nous as the subject of apotméxei, the mind cannot cut off
being from gripping being. Either way it is the thinker who is forced to confront his
or her constant access to being.
10. The alternative translation (e.g., Gallop’s “It must be that what is there for speaking
and thinking of 7s” also asserts, in conjunction with the next sentence, that connection
between language, thought, and being which must be the central point.
11. See Gallop’s textual note and Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, p. 77n7. Cordero, how-
ever, suggests that the original filler could have meant “I will begin”; this leads to the
suggestion that there were only two routes (Phronesis 24 (1979): 1-32; Cordero also
gives an account of recent debates). See also the Introduction and chapter 1, n. 15.
APPENDIX 161
FRAGMENT 3
... For the same thing is there for thinking and for being [Gallop].
FRAGMENT 4
Behold alike things absent from the mind and things present to it firmly.
For you will not cut what-is off from gripping what-is, neither if it is
scattering everywhere, in every way, in ordered array, nor if it is bringing
itself together.
FRAGMENT 5
It is all the same to me where Istart off from, because I'll get back there
again.
FRAGMENT 6
It is fitting to say and to think this: that what-is is. For it can be, whereas
nothing cannot. These things I bid you ponder. First I bar you from this
route of inquiry, but also from the one on which mortals wander, know-
ing nothing, double-headed. For helplessness in their breasts steers a
mind set adrift. They are tossed about, as much deaf as blind, an un-
discerning horde, by whom to be and not to be are considered the same
and not the same—and the route of all is backward-turning.
162 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 7
ov YaO unmote tovto Saphe eivar wr) &dvta-
GAAG ob THAS’ a@’ ddod SiCrjoLos Eloye Vontta
undé o° Edos MoAUTELQOV SOV xaTa THVdE BLAoDw,
vee GOXOTOV OULA xa HYNECOaAV axouTV
or xal YA@ooav, xoeivat 5é Adywr TOMVONOLY ELEYYOV
e& euédev Ondévta.
FRAGMENT 8
. wOvos 6° Ett pUTOS ddoi0
Aetmetar Ms Eotiv: tavty. & Eni ojuat’ ~aor
TOAAG UGA’, WS KyEvnTOV Edv xai avodEDodv goTLV,
ovAOV Wouvoyevés TE xal ATOELES (.. .)!2
or ovdé not Hv od’ ~otat, Exel viv Eat 6uOd mav!3
Ev, ouvexés: tiva yao yévvav diCrjoea adtod;
mH whVEV avENnVEV; oT’ Ex un Edvtos Eo
paovtat o ode vogiv: od yae matdov ovdSE vonTdv
EOTLV OWS OVX ~oTL. TIS’ Gv ULV xal YEEOS DEGEV
VoteQov 7 MEdoVEV, TOD UNdevdc GEEGUEVOV, Div;
OUTWS 1 MéuAVv MEehévat YEEMV EOTLV 7} ODL.
OvdE MoT Ex UN EdvtTOS'4 E—rjoet Tliotios ioxtc
ylyveodat tt ta’ avTO-: Tov Elvexev OdtE yevéodat!®
VS
ott OAAvotat avixe Aixn yardoaoa rédnvotv,
GAN’ Exe: 1) SE xEtotg MEQl tToUTwV év TALS’ ~otLW:
EOTLV 1] OVx EotLV:'® xExeLTat 5° ObV, domEQ aveyxn,
12. There are many variants in this line, and many emendations. In chapter 3 I argue for
Simplicius’s reading for the beginning of the line, oulon mounogenes. For the end of the
line Taran records éd’ateleston from Simplicius and éd’agenéton from Simplicius and
others. Gallop reports suggestions from Taran, Owen, and Mourelatos (teleston, teleion,
teléen) involving the sense of completeness or perfection, and this must have been the
meaning, given that the end of the line looks forward specifically to lines 42-49.
Whence “perfect.”
133 Gallop places a comma here, but I try to showin chapter 3 that the unity of what-is
is viewed from many different perspectives; thus homou pan bears directly on hen.
14. See chapter 4 for reasons for retaining the manuscript reading ek mé eontos here.
15. Perishing seems to be associated in Parmenides’ mind with the future, as we can tell
from the mellei esesthai in 20. The reasons for this are obscure unless it is clear in his
mind that what-is always already exists. As Mourelatos observes, the aoristic comings-
to-be in 13 and 19-20 are appropriate to a consideration of coming-to-be in general
as a punctual event somewhere in time.
16. Gallop (in his book andin his Monist article) makes the interesting suggestion that a
question mark should be printed here. I do not see how to rule this out or to prove
it; it is unconnected with an existential reading, and a court renders its verdict with
an affirmation or a denial. But, as Gallop says, lively dialectical questions are effectively
used by Parmenides.
APPENDIX 163
FRAGMENT 7
For this will never be brought to pass: that things that are not are. But
you keep your thought away from this route of inquiry, and do not let
long-standing habit take you along it by force, to ply an aimless eye and
echoing ear and tongue. Instead, judge with your reason the very con-
tentious challenge that has been uttered by me.
FRAGMENT 8
All that remains is the account of the route, “that it is.” Along it there
are very many signposts that what-is is ungenerable and unperishing, a
whole of a single kind, unmoving, and perfect. Nor was it, nor will it be,
since it is now altogether one, cohesive. For what birth would you seek
for it? Which way, from what did it grow? Nor will I allow you to say or
think: out of what-is-not. For it cannot be said or thought that it is not.
And what need urged it on to grow later or earlier, starting from noth-
ing? So it must either be completely or not at all. Nor will the strength
of Trust ever permit anything besides it to come to be out of what-is-
not. Because of this, neither to come to be nor to perish did Justice allow,
releasing her bonds: instead, she holds. The decision in these matters
lies in this: it is or it is not. For it has been decided, as it must, to leave
164 APPENDIX
17. For an argument against Owen’s adverbial homoion and in favor of taking estin, without
accent, as copulative here, see chapter 3.
18. Whether houneken in B8.32 means “wherefore” or “because,” the connection between
31 and 32 would seem close. I suggest “wherefore,” because modal personifications
like Ananké in 30 are always used as reasons for things in this poem.
19. For the reading epidees: mé eon instead of epideues: eon see Coxon, Classical Quarterly n.s.
18 (1968): 70-75.
20. See my discussion at the beginning of the Appendix for the accentuation of esti.
21. One dispute in this line is whether to take howneken as “that wherefore,” “that for the
sake of which,” or “that,” introducing the clause “that it is,’ as in Kirk and Raven’s
“what can be thought is only the thought that it is.” But surely, in the context of the
uniqueness of what-is as asserted in the following lines, all that counts is that genuine
thought stands in a unique relationship to what is and is about it, and both sides of
the dispute agree with this.
22. See chapter 4 for the text here and for other considerations in lines 36-38. The present
rendering of en hoi pephatismenon estin in line 35 is only a guess at the description of
the perfect, one-on-one relationship between true thought and being which is the point
of this very obscure line.
23. With Gallop, following Woodbury for the text and Burnyeat for the translation.
APPENDIX 165
the latter unthinkable and nameless (for the route is not a true one) and
to leave the former to be and to be true. And how could what-is be in
the future? How could it ever come to be? If it came to be, it is not, and
likewise if it ever will be. Thus coming-to-be has been doused, and un-
heard-from perishing.
Nor is it divisible, since it is all alike. Nor is it here somewhat more,
which might prevent it from cohering, nor somewhat less, but all of it is
full of what-is. And all of it is cohesive, for what-is draws near to what-
is. But, immovable in the bounds of great bonds, it is beginningless and
endless, since coming-to-be and perishing have been banished far afield,
and it was True Trust who drove them off. Remaining the same and in
the same place, it lies by itself, and thus stays steadfast on the spot. For
mighty Necessity holds it in the bonds of a bound, which holds it in all
around, so that it is not right for what-is to be incomplete. For it is not
lacking; what-is-not would lack everything. The same thing is for think-
ing and is also that for the sake of which there is thought. For, without
what-is (towards which its expression is directed) you will not find think-
ing. For there neither is nor ever will be any other besides what-is, since
it was this which Doom bound to be whole and immovable. Wherefore
it has been named all things that mortals have established, persuaded
that they were true: “to come to be” and “to perish”; “to be” and “not
at all”; “change of place” and “exchange of bright color.”
But since there is an outermost bound, it is perfect, from every side
166 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 9
QAUTAO EELdt] Tavta Phos xal vdE dvduaotat
nal TA Kata opetéoas Suvdmets emi toiol te xal toic,
24. With Gallop, agreeing with Mourelatos’ (Route of Parmenides, p. 123n24) placement of
the comma after est? instead of pantothen.
25. See n. 17 for the accentuation of estin here and the adverbiality of the accompanying
word.
26. Here (rather than at the end of fragment 8) is where the breach between the treatment
of truth and the treatment of opinion begins.
27. Reading gnémais instead of gnémas with Gallop, following Furley.
28. In chapter | I offer an interpretation based on lines 57—58 in which no two forms can
be described as nonidentical without a kind of contradiction. If this is accepted, then
54 must mean that one form (initially unspecified) is not right because its presence
necessitates nonidentity statements. But this—for reasons perhaps not explicitly stated
in the line, but presupposed by its logic—will also mean that neither of a pair of
contrary nonidenticals can be right compared to the noncontrary what-is. Thus it is
not necessary to take ton mian in the sense of ton heterén in order to have it rule out
both forms. “One is not right.” “Which one?” “(Ultimately) either one.” The lack of
initial specificity in the language makes just the philosophical point that is at issue.
29. With Gallop, following Long (‘“Principles,” p. 102) in reading antia instead of the
emendation tantia.
30. Nothing prevents the ironic demotion of a plausibility-word when applied to the cos-
mos of mortals (see Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, p. 231). “Semblance” is intended
to reflect both sides of the irony.
31. Following the punctuation in Diels-Kranz and Taran: hés without accent and comma
after phatizd. But see Gallop on the line.
APPENDIX 167
like the mass of a well-rounded sphere, pushing out equally from the
middle everywhere. For it is not right for it to be any bigger or any
smaller, here or there. For neither is there what-is-not, which might pre-
vent it from attaining sameness, nor is it in any way possible for what-is
to be here more and there less than what-is, since all of it is inviolable.
For, equal from every side, it lies evenly within bounds.
With this I leave off my trustworthy discourse and thought about
Truth. From now on, learn the opinions of mortals, attending to the
deceptive ordering of my words.
They laid down two forms in their minds for naming, of which one is
not right (which is where they are gone astray). They distinguished op-
posites in bodily form and set up signs separate from each other—here
the bright flame of fire, gentle and very light, in every way the same with
itself and not the same with the other. And then, off by itself, contrari-
wise, thick night, a solid and weighty bodily form. All this, I declare to
you, is a world-order in semblance, so that no mortal judgment will ever
outstrip you.
FRAGMENT 9
But since everything has been called light and night, and they have been
assigned according to their properties to various things, everything is
168 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 10
FRAGMENT 11
FRAGMENT 12
FRAGMENT 13
MOWTLOTOV LEV "EEwta Pedov untioato avtov ..
FRAGMENT 14
VUKTLPAES TEQL yalav GAmpEevov GAAGTELOV MHC
32. If “neither has any share of nothingness” (Kirk and Raven), then nothing is without
both, since both are (supposedly) total. (Such an inference would at least go through
if the contraries in “Opinion” are trying to imitate the pervasiveness of “Truth.”)
33. The words about the Moon are from Gallop’s translation.
34. With Gallop, following Sider in reading panton instead of pantéi. Sider’s argument is
that the previous line is about things.
APPENDIX 169
full at once of light and of obscure night, full of both equally, since
neither has any share of nothingness.
FRAGMENT 10
You shall learn the nature of the ether, all the signs in the ethereal
region, and the unseen [or: annihilating] works of the spotless sun’s pure
torch, as well as what they came to be from, and you shall learn the
wandering works of the round-eyed moon and its nature;** you shall
know whence the encircling heaven came to be, and how Necessity, guid-
ing it, bound it to hold the limits of the stars.
FRAGMENT 11
How earth and sun and moon and the common ether and the Milky
Way and outermost Olympus and the hot force of the stars headed for-
ward to come to be.
FRAGMENT 12
The narrower [cosmic rings] are full of unmixed fire, the next ones of
night, and a portion of flame shoots out. In the middle of them is the
goddess who steers everything. For she directs mixing and hateful birth
for everything, dispatching the female to mix with the male, and then
again contrariwise, the male with the female.
FRAGMENT 13
She devised Love first of all the gods.
FRAGMENT 14
FRAGMENT 15
FRAGMENT 15 A
FRAGMENT 16
FRAGMENT 17
FRAGMENT 18
35. Reading hekastot’. . . krasis with Taran (Parmenides, p. 169) and others, in part because
(if I understand correctly) limbs which wander much also do so within the same in-
dividual at different times. Poluplankton is just adornment if an individual always has
the same hrasis. The relativistic remark in 1-2 is not justified (gar) unless 2-3 are also
initially relativistic, i.e., unless it is always the changing nature of the limbs which
thinks (with Raven and others). Absolutistic ambiguities can then work upon the final
words and throughout (Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 256-59).
36. This is the Diels-Kranz changed version of a manuscript reading. An interesting, more
speculative version adopted by Gallop is that of the Wenkebach-Pfaff edition of Galen’s
Commentary on Book Six of Hippocrates’ Epidemics, 11. 46.
37. Adopting (with Gallop) the text and translation of the Parmenides fragment from On
Chronic Diseases 1V.9, in the edition of Caelius Aurelianus, On Acute Diseases and On
Chronic Diseases, edited by Israel Drabkin (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1950).
APPENDIX 171
FRAGMENT 15
[the moon] always looking towards the sunshine.
FRAGMENT 15A
[the earth] rooted in water
FRAGMENT 16
FRAGMENT 17
FRAGMENT 18
When man and woman mingle the seeds of love that spring from their
veins, a formative power maintaining proper proportions molds well-
formed bodies from this diverse blood. For if, when the seed is mingled,
the forces contained therein clash and do not fuse into one, then cruelly
will they plague with double seed the sex of the offspring:
172 APPENDIX
FRAGMENT 19
CORNFORD’S FRAGMENT
‘
38. Reading ozon instead of hoion, but see Gallop’s textual note to Mourelatos, Route of
Parmenides, p. 185n47. Simplicius’ paraphrase monon, as Woodbury (p. 154) sees, plus
the fact that solitariness and immovability are, on the present account, connected in
the poem’s proofs, make it desirable to find both these signposts here in an “epitome
of the poem’s argument” (Mourelatos). This would also be desirable if being is its own
name.
I refrain from translating the fragment here in order to avoid a long discussion;
see alternative translations in Gallop. The fragment is not to be relied on in any case.
APPENDIX 173
FRAGMENT 19
This is how, according to opinion, these things came to be and now are
and will hereafter come to an end when they have matured. For each
men set up a name asasign.
wisemi tic
nok hed eying onande ee
a au 1 ht eat ee
ae
re ~T pe
i
NOTES
INTRODUCTION
. Jack Kerouac, The Scripture of the Golden Eternity (New York: Totem/Corinth, 1970),
SEC200, Daur
_ For the evidence on Parmenides’ life, see Hermann Diels, ed., Die Fragmente der Vor-
sokratiker, 11th ed. (5th and subsequent editions revised by Walter Kranz) (Berlin:
Weidmann, 1964), vol. I, pp. 138—46. (Hereafter cited as Diels-Kranz.)
. For a statement of the case against an uncritical acceptance of the Platonic tradition,
see Friedrich Solmsen, “The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-examined,” in
Alexander P. D. Mourelatos, ed., The Pre-Socratics: A Collection of Critical Essays (Garden
City: Doubleday, 1974), pp. 368-93.
. For a contemporary rehabilitation of Melissus, see Jonathan Barnes, The Presocratic
Philosophers, 2 vols. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979), vol. I, pp. 155-230.
. See ibid.; and Alexander P. D. Mourelatos, The Route of Parmenides (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1970), pp. 130-33.
. See Diels-Kranz, vol. I, pp. 147-65.
. See Theogony 746-57, M. West, ed. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1966), p. 139. Here I think
that David Furley, “Notes on Parmenides” (in E. N. Lee, A. P. D. Mourelatos, and
’ R. Rorty, eds., Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory
Viastos [Phronesis Suppl. Vol. I] [Assen: Van Gorcum, 1973], pp. 1-15), has made it
clear that the ultimate destination of the journey is one in which both the cosmic
opposites have been transcended. The comma is in line 10, after eis phaos, “into the
light,” not in line 9, so that the maidens who come to conduct the young man them-
selves come into the light and do not necessarily come to conduct him into the light.
But the fact that this opens up the possibility of an infernal destination for all parties
does not mean that the house which is thereby reached is the house of darkness alone.
Indeed, a katabasis (descent) to the edge of the world could just as well be spoken of
as an ascent, given the nature of houses occupied equally by day and night, ie.,
transcendent houses.
. The young man’s situation vis-a-vis the goddess is, among other things, the epic situ-
ation of one obtaining directions or hearkening to advice, as Mourelatos has convinc-
ingly shown. In my opinion the comparison with Odysseus and ‘Telemachus does not
depend on the actual topography of fragment 1 (which contains manifestly un-Ho-
meric elements) so much as on the speech situation in this and succeeding fragments.
. For the various meanings assigned since antiquity to Parmenides’ prologue, see Leo-
nardo Taran, Parmenides (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965), pp. 17-31, and
Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 1-46. See also Furley, “Notes on Parmenides”;
Jaap Mansfeld, Die Offenbarung des Parmenides und die Menschliche Welt (Assen: Van
Gorcum, 1964); and Walter Burkert, “Das Proébmium des Parmenides und die Kata-
basis des Pythagoras,” Phronesis 14 (1969): 1-30.
. I do not intend to take a stand here on whether “how” or “that” is the correct trans-
lation. (See Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 47—73; and David Gallop, ed., Par-
175
176 NOTES
menides of Elea: Fragments [Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1984], p. 55.) Any
translation that allows the general declarations of fragment 2 to be expanded into the
actual predications of fragment 8 is sufficient for'my purposes. I especially regret that
time constraints did not permit me to work with Gallop’s book except in the Appendix.
11. For the interpretations of the two routes, see Taran, Parmenides, pp. 32—40; Mourelatos,
Route of Parmenides, pp. 47—73, 269-76; Barnes, Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1, pp. 157—
65. I am committed in chapter | to the existence of three kinds of discourse in the
poem, and I offer evidence for the claim that the route of mortals is not simply the
negative route but in some sense a mixture of positive and negative. The question of
how many routes there are does not depend upon issues in B6.1—3 alone. The partisans
of two or three routes should want only that mortal discourse be neither about pure
being nor about pure nonbeing, regardless of how one actually numbers the routes
or pins them down. Since it is evident that their discourse is not about pure being, but
also that they do make positive existence-assertions and assert positive facts in “Opin-
ion,” what they say has an intermediate status and as such cannot (to give Parmenides
credit) have been disallowed on the grounds that it was totally negative. What they say
is not supposed to be about nonbeing. If it is then claimed that their discourse is
somehow implicitly on the negative route in such a way that there are still only two
routes, the reply will be that this claim is not now essentially different from the one
the partisans of three routes are making—they call the third route a mixture of the
first two anyway, admitting that it has (at least partly) negative content. But then the
question about the number of routes becomes a question more of enumeration than
of philosophical message. See also n. 15 to chapter 1.
12. De Veritate, question 21. Truth (De Veritate) (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1954), pp. 3-32.
13. See Empedocles, fragment 12, and Anaxagoras, fragment 17, in Diels-Kranz.
14. For the doxography, see Taran, Parmenides, pp. 202-30, and Mourelatos, Route of Par-
menides, pp. 194-221.
15. See Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 222-63.
16. For recent doxography, consult the bibliography, also the treatments of general and
particular issues in Taran, Parmenides, Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, and Barnes,
Presocratic Philosophers.
Francis M. Conford, Plato and Parmenides (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1939).
Furth’s phrase.
178 NOTES
and the word homoion, “alike,” in the preceding line should be taken as adverbial.
Owen’s case about homoion depends on the argument that an adjective here would be
unsupported argumentatively in the preceding lines, while an adverb could be taken
as a natural outgrowth of them (“Eleatic Questions,” p. 58). I argue against Owen’s
interpretation of lines 22—25 in chapter 3. The adverbiality of mallon does not mean
that the negation (oude) has to be taken with the copula if sentence-negations are
thought to bear on the sentence as a whole (see my discussion later in this chapter).
Also, mallon could be governing degree of existence here only through implicit inter-
mediary adjectives, like “weighty” or “full.”
. David Gallop, “ ‘Is’ or ‘Is not’?” The Monist 62 (1979): 61-80, p. 65.
. | am indebted to G. E. R. Lloyd and Martha Nussbaum for this objection.
. Moorhouse, Studies in the Greek Negatives, p. 138.
. Ibid., p. 148.
» Ibid., p. 75:
sibideip le
. Ibid., p. 75.
. Ibid.
. Thus I am inasense arguing on the basis of verse fluidity and not trying to undercut
it.
. Moorhouse, Studies in the Greek Negatives, pp. 14-15.
. In this account of incomplete predicates I am agreeing with the consensus defined by
the following: Svend Ranulf, Der eleatische Satz vom Widerspruch (Copenhagen: Gyl-
dendalske Boghandel, 1924); A. Szabé, “Beitrage zur Geschichte der griechischen Di-
alektik,” Acta Antiqua Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae 1 (1951-52): 377-406, “Zur
Geschichte der Dialektik des Denkens,” Act. Ant. 2 (1953-54): 17-57, “Zum Verstand-
nis der Eleaten,” Act. Ant. 2 (1953-54): 243-86, “Eleatica,” Act. Ant. 3 (1955): 67-102;
G. E. L. Owen, “A Proof in the PERI IDEON,” in R. E.Allen, ed., Studies in Plato’s Meta-
physics (New York: Humanities Press, 1965), pp. 293-312; G. E. R. Lloyd, Polarity and
Analogy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966); Alexander Nehamas, “Pre-
dication and Forms of Opposites in the Phaedo,” Review of Metaphysics 26 (1973): 461—
91, “Confusing Universals and Particulars in Plato’s Early Dialogues,” Review of Meta-
physics 29 (1975): 287-306, “Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World,” American
Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1975): 105-17, “Self-Predication and Plato’s Theory of
Forms,” Am. Phil. Quart. 16 (1979): 93-103, “Participation and Predication in Plato’s
Later Thought,” Rev Met. 36 (1980): 343-74; Paul B. Woodruff, “The Socratic Ap-
proach to Semantic Incompleteness,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38
(1978): 453-68; Robert William Jordan, Plato’s Arguments
for Forms (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge Philological Society, 1983), and his “Plato, the Presocratics, and the Law of
Contradiction” (unpublished). Barnes, Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1, pp. 169-70, con-
siders a reading of fragment 6 in which the same principle is at work; he rejects it on
the grounds that “the reasoning it ascribes to Parmenides will stand no weight”
(p. 170). In what follows and in chapter 5, I propose that the reasoning, even if it does
not clearly distinguish between contextual relativity and contradiction, could never-
theless have been part of a serious and deep theory of the parts of sentences in their
relation to truth. There are internal differences within the consensus defined by the
above authors, but I wish to agree with a common result about the nature and im-
portance of Eleatic contradiction.
30. See Charles H. Kahn, “The Thesis of Parmenides,” Review of Metaphysics 22 (1968/69):
700-24.
Sit I argue in chapter 5 that Heraclitus thought we had to drop the qualifiers (as in rule
4) in order to discover the tension in reality. Thus both he and Parmenides have the
180 NOTES
older version of the law of noncontradiction, though one thinks reality breaks the law
and the other does not. I argue that Protagoras sees that sensible relativity can be
thought of as conforming to a different version of the law.
o2: It is clear that to eon (being) is in fact the grammatical subject of the deductions in
fragment 8; I argue above that there is only one such subject. Owen starts out differ-
ently, by deriving the deductions from a general identification of the subject as the
object of discourse or of thought. This initially undetermined approach to the Par-
menidean subject, intended to cut off an earlier tendency to overdetermine the subject
by identifying it with previous cosmologists™ ideas, was intended as a philosophical
razor. It was supposed to make the proofs into arguments for what was not initially
obvious, rather than empty explorations of tautologies or christenings of earlier Na-
turphilosophie, and in these things it succeeded. But—granting Owen his conclusion
that Parmenides felt he needed to argue that being was the subject—it follows that
“what can be talked and thought about” is just being, as Owen says on p. 55: “No one
will deny that, as the argument goes, to gon is a correct description of the subject. The
point is that Parmenides purports to prove that it is a correct description.” The fact
that the conclusion needs proof is, from my point of view, less important.
Bor The process of doing away with discursive plurality begins already in “Truth,” where
being is the single object of all language (38-41) and in the fact that the signposts are
all expressions of the same point and do not have different “meanings” (see chapter 3).
Also, by “canonical discourse,” I mean, e.g., oude diaireton estin (22) or tetelesmenon esti
(42) or even the statement made with Moira (37-38) or with a metaphor of quenching
(21)—that is, whatever directly attributes a predicate to being, implies a direct pre-
dication, or negates one outside the brackets, but I do not mean, e.g., talk of fetters
and chains themselves in isolation from their connection with predication. In chapter 2
I isolate some of this language (the part which contains, among other things, actual
grammatical predicates) for further study. This criterion includes some metaphors
and modalities (in a loose sense of the term) in the canonical language; but here the
language of “Opinion” is used against itself in order to get across a true predicate,
and so the words belong neither to “Opinion” nor to the “other language,” which as
such talks about chariots and gates and does not make a truth-claim about being. Still,
it is difficult, even within fragment 8, to tell which words talk and which tell you how
to talk. My criterion for fragment 8 includes almost everything except the obvious
digressions (15-18, much of 34-41). I claim to have shown that none of the canonical
language in this fragment breaks the rules as I interpret them.
34. This is all taken later in support of the hypothesis that Parmenides was essentially a
rational mystic in the Platonic sense. I have failed to recover the source for the Will
Rogers quotation.
2 For the law of noncontradiction see B7.1; for the law of excluded middle, with an
explicitly legal, juridical metaphor, see B8.15—18. Though I claim in chapters 1 and
5 that the laws are not used in the modern (Platonic or Aristotelian) sense, it is hard
to deny the legalistic function and language of these lines.
. Liddell-Scott-Jones list “decision,” “judgment,” and “trial” under krisis. See also n. 2,
above.
31. Diels, Lehrgedicht, p. 81. “Es scheint selbstverstandlich, da was den Zusammenhang
unterbricht, nicht das potenzirte (mallon eon), sondern nur das verminderte Sein dar-
stellen konne.”
32. Ibid., pp. 81-82. *
33. See the entry in Liddell-Scott-Jones.
34. Diels, Lehrgedicht, p. 81. .
35. Ibid.
36. Owen, “Eleatic Questions,” p. 75 n. 62.
37. Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, pp. 242- 43.~
38. I thank E. D. Francis for his help with the non-Parmenidean Greek evidence.
39. Mourelatos, (Route of Parmenides, pp. 132-33), claiming that words for plurality as such
are never given a negative sense in Parmenides, suggests that a reified dualism of
contraries, rather than plurality, is the Parmenidean antagonist. But the situation in
lines 6—15 surely involves a plurality—the points of time—which is rejected, while the
metaphorical situation in 42—49 involves a plurality which is included; and, if my
interpretation of lines 22—25 is correct, it is precisely a one-many contrast, with non-
identity and contrariety on either side, which is ruled out. On the surface level of
metaphor, at least, it all depends on which kind of plurality one means, though ulti-
mately, I would claim, no plurality is allowed at all.
offspring of a generation from nothing, and so ruling out such a generation for what-
is. More, then, would be needed in order to discard (ii). Stough attempts to reconstruct
fragment 8 on the basis of (ii), and in the process gives the reading some credibility.
However, in the desire to argue against (i) and the emendation and to show that (ii)
suffices, Stough is led to claim that Parmenides does not discuss the generation of
anything from something existing. Nevertheless, as I try to show, lines 36-38 do dis-
cuss the motion out, from what-is, of something existing but other than what-is, though
Stough is right in pointing out that the discussion of genesis as such is restricted to that
of a coming-to-be from what-is-not. (Stough takes the lines to discuss a different sit-
uation, namely, the generation from what-is-not of something existing but other than
what-is.) And yet, if there is a motion out from what-is in lines 36—38, then it is possible
that lines 12—13 discuss the possibility that Stough finds in 36—38. In fact, as I argue
below, this possibility must be found in 12-13, otherwise the poem’s argument will
not be complete. This is my argument against (ii), to which Stough would reply that
the assertion I find in 12—13 would seem to have to do more with proving the unique-
ness of what-is than with arguing against generation. To this I would reply that the
generation from what-is-not of something existing but other than what-is, is indeed a
kind of coming-to-be. Thus Stough’s argument is, I think, undercut by 36-38, and
this means that 12—13 cannot have the meaning described in (ii). (Unless, of course,
~ one takes # more broadly than Stough does to include both what-is and something
existing but other than what-is. In that case the emendation, which Stough also argues
against, would again be destructive.)
Barnes is, however, also too quick in rejecting (i), the coming-into-being of something
besides what-is out of what-is-not. He says: “(i) is impotent as an argument against
generation and cannot constitute an argument against destruction.” I shall agree below
that lines 12-13 do not furnish an argument against destruction, while claiming that
this does not count against the reading (i). However, it is not immediately clear why
Barnes says that (i) is impotent as an argument against generation. It certainly states,
at any rate, that nothing besides being can come from nothing, and thus that a certain
sort of generation is impossible. Does Barnes mean that the generation in question
would, if (i) is adopted, be a generation, not of being, but of something else? This
would be no reason for rejecting (i), even if it were immediately clear that this “some-
thing else” would have to be nothing. Does Barnes then mean that (i) does not argue
its point but merely states it? This is surely no objection to a reading of a Parmenidean
line. I argued in chapter 3 that there is no linear proof for homoion in 22, and where
is the proof of asulon in 48?
At any rate, of the interpretations available of the manuscript reading, it seems that
(i) has the best chance of making sense.
. Stokes, One and Many, p. 254.
. Taran, Parmenides, pp. 95-96.
. Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, p. 101.
. I
SID
OP do not take a stand on the relation of being to time here (but see chapter 6). A full
or complete being on the part of what-is, a freedom from temporal variations, starts,
or stops, would seem to mean that it is eternal, or sempiternal, or exists atemporally.
Critics have attempted to choose among these: see William Kneale, “Time and Eternity
in Theology,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society n.s. 61 (1960-61): 90; G. E. L. Owen,
“Plato and Parmenides on the Timeless Present,” The Monist 50 (1966): 317-40, re-
printed in Mourelatos, ed., The Pre-Socratics, 271-92; Malcolm Schofield, “Did Parmen-
ides Discover Eternity?” Archiv fiir Geschichte der Philosophie 52 (1970): 113-35;
Manchester, “Parmenides and the Need for Eternity,’ Leonardo Taran, “Perpetual
Present and Atemporal Eternity in Parmenides and Plato,” The Monist 62 (1979): 43—
184 NOTES
wider sense than before. For the mutual relationships of modal and assertoric language
in the narrower sense, see chapter 1.
Silk See also G. Jameson, “ “Well-rounded Truth’ and Circular Thought in Parmenides,”
Phronesis 3 (1958): 15-30.
logical dignity. But it goes too far to say that opposites do not apply to Forms even in
the later period: Allen’s reference (in Studies, p. 90), to motion and rest in the Sophist
surely does not apply to the different case of the same and not the same in Sophist
256A; and Parmenides 158A-B, with its distinction between things which have a share
in something and the something in which they share, cannot be cited as a positive
expression of Platonic doctrine if the dialogue is, as Allen claims, aporetic (p. 189).
These two dialogues pose a problem in understanding how the Forms can be qualified
by opposites; but the former at any rate tries to demonstrate that they are so qualified.
This is not to say anything against Allen’s insight about the middle dialogues, however.
. For a good account of Plato’s basic Eleaticism, see the four articles by Szabé listed in
the Bibliography.
19) See Sophist 256A—260B.
20. See R. Hackforth, “False Statement in Plato’s Sophist,” Classical Quarterly 39 (1945): 56—
58; David Ross, Plato’s Theory of Ideas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951); A. L. Peck,
“Plato and the MEGISTA GENE of the Sophist: A Reinterpretation,” Classical Quarterly n.s.
2 (1952): 32-56, “Plato’s Sophist: The Symploké ton ecdéin,” Phronesis 7 (1962): 46-66;
D. W. Hamlyn, “The Communion of Forms and the Development of Plato’s Logic,”
Philosophical Quarterly 5 (1955): 289-302; R. S. Bluck, “False Statement in the Sophist,”
Journal of Hellenic Studies 77 (1957): 181-86; I. M. Crombie, An Examination of Plato’s
Doctrines (2 vols.) (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962), vol. II; W. K. C. Guthrie,
History of Greek Philosophy; J. M. E. Moravcsik, “SUMPLOKE EIDON and the Genesis of
Locos,” Archiv fiir Geschichte der Philosophie 60 (1978): 121-39, “Being and Meaning
in.the Sophist,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 14 (1962): 23—78; J. Stenzel, Plato's Method of
Dialectic (tr. and ed. D. J. Allan) (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964); J. Ackrill, “sum-
PLOKE EIDON,” in Allen, ed., Plato’s Metaphysics, pp. 199-206, “Plato and the Copula:
Sophist 251-259,” in ibid., pp. 207-218; Michael Frede, Pradzkation und Existenzaussage,
Hypomnemata, vol. 18 (Géttingen: Vandenhoeck u. Ruprecht, 1967); R. Robinson,
“Plato’s Consciousness of Fallacy,” in his Essays in Greek Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1969); G. E. L. Owen, “Plato on Not-Being,” in Gregory Vlastos, ed.,
Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press,
1971), vol. I, pp. 223-67; J. Pelletier, “ ‘Incompatibility’ in Plato’s Sophist,” Dialogue
(Canada) 14 (1975): 143-46; RichardJ. Ketcham, “Participation and Predication in
Sophist 251-260,” Phronesis 23 (1978): 42-62; Robert Flower, “G. E. L. Owen, Plato,
and the Verb “To Be,” Apezron 14 (1980): 87-95; Spiro Panagiotou, “The Parmenides
and the ‘Communion of Kinds’ in the Sophist,” Hermes 109 (1981): 167-71;
J. McDowell, “Falsehood and Not-Being in Plato’s Sophist,” in M. Schofield and
M. Nussbaum, eds., Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Philosophy Presented to G. E. L.
Owen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 115-34; works cited in the
Bibliography by Robert William Jordan; and W. G. Runciman, Plato’s Later Epistemology
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962).
But I think that the part of the story that I need can be told without controversy.
21. Translated by F. M. Cornford.
. I give short summaries of interpretations below so that their similarities with and
differences from what I hypothesize in the chapter can be seen. Any interpretation in
which the dialogue’s compresence of opposites is serious discourse about definable
Forms, yet is not allowed to be read as a logical contradiction, is one in which an
apparatus of disambiguation or resolution can play a role. In this sense I am in debt
most to Peck, also to Cornford, Brumbaugh, and Owen.
Harald H6ffding, Bemerkungen tiber den platonischen Dialog Parmenides (Berlin: Bib-
liothek fiir Philosophie 21, 1921). The demonstration is a parody which shows that
Zenonian methods applied to the One yield un-Parmenidean results.
188 NOTES
Harold Cherniss, “Parmenides and the Parmenides of Plato,’ American Journal of Phi-
lology 53 (1932): 122-38. The second half is a “systemic abuse of e:nai” which switches
from one sense to another; the Sophist does not disambiguate.
Francis M. Cornford, Plato and Parmenides (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1939).
The hypotheses are not fallacious but proceed each from a different premise or def-
inition; the differences can be detected; the One is sinbigaous as between hypotheses,
but consistent within each hypothesis.
Richard Robinson, “Plato’s Parmenides,” Classical Philology 37 (1942): 51-76, 159-
86. The dialogue is a gymnastic exercise containing fallacies and ambiguities to be
detected even within each hypothesis. It is not.a statement of doctrine, but is “sceptical.”
Critique of the claim that the Sophist is a solution to the problems posed by the Par-
menides.
W. D. Ross, Plato’s Theory of Ideas, pp. 83-103. The dialogue is a logical exercise in
the detection of fallacies and ambiguities, but one containing real, philosophically
fruitful problems and ideas.
A. L. Peck, “Plato’s Parmenides: Some Suggestions for Its Interpretation,” Classical
Quarterly n.s. 3 (1953): 126-50. The second half exhibits the consequences of sup-
posing either no participation or universal participation; the Sophist unlocks the Par-
menides; the One is contextually variable and so not a Form.
Robert S. Brumbaugh, Plato and the One (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1961).
The second half is a serious (though indirect) exposition of what a theory of Forms
has to be and to explain. The inferences are valid, but some “odd concepts” are
introduced. Interesting treatment of previous views.
W. K. C. Guthrie, History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. V, pp. 53 ff. “Readers are intended
to detect the fallacies, but as a training in how to avoid them” (p. 56).
W. G. Runciman, “Plato’s Parmenides,” pp. 149-84. Criticisms of Ross, Robinson,
Ryle, Cornford. The ambiguities are not clear to Plato; the moral “is that forms are
not definable by deduction from existential hypotheses” (p. 181). The method of the
Parmenides leads to contradictory conclusions and must be replaced by the method of
division.
Gilbert Ryle, Plato’s Progress (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966). Hy-
potheses exhibit consequences of failure to observe type-distinctions.
G. E. L. Owen, “Notes on Ryle’s Plato,” in Oscar P. Wood and George Pitcher, eds.,
Ryle: A Collection of Critical Essays (Garden City: Doubleday, 1970), pp. 341-72. A subtle
treatment. Ambiguities in the Parmenides are disambiguated in the Sophist.
Malcolm Schofield, “The Antinomies of Plato’s Parmenides,” Classical Quarterly n.s. 27
(1977): 139-58. Nice sketches of the universe of discourse in each hypothesis.
R. E. Allen, Parmenides. The dialogue is aporetic; each hypothesis proceeds from
assumptions which must be corrected. The purpose of the second half is to show that
the transcendentals are not definable essences. Allen leaves it to the reader what cor-
rections must be made.
Kenneth M. Sayre, Plato’s Late Ontology (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983).
. See Robinson, “Plato’s Parmenides.”
. Sophist 259C-D.
. Philebus 15D-18D.
. See Metaphysics, book Z, chapters 6, 8, 13-15.
. See Allen, “Participation and Predication,” p. 46n.
. See the “Lehre” section on Thales in Diels-Kranz.
- See “Leben und Lehre” and the two passages quoted in the “Fragmente” section in
ibid.
. See ibid. for the testimonia.
NOTES 189
31. Translated by Jonathan Barnes. See Barnes, Presocratic Philosophers, pp. 69-75, for a
full discussion of dropped qualifications in Heraclitus. See also the treatment of the
metaphysical significance of the compresence of opposites in Kirk, Raven, and Scho-
field, Presocratic Philosophers, pp. 188-97.
S2. See C. J. Emlyn-Jones, “Heraclitus and the Identity of Opposites,” Phronesis 21 (1976):
89-114, but agreeing with Lloyd (Polarity and Analogy, pp. 100-02) that Heraclitus
does not give us a “certain violation” of the modern version of the law. I suggest,
however, that the appearance of contradiction is due not so much to an obscurity of
expression as to the fact that respects are being deliberately dropped. See also Barnes,
Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1, pp. 73—75, and later in my treatment.
30: M. M. Mackenzie, in a thought-provoking paper called “Heraclitus and the Art of
Paradox” (forthcoming), demonstrates that some Heraclitean paradoxes can be re-
solved by adding the appropriate qualifiers and then examines the resulting dialectic
between the sense in which opposites are one and the sense in which they are distinct,
the former (“the unity of opposites”) without qualifiers and the latter (“the opposition
of unity”) with. She remarks that the unity in a sense requires the distinctness, and
vice versa, and that this is, in one sense, precisely the point; yet the underlying par-
adoxical tension between these two principles (as opposed to the things they govern)
remains unresolved. This Heraclitus is one who understands the later version of the
law of noncontradiction and uses it to resolve contradictions in an “object language”
(involving terms like night, day, asleep, awake) while leaving higher-order “common”
terms (e.g., one, many) paradoxical in their mutual interrelationships in a way fruitful
for the metaphysics of individuation. (Here I use “contradiction” interchangeably with
her “paradox,” though the latter is, I think, broader.)
If this view is correct, then it is in fact part of Heraclitus’s strategy to employ the
later law of noncontradiction in dissolving at least certain paradoxes. I argue that the
thrust of Heraclitus requires that the later law not be used, that, in Mackenzie’s terms,
the paradoxes remain fruitfully unresolved even at the lower level where she says they
are resolved. My claim is that, as Mackenzie says, Heraclitus is interested neither
exclusively in a world governed totally by distinctions of respect nor in a world of pure,
undifferentiated unity undivided by such distinctions. But the natural expression for
such a vision of the world would not be even an initial disambiguation of apparent
contradictions into relativities of respect, but rather a formula evoking tension without
settling it (“God is day night”) or stating relativity in such a way as to suggest conflict
or contradiction. I do not deny that the statements in the object-language can be taken
as calling for disambiguation; I only say that even the apparently disambiguating
statements (“For fish good, for humans bad”) could also be taken as presenting us with
contradictions which their author believes are fruitfully irresolvable. Heraclitus might
not have believed that the modern law represented an ultimate truth about the world,
and his paradoxes, it might be claimed, testify to an irresolvable war, a provocative
strife of opposites on the object-language as well. More evidence would be required
in order to show that the essential conflicts are only on the metalevel; indeed, the
relationship between object-language and common language Mackenzie attributes to
Heraclitus would be more appropriate for the Parmenides of this study: consistency
within the former, then inconsistency in the portrait of goddess, chariot, etc.
34. See Barnes, Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1, pp. 176-78.
357 For the motion of one object, see the dichotomy paradox; for the relative motion of
two, see Achilles and the stadium; for finite and infinite divisibility, see fragments 1
and 3; for motion in the place where something is vs. where it is not, the arrow paradox;
but see ibid., p. 276, against regarding this as an explicit dilemma in Zeno.
36. Barnes (ibid., pp. 233-34) argues that the architectonic view of Tannery, Owen, and
190 NOTES
others should be abandoned in favor of a view of Zeno in which each argument makes
its Own separate point against plurality or motion. But the two views are compatible;
surely it is not the case that no argument.can be connected with any other by way of
disjunction. An Eleatic-style, rigid dichotomy between finite and infinite divisibility
would also have been viewed as connecting the two in a single proof.
37. Furth, “Elements of Eleatic Ontology.”
38. It seems clear from 136A—C that any of the Forms can be said to exist, or not to exist,
or to have any other character: kai hotioun allo pathos paschontos. This means that any
two of the Forms can combine to produce a pair of hypotheses equivalent in complexity
to the second half of the Parmenides as we have it, and this means in turn that that
half is only a portion of a much larger method. On the structure of the hypotheses,
see Schofield, Brumbaugh, and Sayre (n. 22 above) and also a Boston University dis-
sertation by John Strang, “The Parmenides and Its Inheritors” (1983).
:
wi }
we t Steet}
itv ow
imine ie are Wy
ew, pete ake PONG bos uit
g% yoasty WiS, Oe ( Ts oe Tey tahini
te! wre @ » Bi any if=: it ae BM he. oa
hed "ee ar ie mat © mas 1% oy aS Fina
A Mp
+ ell ii Bry:ada:al “Reywh”ac
sty ulti’ Taina ky; el Riis ae
en:
i a Lin
uty) repr
a ME J ‘ city a0
GET AE Hi vypage eta My(iL a ke “oe : :
® é 7
ris Ly eraby), ; » 700 S os a er Udi if me
y iipoh
‘ ae > i i sige Fl Pa a v"
Pariah) Mocagt ie i,
Net Mas "olyhlre meant1! ¢diesen OE ae
del
, Ie sf igh: gh st a — *. P
“¢ =o)
iL 4
e er 4
11 oo eee O
Bibliography
Ackrill, J. “Plato and the Copula: Sophist 251-259.” In Allen, ed., Studies in Plato’s
Metaphysics, pp. 207-18.
. “SUMPLOKE EIDON.” in Allen, ed., Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, pp. 199-
206.
Allen, R. E. “Participation and Predication in Plato’s Middle Dialogues.” In his
Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, pp. 43-60.
. “The Argument from Opposites in Republic V.” In John P. Anton and
George L. Kustas, eds., Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1971.
. Plato’s ‘Parmenides’: Translation and Analysis. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983.
, ed. Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics. New York: Humanities Press, 1965.
Allen, R. E., and D. J. Furley, eds. Studies in Presocratic Philosophy (2 vols.). Lon-
don: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1975.
Aquinas, St. Thomas. Truth (De Veritate). Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1954.
Austin, Scott. “Genesis and Motion in Parmenides: B8.12—13.” Harvard Studies
in Classical Philology 87 (1983): 151-68.
. “Parmenides and Ultimate Reality.” Ultimate Reality and Meaning 7 (1984):
220-32.
Barnes, Jonathan. “Parmenides and the Eleatic One.” Archw ftir Geschichte der
Philosophie 61 (1979): 1-21.
. The Presocratic Philosophers. (2 vols.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1979.
Barrett, W. S., ed. Euripides: ‘Hippolytus’ Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1964.
Blofeld, John, tr. The Zen Teaching of Huang Po. London: Rider, 1958.
Bluck, R. S. “False Statement in the Sophist.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77 (1957):
181-86.
Brentlinger, John A. “Incomplete Predicates and the Two-World Theory of the
Phaedo.” Phronesis 17 (1972): 61-79.
193
194 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Shiner, Roger A., and John King-Farlow, eds. New Essays on Plato and the Pre-
Socratics (Canadian Journal of Philosophy Suppl. Vol. II). Guelph, Ontario: Ca-
nadian Association for Publishing in Philosophy, 1976.
Sider, D. “Confirmation of Two ‘Conjectures’ in the Presocratics: Parmenides
B12 and Anaxagoras B15.” Phoenix 33 (1979): 67-69.
Solmsen, Friedrich. “The ‘Eleatic One’ in Melissus.” Mededelingen der koninklijke
Akademie van Wetenschappen n.s. 32, 8 (1969): 221-33.
. “The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-Examined.” In A. P. D. Moure-
latos, ed., The Pre-Socratics: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City: Dou-
bleday, 1974, pp. 368-93.
Sprague, Rosamond K. Plato’s Use of Fallacy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1962.
Stenzel, Julius. Plato’s Method of Dialectic (tr. and ed. D. J. Allan). New York:
Russell & Russell, 1964.
Stokes, Michael C. One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1971.
Stough, Charlotte. “Parmenides’ Way of Truth: B8.12—13.” Phronesis 13 (1968):
91-107.
. “Forms and Explanation in the Phaedo.” Phronesis 21 (1976): 1-30.
Suzuki, Daisetz T. Shin Buddhism. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1970.
Szabé, A. “Beitrage zur Geschichte der griechischen Dialektik.” Acta Antiqua Aca-
demiae Scientiarum Hungariae | (1951-52): 377-406.
. “Zur Geschichte der Dialektik des Denkens.” Acta Antiqua Academiae Scien-
tiarum Hungaricae 2 (1953-54): 17-57.
. ‘Zum Verstandnis der Eleaten.” Acta Antiqua Academiae Scientiarum Hun-
gariae 2 (1953-54): 243-86.
. “Eleatica.” Acta Antiqua Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae 3 (1955): 67—
102.
Taran, Leonardo. Parmenides. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965.
. Review of Mourelatos, Route of Parmenides, in Gnomon 48 (1977): 651-66.
. “Perpetual Present and Atemporal Eternity in Parmenides and Plato.”
The Monist 62 (1979): 43-53.
Tarrant, H. A. S. “Parmenides B1.3: Text, Context, and Interpretation.” Antich-
thon 10 (1976): 1-7.
Untersteiner, Mario. Parmenide: Testimonianze e frammenti. Florence: La nuova Ita-
lia, 1958.
Vlastos, Gregory. “Degrees of Reality in Plato.” In Gregory Vlastos, Platonic
Studies (2nd ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981, pp. 58-75.
Wenkebach, Ernst, and Franz Pfaff. Galeni in Hippocratis Epidemiarum Librum VI
Commentaria I-VIII. Berolini in Aedibus Academiae Litterarum MCMLVI.
White, F. C. “Plato’s Middle Dialogues and the Independence of Particulars.”
Philosophical Quarterly 27 (1977): 193-213.
Woodbury, Leonard. “Parmenides on Names.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philol-
ogy 63 (1958): 145-60.
Woodruff, Paul B. “The Socratic Approach to Semantic Incompleteness.” Phi-
losophy and Phenomenological Research 38 (1978): 453-68.
Index
Allen, Reginald E., 129 Canonical discourse: “is” and “isn’t” in, 29—
Alpha-privatives. See Predicates, alpha-pri- 31, 38-39, 47, 137-39; truth and falsity
vative in, 32, 33—37, 137-39; and noncontradic-
Ammonius, 70, 71 tion, 36-39, 137-39; criteria of, 37—38;
Anaxagoras, 5, 117, 118 and self-referential inconsistency, 40—42,
Anaximander, 130-31 139; and vagueness, 138
Apollo (Nietzsche), 145-47, 150-51 Chariot, 3, 29, 40, 41
Aquinas, Thomas, 5 Christianity, 8, 142—44, 146—47, 151-53
Aristophanes, 31 Collations: and contraries, 89, 91-92
Aristotle, 2, 6, 8, 14, 31, 33, 38, 61, 121, Coming-to-be, 45, 47, 50-51, 57; of other,
126, 128-149 96, 100—03; and Karsten emendation,
Assertions: assertoric “ouk esti” barred in, 100—05; six forms of, 104; and modality,
12-13, 22-29, 30, 36-37, 118, 138; ex- 112
istential reduction of, 18—20; modal, 23, Contradiction, logical: and canonical dis-
D527. 29. OW Silo Sence alsomelsi- course, 20, 32—36, 37, 38; and contextual
Saloni relativity, 33-34, 36, 37, 119-20, 123,
negative, 18, 21, 22, 29, 31,.30, 415-1 2: 127; and dropped qualifiers, 34, 36, 37,
intentional use of, 18—20; and bounded- 116, 118, 119; and truth, 39-40; and
ness, 138 contraries, 50—51; in immanent world,
—negative existential: barred from 119-21; post-Parmenidean, 125, 127; in
“Truths le 13 1922-30) 3375. LS: pre-Socratic thought, 130-32, 134; and
138 boundedness, 137—40; and predication,
—positive, 12, 18-20, 23-30, 38, 47, 112 138
Contraries, 8, 46, 47, 56-58, 65—95 passim,
Barnes, Jonathan, 13, 18-20, 21, 716, 155= 110, 111, 153; “more” and “less,” 46, 49—
57 50, 68, 75, 76-83, 88, 90; and contradic-
Being. See What-is tion, 50—51; in Time-section, 53, 56, 86—
Blake, William, 65 87, 88, 90-91, 93; in Mass-Space section,
Boundedness, 5, 6, 17, 84, 106, 136-39, 54, 56-57, 68-83, 88, 90-91, 93; in
142, 149-50, 153; and “is,” 137-39; and Sphere-section, 55, 57, 84-86, 88, 89-90,
contradiction, 137—40; and canonical dis- 93; “later” and “earlier,” 57, 86—87, 90;
course, 138—40; and truth, 139; and neg- in “Opinion,” 66, 109-10; disjunctive/
ative theology, 139-43, 144, 147; con- conjunctive formulas of, 67, 85-87; “big-
junction of, with unboundedness, 142— ger” and “smaller,” 76, 85-86, 88, 90;
44, 150-52 nested, 89; contexts of, 90, 93; philosoph-
Buddhism, 8, 142—44, 147, 150, 151, 152 ical rationale for, 92—95; and the other,
Burnet, John, 70, 97 109-10; and plurality, 113, 133; and
dropped qualifiers, 116, 118-19
Calogero, Guido, 14, 36 Copula, 14, 29, 37—40. See also “Is”
199
200 INDEX
Cornford, Francis M., 14, 155 Immovability: and the other, 101—03; qual-
itative and locomotive, 102, 106. See also
Democritus, 117 Unmoving
Dialectic. See Methodology Inconsistency, self-referential: alleged, 15—
Diels, Hermann, 10, 68, 76, 77, 79, 97, 100 18, 20; intentional, 40-41, 138-40; and
Dionysodorus, 39, 118, 122 boundedness, 138—40
Dionysos (Nietzsche), 145—47 Infinity. See Unbouhdedness
Disambiguation, 120, 127-28 Inhomogeneity, 105, 110. See also Whole/of
Dissoi Logoi, 118, 119, 123 asingle kind
Divisibility, 46-47, 48, 50, 76-83. See also “Is,” 11-43 passim, 47, 115; existential, pre-
Whole/of a single kind dicative, fused, delimited, 14—15; and as-
Doom, 5, 26, 54, 74, 100—04, 108, 111, 113 sertoric negation, 22-29, 30, 138; in
Dyads. See Predicates, double canonical discourse, 37, 38-39, 47, 115,
137-39; influence of Parmenidean views,
Einstein, Albert, 147 38—40; and dropped predicates, 119; and
Eliot, T. S., 154 sensible world, 123; and boundedness,
Empedocles, 5, 81, 117, 118 137-39
Enumeration method, 8, 49-50, 94-95, “Isn’t”: barred from assertoric “is,” 12—13,
108-09, 114-15, 137-39; in pre-Socratic 19, 22-29, 30, 31, 37, 118, 138: permis-
thought, 132-35; in Plato, 134-35 sible uses of, 22, 26, 28-29, 30; modal
Euthydemus, 32, 39, 117, 118, 121, 123 use of, 23, 30, 31, 37; contradictoriness
Excluded Middle, law of, 62, 63, 153 of, 30, 36-37; as name for negative route,
SF
Fichte, Johann G., 16
Finite. See Boundedness Jesus, 142, 146
Fire (Heraclitus), 140, 141 Jordan, Robert W., 121
Fire and Night, 6, 17, 19, 34-36, 79, 125, Justice, 3, 5, 12, 106, 111-13
132; as contrary, 66, 79, 110; mimic of
what-is, 109-10 Kahn, Charles H., 36
Forms (Platonic), 38; contextual relativity Kant, Immanuel, 16, 146
of, 123-32, 134; and dropped qualifiers, Karsten emendation, 96-108
124-25, 127-28 Kneale, William, 107
Furth, Montgomery, 13, 15, 16, 19, 36, 103 Kranz, Walther, 10, 97
Melissus, 2, 69—70, 71, 117, 136 108; and contraries, 109-10; and bound-
Metalanguage: and paradox, 17-18 edness, 138—39
Methodology: of enumeration, 8, 9, 49-50, Owen, G. E. L., 38, 69, 79, 85, 107, 117,
94-95, 108-09, 114-15, 137-39; dialec- 121; on Parmenidean language, 13, 15,
tical, 61-64, 103, 108, 114 16; Mass-space section in, 73—75
Modalities, 23, 25-30, 31, 32, 35, 110-13,
153; post-Parmenidean, 111-12; philo- Paradox, 17, 40. See also Inconsistency
sophical rationale for, 113-15; denial of, Parmenides, 127-28, 134-35
133 Particular (Platonic), 124-25, 128-29
Monadic. See Predicates, single Pentheus, 151
Monism, Parmenidean, 34, 39, 138 Perfect/complete, 4, 12, 47, 48, 55-56, 66,
Moorhouse, A. C., 27, 28, 29, 31 84-86, 90; negative proof, 12, 55-56, 63
Mourelatos, Alexander P. D., 14, 21, 36, 38, Perishing,45, 47, 50-51, 57; and Karsten
75, 80, 98, 107, 155, 157; plurality in, emendation, 100—08. See also Ungenera-
20-22, 69; on contraries, 68; Mass-space ble/unperishing
section in, 74-75 Phaedo, 32, 33, 123-27
Mysticism, 9 Philebus, 128
Philosophical rationale: for “ouk esti” use,
23-24; for predication method, 60—64;
Necessity, 5, 47, 111-12
for contraries, 92—95; for modalities,
Negation: kinds of, delimited, 12—14; and
113-15
double negation, 13, 38, 39; general vs.
Plato, 2, 6, 8, 14, 18, 71, 121-30, 132, 134,
focused, 21; predicate, 25-30; subject,
149; and inconsistency, 16; on logic, 38,
25-30: modal, 25-30; 31, 32, 35, 37,
61; on qualifiers and predicates, 122, 129
110-13, 153; sentence, 26, 28, 29; innoc-
Plurality of what-is: 69-70, 87, 88, 89; ab-
uous, 26—29, 38; and canonical discourse,
stract/concrete, 78, 83, 91—92; and con-
29-31, 38-39, 137-39; and determinacy,
traries, 133
149
Plutarch: variant reading in, 69-70
Negative theology: and boundedness, 139—
Prauss, Gerold, 121
40, 144, 147, 149; Pseudo-Dionysian,
Predicates: relations between kinds of, 47,
140-41
48, 49; widening in meaning of, 102, 108;
Nehamas, Alexander, 121
and boundedness, 138; and contradic-
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 8, 145—47
tion, 138
Nirvana, 143—44
—alpha-privative, 12, 22, 46-47, 50-51,
Noncontradiction, law of, 115, 121, 125,
53—56, 102, 111; and assertoric “is,” 22—
153; and canonical discourse, 32—36, 37, 28; and negation, 25-26, 29, 112; logical
39: normative force of, 62, 63; and relations of, 51, 58, 59; in Time-section,
Forms, 126-27; in Hegel, 148—49
52—53; and canonical discourse, 138
Nussbaum, Martha, 13 —double, 46, 48-51, 56-57, 60, 113; logi-
cal relations of, 51, 58, 59; use of re-
Object-language: and paradox, 17-18 stricted, 52—54, 56—57; no mean in, 56—
Odyssey, 80 57; thematic and formal significance of,
Ontology: and logic, 1, 9, 38-39, 64, 114— 57, 60-61; and modal negation, 111
15, 153-54; “is” in, 38-39; and theory of —dropping of, 116, 119, 122, 123, 153; in
truth, 114—15; and contextual relativity, pre-Socratic thought, 130-32
123 —incomplete, 34, 120 .
“Opinion,” 4, 6-7, 17, 19, 126; and “Truth,” —single, 46, 48, 49, 54, 57-58, 113; use of
6-7, 34-35; and negation, 34, 35, 40-41; restricted, 52-57; thematic and formal
and contraries, 66, 109-10, 113 significance of, 57-58, 60-61; logical re-
Other, the: coming-to-be of, 100-03, 107— lations of, 59
09, 125, 153; and immovability, 101—03; —triple, 46-49, 51, 53-58, 60, 113; logical
and kinesis, 105-06; and methodology, relations of, 49-51, 59; use of restricted,
202 INDEX
Predicates—triple (continued) Sophist, 11, 18, 34, 38-39, 117, 123, 126—
52-54, 56-57; mean in, 56—57; thematic 28, 149
and formal significance of, 57-58, 60-61; Sophistical Refutations, 118
and contraries, 66 Space: paradoxicality of, 133
Predications: existential reduction of, 20— Sphere, of what-is, 84—86; and bounded-
21; Parmenides’ conscious methodology ness, 136, 139, 143, 147-48, 151-52. See
of, 61-64 also Boundedness; What-is.
—negative, 12, 15, 22, 23, 28, 29, 47-49, Sphere-section: predicates in, 52, 55-56;
62-63. See also Predicates, alpha-privative mean in, 57; contraries in, 57, 84—86, 88,
—positive, 12, 20, 28, 29, 46-49, 51, 52- 89-90, 91
53, 62-63 Sprague, Rosamond K., 117, 122
Principles, logical: Parmenides’ conscious Stokes, Michael C., 69, 71, 72, 73, 74, 96,
use of, 61—64. See also Noncontradiction, 97, 100, 106-07
law of; Excluded middle, law of Subordination, 48, 49—50
Protagoras, 120—23, 127 Symposium, 81
Syntax, 29
Qualifiers, dropping of, 33-36, 37, 38; and Szabé, A., 121
predicates, 116, 118, 120, 122; and con-
tradiction, 121, 124, 128-29; in Phaedo, Taran, Leonardo, 13, 18—20, 68, 78, 96, 99,
124-25; and contextual relativity, 125— 100, 103, 104, 155, 157
29; in pre-Socratic thought, 130-32 Thales, 8, 130
Thus Spake Zarathustra, 145
Raven, J. E., 14
Time: paradoxicality of, 133
Ranulf, Svend, 121, 138
Time-section: ring-composition of, 52-54;
predicates in, 52-54, 56; contraries in,
Reinhardt, Karl, 96
53, 56, 86-87, 88, 90-91; plurality of, 87
Relativity, contextual, 8, 32, 33, 36, 37, 38,
Traherne, Thomas, 136
118; and contradiction, 33, 35, 37, 119—
Transcendent, the: boundedness of, 136—
21, 123-25; and dropped predicates,
39, 141, 150, 151, 153; unboundedness
119, 121; in immanent world, 120-28;
of, 137, 139, 141-44, 147, 150, 151; co-
and dropped qualifiers, 121, 124, 125; in
incidence of, with immanent, 147-48,
pre-Socratic thought, 130-33; and deter-
149, 150
minacy, 149
Transcendental argument, 140
Republic, 123, 125
Trinity, the, 137, 152-53
Rightness, 111, 112
Triads, triplets. See Predicates, triple
Ring-composition: in Time-section, 52-54
True Trust, 17, 50, 105, 111-13
Robinson, Richard, 128
“Truth”: routes of delimited, 4
Routes: of what-is, what-is-not, opinion, de-
Truth, 6, 18, 32; Parmenidean conception
limited, 4
of, 32-33, 36-37, 39-40, 138-39; posi-
tive and negative language in, 114-15
Samsara, 143, 144
Schofield, Malcolm, 107 Unboundedness, 136-54 passim; of the im-
Secundum quid, fallacy of, 124, 132 manent, 136-37; and negative theology,
Sensible world. See Immanent world 139-40, 142-44, 147, 149: horizontal
Signposts: negative proof for, 12, 15, 63; and vertical, 146-47
contraries in proofs for, 47, 63, 90-93, Ungenerable/unperishing, 4, 5, 11, 33, 47,
96-115 passim; assertions and denials in, 49, 53-54, 66, 86-87, 88, 92-93, 99,
47—48. See also Perfect/complete; Ungen- 103-08, 112; negative proof, 12, 47, 63
erable/unperishing; Unmoving; Whole/of Unmoving, 4, 5, 11, 47-49, 54, 66, 90, 101—
a single kind 02, 103, 106, 112; negative proof, 12, 47
Simplicius, 2, 100 Untersteiner, Mario, 69, 71
Solmsen, Friedrich, 69, 70, 71 Variability, contextual. See Relativity
INDEX 203
What-is: boundedness of, 5, 6, 17, 84, 106, Epei: role of, in signpost arguments, 72—75;
108, 113, 136-39, 142-43, 150, 153; ob- introductory role of, 73-75, 99
ject of language, 5, 17, 36; subject of as- Epidees, 12, 15, 23, 34
sertion, 38, 101, 136; coherence of, 50, Esti. See “Is”
69, 71, 76-77; and predication, 58; one- Genesis, 100, 105
ness of, 70—71; atemporality of, 72-75, Hésson, 66, 67, 79, 81
99, 103-07, 136; spatiality of, 74-75; co- Homoion, 65, 70
hesiveness of, 76-77, 78; symmetry of, Husteron, 66, 86, 97, 99
84; contraries and, 92—95; coming-to-be Ison, 65
at a time, 97—99; the other between, and Katabasis, 3
what-is-not, 99-103, 104; immovability Kinésis, 100, 105. See also Other, the
of, 100—03; as truth, 115 Krisis, 5, 63
What-is-not: and coming-to-be of what-is, Mallon, 66, 67, 79, 81
98, 100-01, 107 Mé, 100; emended to tou in B8.12, 96-108;
Whole/of a single kind, 4, 5, 12, 33, 46—48, sufficiency of, in B8.12, 103-04, 107
54, 66-70, 73-83, 90, 101-02, 109-10; Méden, 22, 25, 104
negative proof, 12, 54, 63, 68, 73; variant Meizon, 66
Moira, 103, 111-13
readings of, 69-70; “epei’” in proof for,
Mounogenes. See Whole/of a single kind
72-75
Mounon, 70
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 15, 16
Nooi, 13
Woodruff, Paul B., 121
Olethros, 103, 104, 106. See also Ungenera-
ble/unperishing
Xenophanes, 2 Ouk esti. See “Isn't”
Oulomeles, 69—70
Zen, 16 Oulon. See Whole/of a single kind
Zeno, 2, 16, 102, 117-19, 120, 123, 127, Ou themis estin, 12
132-34 Pampan, 65, 98, 99
Pantéi, 81, 85
Pistis Aléthés, 111-13
SOME GREEK TERMS Prosthen, 66, 86, 97, 99
Agenéton. See Ungenerable/unperishing Séma, 69
Sémeion, 69
Akinéton. See Immovability
Suneches, 69, 70, 71, 77
Allo, 104
Sunagogé, 94
Ananké, 111-13
Té: and contraries, 67-68, 79-83, 87; in
Anarchon, 12 Homer, 80; single use of, 80-83, 87; dou-
Anélethron. See Ungenerable/unperishing ble use of, 81—82, 85
Apauston, 12 Téi kai téi, 81
Apeiron, 130-31 Téa é Tei, 81
Ateleutéton, 12 Tetelesmenon. See Perfect/complete
Atremes. See Unmoving Themis, 111-13
Baioteron, 66 Ti, 104, 107
Cheiroteron, 66 To eon, 99, 104. See also What-is
Diaresis, 94 Tos, 105
Diaireton. See Divisibility Tou: emendation of, for mé in B8.12, 96—
Diké, 111-13 108 a
r a me 7 J
ne f ‘ f
ataanetee ae
6 a a TE eeSt A At é
i er 4 Mist
he x 2 ‘ rae aoe
|
didily steak ee
oh
nese:
dot
re data © an i
Ve
f aaa en
al
OTy .®,
‘
hee
a ed bak
(ty :
j atk ot oa satpe Dar ide
ua a 7 Hipgeth
tf .
A ieee
’ os De
‘ Ny
ea? On ce
Uk aan
[Wc Memorial Library|
Cumberland Cslege
Witismsbu:g, KY 40769
lil) |jin
—-
=="
E====0
s————=)
>
_—=—===0)